Naturalism (Philosophy)
Naturalism (Philosophy)
Naturalism (Philosophy)
(philosophy)
In philosophy, naturalism is the idea that only natural laws and forces
(as opposed to supernatural ones) operate in the universe.[1] In its
primary sense,[2] it is also known as ontological naturalism, metaphysical
naturalism, pure naturalism, philosophical naturalism and
antisupernaturalism. "Ontological" refers to ontology, the philosophical
study of what exists. Philosophers often treat naturalism as equivalent to
materialism.
In the 20th century, Willard Van Orman Quine, George Santayana, and
other philosophers argued that the success of naturalism in science
meant that scientific methods should also be used in philosophy.
According to this view, science and philosophy are not always distinct
from one another, but instead form a continuum.
— Dubray 1911
History of naturalism
With the rise and dominance of Christianity in the West and the later
spread of Islam, metaphysical naturalism was generally abandoned by
intellectuals. Thus, there is little evidence for it in medieval philosophy.
Modern philosophy
It was not until the early modern era of philosophy and the Age of
Enlightenment that naturalists like Benedict Spinoza (who put forward a
theory of psychophysical parallelism), David Hume,[11] and the
proponents of French materialism (notably Denis Diderot, Julien La
Mettrie, and Baron d'Holbach) started to emerge again in the 17th and
18th centuries. In this period, some metaphysical naturalists adhered to a
distinct doctrine, materialism, which became the dominant category of
metaphysical naturalism widely defended until the end of the 19th
century.
Thomas Hobbes was a proponent of naturalism in ethics who
acknowledged normative truths and properties.[12] Immanuel Kant
rejected (reductionist) materialist positions in metaphysics,[13] but he was
not hostile to naturalism. His transcendental philosophy is considered to
be a form of liberal naturalism.[14]
Contemporary philosophy
A politicized version of naturalism that has arisen in contemporary
philosophy is Ayn Rand's Objectivism. Objectivism is an expression of
capitalist ethical idealism within a naturalistic framework. An example of
a more progressive naturalistic philosophy is secular humanism.
— Papineau 2007
In contemporary continental philosophy, Quentin Meillassoux proposed
speculative materialism, a post-Kantian return to David Hume which can
strengthen classical materialist ideas.[22]
Etymology
The term "methodological naturalism" is much more recent, though.
According to Ronald Numbers, it was coined in 1983 by Paul de Vries, a
Wheaton College philosopher. De Vries distinguished between what he
called "methodological naturalism", a disciplinary method that says
nothing about God's existence, and "metaphysical naturalism", which
"denies the existence of a transcendent God".[23] The term
"methodological naturalism" had been used in 1937 by Edgar S.
Brightman in an article in The Philosophical Review as a contrast to
"naturalism" in general, but there the idea was not really developed to its
more recent distinctions.[24]
Description
A 21st century image of the universe and a 1888 illustration of the cosmos
Arthur Newell Strahler states: "The naturalistic view is that the particular
universe we observe came into existence and has operated through all
time and in all its parts without the impetus or guidance of any
supernatural agency."[29] "The great majority of contemporary
philosophers urge that that reality is exhausted by nature, containing
nothing 'supernatural', and that the scientific method should be used to
investigate all areas of reality, including the 'human spirit'." Philosophers
widely regard naturalism as a "positive" term, and "few active
philosophers nowadays are happy to announce themselves as 'non-
naturalists'". "Philosophers concerned with religion tend to be less
enthusiastic about 'naturalism'" and that despite an "inevitable"
divergence due to its popularity, if more narrowly construed, (to the
chagrin of John McDowell, David Chalmers and Jennifer Hornsby, for
example), those not so disqualified remain nonetheless content "to set
the bar for 'naturalism' higher."[30]
Methodological naturalism
The position that the study of the function of nature is also the study of
the origin of nature is in contrast with opponents who take the position
that functioning of the cosmos is unrelated to how it originated. While
they are open to supernatural fiat in its invention and coming into
existence, during scientific study to explain the functioning of the cosmos,
they do not appeal to the supernatural. They agree that allowing
"science to appeal to untestable supernatural powers to explain how
nature functions would make the scientist's task meaningless, undermine
the discipline that allows science to make progress, and would be as
profoundly unsatisfying as the ancient Greek playwright's reliance upon
the deus ex machina to extract his hero from a difficult predicament."[55]
W. V. O. Quine
W. V. O. Quine describes naturalism as the position that there is no
higher tribunal for truth than natural science itself. In his view, there is no
better method than the scientific method for judging the claims of
science, and there is neither any need nor any place for a "first
philosophy", such as (abstract) metaphysics or epistemology, that could
stand behind and justify science or the scientific method.
Karl Popper
Karl Popper equated naturalism with inductive theory of science. He
rejected it based on his general critique of induction (see problem of
induction), yet acknowledged its utility as means for inventing
conjectures.
Alvin Plantinga
Alvin Plantinga, Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at Notre Dame, and a
Christian, has become a well-known critic of naturalism.[58] He suggests,
in his evolutionary argument against naturalism, that the probability that
evolution has produced humans with reliable true beliefs, is low or
inscrutable, unless the evolution of humans was guided (for example, by
God). According to David Kahan of the University of Glasgow, in order
to understand how beliefs are warranted, a justification must be found in
the context of supernatural theism, as in Plantinga's
epistemology.[59][60][61] (See also supernormal stimuli).
— Alvin Plantinga,
Naturalism Defeated?:
Essays on Plantinga's
Evolutionary Argument
Against Naturalism,
"Introduction"[62]
The argument is controversial and has been criticized as seriously flawed,
for example, by Elliott Sober.[63][64]
Robert T. Pennock
Robert T. Pennock states that as supernatural agents and powers "are
above and beyond the natural world and its agents and powers" and
"are not constrained by natural laws", only logical impossibilities
constrain what a supernatural agent cannot do. He says: "If we could
apply natural knowledge to understand supernatural powers, then, by
definition, they would not be supernatural." As the supernatural is
necessarily a mystery to us, it can provide no grounds on which one can
judge scientific models. "Experimentation requires observation and
control of the variables.... But by definition we have no control over
supernatural entities or forces." Science does not deal with meanings; the
closed system of scientific reasoning cannot be used to define itself.
Allowing science to appeal to untestable supernatural powers would
make the scientist's task meaningless, undermine the discipline that
allows science to make progress, and "would be as profoundly
unsatisfying as the ancient Greek playwright's reliance upon the deus ex
machina to extract his hero from a difficult predicament."[65]
See also
Atheism
Clockwork universe
Daoism
Deism
Dysteleology
Empiricism
Hylomorphism
Legal naturalism
Liberal naturalism
Materialism
Monism
Naturalist computationalism
Naturalistic fallacy
Naturalistic pantheism
Philosophy of nature
Physicalism
Platonized naturalism
Poetic naturalism
Religious naturalism
Scientism
Sociological naturalism
Supernaturalism
Transcendental naturalism
Vaisheshika
References
Citations
1. "naturalism" (http://www.oed.com/view/E
ntry/125337?redirectedFrom=naturalis
m) . Oxford English Dictionary Online.
2. Papineau, David (22 February 2007).
"Naturalism" (http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/spr2007/entries/naturalism/#N
atPhy) . In Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"According to philosopher Steven
Lockwood, naturalism can be separated
into an ontological sense and a
methodological sense."
3. Kurtz, Paul (Spring 1998). "Darwin Re-
Crucified: Why Are So Many Afraid of
Naturalism?" (https://web.archive.org/we
b/20121018023306/http://www.secularhu
manism.org/library/fi/kurtz_18_2.html) .
Free Inquiry. 18 (2). Archived from the
original (http://www.secularhumanism.or
g/library/fi/kurtz_18_2.html) on 18
October 2012. Retrieved 6 April 2011.
4. Schafersman 1996, Methodological
naturalism is the adoption or
assumption of naturalism in scientific
belief and practice without really
believing in naturalism.
5. Chatterjee, A (2012). "Naturalism in
Classical Indian Philosophy" (http://plat
o.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/
naturalism-india/) . In Zalta, Edward N.
(ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition).
6. Riepe, Dale (1996). Naturalistic
Tradition in Indian Thought. Motilal
Banarsidass Publ. pp. 227–246.
ISBN 978-8120812932.
7. Leaman, Oliver (1999). Key Concepts in
Eastern Philosophy. Routledge. p. 269.
ISBN 978-0415173629.
8. O'Keefe, Tim (2010). Epicureanism.
University of California Press. pp. 11–13.
9. See especially Physics, books I and II.
10. Hankinson, R. J. (1997). Cause and
Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought
(https://books.google.com/books?id=iwf
y-n5IWL8C) . Oxford University Press.
p. 125. ISBN 978-0-19-924656-4.
11. William Edward Morris, "David Hume"
(https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hum
e/) , The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (21 May 2014), Edward N.
Zalta (ed.)
12. Abizadeh, A. (2018). Hobbes and the
Two Faces of Ethics (https://books.googl
e.com/books?id=CWJjDwAAQBAJ&pg=
PA23) . Cambridge University Press.
p. 23. ISBN 978-1-108-41729-7. Retrieved
14 June 2023.
13. Rohlf, Michael (28 July 2020).
"Immanuel Kant". Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plat
o.stanford.edu/entries/kant/) .
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University.
14. Hanna, Robert, Kant, Science, and
Human Nature. Clarendon Press, 2006,
p. 16.
15. Frederick C. Beiser(2002), German
Idealism: The Struggle Against
Subjectivism 1781–1801, Harvard
university Press, p. 506.
16. Axel Honneth, Hans Joas, Social Action
and Human Nature, Cambridge
University Press, 1988, p. 18.
17. See Georgi Plekhanov, "For the Sixtieth
Anniversary of Hegel's Death" (1891).
See also Plekhanov, Essays on the
History of Materialism (1893)
and Plekhanov, The Development of the
Monist View of History (1895).
18. Owen Chadwick, The Secularization of
the European Mind in the Nineteenth
Century, Cambridge University Press,
1990, p. 165: "During the 1850s German ...
scientists conducted a controversy
known ... as the materialistic controversy.
It was specially associated with the
names of Vogt, Moleschott and
Büchner" and p. 173: "Frenchmen were
surprised to see Büchner and Vogt. ...
[T]he French were surprised at German
materialism".
19. The Nineteenth Century and After, Vol.
151 (https://books.google.com/books?id=
8-VXAAAAIAAJ&q=) , 1952, p. 227: "the
Continental materialism of Moleschott
and Buchner".
20. Papineau, David "Naturalism" (http://pl
ato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism/) ,
in "The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy"
21. Papineau, David (2011). "The Rise of
Physicalism" (https://web.archive.org/we
b/20160601180141/http://ebooks.cambrid
ge.org/ebook.jsf?bid=CBO978051157079
7) . In Gillett, Carl; Loewer, Barry (eds.).
Physicalism and its Discontents.
Cambridge.
doi:10.1017/CBO9780511570797 (https://d
oi.org/10.1017%2FCBO9780511570797) .
ISBN 9780521801751. Archived from the
original (http://ebooks.cambridge.org/e
book.jsf?bid=CBO9780511570797) on 1
June 2016. Retrieved 9 January 2018.
22. Quentin Meillassoux (2008), After
Finitude, Bloomsbury, p. 90.
23. Nick Matzke: On the Origins of
Methodological Naturalism (http://www.
pandasthumb.org/archives/2006/03/on
_the_origins.html) Archived (https://we
b.archive.org/web/20060903191457/htt
p://www.pandasthumb.org/archives/200
6/03/on_the_origins.html) 2006-09-03
at the Wayback Machine. The Pandas
Thumb (March 20, 2006)
24. "ASA March 2006 – Re: Methodological
Naturalism" (https://archive.today/2012
0801144730/http://www.calvin.edu/archiv
e/asa/200603/0501.html) . Archived
from the original (http://www.calvin.edu/
archive/asa/200603/0501.html) on 1
August 2012. Retrieved 18 June 2006.
25. Schafersman 1996.
26. Sagan, Carl (2002). Cosmos. Random
House. ISBN 9780375508325.
27. Danto 1967, p. 448.
28. Stone 2008, p. 2: Personally, I place
great emphasis on the phrase "in
principle", since there are many things
that science does not now explain. And
perhaps we need some natural piety
concerning the ontological limit
question as to why there is anything at
all. But the idea that naturalism is a
polemical notion is important"
29. Strahler 1992, p. 3.
30. Papineau 2007.
31. (Plantinga 2010)
32. Priddy, Robert (1998). "Chapter Five,
Scientific Objectivity in Question" (htt
p://robertpriddy.com/lim/5.html) .
Science Limited.
33. Whitehead 1997, p. 135.
34. Boldman, Lee (2007). "Chapter 6, The
Privileged Status of Science" (http://pre
ss-files.anu.edu.au/downloads/press/p98
831/pdf/ch0615.pdf) (PDF).
35. Papineau, David "Naturalism" (http://pl
ato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism/) ,
in The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, quote, "The great majority
of contemporary philosophers would
happily... reject 'supernatural' entities,
and allow that science is a possible
route (if not necessarily the only one) to
important truths about the 'human
spirit'."
36. Heilbron 2003, p. vii.
37. Chen 2009, pp. 1–2.
38. Durak 2008.
39. Vaccaro, Joan. "Reality" (http://www.ict.g
riffith.edu.au/joan/atheism/reality.php) .
Retrieved 22 December 2017.
40. Vaccaro, Joan. "Objectiveism" (http://ww
w.ict.griffith.edu.au/joan/atheism/objecti
vism.php) . Retrieved 22 December
2017. "Objective reality exists beyond or
outside our self. Any belief that it arises
from a real world outside us is actually
an assumption. It seems more beneficial
to assume that an objective reality
exists than to live with solipsism, and so
people are quite happy to make this
assumption. In fact we made this
assumption unconsciously when we
began to learn about the world as
infants. The world outside ourselves
appears to respond in ways which are
consistent with it being real. The
assumption of objectivism is essential if
we are to attach the contemporary
meanings to our sensations and feelings
and make more sense of them."
41. Sobottka 2005, p. 11.
42. Gauch 2002, p. 154, "Expressed as a
single grand statement, science
presupposes that the physical world is
orderly and comprehensible. The most
obvious components of this
comprehensive presupposition are that
the physical world exists and that our
sense perceptions are generally
reliable."
43. Gould 1987, p. 120, "You cannot go to a
rocky outcrop and observe either the
constancy of nature's laws or the
working of known processes. It works the
other way around." You first assume
these propositions and "then you go to
the outcrop of rock."
44. Simpson 1963, pp. 24–48, "Uniformity is
an unprovable postulate justified, or
indeed required, on two grounds. First,
nothing in our incomplete but extensive
knowledge of history disagrees with it.
Second, only with this postulate is a
rational interpretation of history
possible and we are justified in seeking
—as scientists we must seek—such a
rational interpretation."
45. Gould 1965, pp. 223–228.
46. Gould 1984, p. 11.
47. Hooykaas 1963, p. 38.
48. "Simple Random Sampling" (https://we
b.archive.org/web/20180102073443/htt
p://www.betterevaluation.org/evaluation-
options/simplerandom) . Archived from
the original (http://betterevaluation.org/
evaluation-options/simplerandom) on 2
January 2018. Retrieved 6 January 2018.
"A simple random sample (SRS) is the
most basic probabilistic option used for
creating a sample from a population.
Each SRS is made of individuals drawn
from a larger population, completely at
random. As a result, said individuals
have an equal chance of being selected
throughout the sampling process. The
benefit of SRS is that as a result, the
investigator is guaranteed to choose a
sample which is representative of the
population, which ensures statistically
valid conclusions."
49. "Kitzmiller v. Dover: Day 3, AM: Robert
Pennock (continued)" (http://www.talkori
gins.org/faqs/dover/day3am2.html) .
www.talkorigins.org.
50. Scott, Eugenie C. (1996). " "Creationism,
Ideology, and Science" ". In Gross; Levitt;
Lewis (eds.). The Flight From Science
and Reason. The New York Academy of
Sciences. pp. 519–520.
51. Scott, Eugenie C. (2008). "Science and
Religion, Methodology and Humanism"
(http://ncse.com/religion/science-religion
-methodology-humanism) . NCSE.
Retrieved 20 March 2012.
52. Ecklund, Elaine Howard (2010). Science
vs. Religion: What Scientists Really
Think. Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0195392982.
53. [[wikisource:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area
School District/4:Whether ID Is
Science#4. Whether ID is Science
|Kitzmiller v. Dover: Whether ID is
Science]]
54. "Kitzmiller v. Dover: Day 3, AM: Robert
Pennock (continued)" (http://www.talkori
gins.org/faqs/dover/day3am2.html) .
www.talkorigins.org.
55. Pennock, Robert T. (10 June 2015).
"Supernaturalist Explanations..." (https://
web.archive.org/web/20150610013620/ht
tp://www.msu.edu/~pennock5/research/p
apers/Pennock_SupNatExpl.html)
msu.edu. Archived from the original (htt
p://www.msu.edu/~pennock5/research/pa
pers/Pennock_SupNatExpl.html) on 10
June 2015. Retrieved 16 June 2021.
56. Lynne Rudder (2013). Naturalism and
the First-Person Perspective (https://boo
ks.google.com/books?id=9G_bIWzgjFkC
&pg=PA5) . Oxford University Press.
p. 5. ISBN 978-0199914746.
57. Quine has argued that "Epistemology,
or something like it, simply falls into
place as a chapter of psychology." The
Quinean view that we should abandon
epistemology for psychology, however, is
not widely accepted by contemporary
naturalists in epistemology. See
Feldman, Richard (2012). "Naturalized
Epistemology" (http://plato.stanford.ed
u/archives/sum2012/entries/epistemolog
y-naturalized/) . In Zalta, Edward N.
(ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Summer 2012 ed.).
Retrieved 4 June 2014. "Quinean
Replacement Naturalism finds relatively
few supporters."
58. Beilby, J.K. (2002). Naturalism
Defeated?: Essays on Plantinga's
Evolutionary Argument Against
Naturalism (https://books.google.com/b
ooks?id=p40tc_T7-rMC&pg=PR9) . G –
Reference, Information and
Interdisciplinary Subjects Series. Cornell
University Press. p. ix.
ISBN 9780801487637. LCCN 2001006111
(https://lccn.loc.gov/2001006111) .
59. "Gifford Lecture Series – Warrant and
Proper Function 1987–1988" (https://web.
archive.org/web/20120104024641/http://
www.giffordlectures.org/Browse.asp?PubI
D=TPWAPF&Cover=TRUE) . Archived
from the original (http://www.giffordlect
ures.org/Browse.asp?PubID=TPWAPF&C
over=TRUE) on 4 January 2012.
Retrieved 14 January 2012.
60. Plantinga, Alvin (11 April 2010).
"Evolution, Shibboleths, and
Philosophers — Letters to the Editor" (ht
tp://chronicle.com/article/Evolution-Shib
boleths-and/64990/) . The Chronicle of
Higher Education. "...I do indeed think
that evolution functions as a
contemporary shibboleth by which to
distinguish the ignorant fundamentalist
goats from the informed and
scientifically literate sheep.
References
External links
Retrieved from
"https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?
title=Naturalism_(philosophy)&oldid=122512133
9"
This page was last edited on 22 May 2024, at
14:03. •
Content is available under CC BY-SA 4.0
unless otherwise noted.