Brown Richerson 2014 For PURE

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 40

Applying evolutionary theory to human behaviour: past differences and current debates

Gillian R. Brown1 and Peter J. Richerson2

1
School of Psychology and Neuroscience, University of St Andrews, U.K.

2
Department of Environmental Science and Policy, University of California, Davis, U.S.A.

Citation:

Brown, G. R. and Richerson, P. 2014. Applying evolutionary theory to human behaviour: past

differences and current debates. Journal of Bioeconomics 16: 105-128.

Corresponding author:

Dr Gillian Brown,

School of Psychology & Neuroscience,

University of St Andrews,

South Street,

St Andrews, KY16 9JP, U.K.

grb4@st-andrews.ac.uk

1
Abstract

The aim of this paper is to provide non-specialist readers with an introduction to some current

controversies surrounding the application of evolutionary theory to human behaviour at the

intersection of biology, psychology and anthropology. We review the three major contemporary

sub-fields; namely Human Behavioural Ecology, Evolutionary Psychology and Cultural

Evolution, and we compare their views on maladaptive behaviour, the proximal mechanisms of

cultural transmission, and the relationship between human cognition and culture. For example,

we show that the sub-fields vary in the amount of maladaptive behaviour that is predicted to

occur in modern environments; Human Behavioural Ecologists start with the expectation that

behaviour will be optimal, while Evolutionary Psychologists emphasize cases of ‘mis-match’

between modern environments and domain-specific, evolved psychological mechanisms.

Cultural Evolutionists argue that social learning processes are effective at providing solutions to

novel problems and describe how relatively weak, general-purpose learning mechanisms,

alongside accurate cultural transmission, can lead to the cumulative evolution of adaptive

cultural complexity but also sometimes to maladaptative behaviour. We then describe how the

sub-fields view cooperative behaviour between non-kin, as an example of where the differences

between the sub-fields are relevant to the economics community, and we discuss the hypothesis

that a history of inter-group competition can explain the evolution of non-kin cooperation. We

conclude that a complete understanding of human behaviour requires insights from all three

fields and that many scholars no longer view them as distinct.

Keywords: human behavioural ecology, evolutionary psychology, cooperation, gene-culture co-

evolution, cultural group selection

2
1 Applying evolutionary theory to human behaviour

The application of evolutionary theory to the study of human behaviour has a long and

contentious history (Boakes 1984; Laland and Brown 2011). Over this history, the fields of

economics and the biological sciences have drawn inspiration from each other, but the social and

biological sciences have also been in apparent conflict (Hodgson and Knudsen 2008; Witt 1999).

In order for communication between different academic fields to be successful, individual

researchers need to meet the challenge of incorporating the most recent advances from multiple

disciplines. This challenge is certainly not straightforward, but is aided by inter-disciplinary

journals, such as the Journal of Bioeconomics. The aim of this paper is to contribute to this inter-

disciplinary discussion by presenting a brief summary of some of the current debates at the

interface of biology, anthropology, and psychology, thereby provide readers with information

about the issues that are being discussed at this relevant junction.

Our approach is, in itself, somewhat controversial: we present a number of sub-fields

within the evolutionary human behavioural sciences (namely Human Behavioural Ecology,

Evolutionary Psychology and Cultural Evolution) and draw distinctions between some of the

underlying assumptions of the research conducted under each of these headings. Other

researchers have argued instead that the sub-fields are highly complementary and exhibit a large

degree of overlap (Alcock 2001). We agree with this latter statement to some extent, and we

have previously discussed the fact that some research topics have been successfully viewed from

multiple perspectives (Brown et al. 2011; Laland and Brown 2011). In addition, we acknowledge

that several researchers have successfully combined more than one of the approaches within their

own research and have bridged between the sub-fields (e.g., Kaplan and Gangestad 2005).

However, we also believe that the distinctions between the sub-fields are real; for example, the

sub-fields differ significantly in methodology, views on which evolutionary processes are

relevant, and consequently on the most likely explanations for important aspects of human

3
behaviour. Evolutionary epistemologists, like Donald Campbell, have argued that science

progresses by scientists considering the adequacy of different proposals against the best evidence

we can bring to bear on the subject (Heyes and Hull 2001). If so, science will progress best when

whatever differences exist are clearly delineated. Hence, in this paper we take for granted the

many agreements between the three areas and focus on the differences. Indeed, many current

practitioners, particularly younger scientists, do not conceive of themselves as members of

separate fields and view the issues that once divided them on their way to solution.

We first provide a brief introduction to human sociobiology, as exemplified by Wilson’s

(1975) book, Sociobiology: the New Synthesis, given that many of the current debates within the

field stem from discussions that surrounded the conception of this field. The next sections then

provide short summaries of the three main sub-fields that characterise current research – Human

Behavioural Ecology, Evolutionary Psychology and Cultural Evolution (for a more detailed

discussion, see Laland and Brown 2011). The following section then examines some of the key

debates between the sub-fields, including questions of whether human beings exhibit

maladaptive behaviour in modern environments, and what the relationships are between human

cognition and our evolving culture, focusing particularly on the debates between Evolutionary

Psychology and Cultural Evolution. As an example of where the differences between the sub-

fields are relevant to the economics community, we discuss alternative perspectives on

cooperative behaviour between non-kin. We conclude that the disagreements between the sub-

fields are indeed over substantive scientific issues that need to be settled by future research.

2 Human sociobiology

In 1975, Edward O. Wilson, a Harvard professor of entomology, published Sociobiology: the

New Synthesis, in which he promoted recent advances that were being made within the field of

4
evolutionary biology. Naïve group-selectionist views were being rapidly overtaken by the

‘gene’s-eye’ perspective, as exemplified by the work of William Hamilton, Robert Trivers and

George Williams. This new perspective was revolutionising the application of evolutionary

theory to non-human animals, and the ground-breaking research of Hamilton, Trivers and others

has been hugely influential in the field of animal behaviour to this day (e.g., Danchin et al.

2008). More controversially, Wilson (1975; 1978) applied these theoretical advances to human

behaviour (Human Sociobiology), providing evolutionary explanations for topics such as

aggression, religion and homosexuality. Despite gaining many followers, Wilson’s comments on

human behaviour resulted in hostile attacks from some critics (e.g., Allen et al. 1975; Rose et al.

1984), including accusations of genetic determinism, storytelling and ignoring the influence of

culture on human behaviour. Partly as a result of this hostility, many researchers who were

applying evolutionary principals to the study of human behaviour mostly sought to distance

themselves from Wilson’s sociobiology during the 1970s and 1980s, and the term ‘Human

Sociobiology’ has generally fallen out of favour. However, other researchers, such as Sarah

Hrdy, have been keen to highlight that sociobiological theory contributed a considerable amount

to our understanding of animal behaviour and provided fertile ground for more recent

applications of evolutionary theory to human behavior (Segerstråle 2000). In addition, Wilson

embraced the emerging field of cultural evolution (Lumsden and Wilson 1981), and Wilson has

continued to call for greater integration between the biological and social sciences (e.g., Wilson

1998).

3 Human Behavioural Ecology

During the 1970s, anthropologists had already begun to apply contemporary concepts from

evolutionary biology, such as optimality modelling and evolutionary game theory, to

5
observational data gathered from a diverse range of human populations (Chagnon and Irons

1979). One of the key concepts within this sub-field, now referred to as Human Behavioural

Ecology, is the idea that human behaviour is extremely flexible, and adaptive behaviour can be

produced in response to a broad range of environmental variables (Borgerhoff-Mulder and

Schacht 2012). Typically, Human Behavioural Ecologists appeal to the ‘phenotypic gambit’

(Grafen 1984), which allows researchers to test the prediction that behavior is fitness-optimizing

in the particular environment under study without recourse to understanding the mechanisms

involved. Such mechanisms could include a combination of genetic adaptation, physiological

plasticity or culturally transmitted information. These researchers thus do not generally concern

themselves with the mechanistic processes that are the central focus of the other major sub-

fields. Early proponents of Human Behavioural Ecology, such as Richard Alexander, Napoleon

Chagnon and William Irons, attempted to explain human behaviour based on the assumption that

individuals behave in a manner that maximises their reproductive success, with particular

emphasis on foraging and reproductive behaviour. A strength of this approach is that it typically

tries to explain concrete human behavior in real-world environments. Most Human Behavioural

Ecology research has focused on non-Westernised societies with small-scale subsistence patterns

and a relative absence of modern contraceptive technology (Borgerhoff Mulder and Schacht

2012). However, other researchers have pointed out that there are good evolutionary reasons to

expect that Human Behavioural Ecology approaches can be effective when applied to data from

Westernised societies (Laland and Brown 2006), and the field of Human Behavioural Ecology

has broadened since its inception to incorporate research on a wider range of populations and

research topics (Nettle et al. 2013; Brown 2013), including consideration of the processes of

cultural evolution (Borgerhoff Mulder and Schacht 2012).

4 Evolutionary Psychology

6
The term ‘evolutionary psychology’ has a long history, including appearing in William James’

(1890, p. 146) Principles of Psychology, and could be used to refer to any evolutionary

perspective on the human mind. Given the remarkable size of the human brain and its unique

products like language and cumulative culture, every student of human evolution is an

evolutionary psychologist. However, the term Evolutionary Psychology is now commonly used

to describe a highly influential school of the human evolutionary sciences that was founded by

Donald Symons, Leda Cosmides and John Tooby (e.g., Symons 1989; Tooby and DeVore 1987;

Cosmides and Tooby 1987; Tooby and Cosmides 1992). Since the 1980s, Cosmides, Tooby,

David Buss and Steven Pinker, in particular, have promoted the idea that the human brain

consists of specialised psychological mechanisms that have evolved in response to recurrent

selection pressures acting on our human ancestors. Evolutionary Psychologists argue that the

most important stage of history for understanding the evolution of the human mind is the

Pleistocene epoch when our ancestors were living as hunter-gatherers on the African savannah

(Cosmides and Tooby 1987). Evolutionary Psychologists aim to describe the evolved

psychological mechanisms that underlie human cognition, with an emphasis on domain-specific

information processing devices that provide human beings with a universal toolkit of mental

adaptations. These researchers argue that selection will have favoured psychological mechanisms

that are suited to efficiently solving problems within specific domains, and this perspective has

been applied to a broad range of topics, including mate choice, aggression, social exchange and

morality (Buss 2005). While critics argue that Evolutionary Psychology will benefit from

incorporating advances from adjacent research fields (Bolhuis et al. 2011), Evolutionary

Psychology is perhaps the most impactful of the contemporary approaches, in terms of numbers

of practitioners and wider dissemination. For example, Steven Pinker’s (1994) book The

Language Instinct is one of the most highly cited books in the entire field.

7
5 Cultural Evolution

The idea that Darwin’s theory of natural selection can be applied to entities other than genes was

endorsed by Darwin (1871) himself, when he applied the idea of natural selection to language

evolution and proposed an important role for traditions in human evolution. The gene itself was

not part of Darwin’s pre-Mendelian vocabulary, of course. The idea of universal Darwinism has

since spread to many scientific disciplines (Plotkin 1994). Researchers within the field of

Cultural Evolution have applied evolutionary theory to human cultural traits and have shown

how mathematical models can be used to understand how the frequencies or distributions of

different cultural variants change over time (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman 1981; Boyd and

Richerson 1985). More broadly, the field of gene-culture co-evolution investigates how genes

and culture co-evolve (Laland et al. 2010; Richerson and Boyd 2010a). Culture is pragmatically

defined as ‘information capable of affecting individuals’ behaviour that they acquire from

members of their species through teaching, imitation, and other forms of social transmission’

(Richerson and Boyd 2005). Numerous factors can influence the process of information

transmission, such as biases in how individuals learn, biases in which model is chosen, and

preferences for learning or remembering some cultural variants over others (Richerson and Boyd

2005). Cultural Evolutionists thus assume that rather domain-general psychological mechanisms

can bias the acquisition of particular behaviour patterns (Sterelny 2012); for example, ‘copy the

majority’ (or plurality) is a learning rule that can potentially be applied across numerous cultural

domains. These relatively domain-general forces are generally weak at the individual level,

agreeing with Tooby and Cosmides (1992) in this regard, but they can act as very powerful

evolutionary forces when acting on populations over the evolutionary time scale to cumulatively

“design” complex technologies and social institutions that are far beyond the capabilities of any

one innovator (Boyd et al. 2011a). While the field of Cultural Evolution could once be criticised

for failing to stimulate new empirical research, a sustained and rapidly expanding empirical

8
program began in the late 1990s (e.g., McElreath et al. 2005; Mesoudi and O’Brien 2008;

Henrich and Broesch 2011; Morgan et al. 2012), including large cross-cultural collaborative

projects (e.g. Henrich et. al. 2005, 2010; Henrich and McElreath 2002).

6 Some current debates between the sub-fields

Having given a brief overview of the main sub-fields within the human evolutionary behavioural

sciences, we now highlight some potential points of contention where, in our opinion, the sub-

fields exhibit either quantitative or qualitative differences in their underlying assumptions about

human behaviour (for more extensive discussions, see Brown et al. 2011; Laland and Brown

2011; Boyd et al. 2011a).

6.1 Do human beings exhibit maladaptive behaviour in modern environments?

While all three sub-fields agree that the evolutionary mechanisms they postulate tend to

commonly produce adaptive behaviour, the sub-fields are rather more distinctive in the extent of

maladaptive behaviour that they predict. Many Evolutionary Psychologists argue that, because

the human brain is a highly complex, slowly evolving organ, human beings are likely to exhibit

an ‘adaptive lag’, meaning that much of human behaviour is sub-optimal in modern

environments (Tooby and Cosmides 1992). Any culturally evoked changes in human behaviour

since the end of the Pleistocene are therefore assumed to be largely irrelevant to our

understanding of the evolved human mind. For Tooby and Cosmides (1992), culture is part of

the environment that, along with many other environmental influences, may trigger alternative

developmental pathways, much as identical jukeboxes might play different tunes in different

environments if that is how they were programmed. Barrett (2012) uses a norm of reaction

9
model of how the development of the organism responds to environmental inputs. In this

formulation, evolved mental modules include a function that maps environmental variation onto

behaviour. If human mental adaptations can be characterised as norms of reaction that were

calibrated for hunting and gathering lifeways in Pleistocene environments, then many

maladaptive mismatches between cognitive adaptations and the environment should exist in the

vastly different lifeways of complex societies in the Holocene.

In contrast, human Behavioural Ecologists argue that their research has shown that real-

world data often provide a good fit to models that assume optimal behavioural responses to

current environmental parameters (Borgerhoff Mulder 1991). Human Behavioural Ecologists

start with the assumption that behaviour will be adaptive, but are willing to accept that

maladaptive responses may occur, either as a result of critical environmental triggers or stimuli

being absent, or as a result of culturally transmitted information. Whether behaviour is adaptive

or maladaptive, in terms of genetic fitness, is tested empirically, generally by using long-term

datasets. For example, these researchers have considered conspicuous puzzling cases like the

transition to low fertility in the course of modernization, where fertility appears to be sub-

optimal (Kaplan 1994; Borgerhoff Mulder 1998). The answer Kaplan (1994) gives to the puzzle

of the demographic transition is that, in the unprecedentedly wealthy societies of many

contemporary populations, we inadvertently over-invest in the quality of our offspring and have

too few of them; this is the same sort of mismatch explanation as Evolutionary Psychologists

might give. In contrast, other Human Behavioural Ecologists have pursued the possibility that

sufficiently complex optimality models, involving trade-offs between quality and quantity of

offspring, can shed light on patterns of family size in post-demographic transition societies (e.g.,

Lawson and Mace 2011; Lawson et al. 2012). Human Behavioural Ecologists generally do not

envisage high levels of mal-adaptations in modern environments, because they hold a less

10
domain-specific view of the underlying mechanisms than do Evolutionary Psychologists

(Borgerhoff Mulder et al. 1997).

Evolutionary Psychologists, Human Behavioural Ecologists and Cultural Evolutionists do

appear to agree that maladaptive behavioural responses can result from cultural processes. The

social learning strategies that are studied by Cultural Evolutionists could lead to the acquisition

of maladaptive information (i.e., information that fails to enhance genetic reproductive success)

in some instances, as long as the learning strategies themselves are favoured by selection

(Richerson and Boyd 2005). Take the issue of whether or not to learn from people other than

your parents. On the one hand, doing so will expose a learner to much more cultural variation

than is likely to be present in just two parents, and, to the extent that learning biases let learners

chose adaptive traits, the more variation the better. On the other hand, some harmful cultural

variants may arise that exploit general purpose decision-making systems to the detriment of the

learner’s genetic fitness. For example, Newson and colleagues (2007) used a combination of

models, experiments and survey data to argue that the main cause of the modern decline in

fertility was a sharp increase in the ratio of non-kin to kin in social networks, leading to the

spread of fertility-limiting cultural information between unrelated peers. Weak general-purpose

biases, such as ‘copy the majority’, can sometimes be inadequate defence against specific

maladaptive ideas, perhaps explaining the demographic transition and other oddities of

modernity (Newson and Richerson 2009). The trade-off of increased power of biases against the

risk of acquiring fitness-limiting ideas might well have been optimized by selection in past

societies, and the risk of acquiring maladaptive information might have increased substantially in

modern environments, for example because mass media exposes us to many attractively

packaged cultural variants designed by advertisers to increase their sales, not the recipients

fitness.

11
Given that the cognitive mechanisms underlying human culture are assumed to have been

selected for their overall fitness-enhancing properties, the extent of the ‘adaptive lag’ is likely to

be less extreme than envisaged by some Evolutionary Psychologists (Laland and Brown 2006).

Cultural Evolutionists differ from Evolutionary Psychologists in highlighting the potential for

cultural transmission to produce fitness-maximizing solutions to novel problems, including those

produced by human culture itself. While Cultural Evolutionists certainly have no quarrel with the

idea that the developing organism has many circuits that respond adaptively to evolutionarily

relevant environmental inputs and maladaptively to novel ones, culture is, in their view, a

completely different system. Culture is a system that fairly quickly evolves novel solutions to

novel problems. In this respect, cultural evolution is like a faster version of genetic evolution

(Perreault 2012), and, like genetic evolution, generates design and functionality in traits. The

speed of cultural evolution allows it to explore a very large design space. For example, Arctic

people developed light, swift, safe boats to hunt seals using driftwood and skins, while European

mariners developed large stout wooden sailing ships to pioneer a global commerce in bulk

goods. Knowledge of how to make and operate such complex devices must be transmitted with

reasonable fidelity so that weak relatively general-purpose cognition can, generation by

generation, invent and select improvements in the designs of artifacts and social systems (Tennie

et al. 2009). Where cultural processes induce environmental changes, selection can favour

culturally-transmitted solutions, or generate selection pressures acting on the human genome

(Laland et al. 2010; Richerson and Boyd 2010a; Stearns et al. 2010; Courtiol et al. 2012).

Thus, Cultural Evolutionists expect that many types of temporal and spatial mismatches

between ancestral human adaptations and their current environments will be solved by cultural

evolution fairly quickly; for example, the development of protective clothing and shelter

technology systems has allowed human beings to survive in environments with extreme low

temperatures. Cultural evolution seems to explain why humans have been, if anything, more

12
successful in the Holocene than in the Pleistocene. We have undergone a veritable adaptive

radiation of locally adapted economies using domesticated plants and animals. At the same time,

the disease and nutritional environments created by the cultural evolution of agricultural

subsistence systems have put intense selective pressure on those aspects of human biology for

which cultural fixes have proven elusive (Laland et al. 2010; Richerson and Boyd 2010a; Stearns

et al. 2010); for example, an increasing proportion of starchy food in the diet following the

adoption of agriculture has selected for increasing the number of copies of the enzyme amylase,

which is secreted in saliva to begin the digestion of starch (Perry et al. 2007). More broadly,

many organisms change conditions and factors in their local environments, a process known as

niche construction, and thereby produce an organism-induced change in the selective

environment (Odling-Smee et al. 2003). Niche construction activities lead to feedback loops

between organisms and their environments that alter the selection pressures on the organisms and

their descendants, for example, leading to the fixation of alleles that would otherwise be

deleterious and allowing the persistence of organisms in otherwise hostile environments (Odling-

Smee et al. 2003). The potency of human cumulative culture allows cultural niche construction

to modify selection on human genes (Laland et al. 2001), and socially transmitted information

thus has the ability to shape natural selection pressures, allowing genetic and cultural variation to

co-evolve and novel evolutionary episodes to occur (Laland et al. 2000; Kendal et al. 2011).

In summary, the three sub-fields have strong commonalities. All three take it for granted

that humans possess evolved psychological mechanisms that produce adaptive responses to

environmental cues, as long as the environment is not too dissimilar to ancestral environments.

All three agree that mismatches can occur when modern environments are very dissimilar to

those of our ancestors. All three agree that cultural transmission (or contagion) processes can

sometimes lead to the adoption of behaviour patterns that are maladaptive at the level of gene

transmission. However, Cultural Evolutionists and Human Behavioural Ecologists agree that

13
culture itself can quickly evolve solutions to novel problems, resulting in culturally constructed

environments that fit with our previous adaptations, or that instead lead to new bouts of genetic

evolution (Laland and Brown 2006), while, in contrast, some Evolutionary Psychologists

maintain that cultural evolution has limited explanatory power (Pinker 2010). Thus, the type of

adaptive lag envisaged by Cultural Evolutionists differs from that of the Evolutionary

Psychologists. For Cultural Evolutionists, mis-matches are generally self-induced and can result

in both cultural and genetic responses, with gene-culture co-evolutionary processes potentially

minimising the mis-match between current environments and previous adaptations.

Tooby and Cosmides (1992) provided a sweeping critique of the “Standard Social

Science Model” and its heavy dependence on the concept of transmitted culture, and they

proposed a radically cognitivist alternative. Cultural Evolutionists agree that a blank slate model

of human cognition is untenable, but argue that cognitive constraints on transmitted culture are

considerably weaker than Evolutionary Psychologists allow. If so, the SSSM is quite right to

stress the importance of culture if wrong in its radical attempt to deny any importance to genetic

evolution and the products of genetic evolution, such as important elements of cognition.

Cultural Evolutionists take the massive adaptive radiation of humans in the Holocene based upon

culturally transmitted technology and social institutions, and the lack of a massive mismatch of

Pleistocene-adapted people to Holocene environments, to be some of the best evidence available

for the gene-culture coevolution and cultural niche construction picture of human evolution.

6.2 What is the evolved function of cognition and culture?

Evolutionary Psychologists originally viewed the human mind as consisting of evolved

psychological mechanisms that are content-specific computational processing devices adapted

for Pleistocene hunting and gathering existence (Tooby and Cosmides 1992). (See the discussion

14
below on improvisational intelligence for a discussion of a different, more recent evolutionary

psychological hypothesis about human cognition.) In contrast, Cultural Evolutionists focus on

relatively general-purpose learning mechanisms that produce biases in behavioural outcomes

depending upon the context of learning in addition to the content of the transmitted information

(Richerson and Boyd 2005; Boyd et al. 2011a); for example, a prestige-bias (‘copy prestigious

individuals’) can lead individuals to acquire information about diet, hunting techniques or mates

(Henrich and Gil-White 2001). The human mind is likely to contain both domain-specific and

domain-general psychological mechanisms, allowing for some apparent integration between

these perspectives. Our sensitivity to pain in the human head and face is clearly a domain-

specific adaptation to protect the relatively fragile and important organs of the head from

damage. Many such domain-specific adaptations likely exist. Therefore, the relative importance

of more domain-specific versus more domain-general mechanisms in directing human cognition

and behavior appears to be an empirical question that is amenable to resolution.

However, the sub-fields have different hypotheses about the main adaptive function of

human cognition. According to Cultural Evolutionists, the strongly cognitive picture of the

Evolutionary Psychologists got the main adaptive problem of the Pleistocene wrong. Tooby and

Cosmides (1992) have argued that humans evolved cognitive adaptations to the statistical

regularities of Pleistocene environments. If so, Barrett’s (2012) reaction norm model of

phenotypic flexibility would be adequate. However, according to Cultural Evolutionists, the

ancestral world was insufficiently regular to favour numerous highly specific cognitive

adaptations, and selection instead favoured a smaller number of more general rules. As it turns

out the Pleistocene was a stunningly variable environment that was statistically quite

unpredictable (National Research Council 2002). While early records of climatic variation only

resolved low-frequency glacial cycles with time scales of tens of thousands of years,

paleoclimatologists have recently discovered that glacial environments became increasingly

15
packed with high amplitude noisy variation on times scales of decades to millennia over the last

eight glacial cycles (Loulergue et al. 2008). The Pleistocene is also the culmination of a 50-

million-year-long trend toward drier climates and polar cooling that increased spatial variation in

the Earth’s habitats (Zachos et al. 2001). According to Boyd and Richerson (1985), social

learning would be most useful in environments with lots of unpredictable variation that is

concentrated in events with durations too long for adaptation by individual learning but too short

for genetic adaptations to evolve, just the sorts of variation that typify the Pleistocene. Human

cultural complexity and brain size increases appear to have roughly paralleled this increase in

climatic variability (Richerson et al. 2005).

Cultural Evolutionists thus argue that the evolved psychological mechanisms in the brain

evolved in response to the challenges posed by variable environments and that culture is an

important mechanism by which populations can express adaptive responses to environmental

challenges. In contrast, Human Behavioural Ecology has remained relatively mechanism-neutral,

relying on the ability of optimality and life history models to predict adaptive outcomes in the

presence of hypothesized environmental triggers, regardless of the underlying proximate

mechanisms (Smith 2000). From its inception, this field has included cultural information as one

potential source of adaptive ‘fit’ with the environment. Cultural Evolutionists have no quarrel

with the application of evolutionary models, such as life history and optimal foraging theory

from evolutionary ecology to human populations (e.g. Boughton and O’Connell 1999;

Borgerhoff Mulder 1991; Smith et al. 2001) but do think they have limitations. In particular the

assumption that human populations are always at an adaptive equilibrium is misleading if

cultures are actively evolving, a possibility that Human Behavioural Ecologists have historically

ignored, or at least tried to ignore by choosing “traditional” populations, or at least traditional

behavioural patterns, in apparent equilibrium. For example, Kennett (2005) interprets a pattern

of resource use intensification in aboriginal Southern California in terms of optimal foraging

16
decisions interacting with climate and oceanographic change. But long term patterns of

intensification occur almost everywhere in the Holocene and probably represent the relatively

slow, progressive increase of technical and social sophistication made possible by the shift to

warm, wet, relatively stable climates at the beginning of the Holocene.

Examples such as this strongly suggest that use of the phenotypic gambit has led to a

relative neglect of culture as a transformational force in human evolution (Borgerhoff Mulder

and Schacht 2012; Brown 2013). Human Behavioural Ecologists do seek the source of changes

in physical and social conditions that result in changing optima over time, for example, by asking

why a population changes from matriliny to patriliny in the context of increasing heritable

wealth. However, some Behavioural Ecologists have argued that culture should be treated like

any other proximate mechanism (Nettle et al. 2013), which leads to the neglect of how cultural

transmission can radically affect the dynamics of adaptive change (Brown 2013). Much of the

research within Human Behavioural Ecology involves the application of ahistorical adaptive

equilibrium models that do not take into account past trajectories of cultural evolution, and

culture is treated as a proximal adaptive system responding to exogenous environmental change.

This approach risks ignoring the fact that the very environment to which humans are adapting is

itself partly an endogenous, dynamic product of cultural evolution, an issue that closely parallels

evolutionary economists’ critique of neoclassical models (Nelson and Winter 1982).

In summary, while Evolutionary Psychologists (e.g., Tooby and Cosmides 1992) and

Cultural Evolutionists (e.g., Boyd and Richerson 1985) have generally differed in the emphasis

that is placed on more domain-specific versus more domain-general mechanisms, the difference

between these sub-fields extends beyond this apparently quantitative distinction. For Cultural

Evolutionists, culturally transmitted information has played a vital role in the ability of ancestral

human populations to adapt to, and regulate, unpredictably varying environments, and any

explanations of human behaviour that fail to take cultural evolutionary processes into account

17
will provide only an incomplete understanding. As discussed in the next section, Evolutionary

Psychologists have instead argued that incorporating culture into the equation should have

relatively little impact on how we think about the evolved human mind, as cultural content is

ultimately under genetic control.

6.3 What are the proximal mechanisms of cultural acquisition?

Evolutionary Psychologists and Cultural Evolutionists have quite different views of what

happens in cultural transmission. Evolutionary Psychologists hold what is called an

‘epidemiological’ theory of culture in which cultural variation is rather tightly limited by the

cognitive psychology of representations (Sperber 1984). In the epidemiological model of culture,

Evolutionary Psychologists focus on the role that evolved cognitive processes play in

controlling information transmission, and they stress the importance of representations being

reconstructed in the minds of the learners. For example, Tooby and Cosmides (1992) state that:

The design of human psychological architecture structures the nature of the social

interactions humans can enter into, as well as the selectively contagious transmission of

representations between individuals. Only after the description of the evolved

psychological architecture has been restored as the centerpiece of social theory can the

secondary anti-entropic effects of population-level social dynamics be fully assessed and

confidently analyzed. (p. 48)

And:

Rather than calling this class of representations "transmitted" culture, we prefer terms

such as reconstructed culture, adopted culture, or epidemiological culture. The use of the

word "transmission" implies that the primary causal process is located in the individuals

18
from whom the representations are derived. In contrast, an evolutionary psychological

perspective emphasizes the primacy of the psychological mechanisms in the learner that,

given observations of the social world, inferentially reconstruct some of the

representations existing in the minds of the observed. (p. 118)

While these quotes suggest that information transmission is likely to have low fidelity, as

a result of continual bouts of reconstruction within the minds of observers, recent work in

developmental and comparative psychology shows that human culture does in fact transmit

information quite accurately by cognitive systems apparently selected for that exact purpose

rather than for restricting variation by strongly biasing what can be learned. For example,

experiments by Tomasello, Whiten and colleagues (e.g. Tomasello 1996; Whiten et al. 2009),

which compare the social learning skills of humans and great apes, have shown that young

children are much more accurate imitators than are apes. Children quite faithfully replicate the

arbitrary, non-functional patterns of behaviour that the experimentalists introduce into their

experimental tasks. Apes largely ignore such actions and concentrate on using the demonstration

for clues about how to get the reward the experimenters offer. As a result, children are prepared

to learn skills that have no immediate reward, except perhaps the internal reward of “doing it

right”. Later, these skills often turn out to be critical to building complex artifacts and for

displaying complex, arbitrary signals of group membership, such as “correct” etiquette.

Experiments designed to uncover the cognitive underpinnings of cultural transmission also

strongly suggest that our cognition has evolved so that infants and children could acquire the

quite complex and often counter-intuitive ideas and practices of their culture (Carey 2009;

Buchsbaum et al. 2011; Csibra and Gergely 2011; Harris 2012; Sterelny 2012). Psychological

mechanisms in the learner and in the people acting as teachers or models are both important.

Given the accurate transmission of a wide range of cultural constructions, populations of humans

19
can turn the same rather weak, relatively general-purpose learning schemes that underpin

reinforcement-based individual learning into powerful evolutionary forces that cumulatively

generate complex cultural adaptations faster than can genetic evolution acting on random genetic

variation.

Interestingly, an important example that Pinker and Bloom (1990), Tooby and Cosmides

(1992) and Pinker (1994) use to exemplify their highly cognitively structured model of

epidemiological culture is Chomsky’s proposal that language learning is underpinned by a

content-rich modular system. Cultural evolutionists have been major contributors to the field of

evolutionary linguistics in the years since Pinker and Bloom’s pioneering contribution

(Richerson and Boyd 2010b). Certainly, cultural evolutionists don’t deny that humans are

cognitively prepared to learn and use language, but many linguists now believe that language

may share most of its cognitive learning machinery with other aspects of culture (e.g. Tomasello

2008; Christiansen and Chater 2008; Smith and Kirby 2008; Evans and Levinson 2009; Hurford

2011). Chomsky’s original “principles and parameters” approach to the cognitive foundations of

language did not successfully deal with the vast diversity of grammatical inventions comparative

linguists discovered in the late 20th Century (Newmeyer 2004). Chomsky himself has recognized

the importance of evolution in explaining language but has become a minimalist regarding the

cognitive structures involved (Hauser et al. 2002). Thus, what once was taken to be a convincing

example of a content-rich cognitive system tightly constraining cultural variation is now

plausibly an example of the dominance of cognitive adaptations for teaching and learning a more

weakly constrained body of transmitted culture.

Thus, while many evolutionary psychologists emphasize the cognitive processes that

allow information to be reconstructed in the receiver’s mind and that structure the type of

information that is likely to be received, cultural evolutionists argue for less restriction with

regard to the type of information that is transmitted and point to the evidence that psychological

20
mechanisms favour relatively accurate information transmission, even when such information is

arbitrary or maladaptive. Controversies within the field of language evolution highlight how

researchers are attempting to delineate the specific evolved psychological mechanisms that

underlie human social learning and that give rise to so much cultural diversity.

6.4 Is cultural evolution or improvisational intelligence the better explanation for the

diversity and complexity of human behaviour?

Evolutionary Psychologists have certainly not been blind to the extremely diverse and highly

creative cultural adaptations that are a human specialty. In recent papers, Evolutionary

Psychologists have hypothesized that humans, uniquely among all animals, have what they call

improvisation intelligence (Cosmides and Tooby 2001): individuals can use individual cognition

to invent complex and adaptive cultural traits as needed. As Pinker (2010) puts it:

These cognitive stratagems are devised on the fly in endless combination suitable to the

local ecology. They arise by mental design and are deployed, tested, and fine-tuned by

feedback in the lifetimes of individuals, rather than arising by random mutation and being

tuned over generations by the slow feedback of differential survival and reproduction (p.

8449).

This proposal seems at variance with the argument in Tooby and Cosmides (1992) that general

purpose intelligences are inevitably weak, the cornerstone of their hypothesis that cognitive

mechanisms must be modular. On their original argument, the improvisational intelligence idea

therefore must be wrong. Cosmides and Tooby (2001) admit that the evolution of

improvisational intelligence is enigmatic but believe that an increase in the number of modular

21
structures, together with some means of dealing with the combinatorial explosion involved in

keeping in mind many dimensions of a complex problem, have somehow been solved in humans.

Cultural Evolutionists argue that the improvisational intelligence hypothesis greatly

overstates individual creativity relative to the power of weak, relatively general-purpose learning

systems acting in concert with accurate cultural transmission in leading to the cumulative

evolution of cultural complexity (Boyd et al. 2011a). Much evidence suggests that complex

human “inventions” have in fact been reached by a long history of cumulative improvement by

relatively small steps, a generalization well documented by the pioneering archaeologist and

ethnographer Pitt Rivers in the late 19th Century (Bowden 1991) and widely supported by

numerous modern studies (see Basalla 1988; Henrich 2009 and Mesoudi 2011 for overviews).

Recent successful applications of phylogenetic methods drawn from biology necessarily assume

a pattern of “descent with modification” on the part of some aspects of culture as well as genes

(e.g. Gray et al. 2011; Mace and Jordan 2011). The role of blind variation and small incremental

improvements in the evolution of even comparatively simple artifacts such as paper clips and

dinner forks has been documented by Petroski (1992). Thus Cultural Evolutionists are skeptical

that improvisational intelligence is a sound alternative to cumulative cultural evolution to explain

the complexity and diversity of human cultural adaptations. Certainly humans improvise new

solutions to problems, but such improvisation is heavily reliant on minor refinements of

culturally transmitted knowledge and hence more closely fits the Cultural Evolutionists’

Darwinian model than the Evolutionary Psychologists’ macromutational improvisational

intelligence conception.

7 A case study: non-kin cooperation in humans

The sub-fields also differ sharply over how to explain the large amount of non-kin cooperation in

our species. Everyone agrees that the large-scale societies of the Holocene include a lot of

22
cooperation between distantly related and unrelated people. There is also widespread agreement

among the sub-fields that the proximal mechanisms for ensuring cooperation include such things

as reputation, sanctioning of those who misbehave, and the use of language to negotiate actions,

make promises, and spread reputational information through gossip (Smith 2010). Evolutionary

Psychologists (e.g. Pinker 2010) have explained human cooperation among non-relatives on the

basis of selection for reciprocal exchange plus language being sufficient to create the proximal

mechanisms listed above. In contrast, Cultural Evolutionists propose that a special form of group

selection, cultural group selection, played an important role in the evolution of prosocial

cognitive adaptations and that ongoing cultural group selection plays a role in the evolution of

social institutions (e.g. Richerson and Henrich 2012; Turchin 2009; see also Bowles and Gintis

2011, for a case for culture-facilitated genetic group selection). The basic idea is a modernization

of Darwin’s tribal scale selection hypothesis in the Descent of Man:

It must not be forgotten that although a high standard of morality gives but a

slight or no advantage to each individual man and his children over other men of

the same tribe, yet that an advancement in the standard of morality and an

increase in the number of well-endowed men will certainly give an immense

advantage to one tribe over another. There can be no doubt that a tribe including

many members who, from possessing in a high degree the spirit of patriotism,

fidelity, obedience, courage, and sympathy, were always ready to aid each other

and to sacrifice themselves for the common good, would be victorious over most

other tribes; and this would be natural selection (Darwin 1871: p. 166).

Modern evolutionists have learned that it is hard to make group selection on genetic

variation work on large outbred populations such as human tribes. However, the same is not

necessarily true if the variation on which selection operates is cultural. Neighbouring societies

23
are seldom very different genetically but they are often quite different culturally (Bell et al.

2009). A number of properties of cultural evolution make it easier to generate and preserve

cultural variation at the level of tribes and other large groups (Richerson and Boyd 2005: 203-6).

For example, social institutions usually include a system of rewards that favour those who

conform to the institution and punishments for those who don’t, damping down individual-level

variation within groups (Bowles and Gintis 2011). Immigrants, particularly child immigrants,

tend to adopt the culture of their hosts and lose the culture of their ancestors even as they

interbreed and pass their genes into their host group. Prosocial emotions would have acted as

biases favouring institutions that better satisfied these emotions, and many of the most powerful

societies throughout history, including China, Rome, and the modern West have grown by

selective immigration (Boyd and Richerson 2009). The “design space” for social institutions is

very large, in part because a system of rewards and punishments can stabilize almost any pattern

of behaviour (e.g. Aoki 2001). Human competition is very often between organizations: a

simplified example would be that, in most modern economies, anti-competitive behaviour

between firms is outlawed so that consumers can enjoy the benefits of business firms having to

compete to produce better and less expensive products.

To explain the vast diversity of human social arrangements, Cultural Evolutionists thus

appeal to the importance of culturally transmitted norms and institutions, whereas Evolutionary

Psychologists consider that many forms of interaction between genes and the environment that

occur during the lifetime of an individual may be as important, or more important, than culture in

explaining differences in behaviour (e.g, Pinker 2010). Cultural Evolutionists certainly agree that

gene-environment interactions during the lifespan are highly important, but their concept of the

environment involves complex feedback loops between developing organisms and their socially

inherited environments. Evolutionary Psychologists have been among the stoutest critics of

group selection in any form, as well as doubting the cultural evolution and gene-culture

24
coevolution do any useful work (Footnote 1). Pinker (2010) includes these concepts in a laundry

list of what he considers to be dubious evolutionary ideas:

[I]t seems superfluous, when explaining the evolution of human mental mechanisms, to

assign a primary role to macromutations, exaptation, runaway sexual selection, group

selection, memetics, complexity theory, cultural evolution (other than what we call

“history”), or gene–culture coevolution (other than the commonplace that the products of

an organism’s behavior are part of its selective environment). (p. 8996)

Evolutionary Psychologists have explained non-kin cooperation by appealing to a history of

reciprocal exchange in the Pleistocene that favoured the evolution of specialized cognitive

structures designed, in Cosmides and Tooby’s (1992) famous example, for detecting cheaters in

reciprocal exchanges. Experiments suggest that human subjects are much better at detecting

violations of social contract rules compared to logical similar puzzles involving violations of

other kinds of rules, such as neutral, empirically contingent rules (Cosmides 1989). To explain

the fact that we cooperate in anonymous exchanges in modern societies, Evolutionary

Psychologists argue that the cheater detection modules evolved in an environment where

anonymous exchange was rare and are mis-calibrated for modern environments. As Cosmides

and Tooby (1997) put it in general terms:

. . . [O]ur modern skulls house a stone age mind. The key to understanding how the

modern mind works is to realize that its circuits were not designed to solve the day-to-

day problems of a modern American -- they were designed to solve the day-to-day

problems of our hunter-gatherer ancestors. These stone age priorities produced a brain far

better at solving some problems than others. For example, it is easier for us to deal with

small, hunter-gatherer-band sized groups of people than with crowds of thousands; it is

easier for us to learn to fear snakes than electric sockets, even though electric sockets

25
pose a larger threat than snakes do in most American communities. In many cases, our

brains are better at solving the kinds of problems our ancestors faced on the African

savannahs than they are at solving the more familiar tasks we face in a college classroom

or a modern city. In saying that our modern skulls house a stone age mind, we do not

mean to imply that our minds are unsophisticated. Quite the contrary: they are very

sophisticated computers, whose circuits are elegantly designed to solve the kinds of

problems our ancestors routinely faced.

Specifically, in their functional analysis of social life, Cosmides and Tooby (1997) appear to rest

their case solely on pairwise reciprocal exchange (also see Krasnow et al. 2012):

Sometimes known as "reciprocal altruism", social exchange is an "I'll scratch your back if

you scratch mine" principle. Economists and evolutionary biologists had already explored

constraints on the emergence or evolution of social exchange using game theory,

modeling it as a repeated Prisoners' Dilemma. One important conclusion was that social

exchange cannot evolve in a species or be stably sustained in a social group unless the

cognitive machinery of the participants allows a potential cooperator to detect individuals

who cheat, so that they can be excluded from future interactions in which they would

exploit co-operators.

Thus, even in experiments where researchers guarantee anonymity, human cognition, these

authors argue, calculates as if we still live in small-scale societies where familiar others are

observing and noting your behaviour and that these observers are likely to be future reciprocity

partners.

In contrast, Cultural Evolutionists argue that a considerable amount of evidence supports

the hypothesis that a history of cultural group selection can explain the evolution of non-kin

cooperation (Boyd and Richerson 1985; Richerson and Boyd 2005; Chudek and Henrich 2011).

26
Most fundamentally, humans everywhere live in large groups that vary culturally and compete

with one another; by definition, the winners of these competitions spread their social institutions

and other aspects of their culture to daughter societies, attract immigrants from other societies

and are imitated by other societies. For instance, many modern nations in Europe and Latin

America follow legal codes descended from Roman law, speak languages descended from Latin,

and follow religions derived from Roman Christianity. Social identity theorists have documented

the mechanisms by which groups become part of our social identity (Haslam 2001), and

developmental evidence suggests that young children readily learn social norms from caregivers

and others (Chudek and Henrich 2011). Theoretical models have also shown that circumstances

favouring social learning generally lead to conformity of behaviour, with individuals tending to

copy what the majority of the population are doing (e.g., Boyd and Richerson 1985; Nakahashi

et al. 2012; Perreault et al. 2012). Such conformity will tend to minimise behavioural differences

within groups, providing the opportunity for cultural group selection to occur.

Further, humans are not just adept at reciprocal exchange but are also generally adept at

solving problems that require high levels of cooperation, such as occur in managing commons

and the provision of defense. Ethnographic analogy and palaeoanthropology suggest that

ancestral societies by the late Pleistocene were quite large and that non-kin interactions would

not have been uncommon (Powell et al. 2009; Hill et al. 2011). Chudek et al. (in press) review

evidence that suggests that ephemeral interactions with strangers are common in the hunter-

gather ethnographic record. The existence of long distant trade networks in decorative shell and

valuable tool-stone in the Holocene (Baugh and Erickson 1994) and Upper Paleolithic (Klein

2009) suggests that by the latest Pleistocene at least humans were adept at establishing

relationships with strangers. For example, acephalous tribes using the same institutions as mobile

food foragers, but based on more productive subsistence strategies like herding and farming, can

operate on quite large scales. Compared to Evolutionary Psychology, Cultural Evolution stands

27
out in invoking a novel evolutionary mechanism (cultural group selection) to explain the

extraordinary patterns of large scale cooperation in our species.

A series of experiments conducted by Fehr and Gächter (2002) showed that cooperation

in a public goods game could be sustained by altruistic punishment if that strategy was available.

Based on this and other experiments devised by experimental economists, Fehr and Fischbacher

(2003) suggest that cultural group selection and gene-culture coevolution might be required to

explain human patterns of cooperation. However, laboratory experiments have failed to resolve

the issue of whether humans exhibit features consistent with cultural group selection and gene-

culture coevolution for prosocial dispositions. Evolutionary Psychologists Hagen and

Hammerstein (2006) and Delton et al. (2011) have pointed out that, even in experiments where

researchers guarantee anonymity and tell participants that the games are one-shot, human

cognition might still calculate as if we still live in small-scale societies where reciprocity

partners are observing and sanctioning or rewarding their behaviour. However, this criticism

applies to any such experiments, including the classical experiments of Cosmides (1989), which

can only tap proximal mechanisms directly and may speak rather softly about the selection

pressures that led to the mechanisms. For example, a facility for detecting violators of reciprocal

agreements would also be useful for detecting violations of social contracts embedded in

culturally transmitted social institutions. In any case, Chudek and Henrich (2011) point out that

Cosmides’ classic experiment is framed in terms of norm violations, something they argue is not

predicted by reciprocity theory.

Mathew et al. (in press) review evidence suggesting that human cooperation with kin and

unrelated partners is both heavily institutionalized and much more extensive than in most other

animals. They suggest that institutions like marriage that are plausibly subject to cultural group

selection are necessary to produce high levels of kin and partner cooperation; the conventional

evolutionary mechanisms of inclusive fitness and reciprocity are perhaps not sufficient to explain

28
the extensive small-scale cooperation humans exhibit. A hypersensitivity to the possibility of

adverse effects on one’s reputation or exaggerated fear of direct sanction is a plausible proximal

cognitive trait that cultural group selection might have favoured by gene-culture coevolution to

maintain high rates of intragroup cooperation. An increased understanding of the proximal

mechanisms underlying cooperative behaviour does not directly test hypotheses regarding the

evolutionary history of those traits.

A broad empirical and theoretical program is necessary to adjudicate conflicts between

different evolutionary explanations of human cooperation and other important problems.

Evidence for and against alternate evolutionary explanations must be sought across a series of

consilient domains. Mathematical models are useful to check the logical coherence of

explanations. Typically, all too many models are logically coherent and the real issue is which

one best fits the data (e.g. Boyd et al. 2011b). Alternate formal models can also be fit directly to

data using modern maximum likelihood based methods (Efferson and Richerson 2007;

Borgerhoff Mulder and Beheim 2011). Data from microevolutionary studies demonstrating that

cultural group selection and gene-culture coevolution operates in concrete cases is important

(e.g. Mathew and Boyd 2011), and such studies must link microevolutionary evidence to

macroevolutionary patterns. For example, some cases of culture led gene-culture coevolution due

to the Holocene switch to agricultural subsistence are reasonably convincing (Laland et al. 2010,

Richerson et al. 2010a). Paleoenvironmental and paleoanthropological data are necessary to

understand what selective pressures acted on past human populations, and analyses of patterns of

adaptive and maladaptive behaviour are often quite informative. In the case of explanations of

human cooperation, as in other areas we have reviewed here, hot debates on this issue seem

likely to persist for some time.

29
8 Conclusion

In general, researchers within the sub-fields of Human Behavioural Ecology, Evolutionary

Psychology and Cultural Evolution agree that evolutionary theory can be usefully applied to the

study of human behaviour. In addition, there are numerous signs that integration of the sub-fields

is being achieved. For example, Human Behavioural Ecologists are incorporating cultural

transmission into their models of behavioural diversity (e.g. Borgerhoff Mulder et al. 2009; Hill

et al. 2009; Currie et al. 2010), and Evolutionary Psychologists increasingly make use of cultural

evolution and vice versa (e.g. Atran and Ginges 2012; Norenzayan and Gervais 2012; Chudek et

al. 2012). However, we believe that some of the issues that divided the three approaches in the

past do remain open and that both theoretical and empirical investigations are required to resolve

them. For example, there is as yet no consensus on the exact roles of genes, individual learning,

and social learning in human development (e.g. Spencer et al. 2009). Within evolutionary

biology itself, similarly broad issues are currently being discussed and debated, such as

usefulness of the distinction between proximate and ultimate explanations (Laland et al. 2011;

2012) and the role of multi-level, group selection (Eldaker and Wilson 2011; Wilson et al. 2008),

and such debates are highly relevant to researchers that are applying evolutionary principles to

economics. For the novice researcher, these debates might appear daunting, but we hope that

continued cross-disciplinary discussion and exchange of ideas will provide an ever richer

understanding of human behaviour.

Footnotes

1) See a debate initiated by Steven Pinker’s essay The False Allure of Group Selection in

the online magazine Edge (http://www.edge.org/conversation/the-false-allure-of-group-

selection).

30
Acknowledgements

This article stems from the authors’ attendance at a Max Planck symposium on ‘Biological

determinants and contingencies of economic behavior’ at the Ringberg Castle, Munich. We

thank the organiser, Prof. Ulrich Witt for the invitation to participate in the symposium, and we

are grateful to the other participants for many stimulating discussions. We also grateful for

comments on the manuscript from Curtis Atkisson, Clark Barrett, Rob Boyd, Joe Henrich,

Robert Kurzban, Monique Borgerhoff Mulder, Kevin Laland, Lesley Newson and Ryan

Schacht.

References

Alcock, J. (2001). The Triumph of Sociobiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Allen, E., et al. (1975). Letter. New York Review of Books, 13 Nov, 182, 184–186.

Aoki, M. (2001). Toward a Comparative Institutional Analysis. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

Atran, S., & Ginges, J. (2012). Religious and sacred imperatives in human conflict. Science, 336, 855-857.

Barrett, H. C. (2012). A hierarchical model of the evolution of human brain specializations. Proceedings of the

National Academy of Science, 109, 10733-10740.

Basalla, G. (1988). The Evolution of Technology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Baugh, T. G., & Ericson, J. E. (1994). Prehistoric Exchange Systems in North America. New York: Plenum.

Bell, A. V., Richerson, P. J., & McElreath, R. (2009). Culture rather than genes provides greater scope for the

evolution of large-scale human prosociality. Proceeding of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 106,

17671-17674.

Boakes, R. (1984). From Darwin to Behaviourism: Psychology and the Minds of Animals. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Bolhuis, J. J., Brown, G. R., Richardson, R. C., & Laland, K. N. (2011). Darwin in mind: new opportunities for

evolutionary psychology. PLoS Biology, 9, e1001109.

31
Borgerhoff Mulder, M. (1991). Human behavioural ecology. In J. R. Krebs & N. B. Davies (Eds), Behavioural

Ecology: an Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.

Borgerhoff Mulder, M. (1998). The demographic transition: Are we any closer to an evolutionary explanation?

Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 44, 266-272.

Borgerhoff Mulder, M., & Beheim, B. A. (2011). Understanding the nature of wealth and its effects on human

fitness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 366, 344-356.

Borgerhoff Mulder, M., Bowles, S., Hertz, T., Bell, A., Beise, J., Clark, G., et al. (2009). The Intergenerational

Transmission of Wealth and the Dynamics of Inequality in Pre-Modern Societies. Science, 326, 682-88.

Borgerhoff Mulder, M., Richerson, P. J., Thornhill, N. W., & Voland, E. (1997). The place of behavioral ecological

anthropology in evolutionary social science. In P. Weingart, S. D. Mitchell, P. J. Richerson, & S. Maasen (Eds),

Human by Nature: Between Biology and the Social Sciences. (pp. 253–282). New Jersey: Erlbaum.

Borgerhoff Mulder, M., & Schacht, R. (2012). Human behavioural ecology. In Encyclopedia of Life Sciences. (Pp 1-

10). Chichester: John Wiley.

Bowden, M. (1991). Pitt Rivers: The Life and Archaeological work of Lieutenant-General Augustus Henry Lane

Fox Pitt Rivers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2011). A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and its Evolution. Princeton: Princeton

University Press.

Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2009). Voting with your feet: payoff biased migration and the evolution of group

beneficial behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 257, 331-339.

Boyd, R., Richerson, P. J., & Henrich, J. (2011a). The cultural niche: why social learning is essential for human

adaptation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 108, 10918-10925.

Boyd, R., Richerson, P. J., & Henrich, J. (2011b). Rapid cultural adaptation can facilitate the evolution of large-

scale cooperation. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 65, 431-444.

Broughton, J. M. & O'Connell, J. F. (1999). On evolutionary ecology, selectionist archaeology, and behavioral

archaeology. American Antiquity, 64, 153-165.

Brown, G. R. (2013). Why mechanisms shouldn’t be ignored. Behavioral Ecology, 24, 1041-1042.

Brown, G. R., Dickins, T., Sear, R., & Laland, K. N. (2011). Evolutionary accounts of human behavioural diversity.

Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 366, 313-324.

32
Buchsbaum, D., Gopnik, A., Griffiths, T. L., & Shafto, P. (2011). Children’s imitation of causal action sequences is

influenced by statistical and pedagogical evidence. Cognition, 120, 331-340.

Buss, D. M. (Ed.) (2005). The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

Carey, S. (2009). The Origin of Concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., & Feldman, M. W. (1981). Cultural Transmission and Evolution: a Quantitative Approach.

Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Chagnon, N. A., & Irons, W. (1979). Evolutionary Biology and Human Social Behavior: an Anthropological

Perspective. North Scituate, MA: Duxbury Press.

Christiansen, M. H., & Chater, N. (2008). Language as shaped by the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 489-

558.

Chudek, M., Heller, S., Birch, S., & Henrich, J. (2012). Prestige-biased cultural learning: bystander’s differential

attention to potential models influence children’s learning. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, 46-56.

Chudek, M., & Henrich, J. (2011). Culture–gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emergence of human

prosociality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, 218-226.

Chudek, M., Zhao, W., & Henrich, J. (In press). Culture-gene coevolution, large-scale cooperation and the shaping

of human social psychology. In B. Calcott, R. Joyce & K. Sterelny, (Eds), Signaling, Commitment, and

Emotion. Boston, MA: MIT Press.

Cosmides, L. (1989). The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with

the Wason selection task. Cognition, 31, 187-276.

Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1987). From evolution to behavior: evolutionary psychology as the missing link. In J.

Dupré, (Ed.), The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J.

Tooby (eds), The Adapted Mind. Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture (pp. 163-228). New

York: Oxford University Press.

Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1997). Evolutionary psychology: a primer. Center for Evolutionary Psychology,

University of California Santa Barbara. http://www.psych.ucsb.edu/research/cep/primer.html

Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2001). Unravelling the enigma of human intelligence: Evolutionary psychology and the

multimodular mind. In R. J. Sternberg & J. C. Kaufman (Eds.), The Evolution of Intelligence (pp.145-199).

Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

33
Courtiol, A., Pettay, J. E., Jokela, M., Rotkirch, A., & Lummaa, V. (2012). Natural and sexual selection in a

monogamous historical human population. PNAS, 109, 8044-8049.

Csibra, G., & Gergely, G.. (2011). Natural pedagogy as an evolutionary adaptation. Philosophical Transactions of

the Royal Society B, 366, 1149-1157.

Currie, T. E., Greenhill, S. J., Gray, R. D., Hasegawa, T., & Mace, R. (2010). Rise and fall of political complexity in

island South-East Asia and the Pacific. Nature, 467, 801-804.

Danchin, É., Giraldeau, L.-A., & Cézilly, F. (Eds.) (2008). Behavioural Ecology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Darwin, C. (1871). The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex. London: John Murray.

Delton, A. W., Krasnow, M. M., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2011). Evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty

can explain human generosity in one-shot encounters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108,

13335-13340.

Efferson, C., & Richerson, P. J. (2007). A prolegomenon to non-linear empiricism in the human sciences. Biology

and Philosophy, 22, 1-33.

Eldakar, O. T., & Wilson, D. S. (2011). Eight criticisms not to make about group selection. Evolution, 65, 1523-

1526.

Evans, N., & Levinson, S. C. (2009). The myth of language universals: language diversity and its importance for

cognitive science. Behav. Brain Science, 32, 429-492.

Fehr, E., & Gachter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415, 137-140.

Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of human altruism. Nature, 425, 785-791.

Grafen, A. (1984). Natural selection, kin selection, and group selection. In J. R. Krebs & N. B. Davies (eds.),

Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach (pp 62-84). Oxford: Blackwell Scientific.

Gray, R. D., Atkinson, Q. D., & Greenhill, S. J. (2011). Language evolution and human history: what a difference a

date makes. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 1090-1100.

Hagen, E. H., & Hammerstein, P. (2006). Game theory and human evolution: A critique of some recent

interpretations of experimental games. Theoretical Population Biology, 69, 339-348.

Harris, P. L. (2012). Trusting What You're Told: How Children Learn From Others. Cambridge MA: Harvard

University Press.

Haslam, S. A. (2001). Psychology in Organizations: The Social Identity Approach. London: Sage Publications.

Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., & Fitch, W. T. (2002). The faculty of language: What is it, who has it, and how did it

evolve? Science, 298, 1569-1579.

34
Henrich, J. (2009). The evolution of costly displays, cooperation and religion: credibility enhancing displays and

their implications for cultural evolution. Evolution and Human Behavior, 30, 244-260.

Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Gintis, H., Fehr, E., Camerer, C., et al. (2005). ‘Economic Man’ in Cross-Cultural

Perspective: Ethnography and Experiments from 15 small-scale societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28,

795-855.

Henrich, J., & Broesch, J. (2011). On the nature of cultural transmission networks: evidence from Fijian villages for

adaptive learning biases. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366, 1139-

1148.

Henrich, J., Ensimger, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., et al. (2010). Markets, Religion,

Community Size, and the Evolution of Fairness and Punishment. Science, 327, 1480-1484.

Henrich, J., & Gil-White, F. J. (2001). The evolution of prestige - Freely conferred deference as a mechanism for

enhancing the benefits of cultural transmission. Evolution and Human Behavior, 22, 165-196.

Henrich, J., & McElreath, R. (2002). Are Peasants Risk Averse Decision-Makers. Current Anthropology, 43, 172-

181.

Heyes, C. M., & Hull, D. L. (2001). Selection Theory and Social Construction: The Evolutionary Naturalistic

Epistemology of Donald T. Campbell. New York: State University of New York Press.

Hill, K., Barton, M., & Hurtado, A. M. (2009). The emergence of human uniqueness: Characters underlying

behavioral modernity. Evolutionary Anthropology, 18, 174-187.

Hill, K. R., Walker, R. S., Božičević, M., Eder, J., Headland, T., Hewlett, B., et al. (2011). Co-residence patterns in

hunter-gatherer societies show unique human social structure. Science, 331, 1286-1286.

Hodgson, G. M., & Knudsen, T. (2008). In search of general evolutionary principles: why Darwinism is too

important to be left to the biologists. Journal of Bioeconomics, 10, 51-69.

Hurford, J. R. (2011). The Origins of Grammar: Language in the Light of Evolution II. Oxford: Oxford University

Press.

James, W. (1890). The Principles of Psychology, Volume 1. Henry Holt & Company (reprinted 1950, Dover Press).

Kaplan, H. (1994). Evolutionary and wealth flows theories of fertility: Empirical tests and new models. Population

and Development Review, 20, 753-791.

Kaplan, H. S., & Gangestad, S. W. (2005). Life history theory and evolutionary psychology. In D. M. Buss, (Ed.),

Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (pp. 68-95). New York: Wiley.

35
Kendal, J., Tehrani, J. J., & Odling-Smee, J. (2011). Human niche construction in interdisciplinary focus.

Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B, 366, 785-792.

Kennett, D. J. (2005). The Island Chumash: Behavioral Ecology of a Maritime Society. Berkeley: University of

California Press.

Klein, R. G. (2009). The Human Career: Human Biological and Cultural Origins. 3rd edition. Chicago: University

of Chicago Press.

Krasnow, M. M., Cosmides, L., Pedersen, E. J., & Tooby, J. (2012). What are punishment and reputation for? PLoS

ONE, 7: e45662.

Laland, K. N., & Brown, G. R. (2006). Niche construction, human behaviour and the adaptive-lag hypothesis.

Evolutionary Anthropology, 15, 95-104.

Laland, K. N., & Brown, G. R. (2011). Sense and Nonsense: Evolutionary Perspectives on Human Behaviour. 2nd

Edition. Oxford University Press.

Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J., & Feldman, M. W. (2000). Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural

change. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 131–175.

Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Feldman, M. W. (2001). Cultural niche construction and human evolution.

Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 14, 22–33.

Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2012). More on how and why: cause and effect in

biology revisited. Biology and Philosophy, on-line.

Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Myles, S. (2010). How culture shaped the human genome: bringing genetics

and the human sciences together. Nature Reviews Genetics, 11, 137-148.

Laland, K. N., Sterelny, K., Odling-Smee, J., Hoppitt, W., & Uller, T. (2011). Cause and effect in biology revisited:

is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science, 334, 1512-1516.

Loulergue, L., Schilt, A., Spahni, R., Masson-Delmotte, V., Blunier, T., Lemieux, B., et al. (2008). Orbital and

millennial-scale features of atmospheric CH4 over the past 800,000 years. Nature, 453, 383-386.

Lawson, D. W., Alvergne, A., & Gibson, M. A. (2012). The life-history trade-off between fertility and child

survival. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, online.

Lawson, D. W., & Mace, R. (2011). Parental investment and the optimization of human family size. Philosophical

Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 333-343.

Lumsden, C. J., & Wilson, E. O. (1981). Genes, Mind, and Culture: The Coevolutionary Process. Cambridge, MA:

Harvard University Press.

36
Mace, R. & Jordan, F. M. (2011). Macro-evolutionary studies of cultural diversity: A review of empirical studies of

cultural transmission and cultural adaptation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 402-411.

Mathew, S., & Boyd, R. (2011). Punishment sustains large-scale cooperation in prestate warfare. Proceedings of the

National Academy of Sciences, 108, 11375-11380.

Mathew, S., Boyd, R., & Van Veelen, M. (In press). Human cooperation among kin and close associates. In P. J.

Richerson & M. Christiansen, (eds). Cultural Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

McElreath, R., Lubell, M., Richerson, P. J., Waring, T. M., Baum, W., Edsten, et al, (2005). Applying evolutionary

models to the laboratory study of social learning. Evolution and Human Behavior, 26, 483-508.

Mesoudi, A. (2011). Cultural Evolution: How Darwinian Theory Can Explain Human Culture and Synthesize the

Social Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Mesoudi, A., & O’Brien, M. J. (2008). The cultural transmission of Great Basin projectile-point technology I: an

experimental simulation. American Antiquity, 73:,3-28.

Morgan, T. J. H., Rendell, L. E., Ehn. M., Hoppitt, W. J. E., & Laland, K. N. (2012). The evolutionary basis of

human social learning. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 1729, 653-662.

Nakahashi, W., Wakano, J. Y., & Henrich, J. (2012). Adaptive social learning strategies in temporally and spatially

varying environments: how temporal vs spatial variation, number of cultural traits, and costs of learning

influence the evolution of conformist-biased transmission, payoff-biased transmission, and individual learning.

Human Nature, 23, 386-418.

National Research Council. (2002). Abrupt Climate Change: Inevitable Surprises. Washington, D.C.: National

Academy Press.

Nelson, R. R., & Winter, S. G. (1982). An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Cambridge, MA: Belknap

Press of Harvard University Press.

Nettle, D., Gibson, M. A., Lawson, D. W., & Sear, R. (2013). Human behavioral ecology: current research and

future prospects. Behavioral Ecology, 24, 1031-1040.

Newmeyer, F. J. (2004). Against a parameter-setting approach to typological variation. Linguistic Variation

Yearbook, 4, 181-234.

Newson, L., Postmes, T., Lea, S. E. G., Webley, P. M., Richerson, P. J., & McElreath, R. (2007). Influences on

communication about reproduction: The cultural evolution of low fertility. Evolution & Human Behavior, 28.

Newson, L., & Richerson, P. J. (2009). Why do people become modern: a Darwinian mechanism. Population and

Development Review, 35, 117-158.

37
Norenzayan, A., & Gervais, W. (2012). The cultural evolution of religion. In E. Slingerland & M. Collard, (Eds.),

Creating Consilience: Integrating Science and the Humanities (pp. 243-265). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Odling-Smee, F. J., Laland, K. N., & Feldman, M. W. (2003). Niche Construction: The Neglected Process in

Evolution. Princeton, NJ: Monographs in Population Biology 37; Princeton University Press.

Perreault, C. (2012). The pace of cultural evolution. PLoS ONE, 7:e45150.

Perreault, C., Moya, C., & Boyd, R. (2012). A Bayesian approach to the evolution of social learning. Evolution and

Human Behavior, 33, 449-459.

Perry, G. H., Dominy, N. J., Claw, K. G., Lee, A. S., Fiegler, H., Redon, R., et al. (2007). Diet and the evolution of

human amylase gene copy number variation. Nature Genetics, 39, 1256-1260.

Petroski, H. (1992). The Evolution of Useful Things. New York: Vintage Books.

Pinker, S. (1994). The Language Instinct. New York: W. Morrow & Co.

Pinker, S. (2010). The cognitive niche: Coevolution of intelligence, sociality, and language. Proceedings of the

National Academy of Sciences, 107, 8993-8999.

Pinker, S., & Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, 707-784.

Plotkin, H. (1994). Darwin Machines and the Nature of Knowledge. New York: Penguin.

Powell, A., Shennan, S., & Thomas, M. G. (2009). Late Pleistocene demography and the appearance of modern

human behavior. Science, 324, 1298-1301.

Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution. Chicago:

Chicago University Press.

Richerson, P. J., Bettinger, R. L., & Boyd, R.. (2005). Evolution on a restless planet: Were environmental variability

and environmental change major drivers of human evolution? In F. M. Wuketits & F. J. Ayala (eds.),

Handbook of Evolution: Evolution of Living Systems (including Hominids) (pp. 223-242). Wiley-VCH,

Weinheim.

Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2010a). Gene-culture coevolution in the age of genomics. Proceedings National

Academy of Science USA, 107, 8985-8992.

Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2010b). Why possibly language evolved. Biolinguistics, 4, 289-306.

Richerson, P., & Henrich, J. (2012). Tribal social instincts and the cultural evolution of institutions to solve

collective action problems. Cliodynamics: the Journal of Theoretical and Mathematical History, 3, 38-80.

Rose, S., Lewontin, R. C., & Kamin, L. J. (1984). Not in Our Genes: Biology, Ideology, and Human Nature.

London: Penguin Books.

38
Segestråle, U. (2000). Defenders of the Truth: the Sociobiology Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Smith, E. A. (2000). Three styles in the evolutionary analysis of human behavior. In L. Cronk, N. Chagnon & W.

Irons (Eds). Adaptation and Human Behavior: an Anthropological Perspective. (pp. 27-46). New York: Aldine

de Gruyter.

Smith, E. A. (2010). Communication and collective action: language and the evolution of human cooperation.

Evolution and Human Behavior, 31, 231-245.

Smith, E. A., Borgerhoff Mulder, M., & Hill, K. (2001). Controversies in the evolutionary social sciences: a guide

for the perplexed. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 16, 128-135.

Smith, K., & Kirby, S. (2008). Cultural evolution: implications for the human language faculty and its evolution.

Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 363, 3591-3603.

Spencer, J. P., Blumberg, M. S., McMurray, B., Robinson, S. R., Samuelson, L. K., & Tomblin, J. B. (2009). Short

Arms and Talking Eggs: Why We Should No Longer Abide the Nativist–Empiricist Debate. Child

Development Perspectives, 3,79-87.

Sperber, D. (1984). Anthropology and psychology: Towards an epidemiology of representations. Man, 20, 73-89.

Stearns, S. C., Byars, S. G., Govindaraju, D. R., & Ewbank, D. (2010). Measuring selection in contemporary human

populations. Nature Reviews Genetics, 11, 611-622.

Sterelny, K. (2012). The Evolved Apprentice: How Evolution Made Humans Unique. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Symons, D. (1989). A critique of Darwinian Anthropology. Ethology and Sociobiology ,10, 131-143.

Tennie, C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Ratcheting up the ratchet: on the evolution of cumulative culture.

Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364, 2405-2415.

Tomasello, M. (1996): Do apes ape? In Galef, B. G. Jr, (ed), Social Learning in Animals: The Roots of Culture (pp.

319-346). San Diago, CA: Academic Press.

Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J.

Tooby (eds), The Adapted Mind. Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture (pp. 137-159). New

York: Oxford University Press.

Tooby, J., & DeVore, I. (1987). The reconstruction of hominid behavioral evolution through strategic modeling. In

W. G. Kinzey (ed.), The Evolution of Human Behavior: Primate Models (pp. 183-237). Albany, NY: SUNY

Press.

Turchin, P. (2009). A theory for the formation of large empires. Journal of Global History, 4, 191-217.

39
Whiten, A., McGuigan, N., Marshall-Pescini, S., & Hopper, L. M. (2009). Emulation, imitation, over-imitation and

the scope of culture for child and chimpanzee. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological

Sciences, 364, 2417-2428.

Wilson, D. S., van Vugt, M., & O’Goram, R. (2008). Multilevel selection theory and major evolutionary transitions:

implications for psychological science. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17, 6-9.

Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: the New Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Wilson, E. O. (1978). On Human Nature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Wilson, E. O. (1998). Consilience: the Unity of Knowledge. London, UK: Abacus.

Witt, U. (1999). Bioeconomics as economics from a Darwinian perspective. Journal of Bioeconomics, 1, 19-34.

Zachos, J., Pagani, M., Sloan, L., Thomas, E., & Billups, K. (2001). Trends, rhythms, and aberrations in global

climate 65 Ma to present. Science, 292, 686-693.

40

You might also like