Traditional Logic I Student Book Sample

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

Table of Contents

Table of Contents

A Note to the Teacher.....................................................................................................................v

Introduction......................................................................................................................... 1

Simple Apprehension (Term)

Chapter 1: What is Simple Apprehension?.................................................................................9


Chapter 2: Comprehension and Extension...............................................................................15
Chapter 3: Signification and Supposition..................................................................................23

Judgment (Proposition)

Chapter 4: What is Judgment?.................................................................................................31


Chapter 5: The Four Statements of Logic.................................................................................39
Chapter 6: Contradictory and Contrary Statements..................................................................49
Chapter 7: Subcontraries and Subalterns.................................................................................61
Chapter 8: Distribution of Terms................................................................................................71
Chapter 9: Obversion, Conversion, and Contraposition...........................................................81

Deductive Inference (Syllogism)

Chapter 10: What is Deductive Inference?...............................................................................95


Chapter 11: Terminological Rules for Categorical Syllogisms.................................................107
Chapter 12: Quantitative Rules for Categorical Syllogisms....................................................115
Chapter 13: Qualitative Rules for Categorical Syllogisms......................................................125

Chapter 14: Review........................................................................................................ 133

Glossary of Terms.......................................................................................................... 145


Introduction

What is Logic?

Introduction. T
 he best way to answer the question “What
is logic?” is with a definition. But that is easier said than done. Throughout
history, many people have thought and written about the subject of logic and
many people have offered definitions. Some of them are useful and some are
not.
Logic is the
Josiah Royce, an American philosopher, defined logic as “the science of science of right
order,” but this definition is so general that it really could include things thinking.
outside of logic, and so it really doesn’t tell us much.
Other definitions are a little too simple. The writer Oliver Wendell Holmes
said, “Logic is logic. That’s all I say.” That obviously won’t help us.
The writers of a book on fallacies (we’ll explain what those are later)
defined logic as “the defense against trickery.” That’s one thing logic is, but
certainly not all.
Much better is the definition given by Raymond McCall: “Logic in general
is the science of right thinking.” Jacques Maritain, a very famous philosopher,
had a similar definition. “Logic,” he said, “is the art which enables us to
proceed with order, ease, and correctness in the act of reason itself.”
Irving Copi, who wrote a book on logic still used in many colleges, gets
even a little more specific. “The distinction between correct and incorrect
reasoning is the central problem with which logic deals.” As you proceed in
this book, you will see that this is so.
Aristotle is
The History of Logic. T he eighteenth-century German considered the
philosopher Immanuel Kant called Aristotle, the ancient Greek philosopher,
the “father of logic.” If we are thinking only of traditional, or formal, logic
father of logic.
(which is the only kind of logic we study in this book), this is true. In fact,
formal logic has changed hardly at all since the time of Aristotle, who lived
from 384-322 B.C.
Shortly after the time of Aristotle, another Greek philosopher laid the
groundwork for modern symbolic logic—his name was Chrysippus (279-206
B.C.). During the Middle Ages, the kind of logic developed by Chrysippus

1
Introduction

did not receive much attention. But in the 17th and early 18th centuries,
philosophers began to take another look at the logical system of Chrysippus.
One of the first and most famous of these is Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1781-
1848). Since then, many advances have been made in symbolic logic.
In addition, another form of logical thought, called induction, has become
a part of the subject that we know as logic. John Stuart Mill (1806-1873),
who lived in the 19th century, pioneered the theories about induction that
we study today.
The two main At the end of the 19th century and into our own, other logical methods
branches of logic have been developed, many of which have as much, if not more, to do with
mathematics than with philosophy. Gottlob Frege (1848-1925), Alfred
are formal logic
North Whitehead (1861-1947), and Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) are names
and material associated with the more modern kinds of mathematical logic.
logic. For our purposes, we will stick to the formal logic of Aristotle, which is
just as useful today as it was when it was set forth over 2,300 years ago.
The Two Main Branches of Logic. There are two main
branches of logic. One is called formal, or “minor,” logic, the other material,
or “major,” logic. The two branches are quite distinct and deal with different
problems.
Material logic is concerned with the content of argumentation. It deals
with the truth of the terms and the propositions in an argument.
Formal logic is interested in the form or structure of reasoning. The truth
of an argument is of only secondary consideration in this branch of logic.
Formal logic is concerned with the method of deriving one truth from another.
The distinction between these two branches of logic was nicely described
by G. K. Chesterton:
Logic and truth … have very little to do with each other. Logic is concerned merely with
the fidelity and accuracy with which a certain process is performed, a process which can
be performed with any materials, with any assumption. You can be as logical about grif-
fins and basilisks as about sheep and pigs.… Logic, then, is not necessarily an instrument
for finding out truth; on the contrary, truth is a necessary instrument for using logic—for
using it, that is, for the discovery of further truth.… Briefly, you can only find truth with
logic if you have already found truth without it.

Three This last remark of Chesterton’s is important. It is not the purpose of formal
logic to discover truth. That is the business of everyday observation and, in
important terms certain more formal circumstances, empirical science. Logic serves only to
in logic are truth, lead us from one truth to another.
validity, and That is why, for example, you should not call a statement of fact logical
or illogical (although this is commonly done in everyday argument). You
soundness. should instead call it true or false. Likewise, you should not call an argument
(which contains several statements of fact) true or false. You should only call
it valid or invalid. Validity is the term we use when we mean to say that
an argument is logical. The term soundness, however, can be applied to an
argument to say something about both its truth and its validity.

2
Introduction

Truth, Validity, and Soundness. T ruth means the


correspondence of a statement to reality. An argument is valid when its
conclusion follows logically from its premises. The term ‘soundness’ is used to
indicate that all the premises in an argument are true and that the argument
is valid.
An argument can contain true premises and still be invalid. Likewise, it
can be perfectly valid (or logical, if you prefer) and contain false premises.
The verbal
But if an argument is sound, its premises must be true and it must be valid.
expression
If this sounds confusing, don’t worry: these concepts will become clearer of a simple
as we progress through the material in this book. apprehension is
The Components of an Argument. An argument contains called the term.
several components. In order to illustrate what these components are and
how they work in the reasoning process, let us begin with a simple argument:
All men are mortal
Socrates is a man
Therefore, Socrates is mortal
The first two statements are premises and the last is the conclusion. All
arguments must have at least two premises and one conclusion.
On the face of it, this argument contains a number of words making
up three statements which fit together into what looks and sounds like an
argument. But there is more here than meets the eye.
In formal logic, we recognize three kinds of logical processes. We recognize
that each of these originates in a mental act, but that each also manifests
itself as (and is known to us in the form of) a verbal expression.
Term. The mental act involved in the first of these three logical
processes is called simple apprehension. We call the verbal expression of
simple apprehension the term. A simple apprehension occurs when we first
form in our mind a concept of something. When we put this concept into words,
we have put this simple apprehension in the form of a term.
At the point of simple apprehension, we do not affirm or deny anything
about it. We just possess or grasp it.
If in your mind, for example, you think of this book (the one you’re reading
right now), you are performing this first logical process. You are having a
simple apprehension. And if you speak or write anything about it, you will
have to use a term, the term ‘book.’
In the argument above (the one about Socrates), there are three terms
representing three simple apprehensions. The first is ‘men’; the second is
‘Socrates’; and the third is ‘mortal.’ Each one of these represents in our mind
a concept that we have transformed into a word. The concept we call the
simple apprehension and the word we call the term.

Mental Act Verbal Expression

Simple Apprehension Term

3
Introduction

Proposition. T  he mental act involved in the second of these


three logical processes is called judgment. The verbal expression of a
judgment is called a proposition. We perform a judgment any time we think
The verbal in our mind that something is something else (which we call affirmation),
and also when we think that something is not something else (which we call
expression of
denial). To judge is to affirm or deny.
a judgment If you think that this book is boring, then you are performing a judgment.
is called a If you verbally express this judgment, you will have to do it in the form of a
proposition. proposition, the proposition “This book is boring.” The judgment is the mental
act you have when you think that this book is boring, and the proposition is
the statement you make to express that thought.
In the argument above, there are three propositions expressed. The first
is “All men are mortal”; the second is “Socrates is a man”; and the third is
“Socrates is mortal.” Each one of these represents in our mind a thought that
something is something else: that all ‘men’ are ‘mortal’; that ‘Socrates’ is a
‘man’; and that ‘Socrates’ is ‘mortal.’
We should point out that some people use the word ‘statement’ instead
of ‘proposition.’ They mean the same thing, but to be consistent, we will use
the word ‘proposition.’

Mental Act Verbal Expression

Judgment Proposition

The verbal Syllogism. The mental act involved in the third of these three
logical processes is called deductive inference. We call the verbal expression
expression of of deductive inference the syllogism. A deductive inference occurs when we
a deductive make the logical connections in our mind between the terms in the argument
in a way that shows us that the conclusion either follows or does not follow
inference is from the premises. When we verbally express this in an argument, we have
called a syllogism. put this deductive inference in the form of a syllogism.
It is at this point that we are said to make progress in knowledge. It is
through the process of deductive inference, as expressed in a syllogism, that
we can say, as we explained above, that we have gone from one truth or set
of truths to another truth.
Let’s say the reason you think this book is boring is because you think
all books are boring. If this were true, you would be performing a deductive
inference. You would be thinking to yourself, all books are boring, and this
is a book. Therefore, this book is boring. And if you verbally expressed this
deductive inference, you would do it in the form of a syllogism. The judgment
expressed by “All books are boring” and “This is a book” are different than the
judgment “This book is boring.” Through deductive inference, however, you
can go from these first two to the last one. In this way, you have gone from
one set of truths to another truth (if indeed they are true, which hopefully
they are not).

4
Introduction

We would say that the argument above (the one about Socrates), in its
entirety, is a syllogism. It expresses a deductive inference that logically
connects certain simple apprehensions that are parts of three judgments.
And this process has been expressed in the form of a syllogism.

Mental Act Verbal Expression

Deductive Inference Syllogism

If we now put this all together, keeping our distinction between mental
acts and verbal expressions, it would look like this: The initial
Mental Act Verbal Expression act—picking up
his foot—is like
Simple Apprehension Term the initial logical
Judgment Proposition
Deductive Inference Syllogism
act of simple
apprehension.
In order to give ourselves a mental picture of these three logical processes, Taking a full step
let us think of a man walking. In order to get from, say, one room to another, is like making
he has to pick up his foot and take several steps in order to get to the room
that is his destination. The initial act—picking up his foot—is like the a judgment.
initial logical act of simple apprehension. Taking a full step is like making And stringing
a judgment. And stringing all the steps together into one movement is like all the steps
deductive inference—we move from one place to another.
together into
Summary. W  e started out by defining logic as “the science of one movement
right thinking.” We said there are two main branches of logic. One is called is like deductive
formal, or minor, logic, the other material, or major, logic. Material logic inference.
is concerned with the content of argumentation. Formal logic is interested in
the form or structure of reasoning. We defined truth as correspondence with
reality. We said an argument is valid when its conclusion follows logically
from its premises. And we said that soundness indicates that all the premises
in an argument are true and that the argument is valid.
We said also that all arguments must contain two premises and a
conclusion. And we said, finally, that there are three mental acts that make
up the logical process: simple apprehension, judgment, and deductive
inference. These three mental acts correspond to three verbal expressions:
term, proposition, and syllogism.

5
Introduction

Exercises for Day 1. R


 ead the entire chapter. You may read it fairly quickly on this
first reading. Don’t expect to understand everything you read. Try only to get a general idea of what the
chapter is about. Next, read the beginning sections of the introduction: “The History of Logic” and “The
Two Main Branches of Logic.” Read these sections carefully and try to fully understand them.

1. Based on what you have read in this chapter, what is the definition of logic?

2. Who was called the “father of logic”?

3. Who laid the groundwork for modern symbolic logic?

4. Give the name of one philosopher who made advances in symbolic logic.

5. Who pioneered the theories about induction that we study today?

6. Give the names of three people whose names are associated with modern kinds of mathematical logic.

7. Give the names of the two main branches of logic.

8. Explain the first of the main branches of logic (in Question 7) and describe it in your own words.

9. Explain the second of the main branches of logic (in Question 7) and describe it in your own words.

10. Indicate whether the following statements are true or false:

T F The purpose of formal logic is to discover truth.


T F It is necessary to have logic in order to discover truth.
T F Logic leads us from one truth to another.
T F A statement can be true or false.
T F A statement can be valid or invalid.
T F An argument can be true or false.
T F An argument can be valid or invalid.
T F Truth is only of secondary consideration in formal logic.

Exercises for Day 2. Read “Truth, Validity, and Soundness” and “The Components of
an Argument.” Read them carefully.

11. On the basis of today’s reading, define ‘truth.’

12. On the basis of today’s reading, explain what it means to say an argument is valid.

13. On the basis of today’s reading, define ‘soundness.’

14. Indicate whether the following statements are true or false:


T F An argument can contain true premises and be invalid.
T F An argument can be sound and contain false premises.
T F A sound argument must be valid.
T F A valid argument must be sound.
T F An argument with true premises can be unsound.
T F An argument can contain only one premise.
6
Introduction

15. In the following argument, identify the premises and the conclusion by writing the words ‘premise’
or ‘conclusion’ in the space next to the statement.

All men are mortal


Socrates is a man
Therefore, Socrates is mortal

16. Name the three types of logical processes (or acts of the mind) involved in logic.

Exercises for Day 3. R


 ead “Term” and “Proposition.”
17. Each of these logical processes or mental acts (in Question 16 above) originates in a _____________
___________ and manifests itself in the form of a ______________________________ .

18. What is the mental act involved in the first of the three kinds of logical processes?

19. What is the verbal expression connected to this mental act (in Question 18)?

20. What occurs in our minds when we have a simple apprehension?

21. If you think of this book and have the concept in your mind, you are having a simple apprehension.
What is the term you use to verbally express this particular simple apprehension?

22. Name the terms included in the argument in Question 15 above.

23. What does each one of these terms (in Question 22) represent?

24. What is the mental act involved in the second of the three kinds of logical processes?

25. What is the verbal expression connected to this mental act (in Question 24)?

26. What occurs in our minds when we perform a judgment?

27. If you think that this book is boring by affirming in your mind that this is so, your mind is
performing a judgment. What is the term you use to verbally express this judgment?

28. Indicate the propositions included in the argument in Question 15 above.

29. What does each one of these propositions (in Question 28) represent?

Exercises for Day 4. R


 ead “Syllogism” and “Summary.” Read them carefully.

30. What is the mental act involved in the third of the three kinds of logical processes?

31. What is the verbal expression connected to this mental act (in Question 30)?

32. Describe in no less than one and no more than three sentences what occurs in our minds when we
engage in deductive inference.

7
Introduction

33. If you think that because all books are boring and that this is a book, and that therefore this book is
boring, your mind engaged in deductive inference. What is the term you use to verbally express this
deductive inference?

34. Fill out the chart below, listing the mental acts and their corresponding verbal expressions in the
order in which we have covered them:

Mental Act Verbal Expression

 ___________________  ___________________

 ___________________  ___________________

 ___________________  ___________________

35. Draw a line to indicate which action best describes what each mental act is like:

Taking a step Simple Apprehension

Picking up your foot Deductive Inference

Walking from one place to another Judgment

You might also like