SSRN Id3517589
SSRN Id3517589
SSRN Id3517589
Brian Leiter*
bleiter@uchicago.edu
January 10, 2020
This essay offers a programmatic statement for a realist theory of law. Although I have been
influenced by (and written about) the work of earlier American, Scandinavian, Italian and other legal
realists, this is not an essay about what others have thought. This is an essay about what I take realism
about law to mean and what its theoretical commitments are; I shall use other realists to sometimes
illustrate the distinctive positions of a realist theory of law, but will make clear where I depart from
them.
A realist theory of law involves both a “realist” and a “naturalistic” perspective on law. Let me
“Realism” describes a theoretical outlook that is no longer fashionable in the universities, and
also one that has nothing to do with the metaphysical doctrine picked out by the same word. Realists in
the latter sense are concerned only about the mind-independent status of some class of entities (for
example, values). By contrast, “realism” in the sense at issue here takes no stand on metaphysical
questions, that is, the “scholastic” question, as Marx called it, about the “reality or non-reality of
thinking.”
Realism, in the sense at issue for jurisprudence, reflects a quite different intellectual tradition,
usually associated with Thucydides, Machiavelli, and Nietzsche, among others (see, e.g., Leiter 2012).
There are two key components of realism in this sense. First, realists aim to describe how things really
*
Karl N. Llewellyn Professor of Jurisprudence and Director of the Center for Law, Philosophy & Human
Values, University of Chicago. These thoughts crystallized in the course of a series of seminars on realist
jurisprudence I presented at the École des Haute Études en Sciences Sociales in Paris in June 2019. I am grateful to
Prof. Otto Pfersman for inviting me and for his contributions to the seminars, as well as those of the students. I
was also helped by discussion with students in my fall 2019 graduate seminar on current issues in general
jurisprudence at the University of Chicago. Finally, I am grateful to Joshua Fox, a PhD student at the University of
Chicago, for outstanding research assistance.
reality, not what we might wish them to be. Realists also do not suppose that the way things are will
make “moral sense” or turn out to be morally defensible: it can (and often does) turn out that law and
its operations are morally objectionable or worse. Realists can be animated by normative hopes,
certainly, but they do not build them in to the account of their subject-matter (contrast, for example,
Ronald Dworkin’s jurisprudence which builds a moral obligation to obey the law into his account of the
nature of law). In the first instance, we need to understand what is really going on: for example, what
are people’s real motivations, what are they actually doing (independent of what they say they are
doing). Thucydides and Machiavelli are the lodestars of the realist tradition in political thought: do not
pay attention to the self-serving pontifications of the leaders of Greek or Italian city-states, they teach
us; understand that in reality they are all bent on power, glory and survival. Thucydides sets these facts
before the reader, and lets the reader draw the conclusion: unbridled lust for power and glory led to
the ruin of Athens. Machiavelli addresses himself to those who rule now, and tells them what they
must do to hold on to their power. Realists like Thucydides and Machiavelli tell us how politics really
works, in ancient Greece or Renaissance Italy; they withhold moral judgment even if, as with
Because realism means understanding reality, realists are necessarily “naturalists” in the
following precise sense: in describing and explaining what is really going on they rely only on those
mechanisms and entities that are explanatorily fruitful in the successful empirical sciences (those
sciences being our only reliable guide to what is real). Naturalism is the second crucial commitment of
realist jurisprudence. Of the historical legal realists, the Scandinavians were most explicit about
commitment to naturalism, while the Italians and the Americans, in different ways, presuppose a
naturalistic worldview (even though the Americans were philosophically unsophisticated). Insofar as
only what is naturalistically explicable can be real, naturalism must be central to the realist worldview.
the most important philosophical naturalist of the 20th-century, was, ironically, often a very bad Quinean
in many respects. The crucial commitment of naturalism, as even Quine professed, is a posteriori:
whatever works in the successful sciences is admissible into a naturalist ontology. Yet Quine remained
committed1 to two failed scientific research programs: physicalism (the idea that everything real must
philosopher, Jerry Fodor, pointed out in the 1970s,2 reduction to physics has not marked the last half-
century of scientific research; instead, there has been a proliferation of special sciences—biological and
cognitive sciences most notably—that proceed without even the pretense of being reducible to physics.
Promoters of 'naturalizing' [i.e., physicalist reductionist] projects are often driven, I think, by
representation -- of reference or attribution that can be correct or incorrect and that helps type-
but in scientific explanation in psychology. There is nothing unnatural or supernatural about such
science. There is no basis, even a prima facie one, to the worry that psychological notions are
invitations to mystery or miracle. Even if there were such basis, the role that these notions play in
powerful empirical science would undermine it. . . . I know of no good ground for thinking that. . .
[psychologists'] explanatory claims must be twisted into the mold of biological or information-
1
In one of his late works, Pursuit of Truth, Quine professed commitment to Davidsonian anomalous
monism, although for reasons that seem hard to square with his other commitments. See Quine, 1990, pp. 70-73.
2
Fodor, 1975, pp. 9-26.
explanatorily successful.3
For naturalists, explanatory and predictive fruitfulness is the mark of the real and the knowable, not
some a priori and empirically unmotivated assumption that everything must be reducible to physics.
Quine himself was “officially” a resolutely methodological naturalist in this sense—even allowing that
we would have to jettison “empiricism” (the view that all knowledge derives from sensory experience) if
telepathy turned out to work4--yet in practice he remained wedded to the failed science of the middle of
the last century. That also explains his behaviorism in psychology, long after the collapse of that
research program, which began with Noam Chomsky’s famous critique of B.F. Skinner,5 and was brought
to a conclusion by the flourishing of the cognitive sciences that Fodor emphasized and to which he
contributed.
In short, naturalism is not committed to physicalism, to the view that only physical events and
properties are real. Naturalists take successful empirical sciences as a constraint on their ontology, and
we now know that unreduced psychological or mental facts are central to the scientific understanding of
understand it, that it rules out appeal to all evaluative or normative facts, which play no role in any
successful explanatory paradigms in any discipline.6 Anti-realism about morals in particular—there are
no attitude- or mind-independent facts about what is morally right and wrong—is central to naturalism:
psychological attitudes towards value (e.g., beliefs or affective responses) are often crucial to explaining
human behavior, but we do not need to posit the existence of any mind-independent (objective) facts
about moral values. This kind of anti-realism about morals is currently controversial among bourgeois
3
Burge, 2010, pp. 296-297.
4
Quine, Pursuit of Truth, 1990, pp. 20-21.
5
Chomsky, 1959.
6
See, e.g., Leiter, 2007; and Leiter, 2019, Chapters 1, 2 and 4.
their class and thus suffer from “group polarization” as the social psychologists call it,7 but it does have
the weight of intellectual history on its side: since Nietzsche, most of modernity has rejected both God
and an objectively true morality. The absence of objective facts about moral value is fatal to the views
of Dworkin and to the Catholic natural lawyers, among others, but I shall not dwell on that here. They
are not part of modernity, and it would surely be best if we could pass over them in silence.
In the preceding sense, legal realism is “realism” and “naturalism” about the social phenomenon
To start, realists about law acknowledge that in any functioning legal system, law operates
primarily outside the courts. This was a central contention of H.L.A. Hart’s jurisprudence: legally valid
norms guide how ordinary people buy homes, make wills, enter contracts, avoid taxes, and structure
many other aspects of their lives. Adjudication is a fringe phenomenon in a functioning legal system:
most individuals consult lawyers in order to accomplish certain goals, not to end up in court.
Jurisprudential theories—once again, Dworkin’s most infamously--that organize their claims about the
Yet law outside the courts appears in two guises: what the “law books” say, and what legal and
other actors actually do. “Law in the books” and “law in action” is how realists often mark the contrast,
and the difference is important: norms for behavior can be legally valid, as Hart showed, but ignored in
practice. The posted speed limits on the roads are the most familiar example in many jurisdictions: it is
clearly illegal to drive beyond a certain speed limit, and yet it is common for drivers to recognize that no
one will actually be sanctioned unless they greatly exceed that limit. In any legal system that has
7
See, e.g., Myers, 1975; Lord et al., 1979; Zuber et al., 1992; Sunstein, 2002.
8
Most self-identified realists, including the Americans and the Italians, focus primarily on adjudication, but
insofar as they do not generally equate what goes on in courts with a theory of the nature of law, they do not
make Dworkin’s mistake.
The gap is not just between enforcing the rule “in the books” and enforcing a different norm
(as in the speed-limit case), but also between how the rules “in action” are enforced against different
parties: here facts about economic class, political power, racial or ethnic identity, and other
demographic and social characteristics figure in how the same legally enforced rules play out (this is
perhaps most notorious in the arena of how police interact with citizens, but it extends well beyond that
arena). A realist theory must also capture this second kind of gap—call it realism about enforcement
practices--between the “law in the books” and the “law in action.” Realism about enforcement calls
attention to the way in which valid legal norms are and are not applied in real life; realism about
enforcement practices accepts that legally valid norms are applied in real life, but notes how that
When we do get to those matters that arise in the courts, legal realists emphasize the inevitable
indeterminacy of what we call “legal reasoning,” at least in some range of cases (what range of cases will
vary by jurisdiction, for reasons that will become apparent). Legal reasoning is supposed to be the
“method” by which courts arrive at a judgment based on the facts of the case and the relevant valid law.
In reality, in every known jurisdiction, “legal reasoning” may circumscribe the outcome a court can
legitimately reach, but it often affords the court latitude about the particular choice of outcome. More
precisely, the most plausible version of the indeterminacy thesis about law9 is that the class of legal
reasons—that is, the reasons that may properly justify a judicial decision—underdetermines the decision
a judge must reach; legal reasons limits the possible outcomes to the case, but the judge has available
equally legitimate legal arguments for more than one decision even within the circumscribed field of
possible decisions. The task of a realist theory of adjudication is both to explain why legal reasoning is
9
Leiter, 2007, pp. 9-12.
There are various possible grounds of legal indeterminacy: H.L.A. Hart emphasized the “open
texture” of natural languages,10 while the American and Italian Realists have emphasized the
interpretive latitude judges enjoy in how they construe statutory provisions and precedents.11 The idea
that judges have interpretive latitude is a claim about the legitimate interpretive moves a judge can
make when confronted with legal sources, whether legislative or constitutional or judicial. The notion
facts about legal actors: differing interpretations are “legitimate” insofar as they are accepted in fact by
other legal actors, especially other judges, as acceptable interpretations. This is often called a
contrast to the “philosophical” conception which asks whether the interpretations are really justified by
reference to some normative standard. That realists rely on a sociological conception of legitimacy
means, of course, that the extent of indeterminacy will vary depending on the facts about the attitudes
and practices of officials in different legal jurisdictions. This is as it should be: the scope of the
indeterminacy of legal reasoning will vary by jurisdiction, even if every jurisdiction exhibits
indeterminacy to some degree. That the conception is sociological also explains why, for example, the
American Realists can claim that indeterminacy is an issue primarily at the various stages of appellate
review: this is an empirical claim about the interpretive latitude officials have in those kinds of cases,
and is compatible, of course, with legal reasoning being determinate and judicial outcomes being
10
Hart, 2012, pp. 124-136.
11
See, e.g., Leiter, Naturalizing Jurisprudence, 2007, pp. 73-78; Guastini, 2011.
12
I am grateful to Leslie Green who has pressed me on this issue.
realist one.13 This is not true, to be sure, of all theories that have claimed to be “positivist” theories, but
it is true of the most important one, H.L.A. Hart’s, despite his confusions about the American and
Scandinavian Realists that I have written about previously14. But Hart is a realist insofar as he recognizes
that law operates mostly outside the courts; that inside the courts, some decisions are legally
indeterminate; that the nature of law is naturalistically explicable in terms of psycho-social facts about
human behaviors and attitudes, particularly those of officials; and that law is not necessarily a good
thing, that it has costs, and that it is always an open question whether law generates moral obligations
of compliance. Hart’s mistake regarding legal reaslim was in taking both the Americans and the
Scandinavians to be answering his questions, rather than their own. In both cases, he wrongly
understood them to be proffering an analysis of the concept of law, understood as that concept implicit
in ordinary language that captured features of law intelligible to an ordinary person familiar with a
modern municipal legal system. The American Realists had neither interest in, nor even an
understanding of, a project of conceptual analysis,15 and in fact presupposed in their arguments for the
indeterminacy of legal reasoning a positivist conception of legal validity.16 The Scandinavian Realist, Alf
Ross—the only one Hart really engaged with—was also quite clear that his project was not one of
ordinary-language conceptual analysis, but rather an effort to explain how central legal concepts like
“obligation,” “duty” and “right” could be located within a fairly austere naturalistic worldview;17 Ross
explicitly acknowledged that this analysis could not do justice to the concept of law deployed by an
13
See Leiter, 2020; and Leiter, 2007, pp. 59-80.
14
Leiter, 2007, 17-18.
15
One exception was Felix Cohen, nowhere cited by Hart.
16
Leiter, 2007, pp. 59-80.
17
Leiter, 2020.
obscured the essential connection between positivist and realist views about law.
The connection is particularly clear in the case of the realist indeterminacy thesis. Any thesis to
the effect that legal reasons fail to justify a unique decision in some range of cases presupposes that we
know the difference between “legal” and “non-legal” reasons, including “legal” and “non-legal” norms.
Positivists and anti-positivists will draw the line at different places, and how they draw the line bears on
the indeterminacy thesis. If a realist says the judge’s decision reflected his moral judgment about the
merits of the case, and if the moral considerations the judge relied on would, in fact, only justify one
decision (the one the judge reached), that only shows legal reasoning to be indeterminate if, in fact,
those moral considerations were not “part of the law” or “legally binding.” Hard positivism about law
and legal validity19 can easily explain this: the moral norms are not accepted as criteria of legal validity
from an “internal point of view”—that is, they are neither invoked as justifying a decision, nor are
deviations from them criticized by reference to those norms--and so are not part of the rule of
recognition.20 That positivism is necessary for the realist arguments for indeterminacy to work does not
show, of course, that positivism is correct. Positivism is vindicated, however, on naturalistic and
explanatory grounds, precisely the same considerations that commend realism: that is, a positivist
theory of law figures in the most explanatorily fruitful explanations of legal phenomena, such as judicial
decisions.21
I mentioned already that a realist theory of law, because it is also a naturalistic theory, eschews
reference to objective moral values. Here again Hart is a model realist about law: it is not simply that
the existence of law in some society is, on his view, a complicated empirical, not moral, fact (a psycho-
18
See, Holtermann, 2014, pp. 165–186.
19
By “hard positivism” I mean the view that the criteria of legal validity cannot include moral criteria.
20
Even versions of “soft” positivism are compatible with this conclusion, given that realists most often
point to non-legal norms influencing decision that are not norms judges do or would acknowledge as decisive.
21
See again Leiter, 2020; and also Leiter, 2009; and Leiter, 2007, 121-136.
of citizens to legally valid norms22), it is that he correctly glosses moral and normative concepts, like
“obligation,” entirely in behavioral terms, that is, what people are disposed to say and do, rather than in
terms of any cognitive (i.e., referential) content those terms might have. So, for example, Hart says
that, “Rules are conceived and spoken of as imposing obligations when the general demand for
conformity is insistent and the social pressure brought to bear upon those who deviate or threaten to
deviate is great….[T]he insistence on importance or seriousness of social pressure behind the rules is the
primary factor determining whether they are thought of as giving rise to obligations.”23 This is Hart’s
reasonable attempt at naturalizing normative talk in terms of things that do exist, namely, the
observable behavior (including verbal behavior) of people. Alf Ross pursued a related but different
strategy, namely, one of translation of normative talk into talk about predictions of behavior in order to
preserve the apparently cognitive content of legal claims. But both theorists share the same naturalistic
One must acknowledge that some later positivists in the Anglophone tradition have abandoned
the realism and naturalism of Hart’s approach; Joseph Raz is the most striking case. Raz is a moral realist
22
Hart, 2012, pp. 116-117.
23
Hart, 2012, pp. 86-87.
24
Of the many dubious claims in Scott Shapiro’s book Legality (2011), the most startling is related to the
issue noted in the text. Shapiro claims that Hart believes that “rules are nothing but social practices” (p. 95) but
objects that, “Social rules cannot be reduced to social practices because rules and practices belong to different
metaphysical categories. Rules are abstract objects….Practices, on the other hand, are concrete events. They take
place within the natural world and causally interact with other physical events” (p. 103). Shapiro deems this a
“category mistake” on Hart’s part, and uses that alleged mistake to motivate the baroque apparatus of his
alternative theory. John Gardner and Timothy Macklem (2011), in their devastating critique of the book
(https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/legality/), note one possible reply: Hart does not “identify the practice exactly with the
rule. He identifies the content of the practice, or part of it, with the content of the rule,” so no category mistake
there. But Kevin Toh has suggested to me what I think is a stronger response: Hart is only offering a reductive,
behavioral analysis of what it is to “accept a rule from an internal point of view”; the unit of analysis is “acceptance
of a rule” not “rule.” Indeed, the introduction of social rules in The Concept of Law begins with the question,
“What is the acceptance of a rule?” (Hart, 2012, p. 55), the answer being the behavior of those who accept the
rule, i.e, “criticism (including self-criticism), demands for conformity, and in acknowledgments that such criticism
and demands are justified, all of which find their characteristic expressions in the normative terminology of
‘ought’, ‘must’, and ‘should’, ‘right’ and ‘wrong’” (p. 57).
10
thinking this are obscure. Dogmatic confidence in the objectivity of value became a feature of Oxford
philosophy starting in the 1970s, finding its clearest theoretical articulation decades later in the work of
Derek Parfit, as well as other defenders of explicitly non-naturalist value realism or “realism about
reasons.”26 At the same time, Raz remains committed to the positivist thesis that there can be no
evaluative or content-based criteria of legal validity. Where Raz’s moral realism (in the metaphysical
sense) makes itself apparent is in his view that law necessarily claims authority, even if it ultimately lacks
On Raz’s view, law can only claim authority if it is possible to identify the content of a legal
directive without reference to the underlying (“dependent”) reasons for that directive. This is a
“prerequisite” for claiming authority because what distinguishes a (practical) authority in the first place
is that its directives preempt consideration of the underlying reasons (including, e.g., moral reasons) for
what we ought to do, and in so doing actually makes it more likely that we will do what we really ought
to do.27 For a realist, the problem with Raz’s argument is that it presupposes a highly moralized and
unrealistic conception of what it is for law to claim “authority.” Raz understands authority in terms of
what he calls “the Service Conception,” in which a claim to authority is a claim to provide a subject of
authority better “reasons” for acting in accordance with what Raz calls “right reason” than the subject
would arrive at without the intermediation of the authority.28 (We can gloss, for purposes here, “right
reason” as what one really ought to do.) This view obviously presupposes Raz’s moral realism (and
realism about reasons quite generally), one that is incredible from a legal realist, i.e., naturalist, point of
25
See, e.g., Raz, 2001.
26
Scanlon, 2014 is the strongest representative of the genre in my view; for doubts even about this
version, see Leiter, 2019, Chapter 4.
27
Raz offers this argument to show that no legal positivist can allow that there could be content-based
criteria of legal validity; I mostly agree with his conclusion, but not at all for Raz’s reasons. See again, Leiter, 2020.
28
See Raz, 1985.
11
help its subjects do what they really ought to do? Even a cursory glance at the history of the world
suggests this is implausible: of course law claims authority in the sense of claiming the right to tell those
subject to its jurisdiction what they must do, but the idea that this claim to authority is a claim to Raz’s
Service Conception looks like a moralizing illusion. Legal systems may often claim that they are
requiring people to do what is morally right, or God’s will, or in the public interest, or the will of the
Führer and so on, and thus claim authority to direct their subjects’ behavior, but they do not do so on
the basis that they are thereby performing a “service” for their subjects in helping them conform with
Raz, of course, explicitly repudiates Hart’s realist approach to jurisprudence. Against Hart’s
conceptual and normative argument” such that the account “does not necessarily conform to
everyone’s notion of authority in every detail. It does claim to be an explanatory account in singling out
important features of people’s conception of authority.”29 No theorist thinks their descriptive account
conforms “to everyone’s notion…in every detail,” so this is just a strawman. But where is the evidence
that Raz’s account even captures some “important features of people’s [which people?] conception of
authority”? There is none. Raz has simply smuggled in a moralized conception of authority30—as
providing a service for its subjects—without even the pretense that it satisfies even lax evidential
There are some important normative upshots of realism about law. First, given realism about
both enforcement and enforcement practices, it is never sufficient to evaluate a legal system to know
29
Raz, 1986, pp. 63 and 65.
30
Moralized in the sense that its main aim is to explain why deference to authority by rational subjects can
be justified.
12
must know how and against whom they are enforced. Valid legal norms that are just can turn out to be
unjust along either dimension; and unjust legal norms can turn out to be just along either dimension.
The positivist account of legal validity, which is the only serious account we have, leaves these
evaluative questions open (as it should, since it is only an account of validity), and no competing account
of legal validity settles them. Those that purport to do so—like Dworkin’s and those of some lesser anti-
Second, given realism about adjudication, we need to rethink the role of judges, especially
appellate judges, in a legal system. Since indeterminacy is an inescapable feature of a legal system,
judges must be appointed with that fact in mind. Judges are never merely appliers of the law, they
must always make new law, if only interstitially, although sometimes they do more than that.31 The
quality of their moral and political judgment thus matters as much as their distinctively legal
competence. The lie that judges are simply the instruments of the law-makers is an ideological illusion
that all legal realists oppose, as it deceives the public about the essential role of courts in a polity.
Political elites are rarely fooled on this core, of course, which is why they typically care a great deal
about the composition of the judiciary. Since, however, there is no known political or economic system
in which the preferences of elites are conducive to the well-being of the vast majority, legal realism here
has an important role to play in promoting public, and perhaps even democratic, accountability.
References
Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Co.
31
See, e.g., Leiter, 2015; Spanish translation as Leiter, 2016.
13
Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/legality/.
Guastini, R. (2011). Rule-Scepticism Restated. In L. Green & B. Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in the
Hart, H.L.A. (2012). The Concept of Law. 3rd Edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Holtermann, J. (2014). Naturalizing Alf Ross’s Legal Positivism: A Philosophical Reconstruction. Revus, 24,
165–186.
——— (2009). Explaining Theoretical Disagreement. University of Chicago Law Review, 76, 1215-1250.
——— (2012). In Praise of Realism (and Against Nonsense Jurisprudence). Georgetown Law Journal,
100, 865-893.
——— (2015). Constitutional Law, Moral Judgment, and the Supreme Court as Super-Legislature.
——— (2016). Derecho Constitucional, Juicio Moral y la Supreme Corte como Súper-Legislatura. In A.
Martínez Verástegui (ed.), La Constitución como objeto de interpretación (pp. 77-106). Ciudad de
——— (2019). Moral Psychology with Nietzsche. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
——— (2020). Legal Positivism as a Realist Theory of Law. In P. Mindus & T. Spaak (eds.), The
Lord, C. G., L. Ross, and M.R. Lepper. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The effects of
14
Raz, J. (1985). Authority, Law, and Morality. The Monist, 68(3), 295-324.
——— (2001). Notes on Value and Objectivity. In B. Leiter (ed.), Objectivity in Law and Morals
Scanlon, T.M. (2014). Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sunstein, C. (2002). The Law of Group Polarization. Journal of Political Philosophy, 10(2), 175-195.
Zuber, J., H. Crott, and J. Werner. (1992). Choice Shift and Group Polarization: An Analysis of the Status
of Arguments and Social Decision Schemes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62,
50-61.
15