SSRN Id3517589

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 15

WHAT IS A REALIST THEORY OF LAW?

Brian Leiter*
bleiter@uchicago.edu
January 10, 2020

This essay offers a programmatic statement for a realist theory of law. Although I have been

influenced by (and written about) the work of earlier American, Scandinavian, Italian and other legal

realists, this is not an essay about what others have thought. This is an essay about what I take realism

about law to mean and what its theoretical commitments are; I shall use other realists to sometimes

illustrate the distinctive positions of a realist theory of law, but will make clear where I depart from

them.

A realist theory of law involves both a “realist” and a “naturalistic” perspective on law. Let me

explain how I understand these perspectives.

“Realism” describes a theoretical outlook that is no longer fashionable in the universities, and

also one that has nothing to do with the metaphysical doctrine picked out by the same word. Realists in

the latter sense are concerned only about the mind-independent status of some class of entities (for

example, values). By contrast, “realism” in the sense at issue here takes no stand on metaphysical

questions, that is, the “scholastic” question, as Marx called it, about the “reality or non-reality of

thinking.”

Realism, in the sense at issue for jurisprudence, reflects a quite different intellectual tradition,

usually associated with Thucydides, Machiavelli, and Nietzsche, among others (see, e.g., Leiter 2012).

There are two key components of realism in this sense. First, realists aim to describe how things really

*
Karl N. Llewellyn Professor of Jurisprudence and Director of the Center for Law, Philosophy & Human
Values, University of Chicago. These thoughts crystallized in the course of a series of seminars on realist
jurisprudence I presented at the École des Haute Études en Sciences Sociales in Paris in June 2019. I am grateful to
Prof. Otto Pfersman for inviting me and for his contributions to the seminars, as well as those of the students. I
was also helped by discussion with students in my fall 2019 graduate seminar on current issues in general
jurisprudence at the University of Chicago. Finally, I am grateful to Joshua Fox, a PhD student at the University of
Chicago, for outstanding research assistance.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


are without romantic or moralizing illusions. We want to know what law and legal institutions are like in

reality, not what we might wish them to be. Realists also do not suppose that the way things are will

make “moral sense” or turn out to be morally defensible: it can (and often does) turn out that law and

its operations are morally objectionable or worse. Realists can be animated by normative hopes,

certainly, but they do not build them in to the account of their subject-matter (contrast, for example,

Ronald Dworkin’s jurisprudence which builds a moral obligation to obey the law into his account of the

nature of law). In the first instance, we need to understand what is really going on: for example, what

are people’s real motivations, what are they actually doing (independent of what they say they are

doing). Thucydides and Machiavelli are the lodestars of the realist tradition in political thought: do not

pay attention to the self-serving pontifications of the leaders of Greek or Italian city-states, they teach

us; understand that in reality they are all bent on power, glory and survival. Thucydides sets these facts

before the reader, and lets the reader draw the conclusion: unbridled lust for power and glory led to

the ruin of Athens. Machiavelli addresses himself to those who rule now, and tells them what they

must do to hold on to their power. Realists like Thucydides and Machiavelli tell us how politics really

works, in ancient Greece or Renaissance Italy; they withhold moral judgment even if, as with

Thucydides, there are morals to be drawn from the story told.

Because realism means understanding reality, realists are necessarily “naturalists” in the

following precise sense: in describing and explaining what is really going on they rely only on those

mechanisms and entities that are explanatorily fruitful in the successful empirical sciences (those

sciences being our only reliable guide to what is real). Naturalism is the second crucial commitment of

realist jurisprudence. Of the historical legal realists, the Scandinavians were most explicit about

commitment to naturalism, while the Italians and the Americans, in different ways, presuppose a

naturalistic worldview (even though the Americans were philosophically unsophisticated). Insofar as

only what is naturalistically explicable can be real, naturalism must be central to the realist worldview.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


It is important to understand what naturalism does and does not mean in this context. Quine,

the most important philosophical naturalist of the 20th-century, was, ironically, often a very bad Quinean

in many respects. The crucial commitment of naturalism, as even Quine professed, is a posteriori:

whatever works in the successful sciences is admissible into a naturalist ontology. Yet Quine remained

committed1 to two failed scientific research programs: physicalism (the idea that everything real must

be reducible to physics) and behaviorism in psychology. As another post-Quinean naturalist

philosopher, Jerry Fodor, pointed out in the 1970s,2 reduction to physics has not marked the last half-

century of scientific research; instead, there has been a proliferation of special sciences—biological and

cognitive sciences most notably—that proceed without even the pretense of being reducible to physics.

As another important post-Quinean philosopher, Tyler Burge, has observed:

Promoters of 'naturalizing' [i.e., physicalist reductionist] projects are often driven, I think, by

misconceptions of science. These misconceptions breed misconceptions of mind. The notion of

representation -- of reference or attribution that can be correct or incorrect and that helps type-

individuate kinds of psychological states -- is entrenched not only in common-sense explanation

but in scientific explanation in psychology. There is nothing unnatural or supernatural about such

explanation. Some of the relevant psychology is well-supported, mathematically rigorous, mature

science. There is no basis, even a prima facie one, to the worry that psychological notions are

invitations to mystery or miracle. Even if there were such basis, the role that these notions play in

powerful empirical science would undermine it. . . . I know of no good ground for thinking that. . .

[psychologists'] explanatory claims must be twisted into the mold of biological or information-

1
In one of his late works, Pursuit of Truth, Quine professed commitment to Davidsonian anomalous
monism, although for reasons that seem hard to square with his other commitments. See Quine, 1990, pp. 70-73.
2
Fodor, 1975, pp. 9-26.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


theoretic explanation, or any other explanation in the natural sciences, in order to be

explanatorily successful.3

For naturalists, explanatory and predictive fruitfulness is the mark of the real and the knowable, not

some a priori and empirically unmotivated assumption that everything must be reducible to physics.

Quine himself was “officially” a resolutely methodological naturalist in this sense—even allowing that

we would have to jettison “empiricism” (the view that all knowledge derives from sensory experience) if

telepathy turned out to work4--yet in practice he remained wedded to the failed science of the middle of

the last century. That also explains his behaviorism in psychology, long after the collapse of that

research program, which began with Noam Chomsky’s famous critique of B.F. Skinner,5 and was brought

to a conclusion by the flourishing of the cognitive sciences that Fodor emphasized and to which he

contributed.

In short, naturalism is not committed to physicalism, to the view that only physical events and

properties are real. Naturalists take successful empirical sciences as a constraint on their ontology, and

we now know that unreduced psychological or mental facts are central to the scientific understanding of

human phenomena, contra behaviorism. But it is an equally important upshot of naturalism, as I

understand it, that it rules out appeal to all evaluative or normative facts, which play no role in any

successful explanatory paradigms in any discipline.6 Anti-realism about morals in particular—there are

no attitude- or mind-independent facts about what is morally right and wrong—is central to naturalism:

psychological attitudes towards value (e.g., beliefs or affective responses) are often crucial to explaining

human behavior, but we do not need to posit the existence of any mind-independent (objective) facts

about moral values. This kind of anti-realism about morals is currently controversial among bourgeois

3
Burge, 2010, pp. 296-297.
4
Quine, Pursuit of Truth, 1990, pp. 20-21.
5
Chomsky, 1959.
6
See, e.g., Leiter, 2007; and Leiter, 2019, Chapters 1, 2 and 4.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


philosophers in Anglophone universities, who spend too much time talking to moralizing members of

their class and thus suffer from “group polarization” as the social psychologists call it,7 but it does have

the weight of intellectual history on its side: since Nietzsche, most of modernity has rejected both God

and an objectively true morality. The absence of objective facts about moral value is fatal to the views

of Dworkin and to the Catholic natural lawyers, among others, but I shall not dwell on that here. They

are not part of modernity, and it would surely be best if we could pass over them in silence.

In the preceding sense, legal realism is “realism” and “naturalism” about the social phenomenon

known as “law.” What do legal realists, so understood, reveal to us about law?

To start, realists about law acknowledge that in any functioning legal system, law operates

primarily outside the courts. This was a central contention of H.L.A. Hart’s jurisprudence: legally valid

norms guide how ordinary people buy homes, make wills, enter contracts, avoid taxes, and structure

many other aspects of their lives. Adjudication is a fringe phenomenon in a functioning legal system:

most individuals consult lawyers in order to accomplish certain goals, not to end up in court.

Jurisprudential theories—once again, Dworkin’s most infamously--that organize their claims about the

nature of law around what goes on in court are deeply unrealistic.8

Yet law outside the courts appears in two guises: what the “law books” say, and what legal and

other actors actually do. “Law in the books” and “law in action” is how realists often mark the contrast,

and the difference is important: norms for behavior can be legally valid, as Hart showed, but ignored in

practice. The posted speed limits on the roads are the most familiar example in many jurisdictions: it is

clearly illegal to drive beyond a certain speed limit, and yet it is common for drivers to recognize that no

one will actually be sanctioned unless they greatly exceed that limit. In any legal system that has

7
See, e.g., Myers, 1975; Lord et al., 1979; Zuber et al., 1992; Sunstein, 2002.
8
Most self-identified realists, including the Americans and the Italians, focus primarily on adjudication, but
insofar as they do not generally equate what goes on in courts with a theory of the nature of law, they do not
make Dworkin’s mistake.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


actually existed, there is always a gap between the legally valid rules and the rules that are actually

enforced: call this realism about enforcement.

The gap is not just between enforcing the rule “in the books” and enforcing a different norm

(as in the speed-limit case), but also between how the rules “in action” are enforced against different

parties: here facts about economic class, political power, racial or ethnic identity, and other

demographic and social characteristics figure in how the same legally enforced rules play out (this is

perhaps most notorious in the arena of how police interact with citizens, but it extends well beyond that

arena). A realist theory must also capture this second kind of gap—call it realism about enforcement

practices--between the “law in the books” and the “law in action.” Realism about enforcement calls

attention to the way in which valid legal norms are and are not applied in real life; realism about

enforcement practices accepts that legally valid norms are applied in real life, but notes how that

application really works.

When we do get to those matters that arise in the courts, legal realists emphasize the inevitable

indeterminacy of what we call “legal reasoning,” at least in some range of cases (what range of cases will

vary by jurisdiction, for reasons that will become apparent). Legal reasoning is supposed to be the

“method” by which courts arrive at a judgment based on the facts of the case and the relevant valid law.

In reality, in every known jurisdiction, “legal reasoning” may circumscribe the outcome a court can

legitimately reach, but it often affords the court latitude about the particular choice of outcome. More

precisely, the most plausible version of the indeterminacy thesis about law9 is that the class of legal

reasons—that is, the reasons that may properly justify a judicial decision—underdetermines the decision

a judge must reach; legal reasons limits the possible outcomes to the case, but the judge has available

equally legitimate legal arguments for more than one decision even within the circumscribed field of

possible decisions. The task of a realist theory of adjudication is both to explain why legal reasoning is

9
Leiter, 2007, pp. 9-12.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


indeterminate and identify what influences judges to choose the particular decision they do, within the

realm of those that are legally available.

There are various possible grounds of legal indeterminacy: H.L.A. Hart emphasized the “open

texture” of natural languages,10 while the American and Italian Realists have emphasized the

interpretive latitude judges enjoy in how they construe statutory provisions and precedents.11 The idea

that judges have interpretive latitude is a claim about the legitimate interpretive moves a judge can

make when confronted with legal sources, whether legislative or constitutional or judicial. The notion

of “legitimacy” at issue here is a thoroughly naturalized one, to be understood in terms of psycho-social

facts about legal actors: differing interpretations are “legitimate” insofar as they are accepted in fact by

other legal actors, especially other judges, as acceptable interpretations. This is often called a

“sociological” conception of legitimacy—social acceptance by others is the mark of “legitimacy”--in

contrast to the “philosophical” conception which asks whether the interpretations are really justified by

reference to some normative standard. That realists rely on a sociological conception of legitimacy

means, of course, that the extent of indeterminacy will vary depending on the facts about the attitudes

and practices of officials in different legal jurisdictions. This is as it should be: the scope of the

indeterminacy of legal reasoning will vary by jurisdiction, even if every jurisdiction exhibits

indeterminacy to some degree. That the conception is sociological also explains why, for example, the

American Realists can claim that indeterminacy is an issue primarily at the various stages of appellate

review: this is an empirical claim about the interpretive latitude officials have in those kinds of cases,

and is compatible, of course, with legal reasoning being determinate and judicial outcomes being

predictable elsewhere in the legal system.12

10
Hart, 2012, pp. 124-136.
11
See, e.g., Leiter, Naturalizing Jurisprudence, 2007, pp. 73-78; Guastini, 2011.
12
I am grateful to Leslie Green who has pressed me on this issue.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


A realist theory of law is necessarily a positivist theory, and a positivist theory is necessarily a

realist one.13 This is not true, to be sure, of all theories that have claimed to be “positivist” theories, but

it is true of the most important one, H.L.A. Hart’s, despite his confusions about the American and

Scandinavian Realists that I have written about previously14. But Hart is a realist insofar as he recognizes

that law operates mostly outside the courts; that inside the courts, some decisions are legally

indeterminate; that the nature of law is naturalistically explicable in terms of psycho-social facts about

human behaviors and attitudes, particularly those of officials; and that law is not necessarily a good

thing, that it has costs, and that it is always an open question whether law generates moral obligations

of compliance. Hart’s mistake regarding legal reaslim was in taking both the Americans and the

Scandinavians to be answering his questions, rather than their own. In both cases, he wrongly

understood them to be proffering an analysis of the concept of law, understood as that concept implicit

in ordinary language that captured features of law intelligible to an ordinary person familiar with a

modern municipal legal system. The American Realists had neither interest in, nor even an

understanding of, a project of conceptual analysis,15 and in fact presupposed in their arguments for the

indeterminacy of legal reasoning a positivist conception of legal validity.16 The Scandinavian Realist, Alf

Ross—the only one Hart really engaged with—was also quite clear that his project was not one of

ordinary-language conceptual analysis, but rather an effort to explain how central legal concepts like

“obligation,” “duty” and “right” could be located within a fairly austere naturalistic worldview;17 Ross

explicitly acknowledged that this analysis could not do justice to the concept of law deployed by an

13
See Leiter, 2020; and Leiter, 2007, pp. 59-80.
14
Leiter, 2007, 17-18.
15
One exception was Felix Cohen, nowhere cited by Hart.
16
Leiter, 2007, pp. 59-80.
17
Leiter, 2020.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


insider to the legal system.18 Hart’s misguided, albeit influential, dispute with legal realism has

obscured the essential connection between positivist and realist views about law.

The connection is particularly clear in the case of the realist indeterminacy thesis. Any thesis to

the effect that legal reasons fail to justify a unique decision in some range of cases presupposes that we

know the difference between “legal” and “non-legal” reasons, including “legal” and “non-legal” norms.

Positivists and anti-positivists will draw the line at different places, and how they draw the line bears on

the indeterminacy thesis. If a realist says the judge’s decision reflected his moral judgment about the

merits of the case, and if the moral considerations the judge relied on would, in fact, only justify one

decision (the one the judge reached), that only shows legal reasoning to be indeterminate if, in fact,

those moral considerations were not “part of the law” or “legally binding.” Hard positivism about law

and legal validity19 can easily explain this: the moral norms are not accepted as criteria of legal validity

from an “internal point of view”—that is, they are neither invoked as justifying a decision, nor are

deviations from them criticized by reference to those norms--and so are not part of the rule of

recognition.20 That positivism is necessary for the realist arguments for indeterminacy to work does not

show, of course, that positivism is correct. Positivism is vindicated, however, on naturalistic and

explanatory grounds, precisely the same considerations that commend realism: that is, a positivist

theory of law figures in the most explanatorily fruitful explanations of legal phenomena, such as judicial

decisions.21

I mentioned already that a realist theory of law, because it is also a naturalistic theory, eschews

reference to objective moral values. Here again Hart is a model realist about law: it is not simply that

the existence of law in some society is, on his view, a complicated empirical, not moral, fact (a psycho-

18
See, Holtermann, 2014, pp. 165–186.
19
By “hard positivism” I mean the view that the criteria of legal validity cannot include moral criteria.
20
Even versions of “soft” positivism are compatible with this conclusion, given that realists most often
point to non-legal norms influencing decision that are not norms judges do or would acknowledge as decisive.
21
See again Leiter, 2020; and also Leiter, 2009; and Leiter, 2007, 121-136.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


social fact about the practices of officials in deciding questions of legal validity, and about the obedience

of citizens to legally valid norms22), it is that he correctly glosses moral and normative concepts, like

“obligation,” entirely in behavioral terms, that is, what people are disposed to say and do, rather than in

terms of any cognitive (i.e., referential) content those terms might have. So, for example, Hart says

that, “Rules are conceived and spoken of as imposing obligations when the general demand for

conformity is insistent and the social pressure brought to bear upon those who deviate or threaten to

deviate is great….[T]he insistence on importance or seriousness of social pressure behind the rules is the

primary factor determining whether they are thought of as giving rise to obligations.”23 This is Hart’s

reasonable attempt at naturalizing normative talk in terms of things that do exist, namely, the

observable behavior (including verbal behavior) of people. Alf Ross pursued a related but different

strategy, namely, one of translation of normative talk into talk about predictions of behavior in order to

preserve the apparently cognitive content of legal claims. But both theorists share the same naturalistic

impulse: to purge their theory of law of reference to normative facts.24

One must acknowledge that some later positivists in the Anglophone tradition have abandoned

the realism and naturalism of Hart’s approach; Joseph Raz is the most striking case. Raz is a moral realist

22
Hart, 2012, pp. 116-117.
23
Hart, 2012, pp. 86-87.
24
Of the many dubious claims in Scott Shapiro’s book Legality (2011), the most startling is related to the
issue noted in the text. Shapiro claims that Hart believes that “rules are nothing but social practices” (p. 95) but
objects that, “Social rules cannot be reduced to social practices because rules and practices belong to different
metaphysical categories. Rules are abstract objects….Practices, on the other hand, are concrete events. They take
place within the natural world and causally interact with other physical events” (p. 103). Shapiro deems this a
“category mistake” on Hart’s part, and uses that alleged mistake to motivate the baroque apparatus of his
alternative theory. John Gardner and Timothy Macklem (2011), in their devastating critique of the book
(https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/legality/), note one possible reply: Hart does not “identify the practice exactly with the
rule. He identifies the content of the practice, or part of it, with the content of the rule,” so no category mistake
there. But Kevin Toh has suggested to me what I think is a stronger response: Hart is only offering a reductive,
behavioral analysis of what it is to “accept a rule from an internal point of view”; the unit of analysis is “acceptance
of a rule” not “rule.” Indeed, the introduction of social rules in The Concept of Law begins with the question,
“What is the acceptance of a rule?” (Hart, 2012, p. 55), the answer being the behavior of those who accept the
rule, i.e, “criticism (including self-criticism), demands for conformity, and in acknowledgments that such criticism
and demands are justified, all of which find their characteristic expressions in the normative terminology of
‘ought’, ‘must’, and ‘should’, ‘right’ and ‘wrong’” (p. 57).

10

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


in the metaphysical sense: he takes there to be objective moral values,25 although his reasons for

thinking this are obscure. Dogmatic confidence in the objectivity of value became a feature of Oxford

philosophy starting in the 1970s, finding its clearest theoretical articulation decades later in the work of

Derek Parfit, as well as other defenders of explicitly non-naturalist value realism or “realism about

reasons.”26 At the same time, Raz remains committed to the positivist thesis that there can be no

evaluative or content-based criteria of legal validity. Where Raz’s moral realism (in the metaphysical

sense) makes itself apparent is in his view that law necessarily claims authority, even if it ultimately lacks

a justification for that claim.

On Raz’s view, law can only claim authority if it is possible to identify the content of a legal

directive without reference to the underlying (“dependent”) reasons for that directive. This is a

“prerequisite” for claiming authority because what distinguishes a (practical) authority in the first place

is that its directives preempt consideration of the underlying reasons (including, e.g., moral reasons) for

what we ought to do, and in so doing actually makes it more likely that we will do what we really ought

to do.27 For a realist, the problem with Raz’s argument is that it presupposes a highly moralized and

unrealistic conception of what it is for law to claim “authority.” Raz understands authority in terms of

what he calls “the Service Conception,” in which a claim to authority is a claim to provide a subject of

authority better “reasons” for acting in accordance with what Raz calls “right reason” than the subject

would arrive at without the intermediation of the authority.28 (We can gloss, for purposes here, “right

reason” as what one really ought to do.) This view obviously presupposes Raz’s moral realism (and

realism about reasons quite generally), one that is incredible from a legal realist, i.e., naturalist, point of

25
See, e.g., Raz, 2001.
26
Scanlon, 2014 is the strongest representative of the genre in my view; for doubts even about this
version, see Leiter, 2019, Chapter 4.
27
Raz offers this argument to show that no legal positivist can allow that there could be content-based
criteria of legal validity; I mostly agree with his conclusion, but not at all for Raz’s reasons. See again, Leiter, 2020.
28
See Raz, 1985.

11

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


view. A legal realist can also rightly wonder: why think that when law claims authority it is claiming to

help its subjects do what they really ought to do? Even a cursory glance at the history of the world

suggests this is implausible: of course law claims authority in the sense of claiming the right to tell those

subject to its jurisdiction what they must do, but the idea that this claim to authority is a claim to Raz’s

Service Conception looks like a moralizing illusion. Legal systems may often claim that they are

requiring people to do what is morally right, or God’s will, or in the public interest, or the will of the

Führer and so on, and thus claim authority to direct their subjects’ behavior, but they do not do so on

the basis that they are thereby performing a “service” for their subjects in helping them conform with

the demands of “right reason.”

Raz, of course, explicitly repudiates Hart’s realist approach to jurisprudence. Against Hart’s

realist aim of a “descriptive jurisprudence,” Raz asserts “there is an interdependence between

conceptual and normative argument” such that the account “does not necessarily conform to

everyone’s notion of authority in every detail. It does claim to be an explanatory account in singling out

important features of people’s conception of authority.”29 No theorist thinks their descriptive account

conforms “to everyone’s notion…in every detail,” so this is just a strawman. But where is the evidence

that Raz’s account even captures some “important features of people’s [which people?] conception of

authority”? There is none. Raz has simply smuggled in a moralized conception of authority30—as

providing a service for its subjects—without even the pretense that it satisfies even lax evidential

demands of a “descriptive sociology” as Hart, the realist, proposed.

There are some important normative upshots of realism about law. First, given realism about

both enforcement and enforcement practices, it is never sufficient to evaluate a legal system to know

29
Raz, 1986, pp. 63 and 65.
30
Moralized in the sense that its main aim is to explain why deference to authority by rational subjects can
be justified.

12

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


what the valid legal norms are; one must know both which valid norms are actually enforced and one

must know how and against whom they are enforced. Valid legal norms that are just can turn out to be

unjust along either dimension; and unjust legal norms can turn out to be just along either dimension.

The positivist account of legal validity, which is the only serious account we have, leaves these

evaluative questions open (as it should, since it is only an account of validity), and no competing account

of legal validity settles them. Those that purport to do so—like Dworkin’s and those of some lesser anti-

positivists—serve only as ideological obfuscations.

Second, given realism about adjudication, we need to rethink the role of judges, especially

appellate judges, in a legal system. Since indeterminacy is an inescapable feature of a legal system,

judges must be appointed with that fact in mind. Judges are never merely appliers of the law, they

must always make new law, if only interstitially, although sometimes they do more than that.31 The

quality of their moral and political judgment thus matters as much as their distinctively legal

competence. The lie that judges are simply the instruments of the law-makers is an ideological illusion

that all legal realists oppose, as it deceives the public about the essential role of courts in a polity.

Political elites are rarely fooled on this core, of course, which is why they typically care a great deal

about the composition of the judiciary. Since, however, there is no known political or economic system

in which the preferences of elites are conducive to the well-being of the vast majority, legal realism here

has an important role to play in promoting public, and perhaps even democratic, accountability.

References

Burge, T. (2010). Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chomsky, N. (1959). Review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior. Language, 35, 26–58.

Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Co.

31
See, e.g., Leiter, 2015; Spanish translation as Leiter, 2016.

13

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


Gardner, J. and T. Macklem. (2011). Review of Legality by Scott Shapiro. Notre Dame Philosophical

Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/legality/.

Guastini, R. (2011). Rule-Scepticism Restated. In L. Green & B. Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in the

Philosophy of Law, Vol. 1, (pp. 138-161). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hart, H.L.A. (2012). The Concept of Law. 3rd Edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Holtermann, J. (2014). Naturalizing Alf Ross’s Legal Positivism: A Philosophical Reconstruction. Revus, 24,

165–186.

Leiter, B. (2007). Naturalizing Jurisprudence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

——— (2009). Explaining Theoretical Disagreement. University of Chicago Law Review, 76, 1215-1250.

——— (2012). In Praise of Realism (and Against Nonsense Jurisprudence). Georgetown Law Journal,

100, 865-893.

——— (2015). Constitutional Law, Moral Judgment, and the Supreme Court as Super-Legislature.

Hastings Law Journal, 66, 1601-1616.

——— (2016). Derecho Constitucional, Juicio Moral y la Supreme Corte como Súper-Legislatura. In A.

Martínez Verástegui (ed.), La Constitución como objeto de interpretación (pp. 77-106). Ciudad de

México: Supreme Corte de Justicia de la Nación.

——— (2019). Moral Psychology with Nietzsche. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

——— (2020). Legal Positivism as a Realist Theory of Law. In P. Mindus & T. Spaak (eds.), The

Cambridge Companion to Legal Positvism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lord, C. G., L. Ross, and M.R. Lepper. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The effects of

prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. Journal of Personality and Social

Psychology, 37(11), 2098–2109.

Myers, D. (1975). Discussion-Induced Attitude Polarization. Human Relations, 28(8), 699-715.

14

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589


Quine, W.V.O. (1990). Pursuit of Truth. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.

Raz, J. (1985). Authority, Law, and Morality. The Monist, 68(3), 295-324.

——— (1986). The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

——— (2001). Notes on Value and Objectivity. In B. Leiter (ed.), Objectivity in Law and Morals

(pp. 194-233). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Scanlon, T.M. (2014). Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Shapiro, S. (2011). Legality. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.

Sunstein, C. (2002). The Law of Group Polarization. Journal of Political Philosophy, 10(2), 175-195.

Zuber, J., H. Crott, and J. Werner. (1992). Choice Shift and Group Polarization: An Analysis of the Status

of Arguments and Social Decision Schemes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62,

50-61.

15

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3517589

You might also like