Addiction
Addiction
Addiction
Addiction
A Philosophical Perspective
Candice L. Shelby
University of Colorado Denver, USA
© Candice L. Shelby 2016
Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2016 978-1-137-55284-6
Preface viii
Acknowledgments x
9 Conclusion 165
Notes 178
Bibliography 200
Index 203
Preface
viii
Preface ix
People have asked me many times over the years why, if everyone else
in my family of origin is dead due to one addiction or another, I am
a tenured professor writing a book on addiction rather than living
under a bridge with a needle in my arm. The reasons are mostly people.
Mitchell Aboulafia, while a professor at the University of Houston-Clear
Lake, encouraged and supported me in the study of philosophy, and
in making the decision to apply to graduate school. He has remained a
great friend and advisor. Likewise, Richard Grandy, Mark Kulstad, and
Steven Crowell at Rice University convinced me that I had something to
contribute to the intellectual world, and helped make that claim come
true with years of continuing support. My colleagues at the University of
Colorado Denver encouraged and supported my work, and many internal
grants awarded by the College of Liberal Arts and Sciences and by the
university made it possible for me to take the time to learn an entirely
new area of philosophy. Mark Bauer pushed me in both his Philosophy
of Biology class and in personal exchanges. Likewise, the international
Code Biology community provided me with the opportunity to interact
with accomplished scholars and exposed me to sophisticated ideas,
without which I would not have been able to move forward. Kathleen
Gargan arranged invitations for me to speak at national meetings of the
LifeRing Secular Recovery organization as I was trying out new ideas
about ways of understanding and addressing addiction. Finally, Matt
Pike provided me with endless hours of discussions, helpful suggestions,
and invaluable critiques of my ideas.
With respect to the production of the book, many heartfelt thanks
go to my editor, Liz Stillwaggon-Swan, whose quick work, insightful
commentaries, and sharp eye improved the manuscript immeasurably.
Esme Chapman answered questions, offered guidance, and provided a
gracious and patient presence at Palgrave Macmillan. Walter Freeman
supplied me with photos of myself that I can actually share. Finally, I
would have been nowhere without my research assistant, Rachael Boice,
who began our association as a graduate assistant, but became at many
points in the process my lifeline. She researched, read, pushed, prodded,
and kept me accountable to my plan. Without her, this book would not
exist. I am forever grateful.
x
1
Introduction – Dismantling the
Catch Phrase
1
2 Addiction
down through its neural systems to its individually acting neurons, with
their particular shapes and internal and external chemical properties,
and trace those in turn even further to their molecular makeup, we are
not going to see how the nonmental creates the mental, as we see how
bricks create a building. But there is a way to understand how the mind
and the brain are connected in a single physical system: by conceiving
of mind as an emergent process, arising from physical processes, but
with autonomous causal and other properties of its own. Assuming this
kind of emergence theory allows us to understand the mind as a process
both arising from and contributing to more complex processes, and we
can understand addiction as a process organized from simpler biological
processes within the context of larger personal and social processes. As
Terrence Deacon frames it, this discussion is going to be about “proc-
esses dependent on processes dependent on processes.”5 Adopting this
view of our physiological and psychological selves, together with some
reconfigured attendant concepts of meaning and value, will allow us to
understand addiction in a different and far more complete way than has
been done before.
This means that we can and must address addiction at many different
levels of analysis, because there is no question of one “level” based at the
“root” of addiction, no one way of understanding what causes it, how
it feels, or how it can be treated. The very concept of causation that we
will have to employ will in and of itself require serious rethinking. This
is not to deny the tremendous importance of recent scientific develop-
ments in understanding the neural pathways, neurotransmitters, plas-
ticity, and synaptic changes characteristic to addiction. Quite on the
contrary, each of the individual levels of organization at which addiction
has been analyzed is valuable, both in its own right, and in terms of its
connections to other levels of organization. This book therefore begins
with a philosophical discussion of just what addiction is, outlining the
conceptual clarifications that need to be made in order to coherently
carry forward our discussion. Chapter 1 introduces the framework that
is used to understand the interrelations of the various levels of organiza-
tion at which addiction manifests. From there, we turn in Chapter 2 to
a discussion of the latest theories of addiction as a biological process,
examining the physiological events and changes characteristically asso-
ciated with addiction. Chapter 3 addresses addiction as a psychological
phenomenon, examining some empirical theories that try to capture
which environments and behaviors predict addiction. In this chapter, we
also consider some theoretical explanations of how and why addiction
arises, focusing principally on attachment theory and trauma theory.
8 Addiction
Conversations about the worst social ills facing our age often focus on
global climate change, or on the stunning inequalities between the rich
and the poor. Many people, though, point to the escalating problem of
addiction as our most challenging, both because of its personal costs
to health and relationships and because of its economic costs to our
own generation and to that of our children. So much has been said
about addiction and its related social ills in the past few decades that
one might think that the concept is clear and our attitudes uniform. The
pervasive “war on drugs” refrain, popular over the past 40 years, seems
to suggest that everyone is on the same page. Terms such as “addiction,”
“disease,” “compulsion,” and “recovery” are thrown around as though
everyone were in agreement about both the existence and the meanings
of these occurrences in human lives. In fact, though, the ideas behind
these terms are more problematic than they first appear. In fact, each is
the subject of controversy.
Some significant ground clearing is called for, then, before discus-
sions can begin about how we as a society might want to address the
increasingly pervasive phenomenon of addiction. Let us start by consid-
ering a variety of responses to the simple question of what addiction
is. Over the past 40 years or so, a generally unchallenged and standard
view has arisen that addiction is a psychiatric disease. The Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM)1 has included addic-
tion among its categories of mental disorders since the 2nd edition
was released in 1968. Since it has come to be coded in accordance
with the World Health Organization’s International Classification of
Diseases,2 even the medical and insurance industries officially accept
the characterization of addiction as a mental disorder, or disease, along
with depression, anxiety, and schizophrenia. I say “officially,” because
10
Some Philosophical Questions (and a New Theory) 11
Substance Abuse, with the first intended to cover more serious cases
than the second. The first, as we will see, refers to behaviors that are
represented by neuroscientists in physiological models. The DSM’s
approach on the one hand seems sound, since a definition of some-
thing as diverse, complicated, and vaguely bounded as addiction would
inevitably be contentious and not much help for diagnostic purposes. At
worst, given the pervasively popular mind/brain dualistic metaphysics,
such a definition would be doomed to either circularity or incoherence.6
On the other hand, the DSM’s checklist method for determining addic-
tion by characterizing two things, neither of which is identical with
what is generally understood by “addiction,” leaves the discipline’s
highest authority in the awkward position of authorizing the diagnosis
and treatment of a generally recognized “disease” without ever saying
what it is.
The criterion method for diagnosis illuminates an important truth,
however, which is that there are no bright lines demarcating where
addiction starts and where it stops, and there is no definitive list of kinds
of addiction that might exist. Substances only begin to tell the tale, if
current research is any indication.7 First, gambling was recognized as
an activity that, as engaged in by certain people, exhibits the hallmarks
of addiction.8 Then research indicated that there could also be addic-
tion to food,9 then video games,10 then shopping, tanning, and other
non-substance-related foci characterized by similar behavior patterns.
The newest version of the DSM, the 5th edition, proposes revisions that
include adding the category “behavior addictions,”11 and foregoing the
current subcategories of substance abuse and dependence, in favor of
the new category “addiction and related disorders.” So, as research on
addiction takes off, so does the scope of the phenomenon included
under the rubric. What might count as an addiction in another 50 years
is anyone’s guess. The line keeps moving.
Even within the set of specific addictions included under the DSM
IV-TR’s list of substance disorders, there is no clear line separating
addicts from nonaddicts. According to the DSM IV-TR, the “essential
feature” of substance dependence, the more serious of the two subclasses
of substance use disorders, is “a cluster of cognitive, behavioral, and
physiological symptoms indicating that the individual continues use
of the substance despite significant substance-related problems.”12 This
description includes so much that it is of little help, although with
respect to the most general and paradigmatic cases, it seems to capture
what is wanted. The description delineates neither necessary nor suffi-
cient conditions, however, for what could be meant by “addiction.” It
Some Philosophical Questions (and a New Theory) 13
Choice theories
define addiction, and to argue against the choice model, in the next
chapter. For the present, what is important is that at the root of the
disagreement between the disease and the choice models of addiction
is the nature of the addict’s failure to control his behavior. What causes
a person to continue using a substance or participating in an activity
when that indulgence is accompanied by problems clearly related to
use? Is this failure voluntary or involuntary, or somewhere in between?
It would seem that either the addict must be compelled to continue
to use – that is, he is simply unable to stop, as those who uphold the
disease model maintain18 – or he is unwilling to do so, as choice theo-
rists believe. Even Heyman notes that, his arguments against the disease/
compulsion model of addiction notwithstanding, many addicts struggle.
Although he is quicker than many to blame addicts for their use, and to
attribute to them excuse making and self-indulgence rather than inca-
pacity, he does recognize that many times addicts hope and believe that
they will not use in the future. They make plans not to use, and yet they
do. Others, such as neuroscientists George Ainslie and John Monterosso
who have no vested interested in Heyman’s position, have observed in
addicts strong inner turmoil and intrapersonal bargaining,19 in which
sufferers agonize over their plight, recognize what is good for them and
what is bad, plan not to use, and have every intention of not using in
the future, yet, when confronted with an opportunity, repeatedly do
exactly the thing that they have judged to be bad for them. People will
often, these researchers note, even while saying such things as “I know
that I shouldn’t do this,” take a drink, light up, or place a bet. So, is the
addict compelled in these cases to indulge her addiction, or does she just
repeatedly make bad choices?
who make judgments and choices. Those who accept the choice model
seem to be committed to something like this. The level at which addic-
tive behaviors should be judged, given this kind of view, is the psycho-
logical, with the possible exception of those who think of addiction as
a “disease of the spirit.” In that (quite popular) case, more is involved
in addiction than just psychological categories and consistently poor
choices, but whatever is involved, it is something beyond physical deter-
mination. In this case, as well as in the cases of other choice models,
the proper manner of address and treatment of addictive difficulties
is through the addict’s character, his motivations, his beliefs, and his
psychological attitudes.
If, on the other hand, actions, ideas, beliefs, and emotions just are,
or are causally determined by, constantly oscillating neurons shooting
neurotransmitters at one another in a perpetual electric storm, then we
have a very different story to tell. Everything, human and otherwise,
this account suggests, is just part of the causal matrix that constitutes
the natural world. Numerous philosophers and neuroscientists have
reached this conclusion on the grounds that humans are not free, for
example, in ethical matters, but merely enjoy (or suffer from) an illu-
sion of free will.32 Taking this approach, and simply leaving the story of
addiction at the level of neurotransmitters and reward circuits, though,
would, at its extreme, leave humans in the unenviable position of being
something akin to confused zombies (that is, zombies under the illu-
sion that they aren’t). Addicts on this account would be helpless to do
anything about their problem, because not only are they compelled
by the brain changes that define their addiction; what is more, even
the causes of any desire they might have to avoid indulgence would
be determined by physical processes over which they have no control.
This view, in other words, taken to its logical conclusion, requires that
we just give up the idea that mentality is something real, with causal
powers and other characteristics of its own. On this view, there is no role
for the psychological per se, because psychological categories can always
be reduced to physical ones.
Rather than either of these alternatives, I argue throughout this book
that the body and the mind of the human being comprise one organic
whole, and that even though “parts” of the person may seem to be in
conflict with one another, particularly in addiction, the same can be
said about the mind itself. The story that addicts have to tell is often one
of deep conflict, but the conflict is between competing impulses in the
whole being. It is not a conflict that can be helpfully resolved through
accepting dualism. Neither will it be resolved, however, by trying to
22 Addiction
suggests that there is a “self” that does the organizing. This, we have just
said, is not the case. “In fact,” as anthropologist Terrance Deacon says,
“the coherent features by which the global wholeness of the system is
identified are emergent consequences, not its prior cause.”37 That is, the
organism that is the whole (the “self,” or the “top” of which we are
speaking) can’t be the controller of the system, because it is itself emer-
gent from that system.
Even with ordinary inanimate objects, according to the best that
current science can tell us, there are no ultimate parts; rather, there are
only processes.38 As was suggested above, Ladyman and Ross hold that,
contrary to standard views, “[p]recisely what physics has taught us is
that matter in the sense of extended stuff is an emergent phenomenon
that has no counterpart in fundamental ontology.”39 In every case,
macrosized objects emerge from molecules in motion. These molecules
themselves consist of atomic-level (and lower) processes, with the
“whole,” or higher-level processes, interacting with other processes in
the environment, until the point when the object’s processes disinte-
grate. It doesn’t matter whether we’re talking about mountains, skate-
boards, or solar systems. All physical things not only can be understood
as processes but moreover are so understood by those at the forefront of
our science. This idea is not new. In fact, one could say that it is as old
as the ancient Greek philosopher Heraclitus, who said, in opposition to
his Ionian contemporaries, that “it is impossible for a man to step into
the same river twice.” But the idea that processes are ultimate is one that
human beings resist intuitively, and with good reason: things around
us seem to be stable, substantive, and persisting. Thus, the process
view of reality has been resisted philosophically at least since Aristotle
asserted, contrary to Heraclitus, that all material objects consist of quali-
ties inhering in a substrate. And the process view has been resisted in
the modern world since Descartes unequivocally distinguished thinking
substance from material substance. It is just easier, personally and scien-
tifically, for us to think of the objects around us (and, by analogy, of the
microentities of which they are constituted) as things. After all, that is
what experience teaches us as children, and that is the level at which we
usually interact with things. However, it is also easier for us to think that
the sun rises and sets than it is to think that the earth rotates, but that
doesn’t make it true.
Even if it is true that all things are ultimately processes, the question
remains why this fact could possibly help provide a fuller understanding
of addiction, a phenomenon that clearly occurs at the macrolevel.
One response is that if addiction is a process, then it is a temporal
Some Philosophical Questions (and a New Theory) 25
abstractions. Surely it is the things that are arranged into patterns that
count. Quite the contrary is true, however, as the history of science
shows. Mark Bickhard reminds us of example after example of Cartesian
substance metaphysics being replaced with process models, as when
the phlogiston theory, according to which a fire-like substance was
released in processes such as burning and rusting (explaining why the
things burning or rusting became lighter) was replaced with the oxida-
tion theory. Similarly, with respect to heat, the caloric theory, according
to which the presence or absence of a substance (caloric) was said to
account for something’s temperature, was ultimately replaced with
the molecular motion analysis. What is more, those who are versed in
quantum physics tell us that there are no ultimate particles, but only
processes of quantum fields, in which what are more easily described
for purely heuristic reasons as particles are instead actually “excitations”
of parts of a quantum field. Again, we think in terms of particles, but
that doesn’t mean that they actually exist as we think of them, even
within the theories of which they are constitutive. In all these cases, it
is patterns of interactions rather than substantial things that ultimately
came to be understood as comprising the events and objects around us,
and the things that we call causes.40
It seems, then, that patterns of organization can and do have causal
efficacy. As Deacon puts it, “[b]ecause there are no material entities that
are not also processes, and because processes are defined by their organi-
zation, we must acknowledge the possibility that organization itself is
a fundamental determinant of causation.”41 On this view, at least in
one sense, the reductionistic physicalists are absolutely right: nothing
is left out once we describe every bit of matter in a system, since what
is left out is not a thing at all. What remain once material substances
are rejected are the patterns of organization ... and the constraints that
those patterns create for others, at higher and lower levels of organ-
ization. Interestingly, it is precisely because of this structure that
process ontology can’t be defended empirically: there is nothing one
could observe that could prove such an ontology to be the right one.
Everything that can be observed is just the stuff that we ordinarily think
is there. What is at issue in this case is whether the patterns themselves
actually count as entities in themselves, exhibiting causal powers attrib-
utable to their own level of specificity. The patterns do count, and they
have been overlooked for far too long, in favor of a mistaken emphasis
on the things that are involved in patterns and that are caused by them.
Substance metaphysics is unwarranted not because it has been proven
false, which would be impossible, but because its implications for trying
Some Philosophical Questions (and a New Theory) 27
The main value of a process ontology for this and other types of
analyses, however, is that it allows for a consistent conception of the
phenomenon of emergence, and hence for a way to conceive of mind as
neither distinct from, nor as reducible to, but as on a continuum with
body – one set of patterns essentially upheld by and integrated with
others, operating in mutual causal loops. This shift in conception is vital
to our having a proper understanding of the nature of organisms, and
minded human organisms in particular, but most particularly for our
purposes, it is important for our understanding the specific character
of addicted humans. Organisms are natural beings, but they are not the
same as nonliving natural beings, even when the latter are involved in
complex dynamic systems. Organisms bring about an increase in order,
or a decrease in entropy, as they self-maintain and develop, whereas it is
the natural tendency of their nonliving molecular components to move
toward a decrease in order, or an increase in entropy. The peculiar prop-
erties characteristic of living beings, as Deacon demonstrates in a metic-
ulously worked-out model, are emergent from properties of nonliving
beings.43 That this must be so is clear from the fact that the first lifelike
process “was not reproduced, it had no parent, and therefore it did not
evolve. It emerged.”44 And mind similarly emerged out of organisms
interacting with their environments. The mental and physical patterns
particular to addiction are also processes that emerge in minded organ-
isms when the conditions are just so.
As important as it is for properly understanding life itself, and, as we
will see, value and even mind, the concept of emergence is not currently
generally accepted in either philosophy or psychology, although in the
physical sciences it is held in higher favor. In philosophy, the theory
of emergence has a long and mottled history. In order to explain and
defend the perspective of this book, which depends centrally on this
concept, it will be necessary to see how emergence, as it is understood
here, is distinct from the version that quite rightly fell out of favor. So
what do we mean by “emergence”? Nothing mysterious, nothing inex-
plicable in terms of purely physical laws. In general, we shall begin by
saying that the concept of emergence used here refers to a property or
entity that exists as a function of two or more things that are themselves
of a different character from the whole. Philosopher J. S. Mill defended
this notion as long ago as 1843, although it was his student George
Henry Lewes who coined the term “emergence.” According to Mill, the
principle of the Composition of Causes (causes that work together to
create an outcome – such as bits of metal of a particular weight coming
together to make a slab of metal whose weight is the sum of the bits)
Some Philosophical Questions (and a New Theory) 29
class of things causes another class of things, which things in turn exert
causal influence on the things that caused them. Second, emergent enti-
ties and their properties would seem to be causally redundant, for since
they result from the microentities on which they rely, any causal effi-
cacy that they exhibit can actually be traced down to those microlevel
entities. So, if emergent entities and properties can be causes, it is only
because of the lower-level entities and properties to which they can be
traced. But in that case, only the lower-level things can be counted as
real. As Kim notes, one way that the above problems can be avoided is
to employ emergent properties conceptually, as levels of (mere) descrip-
tion that might be useful for gaining insight into various aspects of
phenomena in which we are interested, but not to accept them as real.
If emergent properties aren’t taken to be real, with causal efficacy of
their own, then the paradoxes and puzzles disappear. Unfortunately,
however, so do the explanations that we seek.
Another way to avoid the flaws of traditional emergence theory, and
the way that will be defended here, is to deny the foundational assump-
tion of a substance-based world in favor of a process-based one. In
particular, the kinds of processes with which we are concerned here are
those that organize around maintaining far-from-equilibrium systems,
that is, those that operate contrary to the general tendency toward
increasing entropy. A simple example of a self-maintaining system is a
candle flame:
35
36 Addiction
ability to control” his actions. The DMS-IV-TR lists four classes of drug as
capable of instituting this cycle: psychostimulants (methamphetamine,
cocaine), opiates (heroin, morphine, oxycontin), alcohol, and nicotine.
Gambling is the only activity currently listed among the addictive disor-
ders, and even that is characterized as an impulse control disorder and
not as an addiction per se. It is described, though, in terms nearly iden-
tical to those used with substance abuse and dependence, and the list is
liable to grow. Shopping, playing video games, and preoccupation with
sex are among the activities that are already being spoken of in terms of
addiction, or something very close to it.
Hedonic theories
The thing that these substances and at least one activity have in
common is that they produce rewarding experiences, and, for some
people, much greater rewards than do ordinary pleasures, such as food,
exercise, or sex. The notion of being “high” is truly significant here;
the reward experienced is above and beyond the experience of reward
achievable through those other means. What is more, the length of time
that reward is experienced through substances and activities of addic-
tion is far greater than it is for regular, nonaddictive pleasures. That is,
the pleasure of sex may be intense, but it does not last long relative to
the effects of alcohol, cigarettes, or opium. Given both of these facts,
it is not surprising that someone would want to repeat the experience.
Hedonic theories of addiction focus their attention on this feature. The
pleasure, the elevated mood, the alertness or relaxation is brought about
by the addictive substance is immediate, undeniable, and relatively long
lasting, regardless of the negative experiences that may occur in conjunc-
tion with use. Repetition of the cycle continues, because what happens
in conjunction with use does not eliminate the emotional associations of
the satisfaction that use brings. As Joseph LeDoux discovered, memory
is intimately connected with emotion; in fact, his research shows that
the emotional element of any given memory seems to be pretty much
permanent.5 When the memory itself is completely forgotten, the
emotional associations that our brains create with respect to persons,
places, things, and experiences remain intact. Even when the emotion
seems to have been extinguished, so that you no longer experience, say,
fear in the presence of a snake, it can be resurrected by certain stimuli,
such as returning to the place where you saw the snake. An addict may
in the most visceral sense continue to make the connection, “do X for
a good time,” long after she no longer remembers particular experi-
ences of use with pleasure, and even after she no longer remembers the
38 Addiction
Incentive sensitization
In many studies, subjective states of pleasure and persistence in drug
taking have not been found to be highly correlated.8 After repeated expo-
sure to a drug, some people continue to “want,” or be preoccupied with,
a drug even when they no longer even “like” its effects.9 This persist-
ence of “wanting,” or sensitization, to a drug is a significant compo-
nent of the phenomenon of addiction, and one of the main factors that
distinguishes it from drug dependence. Because of associative learning
that takes place, long after exposure to the drug has ceased, an addicted
individual can remain sensitized to cues relating to drugs and activities
of addiction, as well as to the drug or activity itself. As a result, upon
being exposed to images, places, or people associated with the drug of
choice, not to mention the drug itself, the individual is strongly moti-
vated to return to drug seeking and use. Only in some cases do addicts
additionally display an ongoing positive attitude toward their substance
or activity of choice. 10 Often, in the face of directly suffering its harms,
addicts will have a consciously negative attitude toward the object of
their addiction, but that doesn’t stop the craving for it or the seeking it
out. As with an unresolved “sensitive issue” between two people, once it
Addiction and the Individual 39
Habit
Some research has suggested, based on such observations, that the
common phenomenon of habituation, with its attendant automaticity,
could explain the phenomenon of relapse into addictive behaviors.14
This explanation does not do as much work as the motivation salience
sensitivity approach does, however, because most habits are not expe-
rienced in terms of “triggers” that seem to drive people into behaviors.
While entering the freeway might, if I’m not paying attention, result in
my arriving at my university rather than at the dentist’s office, just the
mere sight of the freeway does not set off a perseveration with respect
to the university. Habits can generally be recognized and broken with a
40 Addiction
Neuropsychological accounts
wins, more dopamine reaches the target area, the anterior cingulate part
of the cortex, in which novelty detection, reward values, and error sign-
aling are processed. When one receives the amount of reward expected,
the anterior cingulate remains unchanged, and when one expects a
reward and does not get it, or gets less reward than expected, or even
just gets it later than expected, less dopamine reaches that area of the
cortex.24 So, the theory goes, since drugs and activities of addiction
produce much more dopaminergic activity than do natural rewards,
people repeat them until they become automatic. At this point they
behave like lab rats: when the stimulus (stress, discomfort, or whatever)
is encountered, they hit the reward button.
Neuroscience of habit
Actions that are at one point considered and chosen become overlearned.
That is, certain stimuli come to habitually evoke certain responses,25
such as reaching for your toothbrush evokes the action of reaching for
the toothpaste, much more powerfully than anything else can evoke
toothpaste reaching. Addiction on this kind of theory is just a strong
kind of habituation, since it involves the brain areas involved in all
habituation.26 Since habits are characterized by insensitivity to conse-
quences (they aren’t goal directed; rather, they’re just what we do given
a certain stimulus), some say that habitual learning could account for the
transition from conscious choice to automatic action that occurs in drug
taking. This definition certainly fits the language sometimes employed
with respect to addicts and their “drug habit.” However, although these
strong implicit memory associations would explain a lab rat’s repeat-
edly pushing a lever to self-administer drugs, it is insufficient to explain
human addiction, the service of which, as we have said, often requires
significant planning far down the road from actual use.27 For this reason,
it seems that addiction cannot be just a matter of habituated responses,
although that element certainly does appear to be present.
activity of the brain in a particular area, that the specified area is more
active during that time span than other areas.
All the measuring and representing of activity through these means
is indirect; fMRI does not work by detecting the electrical activity
happening as a neuron fires, or by detecting the rapid increase or
decrease in local metabolism. Rather, it works by measuring the increase
in regional cerebral blood flow in response to the increased metabolism
that happens when a particular part of the brain is operating. These
scans measure activity in the millimeters-large size range, which means
that they are measuring the activity of several million neurons. But a
relatively large-scale picture like that, as we saw in Chapter 1 with the
movement from microlevel patterns to movement at the macrolevel,
might well be (and in fact we will say that it is) the outcome of perhaps
many lower-level patterns working against one another. So, the changes
in metabolic activity recorded are always averages, hiding the particu-
lars of what is happening at greater levels of specificity. Moreover, the
images are always superimposed on background activity, so that the
difference in activity that we attend to obliterates the context in which
this activity is happening. Scientists have no way to distinguish between
the real increase in a particular brain area’s activity and apparent activity
that may be due to some other task being done in that area at the same
time, and random activity that may be a side effect of something else.
Finally, imaging studies never speak to individual brains, but always to
“representative” brains, or statistically significant correlations between
individuals imaged. That is, these studies assume that all brains are
doing the same thing when the same parts are activated, which results
in the conclusion that the particular activity being observed must be
responsible for the experience or change correlated with it. Given what
we have said about the uniqueness of organisms, though, we ought to
be extremely conservative in reaching any conclusions about individ-
uals based on the imaging techniques used in the science that studies
addiction at the neural level.
An even more fundamental assumption made in imaging studies, but
subject to increasing resistance, is the idea that mental processes can
be localized to operations in specific parts of the brain. Connected to
the problem of the interpretation of images, but not identical to it, this
concern addresses the “modularity” assumption popularly adopted by
cognitive neuroscientists. It has long been assumed that particular tasks
are accomplished by, and particular experiences result from, activity
in a specified area of the brain. We saw this assumption operating in
the accounts of addiction given above. A number of neuroscientists,
50 Addiction
said lead author Dr. Mark Hutchinson.39 Perhaps it has been “shown
conclusively” that administration of (+)naloxone, a nonopioid mirror-
image drug, prevents the immune system’s usual amplification effect
on opiates, which should allow drugs such as morphine to be used for
pain management without the additional addiction-forming euphoric
effects occurring. At least in laboratory tests, use of this drug appreciably
reduced opioid self-administration in rats (we have already discussed
the problems with extrapolation from animal models to humans). But,
although this may stop some people who must use opioids for signifi-
cant periods from becoming dependent, what has been achieved is actu-
ally a far cry from what Dr. Hutchinson claims: “The drug (+)naloxone
automatically shuts down the addiction. It shuts down the need to take
opioids, it cuts out behaviors associated with addiction.”40 Thinking
of addiction as an induced disease prompts the misleading conclusion
that it can be obliterated with chemical tricks, just as smallpox can
be prevented with a vaccine. Although such drugs can be extremely
useful tools for avoiding and managing addiction, to think of them as
cure-alls is to miss many of the interlinking levels at which addiction
operates.
In addition to logical, practical, and oversimplification problems, the
conception of addiction as a disease faces some factual challenges as
well. As we saw in Chapter 1, psychologist Gene Heyman opposes the
disease model on the grounds that it defies psychological and sociolog-
ical research results. He points out that the vast majority of people who
ever met the criteria for drug abuse and drug dependency stopped using
drugs by midlife without treatment. This, he says, does not support
the received view of addiction as a chronic disease. The studies show
that addicts who go to clinics continue to use drugs, while those who
do not receive treatment stop. But, the people who end up in studies
about addiction are mostly people who go through treatment clinics.
This gives a skewed picture of remission rates. Also, the evidence that
Heyman produces suggests that “remission” isn’t even the proper word,
for the people who stop taking drugs seem to stay stopped, as though
it were over, rather than simply being held at bay. Finally, people who
go through clinics are much more likely to have other psychiatric or
physical problems than those who do not, and so the proper conclu-
sion to draw, Heyman says, is that when addiction persists, it is because
people don’t have access to other meaningful options. Their lives involve
barriers that other lives do not. This, though, is not a picture of a disease,
although it may be a picture of a phenomenon that accompanies other
diseases.
Addiction and the Individual 53
Behavioral theories
Picoeconomics
The issues that we have just discussed, together with some others that
we will outline below, may make us skeptical of the medical model. An
alternative approach to understanding addiction focuses on behavior.
Behavioral psychological approaches, for instance, maintain that,
while addicts may not win the struggle against their urges, ultimately
no humans are, as the disease model would have it, “out of control.”
People are always moved by their own choices. However, some people
sometimes cannot motivate themselves to choose in a particular case
what they in general want to do. We considered this in Chapter 1 under
the philosophical framework of weakness of will. On George Ainslie’s
picoeconomic approach, addicts’ capitulation to temptation is a result
of two internal motivational forces competing, with one winning out
over the other as a result of proximity in time of the potential reward.43
This theory plays a touch-and-go game with free will, given some of
its assumptions, but at the end of the day, it suggests that although
addicts (and others) capitulate in the face of immediate rewards, they do
have the power to choose otherwise. To see how this theory works, it is
first necessary to agree that any agent is constrained to choose whatever
54 Addiction
option before him promises the greatest reward. This is not to be taken
as the most rational reward, because behavioral economists, unlike clas-
sical economists, include emotions among the factors that figure in our
assessment of value. This may seem like a rather deterministic assump-
tion, but as we observed in Chapter 1, it is difficult to see why anyone
would choose what she does not think promises the greatest reward. The
way to explain repeated capitulation to relapse, Ainslie suggests, is not
to presume that the person as an integrated agent makes no decision
at all, and so is compelled, as though from the outside (whether by her
brain or something else), and is in that sense without control. Nor is the
correct view that the addict chooses freely, from the privileged point of
view of a rational observer. Rather, on Ainslie’s view, the individual is
actually understood to be, or at least to act as, two separate agents, or,
perhaps better, in terms of “one person’s successive motivational states,”
each vying to determine the agent’s choice.44
Ainslie and his colleague John Monterosso found that the fairly ubiq-
uitous phenomenon of judging immediately available goods, even if of
lesser value, as preferable to greater goods available only in the future,
exhibits itself even more sharply in substance-dependent people than
it does in the rest of us. In a series of experiments performed by a host
of behavioral economists, psychologists, and neuroscientists over the
past thirty years, it has been repeatedly shown that smokers, cocaine
and methamphetamine users, and opiate users and heavy social and
problem drinkers all discounted the future much more steeply relative
to the present than did control groups.45 Although the reward might be
shunned, or at least be less valued compared to the longer-term good
(say, of a life free of addiction), when considered from a distance, when
receiving the reward was at hand, preferences suddenly flipped. While
that is true for most of us, the difference in preferences for rewards nearer
rather than further was more pronounced among substance users. For
whatever reason, drug users and drug-dependent subjects discounted
larger but delayed rewards, even when those rewards were monetary,
something presumably having little to do with their addiction, and
even when the delays were very short, these subjects discounted rewards
much more steeply than did nonusers.
Correlation, however, as Monterosso and Ainslie are aware, is not
causation, and even if there is a causal connection, the studies conducted
say nothing about which way the connection goes. Addiction could be
either the cause or the effect of the steeper discounting of future goods
characteristic of addicts. Still, this particular type of discounting, with
preference for long-term goods remaining relatively stable as long as the
Addiction and the Individual 55
shortly available good is still at some distance, but suddenly and sharply
reversing as soon as the shortly available good becomes imminent, does
say something about substance users’ impulsivity, and perhaps suggests
something about their capacity for self-control. These unanticipated
but sharp shifts in preference, Ainslie and Monterosso argue, are best
explained by positing a conflict between two “selves” within the person,
or at least two differentially defined motivational states. The model that
Ainslie proposes presumes, first, that “mental processes are learned to
the extent that they are rewarded,”46 so people do what brings them
reward. Complicating this point, though, is that people don’t simply
prefer one reward over another, plain and simple; rather, their prefer-
ences interact with each other over time. Hyperbolic preference curves,
Ainslie says, in this clearly economically influenced model, show that
contradictory processes compete with each other for the agent’s behavior.
The self at one moment is, he says, “helpless against what future selves
may momentarily prefer,” and has no one to call upon to control those
future selves.47 Thus, although in the time subsequent to indulgence the
addict may truly value a sober future, the self is not unified temporally,
and thus the possibility exists (and the likelihood, if something is not
put in place to prevent it) that when temptation once again presents
itself, the addict’s preferences will suddenly flip, and he will find himself
once again in an addictive pattern of behavior.
Ego depletion
Another behavioral theory of addiction, introduced in Chapter 1, is the
ego-depletion hypothesis. On this hypothesis, self-control is a finite
commodity. Thus, the argument goes, if people experience too much
stress or have too many demands requiring self-control, they will have
diminished resources available for resisting temptations. A number
of experiments have been performed in this area. In one, a group of
experimental subjects were instructed to eat only healthy foods such as
radishes and celery from a buffet, while avoiding available rich desserts.
This group later persisted for a shorter time at a difficult cognitive task
than the control group, which was allowed to eat freely.48 The relevant
exercise of self-control isn’t just of a momentary nature, either, as other
studies have shown. People who have made long-term commitments to
self-control, as do dieters, for example, regularly display more depleted
levels of self-control after having to exercise significant amounts of it in
a particular situation than do those who have not made such commit-
ments. In a series of experiments that show this, chronic dieters and
nondieters were exposed to either tempting situations or nontempting
56 Addiction
episode that is anything but automatic. Unlike the disease model, which
has to see such activity as automated in some sense, the ego-depletion
model, seeing relapse in terms of a shift in judgment brought on by
exhausted stores of energy for self-control, can explain distal activity of
addiction as ends-means reasoning of the usual kind, engaged in once
the decision to use is made.
While both the picoeconomic and the ego-depletion theories do help
illuminate certain elements of addiction, they are no more complete
on their own than is the disease model, since they merely push the
central questions back a step. For instance, with respect to hyperbolic
discounting of the future, it is not clear whether it is this tendency that
brings about addiction or whether addiction brings about short-term
thinking. Some researchers have suggested a cyclical effect, in which
those who tend to become addicted more deeply discount future goods
to begin with, but then as they move into addictive patterns of behavior,
do so to an even greater degree.53 Ego depletion, it should be noted, is a
well-known phenomenon affecting everybody’s choices, and so by itself
it cannot provide an adequate account of addiction. Like the picoeco-
nomic theory, it offers reasons for why people might make the choices
that they do with respect to addictive drugs and activities. Neither,
however, explains what causes only some people to make choices in
what would be recognized as a particularly addictive pattern. Empirical
theories are good as far as they go, but they do not tell us what drives
the distinction between those who would be characterized as addicted
and those who wouldn’t.
60
The Ecology of Addiction 61
more than that will use and even abuse drugs. Mere exposure, it seems,
does not provide a satisfactory explanation of who becomes addicted,
or why. Person-centered considerations are important as well, and an
ecological approach that includes both promises even more.
If there is an answer to the question of who becomes addicted, other
than the genetically doomed, which we will show will also not suffice
as an explanation, the short answer would be “the stressed.” When an
organism is out of sync with its environment, as when the environ-
ment is unpredictable, or denies goods required for survival, such as
early nurturing, food, or water, or threatens the loss of those goods,
or when the organism faces persistent aggression and/or social defeat,
it adapts by producing chemicals that prepare it for emergency. These
chemicals, although essential for dealing with momentary stress, create
an unstable internal milieu when present chronically. In short, when
things do not go smoothly between an organism and its environment,
the organism is stressed. Long-term stress wreaks havoc on the body/
mind. An extensive literature provides evidence that emotional stress
(and particularly interpersonal or social stress for humans) is a theme
running throughout addicts’ lives, from the gestational period through
childhood and adolescence, in the transition from casual use into addic-
tion, to relapse in adults after periods of abstinence.5 Since stress seems
to be part of nearly everyone’s life, it alone cannot be identified as the
cause of addiction, yet it exerts a powerful influence on those prone to
addiction. Let us then consider the specific types and timing of the stress
that is associated with vulnerability to addiction and relapse.
such as the prefrontal cortex, last much longer.6 Since these kinds of
development do not just happen automatically, but must be stimu-
lated by internal and external environments, the types and amounts
of interaction that babies and children engage in will affect how the
emotional systems as well as other systems in their brains develop.
This development in turn influences how and with respect to which
people and things they experience pleasure and pain, attachment, and
value later in life. Early on, babies’ mental and emotional development
literally is a function of their caregiver’s rhythms. Rushes of dopamine
and endogenous opiates hit the synapses every time a baby’s regular
caregiver returns to soothe her, or reacts in an engaged way with her.
Consistent interactions of this nature stimulate the development of the
neurons that release these bonding- and pleasure-associated chemicals,
and the receptors that allow neurons to use them. Stress, though, such
as that brought on by separation from a caregiver, or by interaction with
a highly stressed or an unresponsive caregiver, reduces the amount of
the relevant neurotransmitters that is released. This in turn reduces the
development of both dopamine and opioid receptors. These two condi-
tions together imply that less of these pleasure- and attachment chemi-
cals can be used by postsynaptic neurons.7 Such truncated development
has serious consequences for the kinds of attachments and pleasures
that a person can enjoy, and ultimately for a person’s ability to regulate
her emotions and behaviors.
A substantial body of epidemiological research demonstrates that a
child’s environment in her early years strongly influences her later social
and emotional functioning. With respect to addiction in particular, chil-
dren who live through adverse life experiences have an increased statis-
tical likelihood of using illicit and prescribed drugs later, and of using
them at a younger age than do people who do not have such experiences
as children. In the highly recognized Adverse Childhood Experiences (ACE)
Study of 2003, retrospective research was done on four different age
cohorts with respect to ten categories of adverse childhood experiences
(called ACEs, these include such things as physical abuse, sexual abuse,
neglect, substance abuse or mental illness in the household, etc.). For
each ACE a person experienced, the likelihood that she would engage
in early substance use was two to four times greater than for those who
didn’t have such experiences.8 Compared to people with no such events
in their childhoods, individuals with more than five of the listed life
events were seven to ten times more likely to report drug use or addic-
tion. What is more, this study showed that there was a graded relation-
ship between the total number of ACEs and the age of drinking onset
64 Addiction
across all four age cohorts, dating back to 1900. What this means is
that the relative number of adolescents who had used alcohol increased
in proportion to the number of adverse events they had experienced
in childhood (although the absolute numbers were different in each
of the different cohorts), regardless of the generation of which they
were members. The fact that this graded number was consistent across
all the age groups shows that the effect seems to be independent of
cultural attitudes toward alcohol use, at least within the United States
and within the past century.9 From this research, it seems apparent that
adverse events experienced in childhood correlate with both likelihood
of drug use and abuse, and with earlier use of alcohol, proportional to
the number and degree of such events.
We can talk about the developmental effects that were just discussed
in another way. Consider what happens to children’s brains in terms of
memory and automated responses when they are exposed to stressful
situations, especially traumatically stressful ones. They lay down
memories of those visual, auditory, tactile, olfactory, and perhaps gusta-
tory perceptions together with the emotional inputs that are their own
brains’ reactions to those situations. The experience of father striking
mother, for example, is thus informed by the responses of the child’s
amygdala and other “limbic,” or “emotional brain center” inputs,
as much as it is by the response of the perceptual processing appara-
tuses in operation at the time. These children’s memories thus inform
their expectations, so that at the sight or sound of a similar situation,
the child’s limbic system response will charge into action, ready for
another trauma. Children who are exposed to traumatic stressors, for
this reason, according to one researcher, “exhibit profound sensitiza-
tion of the neural response patterns associated with their traumatic
experiences. The result is that full-blown response patterns (e.g., hyper-
arousal or dissociation) can be elicited by apparently minor stressors.”10
Like ex-soldiers who flinch when a FedEx helicopter shows up on the
horizon, children who are hypersensitized through trauma cannot
regulate their emotional responses to certain stimuli encountered later
in life. Hyperstressed kids experience, in addition to the ordinary effects
of drugs, the additional powerful effect of relief that such substances
provide from their uncomfortable “normal” condition. As a result,
temptation to indulge in such escapes would be difficult for them to
avoid, once they have been exposed to them, and, given the social envi-
ronments of most teens, they will be exposed to them by early adoles-
cence.11 It is no surprise, then that these are the children most likely to
use and abuse addictive substances and activities.
The Ecology of Addiction 65
beget neglectful or harsh mothers, and that has an effect on each subse-
quent generation’s ability to manage stress, and on the likelihood that
affected generations will self-soothe with substances. With regard to
human subjects as well, Greenspan and Shanker affirm the view that
early brain development is dependent in large part on the quality of a
child’s interactions with her caregiver. They say that, regardless of how
much potential a child’s brain has, unless she “undergoes very specific
types of interactive affective experiences that involve the successive
transformations of emotional experience and that are the product of
cultural practices forming the very core of our evolutionary history, that
potential will not be realized in a traditional sense.”22 The reason, on
their view, is that the potential that a child may have “does not reside
in the physical structure of the brain, but is defined only in the types
of complex interactions between biology and experience” that we have
been talking about.23 A child’s cognitive and emotional development,
and thus her vulnerability to addiction, is never a matter of her indi-
vidual brain’s genetic structure unfolding alone. Appeal to the emergent
level of personalities is essential for explaining the development of the
brain that is susceptible to addiction.
The story encompasses even more than offspring and caregiver,
however. As Paul Plotsky discussed at the Culture, Mind, and Brain
Conference held at the University of California, Los Angeles, in 2012,
it was not only the stress of separation, or even the mother’s resulting
agitated behavior that ultimately made the difference in pups’ ability
to regulate their stress responses. Plotsky had shown in earlier exper-
iments results similar to the ones we just discussed – that pups that
suffered separation or loss of their mothers early on consistently showed
later increased responsiveness to both stress and amphetamine. The
neurochemical explanation for this was that the separation resulted
in changes in dopamine transporter expression and, in turn, in signifi-
cantly increased dopamine responses to stress.24 But this change was
hypothesized to be a function not simply of the distress of the pups at
being left alone but also of the disordered behavior of the mother, which
had also suffered from the separation, upon being returned to the cage
with the pups. So far, this seems like simply another example of stressed
mothers’ effects on offspring. When the mothers in Plotsky’s experi-
ment were brought back into a two-room cage, however, rather than
into a standard single-space cage, so that they were able to build new
nests and move their pups, they returned to natural mothering, and the
effects of the pups’ “adverse event” were reversed.25 These results suggest
two things: first, that normal psychological development is not merely
68 Addiction
set involved four groups of rats reared and tested in different environ-
mental conditions: one group was reared and tested in cages; one group
was reared and tested in Rat Park; one group was reared in cages, but
moved to Rat Park shortly before testing began; and one group was
reared in Rat Park, but moved into cages shortly before testing began.
The researchers, in short, tested rats exposed to every combination of
cage/park rearing and testing. The rats were tested continually on their
choice to drink either water or a bittersweet morphine solution, with the
solution being switched out every five days for a more bitter-tasting and
less potent version. At each level of morphine solution tried, the caged
rats, whether reared in cages or in Rat Park, drank much more morphine
than did those that lived in Rat Park during the time of the testing. This
suggests that the present state of distress is more indicative of drug use
than earlier stress later compensated for, and that even an absence of
developmental stress didn’t matter when present conditions deprived
the animals of stimulation and company.
Alexander concluded from these experiments that the drug-centered
view is mistaken: addiction is not caused by drugs themselves. If it were,
living in Rat Park should make no difference in how much rats already
dependent on morphine would drink. The conclusion that Alexander
arrived at was that typical experiments test something other than what
they are intended to test. What they actually test is the effects of labo-
ratory settings on animals, rather than the animal’s natural responses
to drugs. He says that “the intense appetite of isolated experimental
animals for heroin and cocaine in self-injection experiments tells us
nothing about the responsiveness of normal animals and people to
these drugs.” Drugs themselves do not trap mammals (including people)
into addiction, according to this research. This view, as we have said, is
corroborated by the fact that most people who take drugs do not become
addicted to them. For most who imbibe in drugs or alcohol (or gambling),
the stimulation remains just an occasional recreational pleasure. If
Alexander’s team is right, the key to understanding addiction is much
more complex than mere molecular interactions – although again, it
is true that no other thing exists – only other patterns exist, but those
patterns are themselves highly efficacious. Based on these experiments,
the drug-centered view is too simplistic.
An adequate account of addiction requires thinking much more
broadly than just about the individual, or about the individual together
with a drug. We must think of the organism, as we saw in the cases
of the development of children, as operating within an environment
that includes other organisms and patterns of activity that interact in
The Ecology of Addiction 71
Genetic influence
These considerations give us reason to think that the arguments for the
“genetic disposition” to addiction are not as strong as they are believed
to be by many researchers. Although it is often said that alcoholism
“runs in families,” and that is certainly true, in the sense that if one has
an alcoholic parent, one is statistically more likely to be an alcoholic
oneself, that does not establish that alcoholism is a function of genetics.
Alcoholics who are children of alcoholics are, after all, generally raised
in the homes of alcoholics. From what we have seen above, this would
lead us to believe at the very least that the disruption that alcoholism
in the home causes would by virtue of stress alone increase the vulner-
ability of children of alcoholics to addiction. But that is not the only
thing that children of alcoholics have in common. According to the
addiction researchers who focus on genetics, “[h]eritability is the genetic
component of interindividual variation,” and the claim is that “about
50% of this interindividual variation is genetic in origin.”36 That is,
when addiction researchers say that the tendency to addiction is inher-
ited, they mean that it is genetically determined, at least halfway. The
other half is determined by environment.
There are several problems with this kind of claim. For one thing,
heritability estimates are meaningless with respect to individuals, and
so we can’t make any claims about a particular person’s vulnerability
to addiction based on this ratio. This is because, in the first place, an
individual can’t be said to vary with anything. Heritability only makes
sense with respect to a population. Reproductive and selectional pres-
sures don’t work on individuals. Population properties aren’t even a
function of the individuals in the population. They are frequency distri-
butions. For that reason, it is a category mistake to attribute a heritable
factor to an individual, although it is commonly done. In the second
place, heritability can’t be supposed to explain anything about the
specific influence of genes on a trait, because only a trait is big enough
to be selected for, and thus to make the kind of difference that can be
judged heritable or not. Traits aren’t genes, and the link between traits,
particularly behavioral traits, and genes has not been identified. At most
The Ecology of Addiction 73
we can say that there is something that can account for observed differ-
ences. Here’s one reason why: with only about 20,000 protein-coding
genes in the human genome, there just aren’t enough genes to code
for things as specific as assignable behavioral traits, much less degrees
of those behavioral traits.37 And there’s more: in order to tell whether a
trait is selected for, you would have to have a background, or an envi-
ronment, which is identical for all the organisms under consideration.
Against this background, genetics could tell us which individuals had to
have some different genes from the others, since the difference would be
conspicuous. Even then, though, it wouldn’t tell us that the individuals
with similar traits were genetically the same, because there could still be
unexpressed genetic differences. Moreover, this kind of study couldn’t
tell us why a particular trait was observable in any particular individual,
but only why there would be differences among individuals in a popula-
tion. Heritability is a statistical measure concerned with relative differ-
ences among a single population in the same environment. It is not, as
behavioral geneticist Jerry Hirsch points out, a “nature/nurture ratio” to
begin with.38
As Gene Heyman observes, however, there must be some reason why
highly trained people say that addiction is heritable, and some reason
why they say very specific things about that heritability.39 The research
literature that we saw above concluded that genetics contributes about
as much as one’s environment in determining whether a particular indi-
vidual will become an addict, given the opportunity. There are several
reasons why most addiction researchers who focus on this question have
accepted this conclusion. First, two kinds of studies have been touted for
the “strong evidence” that they are said to provide of the heritability of
addictive tendencies. Second, much excitement has been generated by
genetics in general due to the mapping of the human genome, and the
promise that that mapping seems to offer for predicting and reversing
a variety of human problems, both physical and psychological. Finally,
there is the fact that the genetic argument fosters the disease model of
addiction, to which many researchers, as we have seen, are intellectually
wed. For these reasons and perhaps many others, researchers, clinicians,
and sufferers alike have become confident that genetics dictates a lot
when it comes to addiction.
Let us consider more carefully the studies that prompt this confidence.
One kind of study used to detect the heritability of personality traits
such as proneness to addiction involves children who have been adopted
and their two sets of parents. The idea behind this sort of study is that
since children who are adopted have one set of influences contributed
74 Addiction
factors and the same kinds of experiences in the world before adoption.
So, he argues, even those identical twins separated at birth and raised
in different familial environments do not prove the genetic hypothesis.
Nurture has already had a chance to have its effect by the time of birth
and separation, so the genetic factor is not isolable even in this case.
What is more, all twins experience separation trauma when they leave
their mothers, when they leave each other, and when they leave what-
ever caregivers they may have in the time between birth and adoption.
So it would seem that both groups of twins would be equally set up for
vulnerability to addiction on that account (on this reasoning, though,
note that it would seem that all adoptive children are so set up). In the
case of twin studies, as in the case of the adoption studies, the implica-
tion seems to be not that genetics has a clear and strong influence on
the disposition to addiction, nor that it doesn’t; rather, the implication
is that addiction in human beings cannot be reduced to a single level
of analysis, either physiological or psychological. It is a higher-order
pattern that can only result from the complex and dynamic interac-
tion of an indefinite number of factors, including genetic inheritance,
physical environment, and psychological environment.
Other factors
larger study showed that having social anxiety disorder increased the
chances of someone’s having an alcohol disorder by a factor of four.48
Likewise, bipolar disorder is highly correlated with alcohol and other
drug use disorders, but in this case the relationships between the psycho-
logical and use disorders are very hard to disentangle. Researchers do
not seem to have uncovered a single causal order between them. With
respect to marijuana, for instance, it sometimes appears to increase
bipolar symptoms, and sometimes to decrease them.49 If this result
argues for anything, it is that bipolar symptoms may have different
causes in different people. Finally, in the case of major depression,
which is also highly correlated with alcohol problems, the causal arrow
seems to go in the opposite direction from that characteristic of anxiety
and ADHD disorders.50 Whereas researchers conjecture that alcohol is
used as a method of self-medicating ADHD and anxiety disorders, and
in particular social anxiety disorder, depression instead seems to be the
result of alcohol abuse. Much work has been done specifying these rela-
tionships for gender, race, economic status, and a variety of other vari-
ables, but for our purposes the main point is that addiction does not
arise in isolation. It arises in specific contexts, in relation to physical
and/or social environments at various levels of proximity, and it shows
up as both cause and effect.
Another thing to consider prior to an examination of cultural influ-
ences on addiction is that the social world in which we are embedded
is different at different times in our lives, regardless of gender, race, or
economic status. This fact is important to understanding the patterns
of addiction. When children are quite young, as we have seen, their
parents are experienced as virtual extensions of themselves. Everything
that their parents do or do not do affects the child’s own stress and
reactivity levels. When they become adolescents, their peers become
more influential elements of their environments. Even the popular press
has made it known how much they conform to the behavior of their
friends, even more than do adults. Scientific American’s 60-Minute Mind
podcast, for instance, reports on research that suggests that adolescents’
weight is correlated with that of their friends, and not just because they
choose friends who are like them in body type but also because others’
behavior influences their own, to the extent that they gain and lose
weight based on the behaviors of those around them.51 While generally
there is no reason to correlate something such as the influence of friends
on specific behaviors to something as serious as DMS-IV-TR-defined
dependence, since most people who try smoking or drinking or other
drugs will not become addicted, absent any independent evidence for
78 Addiction
Individuals are both created by and give rise to their cultures. Not only
does no one become an addict in a vacuum, but also, in addition to
one’s physical environment and immediate social interactions, human
addiction takes place within a larger culture. As sociologist James Barber
puts it, “[w]e learn to drink, smoke, and take drugs because others show
us not only how to do it but also how to enjoy it.”1 The relation of
addiction to culture is, like all the other levels of analysis that we have
considered, dynamic and complex, and different in every case. In many
of these cases, specifically within the past few hundred years, psychoac-
tive substances and addicted populations have been, and continue to be,
both the cause of and the cure for many of society’s problems. Without
addicted laborers, some of whom were paid in kind for producing the
very substance to which they were addicted, the global markets in
tobacco and caffeine products, such as coffee and tea, could not have
arisen, not to mention the smaller but significant opium, cannabis, and
coca markets.2 The use of these substances played a large role in keeping
laborers laboring, and markets growing. Today, given the DSM-V’s inclu-
sion of food addiction among its listed disorders, we might add the fast-
food market to the list. Low wage-earning fast-food workers often take
advantage of readily available cheap and fast food, saturated with fat
and salt, because it suits both their schedules and their incomes. The
discounts or free food that they often receive at such jobs suggest that
the corporations for which they work find the arrangement mutually
convenient.
79
80 Addiction
political, and cultural environment that gives rise to both the need and
the ability to escape from stressful conditions in the first place.
A cultural construct
The very notion of addiction only became popular as the medical and
insurance industries grew and prospered, and consumerism rose to the
greatest heights it had ever seen. Sociologist Gerda Reith argues that
“[t]owards the end of the nineteenth century, a convergence of inter-
ests between the industrial nation-state and the medical profession
coalesced into a (fragmentary) discourse that postulated a state of ‘addic-
tion’ as a ‘disease of the will,’ and created a new type of individual –
and ‘addict’ – as a distinct identity.”10 As American culture became ever
more industrialized, she says, “[t]he bourgeois emphasis on industrial
productivity and labour discipline elevated the properties of self-regu-
lation and control to personal as well as political virtues, and also gave
rise to an increasing intolerance of behavior regarded as potentially
disruptive.”11 In order for productivity to continually grow, it became
increasingly important for workers to self-regulate their consumption
of certain products. Whatever else they did, workers would have to be
reliably functional in increasingly complex social environments. The
implication of this seems to be that it is the potential for disruption
of socioeconomic flow, rather than the quantity of consumption itself,
that establishes a substance’s or activity’s character as addictive, or the
agent as an addict. In fact, increased quantity of consumption of all
types of goods has consistently been pressed, and has surged radically
over the past one hundred years. Identity itself has come to be created
through one’s patterns of consumption: who one is, is a fluid construct
rather than an essence, a matter of choices rather than of nature.12 An
identity based on choice, though, although it is apparently an identity
created through freedom, is nevertheless based on a freedom of a very
particular, and a very peculiar, sort.
In Daniel Bell’s language from forty years ago, we see in the “cultural
contradictions of capitalism” a “fundamental conflict between the
ascetic values of the protestant work ethic” on the one hand, and “the
hedonistic values of instant gratification that come with capitalist
consumerism” on the other.13 As has become commonly recognized,
Americans, like members of many affluent nations, are bombarded
regularly with advertisements encouraging indulgence in everything
from chocolate to vacations to automobiles and jewelry (“every kiss
begins with Kay”). Meanwhile, and sometimes within fifteen seconds,
84 Addiction
book, The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness.
Arrests for marijuana possession, despite its relative innocuousness
(particularly in comparison to prescription drugs), accounted for nearly
80% of the growth in drug arrests in the 1990s.18 Alexander’s point here
is that it isn’t just anybody who is getting arrested. In the vast majority,
those who comprise these incarcerated populations are people of color.
A commonly cited statistic is that, while African American males consti-
tute about 6% of the general population, they constitute about 35% of
the prison population. And that is just one subgroup of the dispropor-
tionally incarcerated. These populations with high incarceration rates
exhibit less stable and fewer permanent relationships, a situation created
by the incarceration itself. This is not to mention associated phenomena
such as less available stable work and inferior jobs for those who have
been incarcerated, as well as increased exposure to violence and poor
nutrition. These circumstances result in living situations marked by high
levels of stress for everyone involved, which, as we saw in Chapter 3,
render not only adults but also children in such environments more
vulnerable to drug use and abuse.
Further exacerbating the problem is the prevalence of the drugs them-
selves and their attendant dangers in lower socioeconomic neighbor-
hoods. Although individuals in middle and upper socioeconomic classes
enjoy the use of drugs, they do not wish to have them widely avail-
able in their own neighborhoods. It has been argued for decades now
that drug use, drug sales, and addiction have affected poor and minority
communities more harshly than they have white and more affluent
communities, despite the fact that middle-class whites are significantly
more likely than blacks to use illegal drugs and alcohol.19 Reasons for
this include the same race and class discrimination that have resulted in
certain groups being blamed for other social ills, including welfare and
food stamp abuse, and child neglect and abuse, despite available statis-
tics to the contrary. In the case of addiction, we can agree with William
Kornblum that some of the reasons that poor and minority populations
are perceived to have worse addiction problems than others is that the
sale of drugs has typically been located in poorer, more densely popu-
lated areas. Why? For one thing, when individuals are crowded tightly
together, any one person’s activities are less likely to be noticed, When this
crowding reflects a difference in wealth, rather than simple geographic
limitations, people in such situations are also, due to their poverty, likely
to be less valued than their richer counterparts, and therefore less likely
to receive resources dedicated to improving health and safety. Another
reason that drug activity and addiction have affected poor areas more
The Culture of Addiction 87
harshly than rich ones is the lack of opportunity for job training and
education for those already poor in resources and respect. As the United
States has transitioned into an information-based economy, changes in
production methods have often “deprived low-income minority indi-
viduals of better-paying, more secure industrial employment,” leaving
them with little hope and little to do.20 Drug distribution was one of
the few ways in which many people could provide for themselves and
their families, and the option of moving away from such “vice districts”
remained unavailable to most inhabitants. By the 1980s, the ghettos and
immigrant neighborhoods of New York City, Los Angeles, Washington,
DC, and Miami had become loci of the cocaine and crack trades, which
brought with them high levels of homicide and addiction. “The dispro-
portionate involvement of minority and recent immigrant groups in
the illegal drug industry,” Kornblum explains as inextricably linked to
“historical patterns of vice market concentration in stigmatized, segre-
gated communities.”21
It has been argued widely for at least forty years that police forces were
created and continue to exist for the purpose of controlling people of
lower classes.22 While law enforcement often turns a blind eye to infrac-
tions committed by members of the middle and especially the privileged
class, it responds to the socially unacceptable behavior of the poor and
disempowered by “cracking down,” which results in more incarcera-
tion and the perpetuation of the cycle that creates the need for illegal
drug use and distribution and other vice markets. Such tightening of
enforcement and increasing of penalties does nothing to alleviate the
variables that produce the value and even perceived need for drug use.
The stresses, trauma, and hopelessness of living in poverty and discrimi-
nation remain just as they were. In fact, “cracking down” makes all of
these things worse. According to Alexander, the massive incarceration
of largely people of color in connection with drug use operates together
with “a web of laws, regulations, and informal rules, all of which are
powerfully reinforced by social stigma”23 to confine certain people to
the margins of mainstream society and to deny them access to the main-
stream economy. Drug enforcement policy creates a subclass, which
further defines the concepts both of addiction and of whole swathes of
the population. This approach of isolating people of color (and people of
lower socioeconomic classes in general, we can extrapolate), Alexander
charges, operates as a “stunningly comprehensive and well-disguised
system of racialized social control.”24
It’s not just control of recognized marginalized groups that the
construct of addiction achieves, however. The social control extends
88 Addiction
to video gaming to eating to sex to viewing porn can now land you in
treatment if you’re sufficiently rich. For the poor, the “treatment” is
often jail.
In the event that the argument from the ever-expanding types of
culturally specific addiction is not persuasive that addiction is at least in
part a social construct, consider another sort of case. That the astounding
increase in levels of addiction in the West is the result of social attitudes
as much as it is the result of expanding medical insights seems plain
from looking at the contrast between the American response to heavy
indulgence (in this case, in alcohol) and the South Korean response. In
South Korea, heavy drinking by men is “encouraged, even demanded,
in certain social contexts.”25 While social norms and mores discourage
drinking by women and solitary drinking by men, South Korean culture
supports regular drinking contests in bars after work, after which many
contenders have to be carried home. Men who indulge in this manner
are not considered addicted, and drinking in this manner is not consid-
ered a problem. As it happens, even with this high level of consumption,
due to the social structures that constrain the time and circumstances
of a man’s drinking, statistics show that the dependence-to-abuse ratio
is reversed in South Korea relative to the West. That is, although a larger
number of men abuse alcohol in South Korea than in the West, a smaller
percentage of them become physiologically dependent on it than do their
Western counterparts. This suggests that not only do cultures construct
the concept of addiction differently but, moreover, some would not use
the concept of addiction at all, or develop any of the practices or institu-
tions that accompany its recognition as an individual problem requiring
treatment. Different cultural conceptions of the place of excessive indul-
gence within the overall system of customs and practices determine in
large part where there even exists such a thing as addiction. Moreover,
those very social conceptions, norms, and traditions themselves seem to
have a significant influence on the degree to which the population of
users becomes dependent on substances.
Martin Levine and Richard Troiden argue that some addictions have
been completely culturally constructed.26 Consider, for example, the idea
of the sex addict. Levine and Troiden argue that the concepts of sexual
addiction and sexual compulsion are based in cultural beliefs regarding
extrarelational sex that became more openly widespread in the late
1970s and ’80s. Because those who came of sexual maturity in the sexual
liberation movement of the ’60s and ’70s were seen as a threat to social
cohesion, the sexual behaviors developed during that period and shortly
thereafter were construed as deviant by those adhering to traditional
90 Addiction
standards. Levine and Troiden say that, rather than being varieties of
medical conditions, “[s]exual addiction and compulsion refer to learned
patterns of behavior that are stigmatized by dominant institutions.”27
On their view, it is political and social agendas that created the possi-
bility for this kind of addiction to enter the ontology and linguistic
conventions as disorders in need of treatment. Whether this behavior
is portrayed as an addiction or a compulsion, or an impulse control
disorder (these are described slightly differently), Levine and Troiden
argue that the diagnosis rests on “culturally induced perceptions of what
constitutes sexual impulse control.”28 Broad differences characterize the
attitudes and practices of different cultures and different ages. In “sex-
positive” cultures, such as Mangaia, for instance, casual sex with many
different partners is normal. It is the religious emphasis on low sexual
desire and activity that would be seen as abnormal. “There is nothing
intrinsically pathological in the conduct that is presently labeled as
sexually compulsive or addictive,” assert Levine and Troiden. “[T]hese
behaviors have assumed pathological status only because powerful
groups ... define them as such.”29 Characterization of “excessive” sexual
behavior as a disease has its utility as well, though, as we have seen in
the popular press, in exculpating wandering partners of moral wrong.
When politicians and celebrities have found their careers jeopardized by
sexual infidelity, they have in recent years found it convenient to blame
their behavior on an addiction to sex.
The implications of portraying certain types of activities or substance
use in terms of an addictive disease, though, are double-sided. On the
one hand, characterizing people as addicts doubtless creates the poten-
tial for an autonomy-robbing power differential between addicted
people and nonaddicted ones. On the other hand, though, because of
this very diminution in autonomy, the attribution of addiction also
provides an excuse, an escape from responsibility. Being “diagnosed”
is used both as a way of demonizing some individuals, a way of sepa-
rating them from the “healthy” folk, and as a way of releasing them
from responsibility for certain behaviors. The flexibility of the term
serves to make every kind of problem potentially an “addiction,” which
allows the legal system to construe treatment as either or both punitive
and/or rehabilitative, depending on the case. As Gene Heyman points
out, this dual implication of characterizing addiction as a disease existed
before either the legislation governing addictive drugs or the science
behind the medical model existed: “from the start, addiction invited
both legal prohibitions and the impulse to cure it.”30 The very meaning
of admitting to or being accused of being an “addict” carries import
The Culture of Addiction 91
The sort of passive endorsement that we find for locating relief in mind-
altering substances in many cultures sounds not so different from the
“happy hour” created in the 1960s in the United States that became
“binge weekends” for working adults who entered into competitive,
faceless positions in giant corporations. It seems that after-work and
weekend binge drinking and eating, officially loudly bemoaned, serve to
maintain social order, largely by promoting apathy in the face of aliena-
tion, income inequity, and unfulfilling work. When people are either
escaping through indulgence or are hung over and remorseful as a result
of it, serious attention and meaningful change is unlikely to be brought
to bear on the oppressive religious, social and/or economic inequities.
On this view, in which everyone is left on their own to navigate a path
of providing themselves with housing, food, transportation, health-
and childcare, in uncertain circumstances, it is easier to blame those
who cope with the stresses of everyday life by numbing themselves in
some way than it is to take a hard look at the structural and political
arrangements that create the need to self-soothe. In such an environ-
ment, it is much easier to “treat” those who falter in the productivity
cycle by putting them into treatment or jail than it is to take seriously
the circumstances that make life so difficult. As we have noted, appeal
to the disease model, to the power of the drug, and to the “addictive
personality” shifts attention away from any questions that might be
raised about social contributions to people’s misery and self-medication
and distraction, allowing instead everything from drugs to gambling to
video games to shopping to just about anything that one might do or
ingest, to become an object of certain “defective” people’s obsession.
This approach, however, has little to offer toward improving the lot of
the addicted. As noted by Paul Hayes, professor of Drug Policy at the
London School of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine, despite the cultural
narrative to the contrary, “the experience of the overwhelming majority
of addicts” is that “social isolation, economic exclusion, criminality and
fragile mental health preceded their drug use rather than being caused
by it,” and, he argues, until this is understood, we “are doomed to
misdirect our energy and resources toward blaming the outcasts and the
vulnerable for their plight rather than recasting our economic and social
structures to give them access to the sources of resilience that protect the
rest of us.”46
But there’s something even more sinister than institutionalized racism
and classism behind the shifting nature of addiction in the worldwide
96 Addiction
market. As is often the case in seeking causes of crimes and social ills,
it is illuminating to follow the money. In following the money, we find
that, for instance, keeping marijuana illegal has been a priority of certain
organizations that benefit from the financial success of certain prescrip-
tion drug companies. While the general tide of public opinion over the
past several years has turned in favor of relaxing marijuana laws, the
Community Anti-Drug Coalition of America (CADCA), for example, a
vocal opponent of the legalization of marijuana, and other groups at the
forefront of opposition to relaxing marijuana laws, tellingly “derive a
significant portion of their budget from opioid manufacturers and other
pharmaceutical companies.”47 According to a confidential financial
disclosure from the Partnership for Drug-Free Kids, the organization’s
largest donors include “Purdue Pharma, the manufacturer of OxyContin,
and Abbott Laboratories, maker of the opioid Vicodin. Perhaps worse,
Alkermes, a major supporter of the CADCA, makes an opioid, Zohydrol,
which is reportedly ten times as strong as Oxycontin.”48 When forty-two
drug-prevention groups protested approval of Zohydrol, neither CADCA
nor the Partnership for Drug-Free Kids joined the protest. So it seems
that the political urgency of keeping marijuana illegal may derive from
something other than concern for the health and well-being of the
populace.
A good place to look for the source of that urgency might be the
multibillion-dollar pharmaceutical industry. America constitutes only
5% of the world’s population, but consumes 50% of the world’s phar-
maceuticals, and 80% of the world’s narcotics. In 2000, 290 people per
day (106,000 per year) died as a result of their prescription drugs.49
According to the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC),
44 people die in America every day from prescription opioid overdose,
three times as many as die from heroin, meth, and cocaine combined.
Although this rate is rising steadily (the CDC reports a 117% increase
from 1999 to 2012), addiction to these drugs does not have the same
meaning in our culture as addiction to alcohol or other drugs does.
Against these perceptions, however, consider that in 2012, drug over-
dose was the leading cause of accidental death, and 53% of these
deaths were caused by pharmaceuticals. Of those deaths, 72% involved
prescription painkillers. These are not the drug overdoses that we see
in mainstream media, and drug overdose has not yet been publicly
discussed as a serious public health problem. At least there has been
no lessening in the prescribing and selling of these drugs.50 The most
plausible explanation for the continuing proliferation of these drugs,
and the addiction and deaths that come with them, is that they mean
The Culture of Addiction 97
big money, and big money means power. In 2010, Novo Nordisk, Inc.,
for example, saw $2.67B in sales, while by 2009 Bristol-Myers Squibb’s
revenues had a reached $18.8B. But it is the astronomical rate of rise in
these companies’ revenues that is most striking: Eli Lily’s profits, for
instance, rose from $875M in 2003 to $23B in 2010. As a result of the
Medicare Prescription Drug Plan of 2003, the campaign that was led by
a group of legislators, each of whom received hundreds of thousands of
dollars in campaign dollars from pharmaceutical companies, “the phar-
maceutical industry realized an eight billion dollar increase in profit.”51
While it would be going too far to say that our government and the
pharmaceutical industry operate in a conspiratorial way to foster addic-
tion and then blame the addicts for it, it surely would be reasonable to
assert that when an industry has the capacity to influence major policy
decisions, the role of that industry in the social phenomenon of increas-
ingly endemic addiction cannot be ignored.
In 2011, 6.9 million people were under corrective control in the United
States. As we have seen, as many as 80% of those incarcerated were
considered problem users or addicts of alcohol or other drugs. Not all
addictions, though, are equally likely to land a person in prison, or cause
him to be blamed or ostracized. Addiction to cigarettes is not signifi-
cantly correlated with incarceration, nor is video gaming addiction,
food addiction, or gambling addiction. For many of these “diagnosable”
addictions, there is not even much social stigma attached, particularly,
and tellingly, with respect to addiction to work. In many cases, it is the
social meanings of particular drugs and activities that determine whether
engagement with them is associated with blame, shame, and confron-
tations with the law. The primary drugs being used by the adolescents
in the Lend study in Colombia, for example, were marijuana, followed
by basuco, which is similar to crack, as well as cocaine, inhalants, and
street-supplied pills, in short, the drugs of the poor and the young.52 The
drug that to which the Pakistanis were overwhelmingly addicted was
opium, a drug about which Ali says that if you “[v]isit any shop, you will
see beggars, domestic servants, truck drivers and stray children queuing
to purchase this pernicious narcotic,” whereas better-off young people
tend instead to use LSD, marijuana, and morphia.53 In the United States,
marijuana and heroin are cheaper to access than cocaine and prescrip-
tion drugs. In general, the “addiction problem,” and the incarceration
that attends it, seems disproportionately associated with those drugs
98 Addiction
and activities indulged in by the young and the poor. To some degree, it
appears to be the meanings of these substances, as well as of the activi-
ties of gambling and certain kinds of sexual activity, that seem to drive
policy, rather than hard scientific evidence about their relative dangers.
In a 2013 study, obesity accounted for 18% of deaths among adults
between 40 and 85 in America, but since unhealthy weights have
become the norm, it goes virtually unmentioned in public policy, except
for requiring suppliers of unhealthy foods to inform consumers.54 No
public policy regulates the behavior of the consumers of food. At the
same time in the United States, where marijuana has been legalized
in several states, and decriminalized in others, or legalized for medical
use, official US policy nevertheless keeps it on Schedule 1, among the
most dangerous drugs available. But surely this discrepancy cannot be
accounted for by scientific research. In fact, the research argues the other
way, as we can see from the obesity case alone. Policy seems to be driven
by some other force. And there are consequences. Kornblum argues that
categorizing marijuana in this way “helped prepare the way for far more
troublesome drug epidemics in minority communities like Harlem.”55
His argument is that portraying drugs such as marijuana as on a par
with other Schedule 1 substances, since marijuana and some others of
these drugs seem to have few ill effects, leads to the impression that the
government’s cataloging system should be ignored. Other drugs deemed
sufficiently dangerous to be categorized as Schedule 1 drugs, many will
reason, might be just as safe to use. At the same time, categorizing large
numbers of substances as among the most dangerous brings about the
incarceration of large populations for possession of drugs that could
be legalized, decriminalized, taxed, and regulated. As Kornblum says,
“the public at large has supported prohibitions it knows are not effec-
tive because to do so gives people assurance of a moral order however
symbolic,” and however contributory to “the stigma born by racially
distinct people in America.”56 The problem here is that whether drugs or
activities are considered addictive, and therefore are outlawed, is often
much more influenced by social and political leanings and dogmas than
by research findings, or what sociologist Howard Becker once called
“politically inconvenient scientific knowledge.”
Now consider the purported addiction popularly discussed in the
United States in the 1980s and ’90s, but which seems to have lost
momentum recently in the addiction literature: the addiction to work.
This one seems not to fit the mold of other “addictions,” with respect to
social and political attitudes, at least not in highly competitive societies.
Certainly we don’t find workaholics at the forefront of the incarcerated
The Culture of Addiction 99
101
102 Addiction
Concepts
On the view that we have been elaborating, meanings for biological enti-
ties are a function of experience, and experience is always a matter of
interactions between the particular internal and external environments
of organisms. In our pursuit of an understanding of meaning making
and its role in addiction, we are seeking an account that accords with
all that we have come to understand about how human organisms, and
in particular, addicted humans and those who care about them, under-
stand the objects, places, and words involved in the experience of an
addictive pattern. In seeking a theory of meaning that accounts for the
phenomena observed in addiction, it seems important to consider not
just conceptual issues but also the empirical data regarding how our
concepts are built and what that says about their structure and function.
First, since minds are not separate from the world, but are emergent
from it, our conception cannot be that meanings are copies in the mind
of things in the world. The term “copies” implies separation between the
representation and the represented – and two different media in which
those two things exist. That is just what does not exist on the present
account. Second, because of the whole-brain massively recurrent and
dynamic processing from which meanings emerge, they are necessarily
always emotion- and history infused and peculiar to each individual.
Moreover, meanings are not static things, but rather are constantly
evolving processes. The same object or place (or word) can come to have
different meanings to the same person over the course of a day or a
year, and does, as she transitions into or out of addiction. This happens
without the implication that anything correspondingly changes in the
world, or in her perceptual apparatus, although it is true on another
level that everything in the world, including individuals’ perceptual
apparatuses, is always changing. Such change needs an explanation.
In developing our understanding of how addicts conceive of the world,
and how those conceptions can shift, we would do well to keep an eye
110 Addiction
[w]hatever the fidelity may be, neural patterns and the corresponding
images are as much creations of the brain as they are products of the
external reality that prompts their creation. When you and I look
at an object outside ourselves, we form comparable images in our
respective brains. We know this well because you and I can describe
the object in very similar ways, down to fine details. But that does
not mean that the image we see is the copy of whatever the object
outside is like. Whatever it is like, in absolute terms, we do not know.
The image we see is based on changes which occurred in our organ-
isms – including the part of the organism called brain – when the
physical structure of the object interacts with the body. The signaling
devices located throughout our body – in the skin, in the muscles,
in the retina, and so on – help construct neural patterns which
map the organism’s interaction with the object. The neural patterns
are constructed according to the brain’s own conventions, and are
achieved transiently in the multiple sensory and motor regions of
the brain that are suitable to process signals coming from particular
body sites.11
To make all this organizing and meaning making work, babies have
to be motivated to interact with the world, given the significant effort
and overcoming of fear that the task requires, and they are so moti-
vated – through the same reward system that is activated when drugs
of addiction are ingested. They begin to want to interact with the world
because they get positive reinforcement from doing so. “Right from the
beginning,” note psychiatrist Stanley Greenspan and philosopher Stuart
Shanker, in language very well suited to our dynamic complex systems
analysis, “caregivers and infants are engaged in rhythmic, co-regulated
patterns that enable the infant to begin attending to the outside world.”18
Positive and calming feedback provides rewarding experiences for the
child, who otherwise, as we saw in Chapter 3, becomes stressed by the
demands of a highly stimulating and unregulated environment. And
rewarding feedback, as has by now become our mantra, evokes repeti-
tion of the rewarding activity. Such feedback loops become internalized
in the development of concepts as expectations develop and operate in
the activities of perception and response.
Initially, infants experience not the world of things, activities, and
sensations that adults are accustomed to, but rather “a limited number
of global states, for example, calmness, excitement, and distress.”19
Eventually, through soothing interactions in ordinary cases – and
this will show how disruptive the stress we discussed in Chapter 3
can be – these global states become increasingly differentiated and
elaborated. According to Greenspan and Shanker, there is at first in
an infant’s experience just discomfort and distress, then comfort and
calm. Later, there is experience of a discomfort of a particular kind,
followed by comfort of a particular kind. The infant, if responded to
reliably, comes to recognize the caregiver as associated with relief and
comfort, as something good. She develops expectations and emotional
responses based on the caregiver’s responses and emotional state.
As we have seen, the very development of infants’ nervous systems
is shaped by the character of their interactions with a caregiver. The
patterns that form the child’s mind are constrained by the larger ones
that form her emotional environment. As a result, people who experi-
ence heightened stress or trauma in their family relations as children
live in a very different world from those who experience calm and
pleasant nurturing. And, of course, everyone’s sensory apparatuses and
emotional processing systems develop uniquely, with differing degrees
of sensitivity. This means that the tenor of experiences will be different
in different individuals. The same physical encounters carry different
meanings: “a hug feels tight and secure or tight and frightening; a surface
Addiction and Meaning 115
feels cold and aversive or cold and pleasant; and a mobile looks colorful
and interesting or colorful and frightening.”20
The world that each of us inhabits is, then, fundamentally subjective
and emotional, as well as physical and full of potential; it is a function
of mobile, invested, interested, and emotionally experiencing organ-
isms, as well as of its own physical features. Concepts of the meaningful
things in our world are carved out of regular co-occurring sense experi-
ences and their accompanying emotional responses. In physical terms,
repeated encounters with individual objects result in similar neural firing
patterns. But these firing patterns do not include merely informational
inputs from perceptual receptors. “Wired together” with perceptual
information are signals coming from “upstream,” from the emotional
centers in the brain, and from patterns already established. So, the world
that begins by being experienced as undifferentiated global emotional
states comes, as a baby gains more experience, to be differentiated into
things and people and activities to which emotional responses are also
associated.21 The more a given set of inputs and responses fire together,
the more they are inclined to do so, and the more “this type of thing”
comes to be carved out from and related to all the other things included
in the child’s world. As more things come to be distinguished in the
world, one’s concepts become more precise. What is more, as we have
seen, the character of any individual’s responses to the things that he
comes to distinguish in the world is also influenced by others’ responses,
particularly the responses of caregivers in early life, but, as for example
with teenagers, the responses of peers as well. Meaning making, then,
turns out to be essentially social, as well as emotional and perceptual,
rather than syntactical and symbolic, although we can make and mean-
ingfully use symbols as well. The social and physical environments
thus become integrated into an individual’s world, and shape her atti-
tudes, beliefs, and behaviors with respect to any specific stimulus. The
important thing is that meanings are not merely the result of or for
the purpose of processing information; instead, they result from and
perform profoundly important roles in living and acting in a world with
others.
As people move into addictive patterns, they learn the special meanings
of their substance(s) or activity of choice in the same way that anybody
learns meanings: through the emotion-laden experiences that they
have with it. At least at first, the cycle of heightened pleasure, elevated
116 Addiction
beyond what any natural reward could bring, tells the addict that the
drug or activity is a good thing, as are its associated sounds, tastes, sights.
Remember that, since meanings are portrayals of the world, rather than
information received from the world, they will be limited and perspec-
tival, and in some instances starkly incorrect. The good that comes to
be included in the concept of the drug or activity reinforces the impor-
tance connected with it, and thus reinforces the seeking behavior that all
natural goods instigate in humans and other animals, but more so, since
this good is experienced as more powerful than any natural one. As we
have seen, at the physical level, activities and substances that result in a
greater than expected availability of dopamine in the relevant brain areas
are associated with the perception of large rewards, while other activi-
ties and substances, such as food, sex, or solving a puzzle, which result
in relatively less dopamine availability, are perceived to carry smaller
rewards. And these reward experiences and expectations contribute to the
formation of the concepts of their associated activities and substances.
The “special” substances and activities therefore come to have a different
meaning for those who experience them as especially satisfying relative to
other activities or substances. Those substances and activities that arouse
a greater reward response will be conceived as better than others, even if
one “knows” through previous learning, perhaps less viscerally powerful
learning experiences, that they are bad in other respects. Further, not only
do some substances and activities operate to create an overabundance
of reward experience-generating chemicals, but additionally, since indi-
viduals are unique, they will respond differently to each of the dopamine-
burst-creating chemicals and activities. This means that people who
become addicted will have preferences not only for “addictive” things but
also for specific things – they will develop substance or activity preferences.
Naturally, what that particular substance or activity then comes to mean to
the susceptible individual is fundamentally different in many ways from
what it means for others, including positive expectations, importance,
relation to other experiences, and relative value to other activities, as well
as its call for action in specific circumstances. Again, as we have said,
the larger social milieu in which one is exposed to rewarding substances,
activities, or experiences has significant influence on the meaning that
that thing comes to have for an individual or group. Remember the heavy
drinking bouts among Korean men that, due to the social context of their
occurrence, are not amenable to being understood as addictive behaviors,
however unhealthy they might be.
Furthermore, since our concepts hang together to form our individual
worlds, all meanings change (at least to some degree) together. A feature
Addiction and Meaning 117
When an addict has had it, when she is “sick and tired of being tired,”
“hits bottom,” or, as Gene Heyman argues is the case most of the time,
when she is motivated by professional, health, family, or financial
concerns, she will transition out of addiction.22 She will come to see her
addictive behavior differently. In fact, she will come to see everything
differently. This has been called in some frameworks a “spiritual awak-
ening,” and surely it must feel like it, because it is a revolution in one’s
conceptual framework, a complete gestalt shift. It would not even make
118 Addiction
the original gestalt-type shift, the meanings that constitute the addict’s
world can return to the structure in which the substance or activity of
choice takes a central place and influences all associated concepts. This
may result in the individual’s having thoughts totally unconnected to
the substance or activity of addiction (such as “I hate my boss, my job
is overwhelming, I’m so exhausted ... ”), but which lead nevertheless to
the experience of world shift, in which return to use is rated as pref-
erable to abstinence. Anticipation of imminent relief, satisfaction, or
pleasure, as the behavioral economist tells us, predictably evokes this
response, and the more so, the more the anticipation is entertained, and
the more proximal it appears. These facts about our concepts and beliefs
operating unconsciously can be frightful for those struggling with addic-
tive patterns, since they imply that a person’s concept of her preferred
substance or activity might be associated with many triggers that she
has never thought of. Knowing this fact, however, seems to provide a
counterbalance to the power of unconscious effects, for it suggests that
anyone can work daily toward consistently increasing awareness of her
own associations, and thus her own vulnerabilities.
The view of meaning that has been presented in this chapter has been
expressed in light of its main opponent, the atomic linguistic theory.
Although it seems to stand up well in the face of familiar objections, not
all of them have been adequately answered. A couple of issues remain.
One we have already encountered: according to those who hold some-
thing like the atomistic informational view of meaning, prototypes
and meaning holism are doomed from the start because the meaning
of anything affects the meaning of everything. So, the argument goes,
anytime anybody learns anything new, or one meaning is changed in
any way, all meanings are thereby changed. This is seen as unaccept-
able on the grounds that no one would ever have a firm grip on his
own beliefs and desires, much less could two people ever understand
each other. I have expressed these results as features of the perspective,
rather than as bugs in it, for it is a fact in need of an account that our
concepts are constantly changing, subtly shifting, depending on the
context in which we consider them, and so are the beliefs and desires
that are constructed of them. Within constantly changing internal and
external contexts, our conceptual state space (the “space” within which
concepts can be carved out) is constantly morphing, although not to the
extent that our opponents might want to make us think. Our concepts
120 Addiction
122
Phenomenology and Its Implications 123
When Bill Wilson took his first drink, it “produced in him instant feel-
ings of completeness, invulnerability, and an ecstasy that approached
the religious.”1 Similarly, when philosopher Owen Flanagan was twelve
years old and had his first drink of hard cider, what he remembers is
an immediate, powerful feeling: “I felt release from being scared and
anxious. It was good. I did not know, I would not have known to say if
asked at the time, that I was a scared and anxious type.” But he knew
quite well that after imbibing the cider, “a certain eighth-grade boy
was released for a little time from a certain inchoate fear and anxiety.”2
These two experiences are paradigmatic of what we have come to expect
from addicts. These stories are quite different, though, from those who
choked on cigarettes for months, attempting to fit in with the crowd,
only having it slowly dawn on them perhaps years later that they had
difficulty quitting when they finally decided that they no longer wanted
to smoke. They are different as well from the stories of those who gamble
because it is exciting and fun, the same reasons that draw others to video
games – not reasons or feelings anything like those that moved Wilson
and Flanagan. And the Wilson/Flanagan type stories are different from
the experiences related by those who drank or gambled for many years
without any major consequences, only to have serious difficulties crop
up all of a sudden in midlife as a result of their indulgence.
Flanagan is surely correct when he says that we want to know whether
there are any commonalities among the experiences of addicts (he
focuses particularly on alcoholics). He is also right when he says that
we want to know “how the socio-cultural-political ecology normalizes,
124 Addiction
I resigned one job due to the stress and then I would start another one
and that is the one I’m at now and I enjoy the job, but the increase in
work duties just kept piling up where the stress was built up again for
me ... You know, in this day and age, they try to put as much respon-
sibility as they can on people ... I mean management does, basically
to cut costs and that hurts the blue-collar people. I mean, and the
stress just got worse and that is why I started again ... My support has
always been my wife. She pointed out that if I didn’t quit, she would
leave ... I just quit, and, you know, just go for awhile and then the
tension would build up, the stress would build up again and I would
go back to it.6
This ego depletion theory seems to explain key elements of Joe’s expe-
rience in a way that the simpler reward-seeking, withdrawal-avoiding,
and mere habituation models that we have considered cannot. Joe’s
experience and the ego depletion analysis of it seem to accord with the
incentive salience phenomenon, according to which the pull that the
substance or activity of use seems to have emerges when stress rises,
even absent any anticipated pleasure. Joe just seemed to return to the
“solution” of alcohol use every time the pressure built up.
Lance Dodes, a Harvard psychiatrist who was a leader in the develop-
ment of the psychodynamic approach to treating addiction, describes
a similar response in one of his clients. This man was a business owner
who had a history both of alcoholism and of being the victim of embez-
zlement by his own son. “When he discovered that the son’s thefts
from the company were far greater than he had known, Dodes says, “he
ended many months of sobriety in a two-day alcoholic binge.”7 Very
often we see cases in which someone is capable of controlling his use of
his favored substance or activity for days, weeks, months or even years.
He can control it right up to the point at which the emotional issues,
physical exhaustion, financial issues, or some other major stressor is just
too much. Then he capitulates. It seems plausible to conclude that in
these situations the automatic thinking of System 1 takes over.
128 Addiction
People who have this sort of experience in addiction often make deals
with themselves, swear off for a time, and are successful for a time, but
how long that time is ranges widely. In some cases, decades go by with
the promise made good before something incites the switch. In other
cases, it is remarkably short. Caroline Knapp, for instance, tells in her
bestselling memoir, Drinking: A Love Story, of making such a promise to
herself and to her mother at one point, after her drinking had become
disturbing for both of them: “‘I’ll cut down. Two drinks a day. No more
than that. I promise.’ I’d meant it.” But by the end of that same day,
back in Boston, not feeling well and observing people relaxing in deck
chairs, sipping beer from plastic cups, she capitulated.8 When the phys-
ical raggedness that she was feeling due to a hangover combined with
images of people relaxing and enjoying beers, her promise went by the
board in favor of her default response: to drink.
Sometimes the return to use doesn’t seem to be related to anything,
though. So it seems that even in this most prototypical of addictive
patterns – the one most particularly amenable to the dual systems and
related theoretical approaches – many people’s experiences are not
captured. As actress and comedian Kristen Johnston put it, the return to
use sometimes “sneaks up on you and all of a sudden you’re boozing at
the bar, or whatever. And it doesn’t have to be because of you or pres-
sure or this-or-that. It can just be.”9 No system switch seems to have
happened here, no turn to an easier way of thinking seems to have
occurred because of stress, pressure, or any identifiable cognitive load.
Kristen just found herself drinking.
In this case, the very normality of addiction within the family seems to
have played a role in Moore’s falling into her own addictive pattern. Not
every situation, however, in which the presence and use of substances is
taken as normal seems to have much to do with Kennett’s suggestions
for why people fail to exert normative control over their lives. Knapp,
for instance, who grew up in a world starkly contrasting with Celia’s and
Moore’s, says that in her life drink was “just always there.” The daughter
of a psychoanalyst and an artist, a graduate of Brown University, and a
successful writer, this woman was surely not deprived of a concept of
the good life. Nevertheless, in one way, her experience is similar to those
just described. She found the availability of alcohol and daily drinking
the norm: “In my parents’ house the Scotch and the gin sat in a liquor
cabinet, to the left of the fireplace in the living room, and it just emerged,
every evening at cocktail hour. I never saw it run out and I never saw it
replenished either: it was just there.” This experience sounds much like
one of Hammer’s interviewees, Jill, who said, “I really thought everyone
had a cocktail at five. And when I think back, I think, well, [so and so]’s
parents never did that ... but all of my parents’ friends did.”14 Although
these stories do not seem to be illuminated by either a dual systems
analysis or by the self-described addicts’ lacking a concept of the good
life, they are similar in revealing what an impact the presumption of use
can have on the development of addictive practices.
But even without this presumed normality of substance use, some
who do see a very good life as available to them nevertheless become
addicts. Consider the future that Johnston saw for herself:
Despite that my life at this point was sort of a bummer (for an upper-
middle-class, Midwestern kid with plenty to eat, lots of fun vacations, a
Phenomenology and Its Implications 131
beautiful home, and parents who loved her, that is), I knew something
none of my classmates did. Deep inside, I knew someday I’d win.15
As with Knapp, given her privileged family and all the attendant expec-
tations, one can hardly draw from Johnston’s description of her experi-
ence that her inability to exert normative control over her life was a
function either of her not having a conception of the good life or of her
not being able to see such a life as available to her. And, from the other
side, even after successful treatment, Moore did not appear to be able
to see herself in a meaningful life: “Once, I had had the opportunity to
have a wonderful, normal life, and now I never would. It was over. I was
done. I would carry on being detached and cold, pretending that none
of these things had happened.”16 And yet, Moore did go on to a life
of sobriety and continued success. Just like the other stories, hers tells
us that the theories we have examined are sometimes unnecessary and
sometimes insufficient for, and sometimes irrelevant to, providing satis-
factory explanations of the huge variety of manners and circumstances
in which addiction actually occurs in individual lives.
Another theme that Hammer’s group found that tied together a few of
their subjects’ narratives is what the authors call “Pedal to the Metal.”
This type of narrative has as its focus the striking experience that we
saw in Bill W.’s story, and in fact in most of the stories from the book
Alcoholics Anonymous. In these stories, the addictive draw of a substance
was apparent from the first encounter. We see this pattern illustrated
vividly in the memoir of Allison Moore, when she first was exposed
to methamphetamine. After being handed some confiscated meth for
processing, and after confiscating a small line for herself that kept her
up for more than three days, Moore was hooked:
I had told myself when I did that line that I would only try it once. I
would never do it again. But when I started to come down I couldn’t
face being plunged into the icy cold water of my real life. I couldn’t
bear to have those feelings return. I did another line, bigger than the
first. It made me feel calm, confident, excited about my future. Meth
was the answer to all my problems.17
Although Hammer’s group found that this theme was the least common
of all those expressed by their interviewees, Moore’s experience seems
132 Addiction
None of the theories that we have discussed can explain such experi-
ences. There can be no issue of a brain “hijacked” by drugs here, no
question of withdrawal or of interpersonal bargaining. Although it could
be the case that there was trauma early in Bill’s life, it doesn’t seem to be
that he experienced any relief from his first use of tobacco; rather, it is
expressed as a purely pleasurable experience. Perhaps, then, the by-now
largely discounted hedonic theory captures Bill’s experience better than
do any of the others. After that initial use, he kept up his smoking, with
a vengeance, and he “could smoke six or eight” packs of cigarettes if he
were to stay up all night. But pleasure doesn’t seem to be the key factor
in all people who feel immediately addicted to a substance or activity.
Many people who experience addiction in this particular way feel that
it is more a matter of pure urge far more than a matter of any partic-
ular pleasure. These individuals, most of whom admittedly have gone
through a treatment program using this model, seem to understand
themselves in terms of the disease model, specified either as genetically
programmed or as psychologically predisposed to addiction. Hammer’s
group interviewed a woman named Nora who explained her experience
in these terms:
I was an addict before I ever even had that first drink. And that first
drink just sucked me in. I don’t feel like I would have had the same
unmanageability if I had never drank [sic], but I believe that I was an
addict and an alcoholic waiting to happen ... I always wanted more
of everything. Anything if it was like a food that I liked or whatever
I want more than one ... I think it is part of my personality, but there
Phenomenology and Its Implications 133
was not a lot of progression for me. I was hooked on alcohol the
minute I drank.
theories. Certainly neither of the first two explains this pattern. Nor,
however, does this kind of situation describe someone who employs
System 2 to control something until the system is overwhelmed and
the quick and habitual sort of thinking takes over. Moreover, genetic
inheritance and trauma seem to have little to say about this kind of
sudden change in substance use patterns. Perhaps age itself changes
the way in which people react to the effects of certain substances
(there may be cases of gambling or shopping that follow this pattern,
as well). But if age is the issue, then the question arises why in the
prototypical story, as in Knapp’s experience, the progress of addic-
tion has “the feel of a swan dive, a long slow curving arc,”21 while for
people who fit into this group the experience is more like falling off
a cliff.
I would rather lie alone, hour after hour, day after day, week after
week, for almost two months, than to have to tell anyone I needed
them. You see, if I needed them, that would mean I was weak, which
would mean I was flawed. And that would be unacceptable. A fate far
worse than death Original emphasis.22
Likewise, Allison Moore, the vice officer whose police culture didn’t
allow one to “just go and talk about your problems,” kept her troubles
to herself. She says, “I had spent my whole life keeping my own secrets,
believing that if I didn’t tell anyone my story, it couldn’t possibly be
happening to me.”23 Addicts who speak in support groups often talk
about isolation as a major problem, even after they have transitioned
out of active use, because it is such a temptation to take on the world
alone. The reasons that people give for isolating themselves, though,
136 Addiction
When He’s got His evil talons in you, you don’t care. You will lie
to protect Him, no matter what happens. He’s your most devoted
better half, your longtime lover. He’s adoring and reliable and He’s
never let you down. It’s certainly not His fault that He’s killing
you. Like a battered wife, you take Him back even though He just
knocked out your two front teeth. You lie to your weeping mother
even though He’s convinced you to steal the painkillers she actually
needs after a knee-replacement surgery. You will die protecting Him,
no matter what. Because no one will ever, ever love you as much as
He does.25
Medicating pain
And surely no one denies that use of alcohol can relax strongly repressed
emotions; indeed, the disinhibiting effect is what makes it such a central
feature at parties and other social events. One alcohol abuser, though,
put it in intellectual terms, of the sense of “rightness” and confidence
that accompanies use:
The thing that the non-addict needs to know is that there is a zone, for
the addict, equivalent to the zone of athletes, writers, artists ... where
you are ok. You don’t feel threatened by all the problems that you
know face you, and will face you later, with greater strength. You
can enjoy doing anything or nothing. You feel perfect. The fact that
there is a place like that never leaves an addict, like the feeling of
certainty, like the feeling of perfectly excited adrenaline for thrill-
seekers (funny that they’re called that, and not thrill addicts, even
though their yearning for adrenaline can kill them just as easily as
our yearning for the feeling that we want).31
In this case, the relief described as coming from alcohol use is experi-
enced as a truth, amounting to a certainty, in the face of all facts to the
contrary, that life will be ok. Again we have a case that seems amenable
to analysis by the self-medication approach. The kind of alleviation of
anxiety and production of confidence, as we have seen all too often on
the news, can have tremendously negative effects, from drunk-driving
accidents to dancing like a fool at the office party. This certainty, or
feeling of “rightness,” even in things purely intellectual, seems to be as
powerful as that brought about through seeing the proof of a theorem.
It is patently obvious that the feeling of certainty that what one is doing
is good and right is no indicator that it actually is good or right. In
fact, when the source of the feeling is a substance or behavior from
which one has often received short-term pleasure followed by long-term
pain, it is ironic that the impression of certainty can be a characteristic
experience.
The same kind of confident feeling of certainty can be brought about
by cocaine, however, and for Moore was brought about by meth. What is
more, many anxious people will not medicate themselves with alcohol,
no matter how uncomfortable they feel, because the threat of loss of
control presents an even greater source of anxiety. Further, even if it is
Phenomenology and Its Implications 139
true that those who are prone to anxiety and emotion repression turn to
sedatives, we would need to ask why among that population some prefer
alcohol to the exclusion of any other sedating substance, while others
experience the converse, and some get the same measure of relief from
any number of substances. It seems that in light of the research, the
claims of the self-medicating thesis may be defensible in broad, general
terms, and indeed, some components of it are intuitively reasonable, but
given the range of experiences that individuals report with respect to
the substances they favor, the story must be far more complicated. Kyle
Keegan, for example, in his memoir, Chasing the High, thinks of himself
as an addict, plain and simple. He speaks of one dark evening on which
he had failed to secure the heroin he wanted: “instead of getting the fix I
had hoped for, I was offered a match-head of cocaine. Against my better
judgment, I accepted it and made my way to my roof. You see, though
I knew that cocaine without heroin would only make me feel sicker, I
was an addict, and therefore unable to turn down any drug.”32 The senti-
ment “I would take anything you put in front of me” is often echoed
in 12-step rooms. Like Nick, for example, one of the first patients we
encounter in The Realm of the Hungry Ghosts, it is common to hear that
“[t]he reason I do drugs is so I don’t feel the fucking feelings I feel when
I don’t do drugs. When I don’t feel the drugs in me I get depressed.”33
But Nick was both a heroin and a meth addict. If the self-medicating
hypothesis were accurate in its specifics, Nick ought to be seeking only
the meth. Perhaps, though, Nick was treating himself for both rage
and depression. He mentioned that his father had drilled into him as
he was growing up that he was useless, so he certainly had reason for
experiencing both. Likewise, Celia, whose baby was taken from her, was
addicted to both cocaine and heroin. In fact, many of Maté’s patients
would use anything they could get their hands on.
It is difficult to see, then, how this diverse collection of individuals can
be grouped, other than through the fact that they all suffered significant
pain and, due to living in Vancouver’s worst drug slum, all had ample
reason to want to feel differently. But that means that, like the other
theories we have considered, the self-medicating hypothesis on its own
cannot do much explanatory work. Not all those even in Downtown
Eastside were heroin users, despite their pain, although most in that
area were. Most were traumatized, neglected, and sometimes abandoned
as children, which is surely at least part of the explanation for their
urge to self-medicate, and for their strong responses when they did so.
But trauma has been associated with every kind of drug use, not just
that of heroin or alcohol. Further, many of these patients, according
140 Addiction
drinking brandy to help her to sleep (but not becoming addicted to it)
through the cigarette cessation, but not requiring anything to stop the
cocaine use.37
There are experiences at every possible place on the continuum of
difficulty in transitioning out of addiction, from the lightning bolt-
type of event that began Wilson’s move away from alcohol to those like
Henry’s, in which use just seemed to interfere with other things that
he wanted to do. In any case, it seems that the diversity of experiences
of transition out of addiction shows that we have no adequate theory
of it.
Conclusions
143
144 Addiction
Manipulating neurotransmitters
familiar cues. And again, at the level of habitual behavior, the more
often one has followed a particular pattern of action, once that action is
activated, the greater the probability that that pattern of action will be
followed through to completion. But each of these is only a probabilistic
tendency, and the probability of each can be diminished.
For those who reject the medical model of addiction, the habitual
element looms large. From this perspective, addiction can be addressed
in the same way as any other undesirable habit: by doing something else
in place of the addictive activity. Going to meetings with like-minded
others at the time of day when thoughts stray to use has helped innu-
merable individuals. This is often at the end of the day. After the stresses
of a normal day of work, whether at school, at the office, at home, or on
a building site, many people are looking for relief. Addicts have uncon-
sciously developed a default setting that their brains will automatically
resort to for this purpose, and the sensitized pattern will be set off all the
more automatically, the more often they have used their preferred addic-
tive activity for coping. What’s more, the more their physiological and
psychological state has become used to relief from the day’s difficulties,
the greater the likelihood that the deep attractor well of their habituated
response will send them into that default pattern. Finding something
else that provides a significant reward, whether social support, medita-
tion, or a massage, to substitute for the addictive behavior can diminish
the likelihood of pursuing the undesired behavior.3
But addiction involves more than mere habituation. Most habits that
we engage in do not involve an increased sensitivity to the salience of
a particular thing. People generally tie their shoes automatically once
they have the strings in hand, directed by unconscious habit, with the
associated set of neural firing patterns involved later in that process
being set off by those occurring earlier in the process. This happens,
at the neural level, by the operation of a well-established attractor. But
the habituation involved in tying one’s shoe does not result in an urge
to tie one’s shoes every time one sees someone else doing so, nor does
tying one’s shoe once result in the urge to do it again and again, in
the same way that an addict’s imbibing a single dose of her substance
or engaging in a single instance of her activity of choice often results
in a “binge,” or at least in a strong desire for further use or continua-
tion of the activity. The addictive case is much more like the obsessive-
compulsive disorder case, a cyclical disorder in which a strong attractor
is developed to certain thoughts or emotions, which bring about
anxiety that leads to an urgent need to engage in particular behaviors.
Capitulation to that need only satisfies it for a brief while. When the
146 Addiction
Even when there is not the problem of drug infusion throughout the body,
therapies targeting neurocircuitry alone cannot be the whole answer to
providing relief from addiction. In one extreme study involving four
very hard-core alcoholics, for instance, electrode implants were placed
directly into the basal ganglia for the explicit purpose of interrupting
the seeking, motivational circuit, and nothing else in the body. In this
case, as long as the electricity was flowing into the specific areas into
which the electrodes had been implanted, these four men’s cravings
disappeared, but as soon as the electricity was turned off, the cravings
returned to their previous levels, and so there was no extrapolation of
the experiment’s results in the lab to real-world conditions.11 The fact
is, though, that interrupting neural circuits simply will never be suffi-
cient alone to stop addictive patterns in highly complex organisms like
us. Even when Chinese surgeons ablated (burned away with electricity)
the cells in the “pleasure centers,” or nucleus accumbens areas in some
1,000 opiate-addicted patients, reminiscent of the 1950s practice of
frontal lobotomy in America, only 47% of the patients remained free
of opiates five years later, with 53% relapsing, a consequence no better
than chance.12 Unsurprisingly, large numbers of the Chinese patients
experienced side effects, including memory loss, loss of motivation, and
changes in personality.
Possibilities for Change 149
those who live within one kilometer of a park or wooded area suffer
lower rates of depression and anxiety than those who face only concrete
every day. In areas with mostly concrete surroundings (10% green
space), about 2.6% of the population experienced anxiety disorders, and
3.2% dealt with depression, whereas only 1.8% of those living in areas
with abundant green space (90%) experienced anxiety, and 2.4% expe-
rienced depression.17 While these differences are small, and the specific
causes of the results unknown, numerous studies performed since then
support the findings, and anything that makes a difference in occur-
rence rates of these conditions is worth investigating further. Looking
for a single factor to explain the effect is probably wrongheaded. Human
organisms are more likely to flourish in the natural environments of
which we are a part, and that is for a complex set of reasons. The good
news is that even for those living in dense urban areas, there are ways to
take advantage of the positive effects that exposure to nature is shown
to have. Even if we don’t live amid trees and greenery, we can always
take a walk through a park, even if it requires some effort to get there,
and thereby enhance our exposure to both a healthful environment
and to exercise. Commenting on this research, Dr. Kathryn Kotrla of the
Texas A&M College of Medicine agreed with the approach of this book
that such research “highlights very clearly that our Western notion of
body-mind duality is entirely false. The study shows that we are a whole
organism, and when we get healthy that means our body and our mind
get healthy.”18 Where we start is not the issue; many places will do as
well as others. The point is that addiction is a human problem, but one
for which there are many potential opportunities for intervention, and
so much reason for hope.
[w]hen we were invited to China, Japan, India, and Africa to deal with
trauma there, I started to realize how much in Western psychology
we value thinking by figuring things out and how much other
cultures primarily emphasize self-regulation. For me and many of my
colleagues, going to those places has helped us discover ways of regu-
lating autonomic arousal by techniques like breathing, Qui gong,
drumming, or yoga. I have been surprised that something that is so
obvious to me is not central in our pursuit of effective treatments:
learning to regulate your autonomic arousal system is maybe the
single most important prerequisite to dealing with PTSD. Physiological
arousal needs to be calmed down before you can even access your
executive functioning and the rational part of the brain.21
Likewise, Saj Razvi and colleagues at the Love and Trauma Center in
Denver, Colorado, focus on treating trauma at the level of the autonomic
nervous system (ANS). In trauma, the sympathetic nervous system, the
activation portion of the ANS, is overcharged because, unlike in normal
emergencies, there is nothing that the organism can do to resolve the
situation (we can understand this particularly with respect to the kind
of complex, ongoing traumas that often affect people from childhood).
154 Addiction
The switch to a representation of self and world that values sobriety and
self-control over use and indulgence is a true revolution in the thinking
of the addict. As we saw in Chapter 5, it often comes like a gestalt shift
in the way in which one’s world is experienced, or, in another way of
putting it, a total shift in one’s conceptual state space. The experience of
this kind of shift seems in some ways totally inexplicable, and certainly
not subject to conscious control. Meanings systematically switch
together at once, some say “in a moment of clarity.” As in any revolu-
tion, this switch cannot be made to happen from within the system;
rather, such a shift requires stimulation from outside. Perhaps it is for
this reason that 12-step programs place such emphasis on “admitting
that our lives had become unmanageable,” and on “a decision to turn
our lives over to the care of God as we understood him,” because such
an overarching, revolutionary change to many seems to happen without
their input, as if by a miracle. This kind of revolutionary change is at the
very least mysterious, from our ordinary everyday perspective. But on
the present theory, it is the essence of natural. It is simply the result of
a far from equilibrium system’s being affected by a key input, as when a
pile of sand collapses at the addition of just one grain more. Rather than
being a function of magic or of the intervention of a supernatural God,
an overall addictive pattern is changed by changes made in the patterns
that create and sustain it. It may well be that one has been changed
through powers greater than oneself, but they are all natural powers of
one’s own body interacting with its physical and social environment.
As discussed above, research is showing that such a shift can be brought
about with significant reliability by hallucinogenic or magnetic treat-
ment, or by other indirect methods. But work on emotional reactivity,
impulse control, and managing responses to one’s motivation-reward
system within a social context can also be done by yet other means than
those so far mentioned.
An individual who identifies as an addict can improve her odds of
experiencing a revolution in her conceptual framework and thinking
and emotional patterns by taking an introspective approach, and
doing exactly the opposite of trying to seize control of her impulses.
In part, this is a familiar story to those who are aware of the 12-step
program’s “spiritual awakening” experience, which is promised to result
from going through the prescribed steps. Although the kind of funda-
mental shift that I am referring to may sometimes occur after taking
such steps, those particular steps are neither necessary nor sufficient for
Possibilities for Change 157
achieving it. They are not necessary, because other kinds of self-reflec-
tive and socially supportive dynamics have been demonstrated to help
to evoke such a shift. Many people (although no research has been done
to determine the precise numbers) have experienced a shift in thinking
and feeling, and become happy abstainers through LifeRing Secular
Recovery, for example, and Smart Recovery – programs without steps
or a higher power. And working the steps is not sufficient for achieving
revolutionary change. Many who have wholeheartedly attempted to
work through such systems of steps have failed to achieve such a funda-
mental change in feeling and worldview. The more conservative thing
to say is that people who engage in self-revelatory and responsibility-
taking measures, along with taking perhaps many other conscious steps
involving such things as turning attention away from oneself, practicing
conscious gratitude, and helping others, have a higher statistical proba-
bility of entering into and sustaining periods of abstinence and freedom
from addictive symptoms, including cue-based cravings, and so forth.
Given the level of complexity involved in this kind of worldview
change, it won’t happen all at once, even if the gestalt-type switch that
begins a sober career is of a revolutionary character. The new worldview
is held tenuously at first, because holding it necessitates that one resist
“flipping” back to the other pattern, which has gained stability and
strength through untold numbers of repetitions. But the new perspec-
tive can be firmed up over time, with reinforcement and strengthening
coming in a variety of ways from a variety of sources. Rehabituating
one’s thinking, through giving and hearing testimony, speech acts
repeated over and over again about the actuality of change, is one of
the ways in which the newly established gestalt can be strengthened in
an individual. One of the most important things that 12-step programs
can do is help people believe that they can change. Repetitive story-
telling of how life was during the period in which use was paramount,
what happened, and how life is free from the cycle of abuse now can
rehabituate one’s thought patterns to ones that are more conducive to
a happy and peaceful life. Of course, this can happen in many different
types of support and other types of groups. There is nothing proprietary
about those who endorse 12-steps with regard to this function. Likewise,
interacting with people who model the behaviors and attitudes that one
seeks to emulate reinforces one’s own strength, much as parents do for
emotional children, by entraining the weaker, less confident person’s
patterns with those of the stronger, more habituated by success. In this
way, alternative automatic responses can be developed to counter diffi-
cult situations.
158 Addiction
The essential thing is that the addict comes to believe that ceasing
her addictive behavior is possible. Whether addicted or not, people are
moved by their beliefs. In fact, one way that philosophers sometimes
define belief is in terms of that upon which one is willing to act. We
may say that we believe all kinds of things, but if we aren’t willing to
act (“Of course, I trust you!”), that is a clear sign that we don’t actually
believe. This suggests that one way in which a person might become
motivated to abstain from a drug or other addictive activity is to become
firmly convinced that if she does indulge, she will certainly end up in
jail, or in a mental institution, or dead. This is oft-repeated rhetoric in
12-step rooms. Perhaps those who use it believe it. But if prison or insti-
tutionalization is not imminent for a person who nevertheless wants to
stop using a substance or engaging in an activity, those kinds of threats
will not be believed, and will have no power to help her, and they may
even hurt, by driving her away from what might be a very helpful belief,
that she would be better off if she were to stop. This brings up another
caveat regarding 12-step approaches to treating addiction: there is a clear
danger for those who attend meetings of these groups and try to take the
steps but do not manage to get out of the cycle of addictive behaviors.
The danger rests on the fact that “the program” is based on the self-
affirming mantra that it “works for those who work it.” In other words,
continuing in an addictive pattern subsequent to participating in such a
program means personal failure. And this is a failure that singles one out
as particularly hopeless, for, as the Big Book says, “Rarely have we seen
one fail who has thoroughly followed our path.” These programs and
the 90%+ of rehabilitation treatment programs that are based on them,
as has been mentioned, put the responsibility for transitioning out of
addiction squarely on the shoulders of the addict. If she fails to achieve
the goal that the vocal members around her have managed, there is a
clear danger that she will become even more mired in a negative cycle of
self-blame, addictive behavior, remorse, and hopelessness.
Deep psychology
As we have seen, the beliefs that affect motivation need not be true
and, more importantly, they need not even be conscious. The fact that
many, or even most, of our beliefs are not necessarily (or even prob-
ably) conscious has serious implications for addicts. For one thing, as we
know, nearly every addict has memories, accessible or forgotten, of the
substance of their addiction bringing about undeniable pleasure, peace,
satisfaction, or some mix of pleasurable sensations. Without such an
Possibilities for Change 159
Whether used as a tool for control and profit, a weapon for accusation, or
an excuse for inexcusable behavior, the appeal to addiction seems to be
ubiquitous. And yet, as we have seen, it can be applied to virtually anyone
given a particular context. Even in the most paradigmatic cases, it depends
upon a network of genetic, environmental, developmental, psychological,
and sociological factors. The concept “addiction” should be understood
not as a defined and settled phenomenon, the scope of which is delimited
by necessary and sufficient conditions, but instead as a prototype, a locus
within our conceptual state space. Close to that prototype are examples
like the individual who lives in an abandoned building, occupying all her
time and devoting all her resources to shooting up heroin. Further away,
but still within the scope of the concept, is the individual who drinks
coffee most days of the week, and is grumpy when he does not, or who
hasn’t had a drink in months, but continues to think of it daily. Surely
some generalizations can be made across cases; otherwise, there would be
no agreement that in most cases addiction is unwanted, and there would
be no support groups for escaping it. But we do notice that the support
groups are legion in variety, suggesting that many individuals who think
of themselves as addicted do not recognize their experiences as being
similar to those who are addicted to different substances or activities than
they are. Shoppers or gamblers may completely fail to understand how
alcohol or opiate addicts can use such dangerous chemicals, and the latter
two types of individuals may have no interest whatsoever in allures of
the casino or the shopping mall. It is simply not possible to get the kind
of definition that philosophers (and many others) want, and it is wrong-
headed to try.
165
166 Addiction
and within the context of what cultural cues she has been sensitized to.
And all of this plays against the background of the world of meanings
into which she emerges as a self-conscious, reflective being with specific
sensitivities and expectations. The responsiveness of her caregivers, the
games her mother plays with her or the jokes she plays on her, the role
of cigarettes, alcohol, gambling, and other substances of abuse in her
environment, as well as age and brain development at the age of first
exposure to relevant substances or activities, all contribute to the likeli-
hood of her falling into addictive patterns, as does the safety of the entire
family within their cultural environment. This constellation of factors
together with a multitude of others influence an individual’s attitudes,
sensitivities, self-esteem, conception of the future and, in combination
with a multitude of other continually interacting elements, constitute
the complex dynamic that is the individual operating within her world.
The project of attempting to define “real addicts” in terms of one dogma
or another seems unhelpful, if not simply self-serving.
cognitive bias and not as an addictive mental pattern, for it is merely one
of the characteristics of human thought. This particular bias has been
vividly shown in hundreds of studies, including the famous “Invisible
Gorilla” demonstration, to characterize a fundamental feature of the
way human attention operates. When we are focused on one thing,
for example, players in white shirts passing a basketball, we can fail to
notice the most obvious of things also on the scene, such as a person in
a gorilla suit walking right through the scene, stopping to beat its chest
before walking off. Once again, though, when someone has been labeled
an addict, both the term used to express the bias (now “triggers”) and
the strength of its effect (to bring about virtually automatic behaviors)
are understood differently. Those who have stopped their unwanted
behavior while attending self-help meetings, particularly 12-step meet-
ings, with their particular structured type of sharing (recounting “what
it was like, what happened, what it’s like now”), exhibit a different kind
of attentional bias. Particularly in the “pink cloud” that many say char-
acterizes their first few months of sobriety, but also in the stories of those
who have been abstinent for numbers of years, the negative attendants
of their addictive behavior, as well as the positive events and feelings
accompanying abstinence, loom large. Of course, if the suffering was
great, and directly associated with the addictive behavior, then the relief
attending cessation would in fact be great. But those very same events
might well have been seen as “not that bad,” say, prior to an interven-
tion or hospitalization. Which characterization works is a function of
whether an individual’s focus is on the prospect of using again or on
the goal of abstinence. Countless details will escape her awareness in
either situation, but which details escape and which are attended to
have everything to do with what is uppermost in her mind.
This sort of directed attention operates in combination with hindsight
bias, conservatism bias, and the urge to resolve cognitive dissonance,
in all of us. Whether or not one has ever had an experience one would
label “addictive,” human cognition is biased toward telling a story that is
consistent over time, both with respect to expectations and in hindsight.
Neither any of these kinds of biased thinking nor any of the dozens of
others discovered to operate in ordinary healthy human beings is in any
way distinctive of addiction in particular, despite the collective wisdom
of certain circles to the contrary. The designation “addictive thinking”
is more groundless than the label “addict,” and yet these terms in
common parlance are unquestionably taken to embody something real.
This very language promotes particular ways of addressing a continuum
of human problems that are both dismissive of the differences among
172 Addiction
those who have these problems and the similarities between those who
are called addicts and those who are not. Far more helpful for dealing
with real problems in the real world is to understand the diversity to
which complex systems give rise and to deal with the individuals and
the social systems creating them and arising from them in terms of what
they really are.
something. Twelve-step endorsers will usually reply that people like this
are among the lucky few who only need to hit a “high bottom” in order
to be motivated to change. These are probably two ways of saying the
same thing. The important observation is that at some stage something
will happen, and nobody can know in advance what that thing will
be, which will operate as a lever point, triggering huge changes in the
person’s whole way of seeing things. That doesn’t mean that a different
life occurs instantaneously, but it does mean that a critical juncture has
been surpassed and that large portions of what had been a stable pattern
collapse, creating a move into a different one.
The jurisprudence system seems to think that negative reinforce-
ment can motivate people to stop at least certain addictive behaviors.
Gambling or shopping in ways that involve unagreed-upon losses of
others’ money, taking certain drugs, or at least possessing them, and
drinking after a DUI are met with still harsher penalties and sometimes
incarceration. In recent years, university campuses have experienced
rising numbers of their student populations wearing ankle monitors in
order to stop the latter. The problem with this attempt at controlling
people’s behavior is that it depends upon an economic, rather than a
psychological, understanding of motivation. And the presumptions of
that particular model of human behavior have proven so faulty that
even the field of economics has largely discarded them, while the field of
behavioral economics, which focuses on how humans actually behave,
given our implicit biases, has burgeoned. Rewards have been shown to
be more effective than punishments as motivations, as any dog owner
who has been to a training class knows. But even rewards are not always
effective, and sometimes can undermine the goal. Although we have
seen that in some cases drug users can effectively alter their behavior for
financial rewards, in the long run rewards may rob them of their sense
of autonomy and their confidence in their ability to act for intrinsic
reasons.7
In any case, it seems that the factors that enter into an addicted indi-
vidual’s ability to change are legion. Short of defining “hitting bottom”
as whatever it is that happens just prior to an individual’s transitioning
out of an addictive behavior pattern, it seems that crashing to earth
in some traumatic way is neither necessary nor sufficient to achieve
change. On the one hand, many people make a change, as we have
said, on the basis of a simple dissatisfaction with the overall feel of their
lives, while on the other, thousands and even millions of people have
experienced horrific consequences in connection with their use and
have persisted nonetheless. In complex adaptive systems that have the
Conclusion 175
Probability is key
with all their difficulties than it is to create models of them that are
easier to manage, but that don’t translate into real-world answers. In
our case, given our generation’s endemic addictive problems, perhaps
it is worth the trouble to take on the harder problems that address our
actual lived situation.
Notes
178
Notes 179
suggest that even without free will there is moral responsibility, and so the
fact that free will is an illusion is practically unimportant. Others, such
as Patricia Churchland (see, for example, her essay at Newscientist.com,
November 18, 2006) has argued that the concept needs to be revised, and
Daniel Dennett has argued in numerous essays and books since his 1978
Brainstorms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981), but most concertedly in his
Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1984), that human beings have all the free will that anyone could
want.
33. James Ladyman and Don Ross, with David Spurrett and John Collier,
Everything Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2007), 4.
34. Ladyman and Ross, 4.
35. Ladyman and Ross, 4.
36. John H. Holland, Complexity: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2014).
37. Terrence W. Deacon, Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter (New
York: Norton, 2012), 244.
38. Five reasons for believing this are listed on p. 4 of Mark Bickhard, “Some
Consequences (and Enablings) of Process Metaphysics,” Axiomathes 21,
no. 1 (2011): 3–32. See also Mark H. Bickhard and Richard J. Campbell,
“Physicalism, Emergence, and Downward Causation,” Axiomathes 21, no. 1
(2011): 33–56
39. Ladyman and Ross, 20.
40. These examples are paraphrased from Mark Bickhard, “Interactivism:
A Manifesto” New Ideas in Psychology, 27 (2009): 85–89, doi:10.1016/j.
newideapsych.2008.05.001.
41. Deacon, 177.
42. J. C. Anthony and J. E. Helzer, “Syndromes of Drug Abuse and Dependence,”
in Psychiatric Disorders in America: The Epidemiologic Catchment Area Study,
eds. Lee N. Robins and Darrel A. Regie (New York: Free Press, 1991),
116–154; R. C. Kessler, W. T. Chiu, O. Demler, K. R. Merikangas, and
E. E.Walters, “Prevalence, Severity, and Comorbidity of 12-month DSM-IV
Disorders in the National Comorbidity Survey Replication,” Archives of
General Psychiatry 62 (2005): 617–627; L. N. Robins and D. Regier, Psychiatric
Disorders in America (New York: Free Press, 1991); F. S. Stinson, B. F. Grant,
D. Dawson, W. J. Ruan, B. Huang, and T. Saha, “Comorbidity between
DSM-IV Alcohol and Specific Drug Use Disorders in the United States:
Results from the National Epidemiological Survey on Alcohol and Related
Conditions,” Drug and Alcohol Dependence 80 (2005): 105–116; L. A. Warner,
R. C. Kessler, M. Hughes, J. C. Anthony, and C. B. Nelson, “Prevalence and
Correlates of Drug Use and Dependence in the United States. Results from
the National Cormorbidity Survey,” Archives of General Psychiatry, 52 (1995):
219–229.
43. Deacon, ch. 10.
44. Deacon, 291.
45. John Stuart Mill, System of Logic: Rationative and Inductive. (1843) Collected
Works, Vols. 7 and 8 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press: 1996), 371.
46. C. D. Broad, The Mind and Its Place in Nature (London: Kegan Paul, 1925).
182 Notes
47. Carl Hempel and Paul Oppenheim, “Studies in the Logic of Explanation,”
in Hempel’s Aspects of Scientific Explanation (New York: The Free Press, 1965).
Thomas Nagel, The Structure of Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World,
1061), ch. 11. Cited in Jaegwon Kim, “Making Sense of Emergentism,”
Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic
Tradition 95, no. 1/2 (1999): 3–36.
48. Kim, (1999).
49. Bickhard mentions this in “Representational Content in Humans and
Machines,” Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 5
(1993): 285–333, and in “The Biological Emergence of Representation,” in
Emergence and Reduction: Proceedings of the 29th Annual Symposium of the Jean
Piaget Society, eds. T. Brown and L. Smith (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 2002),
105–131, as well as in (2004).
50. Deacon, 265.
51. Deacon, 266.
52. Deacon, 309.
53. Bickhard (2004), 130.
54. Deacon, 535.
55. Deacon, 323.
56. Mark Bickhard, “Consciousness and Reflective Consciousness,” Philosophical
Psychology 18, no. 2 (2005): 218.
13. Daniel Wegner, “Who Is the controller of Controlled Processes?,” The New
Unconscious, ed. Ran R. Hassin, James S. Uleman, and John A. Bargh (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2005), 19–37. John A. Bargh, ed. Social Psychology
and the Unconscious: The Automaticity of Higher Mental Processes (New York:
Psychology Press, 2007); David D. Franks, Neurosociology: The Nexus Between
Neuroscience and Social Psychology (New York: Springer, 2010), Chapter 4.
14. D. B. Newlin and K. A. Strubler, “The Habitual Brain: An ‘Adapted Habit’
Theory of Substance Use Disorders,” Substance Use and Misuse 42, no. 2–3
(2007): 503–526; George Messinis, “Habit Formation and the Theory
of Addiction,” Journal of Economic Surveys 13, no. 4 (2009): 417–442. doi:
10.1111/1467–6419.00089.
15. Daniel J. Siegal, The Developing Mind (New York: Guilford Press, 1999),
28–32.
16. Reinout W. Wiers and Alan W. Stacy, “Implicit Cognition and Addiction,”
Current Directions in Psychological Science 16, no. 6 (Dec. 2006): 292–296.
17. A. E. Kelley and K. C. Berridge, “The Neuroscience of Natural Rewards:
Relevance to Addictive Drugs,” Journal of Neuroscience 22 (2002): 3306–3311.
18. A. E. Kelley and K. C. Berridge, “The Neuroscience of Natural Rewards:
Relevance to Addictive Drugs,” Journal of Neuroscience 22 (2002): 3306–3311;
Steven E. Hyman, Robert C. Malenka, and Eric J. Nestler, “Addiction: The
Role of Reward-Related Learning and Memory,” Annual Review of Neuroscience
29 (2006): 565–598; Koob and Volkow (2010).
19. But even this is not without dispute, as some researchers have argued that
more than one “type” of alcoholism exist, and require independent discussion.
One sort, it is argued, the susceptibility to lose control after drinking begins,
is genetically distinct from the susceptibility to lose control after drinking
begins, and requires a different analysis. While the first kind of alcoholism
may be accounted for in terms of dopamine and hedonic experiences, the
other, characterized by impulse control problems, is attributed to a dysfunc-
tion in serotonin regulation. Both of these “types” of alcoholism, however, are
seen as the result of the interaction of genetic and environmental factors. See
C. R. Cloninger, “Neurogenetic Adaptive Mechanisms in Alcoholism,” Science
236 (1987): 410–416; also Christina S. Barr, Melanie L. Schwandt, Timothy K.
Newman, and J. Dee Higley, “The Use of Adolescent Nonhuman Primates to
Model Human Alcohol Intake: Neurobiological, Genetic, and Psychological
Variables,” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1021 (2004): 221–233.
20. N. D. Volkow, G. J. Want, J. S. Fowler, S. J. Gatley, Y. S. Ding, J. Logan et al.,
“Relationship between Psychostimulant-induced ‘High’ and Dopamine
Transporter Occupancy,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA
93 (1996): 10388–10392; N. D. Volkow and J. M. Swanson, “Variables That
Affect the Clinical Use and Abuse of Methylphenidate in the Treatment of
ADHD,” American Journal of Psychiatry 160 (2003): 1909–1918; A. A. Grace,
“The Tonic/Phasic Model of Dopamine System Regulation and Its Implications
for Understanding Alcohol and Psychostimulant Craving,” Addiction 95,
Suppl. 2 (2000): S119–S128.
21. T. E. Robinson and K.C. Berridge, “Addiction,” Annual Review of Psychology
54 (2003): 25–53.
22. T. E. Robinson and B. Kolb, “Alterations in the Morphology of Dendrites and
Dendritic Spines in the Nucleus Accombens and Pre-frontal Cortex Following
Notes 185
33. Uri Shalev, David Highfield, Jasmine Yap, and Yavin Shaha, “Stress and
Relapse to Drug Seeking in Rats: Studies on the Generality of the Effect,”
Psychopharmacology 150, no. 3 (2000): 337–346; Yavin Shaham, Suzanne Erb,
and Jane Steward, “Stress Induced Relapse to Heroin and Cocaine Seeking in
Rats: A Review,” Brain Research Reviews 33, no. 1 (2000): 13–33.
34. Mara Mather and Nichole R. Lighthall, “Risk and Reward Are Processed
Differently in Decisions Made Under Stress,” Current Directions in Psychological
Science 21, no. 1 (2012): 36–41.
35. Xiao-li Zhang, Jie Shi, Li-yan Zhao, Li-li Sun, Jun Wang, Gui-bin Wang,
David Epstein, and Lin Lu, “Effects of Stress on Decision-Making Deficits in
Formerly Heroin-Dependent Patients after Different Durations of Abstinence,”
American Journal of Psychiatry 168, no. 6 (2011): 610–616.
36. Mary-Anne Enoch and David Goldman, “The Genetics of Alcoholism and
Alcohol Abuse,” Current Psychiatry Reports 3 (2001): 144–151.
37. International Human Genome Sequencing Consortium, “Initial Sequencing
and Analysis of the Human Genome,” Nature 409, no. 6822 (2001): 860–921;
International Human Genome Sequencing Consortium, “Finishing the
Euchromatic Sequence of the Human Genome,” Nature 431, no. 7011 (2004):
931–945.
38. J. Hirsch, “Some History of Heredity-vs-Environment, Genetic Inferiority at
Harvard (?) and The (Incredible) Bell Curve,” Genetica 99 (1997): 207–224.
39. Heyman (2009), 91.
40. C. Robert Cloninger, Michael Bohman, Soren Sigvardsson, “Inheritance of
Alcohol Abuse: Cross-Fostering Analysis of Adopted Men,” Archives of General
Psychiatry 38, no. 8 (1981): 861–868.
41. M. Bohman, S. Sigvardsson, and C. R. Cloninger, “Maternal Inheritance of
Alcohol Abuse: Cross-fostering Analysis of Adopted Women,” Archives in
General Psychiatry 38, no. 9 (1981): 861–868.
42. Jay Joseph, “The ‘Missing Heritability’ of Psychiatric Disorders: Elusive Genes
or Non-Existent Genes?,” Applied Developmental Science 16, no. 2 (2012): 72.
43. R. Plomin, R. Corley, A. Caspi, D. W. Fulker, and J. C. DeFries, “Adoption
Results for Self-Reported Personality: Evidence for Nonadditive Genetic
Effects?,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75 (1998): 211–218.
44. Gabor Maté, In the Realm of Hungry Ghosts: Close Encounters with Addiction
(Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books, 2010), 433–437.
45. Maté (2010), 438.
46. Maté (2010), 439.
47. Joshua P. Smith and Sarah W. Book, “Comorbidity of Generalized Anxiety
Disorder and Alcohol Use Disorders among Individuals Seeking Outpatient
Substance Abuse Treatment,” Addictive Behaviors 35, no. 1 (2010): 42–45.
48. F. R. Schneier, T. E. Foose, D. S. Hasin, R. G. Heimberg, S. M. Liu,
B. F. Grant, and C. Blanco, “Social Anxiety Disorder and Alcohol Use Disorder
Co-morbidity in the National Epidemiologic Survey on Alcohol and Related
Conditions,” Psychological Medicine 40, no. 6 (2010): 977–988.
49. D. A. Regier, M. E. Farmer, D. S. Rae, B.Z. Locke, S. J. Keith, L. O. Judd, and
F. K. Goodwin, “Comorbidity of Mental Disorders with Alcohol and Other
Drug Abuse: Results from the Epidemiological Catchment Area (ECA) Study,”
Journal of the American Medical Association 264 (1990): 2511–2518.
Notes 191
23. See H. Mercier and D. Sperber, “Why Do Humans Reason? Arguments for
an Argumentative Theory,” The Behavioral and Brain Sciences (April 1, 2011),
57–74, for an argument that the function of reasoning in humans is not to
determine optimal behavior or beliefs, but rather to persuade others of what
we are already inclined to do or believe. We “look for arguments that support
a given conclusion, and ceteris paribus, favor conclusions for which argu-
ments can be found.” (p. 57).
16. John Ratey, with Eric Hagerman, Spark: The Revolutionary New Science of
Exercise and the Brain (New York: Little, Brown and Co., 2008), 167–190 and
217–232.
17. Jolanda Mass, Robert A. Verheij, Peter P. Groenewegen, Sjerp de Vries, and
Peter Spreeuwenberg, “Green Space, Urbanity, and Health: How Strong Is the
Relation?,” Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health 60, no. 7 (2006):
587–592, online.
18. Amanda Gardner, “Green Spaces Boost the Body and the Mind,” abcnews.
go.com, October 16, 2009, http://abcnews.go.com/Health/Healthday/green-
spaces-boost-body-mind/story?id=8835912&page=2.
19. www.acestudy.org.
20. Lisa M. Najavits, R. D. Weiss, and S. R. Shaw, “The Link Between Substance
Abuse and Posttraumatic Stress Disorder in Women: A Research Review,”
American Journal on Addictions 6 (1997): 273–283.
21. Bessel van der Kolk with Lisa M. Najavits, “Interview: What Is PTSD Really?
Surprises, Twists of History, and the Politics of Diagnosis and Treatment,”
Journal of Clinical Psychology: In Session, 69, no. 5 (2013): 516–522.
22. Matthew W. Johnson et al., “Pilot Study of the 5-HT2AR Agonist Psilocybin
in the Treatment of Tobacco Addiction,” Journal of Psychopharmacology 28,
no. 11 (2014): 983–992.
23. Many such memoirs are included among addiction self-help books, including,
for example, Caroline Knapp’s Drinking: A Love Story (New York: Dial Press
Trade, 1997).
24. Susan Brison, “Violence and the Remaking of a Self,” The Chronicle of Higher
Education, January 18, 2002, B7. See also Susan Brison, Aftermath: Violence
and the Remaking of a Self (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002; Paris:
Editions Chambon, 2003; Munich: C. H. Beck Verlag, 2004).
25. Donna J. Bridge and Joel L. Voss, “Hippocampal Binding of Novel Information
with Dominant Memory Traces Can Support Both Memory Stability and
Change,” The Journal of Neuroscience 34, no. 6 (2014): 2203–2213.
26. Al-Anon is the sister organization to AA, created to provide support and its
own version of the 12 steps for spouses and others who are in close relation-
ships with addicted individuals. Al-Ateen and Adult Children of Alcoholics
are other such programs available in certain areas.
27. Sarah Huggins Scarbrough, “Breakthroughs in Offender Treatment: A Virginia
Program Makes Inroads with Peer Support, Behavior Modification,” Addiction
Professional 10, no. 5 (2012): 13–15. The research for this article was done
as part of Dr. Scarbrough’s dissertation work. Her study is entitled “Drugs,
Crime, and the Gateway Effect: A Study of Federal Crime Defendants.”
28. UK Home Office Report, “Drugs: International Comparators,” www.gov.uk,
October, 2014, https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/
attachment_data/file/368489/DrugsInternationalComparators.pdf.
29. UK Home Office Report, 46.
30. Wiebke Hollersen, “‘This Is Working:’ Portugal, 12 years after Decriminalizing
Drugs,” Spiegel Online International, March 27, 2013, http://www.spiegel.de/
international/europe/evaluating-drug-decriminalization-in-portugal-12-
years-later-a-891060.html.
31. UK Home Office Report, 5.
Notes 199
9 Conclusion
1. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, “Are Addicts Responsible?” Perspectives from
Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience, ed. Neil Levy (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2013), 126.
2. Amanda Lenhart, “Teens, Social Media and Technology Overview 2015,”
Pew Research Center, Internet, Science, and Tech, www.pewinternet.org,
April 9, 2015, http://www.pewinternet.org/2015/04/09/teens-social-media-
technology-2015/.
3. Richard E. Nisbett and Timothy DeCamp Wilson, “Verbal Reports about
Causal Influences on Social Judgments: Private Access versus Public Theories,”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 35, no. 9 (1977): 613–624; Richard
E. Nisbett and Timothy DeCamp Wilson, “Telling More Than We Can
Know,” Psychological Review 84, no. 3 (1977): 231–359, doi: 10.1037/0033–
295X.84.3.231. Petter Johansson, Lars Hall, Sverker Sikstrom, Betty Tarning,
and Andreas Lind, “How Something Can Be Said about Telling More Than We
Can Know: On Choice Blindness and Introspection,” Conscious and Cognition
15, no. 4 (2006): 673–692.
4. Daniel Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown, and Company,
1991), 115–138.
5. Ryan T. McKay and Daniel C. Dennett, “The Evolution of Misbelief,” Brain and
Behavioral Sciences 32 (2009): 493–561.
6. John H. Holland, Hidden Order: How Adaptation Builds Complexity (New York:
Helix Books, 1995), 39–40, 93–97, and 165–167.
7. C. L. Hart, M. Haney, R. W. Foltin, and M. W. Fischman, “Alternative
Reinforcers Differentially Modify Cocaine Self-Administration by Humans,”
Behavioral Pharmacology 11, no. 1 (2000): 87–91. Also see William W. Stoops,
Joshua A. Lile, Paul E. A. Glaser, Lon. R. Hays, and Craig R. Rush, “Alternative
Reinforcer Response Cost Impacts Cocaine Choice in Humans,” Progress in
Neuro-Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry 36, no. 1 (2012): 189–193.
Bibliography
Alexander, Michelle. The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of
Colorblindness. New York: The New Press, 2010.
American Psychiatric Association Committee on Nomenclature and Statistics.
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders IV-TR. Washington DC:
American Psychiatric Association, 1994.
Bateson, Gregory. “The Cybernetics of Self: A Theory of Alcoholism,” in Steps
to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution and
Epistemology. San Francisco: Chandler Publishing Company, 1982, 315–345.
Bickhard, Mark, “Process and Emergence: Normative Function and
Representation,” Axiomathes: An International Journal in Ontology and Cognitive
Systems 14 (2004): 135–169.
Churchland, Paul. Neurophilosophy at Work. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2007.
Courtwright, David T. Forces of Habit: Drugs and the Making of the Modern World.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001.
Damasio, Antonio. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of
Consciousness. New York: Harcourt, 1999.
Deacon, Terrance W. Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter. New York:
Norton, 2012.
Dennett, Daniel. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1984.
Dennett, Daniel. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company,
1991.
Dodes, Lance. “Psychodynamic Practice: Individuals, Groups and Organisations,”
Psychodynamic Practice: Individuals, Groups and Organizations, Special Issue: The
Psychodynamics of Substance Abuse 15, no. 4 (2009): 381–393.
Dube, Shanta R., Felitti, Vincent J., Dong, Maxia, Chapman, Daniel P., Giles,
Wayne H., and Anda, Robert F. “Childhood Abuse, Neglect, and Household
Dysfunction and the Risk of Illicit Drug Use: The Adverse Childhood Experiences
Study,” Pediatrics 111, no. 3 (2003): 564–572.
Everitt, B. J., Dickinson, A, and Robbins, T. W. “The Neuropsychological Basis of
Addictive Behavior,” Brain Research Review 36 (2001): 129–138.
Everitt, B. J., and Robbins, T. W. “Neural Systems of Reinforcement for Drug
Addiction: From Actions to Habits to Compulsion,” Nature Neuroscience 8
(2005): 1481–1489.
Flanagan, Owen. “What Is It Like to Be An Addict?”, in Addiction and Responsibility,
ed. Jeffrey Poland and George Graham. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. 2011,
269–292.
Flanagan, Owen. “Phenomenal Authority: The Epistemic Authority of Alcoholics
Anonymous,” in Addiction and Self-Control: Perspectives from Philosophy,
Psychology, and Neuroscience, ed. Neil Levy. New York: Oxford University Press.
2013, 269–292.
200
Bibliography 201
Foddy, Bennett. “Addiction and Its Sciences: Philosophy,” Addiction 106 (2010):
25–31.
Fodor, Jerry. The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell, 1975.
Fodor, Jerry. RePresentations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981.
Greenspan, Stanley I., and Shanker, Stuart. The First Idea: How Symbols, Language,
and Intelligence Evolved From Our Primate Ancestors to Modern Humans. Cambridge,
MA: Da Capo Press, 2004.
Helm, Christine, Plotsky, Paul M. and Nemeroff, Charles B. “Importance of
Studying the Contributions of Early Adverse Experience to Neurobiological
Findings in Depression,” Neuropsychopharmacology 29, no. 4 (2004): 205–217.
Heyman, Gene. Addiction: A Disorder of Choice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 2009.
Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2011.
Kennett, Jeanette. “Just Say No? Addiction and the Elements of Self-Control,” in
Addiction and Self-Control: Perspectives from Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience,
ed. Neil Levey. New York: Oxford University Press, 2013, 144–164.
Knapp, Caroline. Drinking: A Love Story. New York: Bantam Doubleday Dell
Publishing Group. 1996.
Koob, G. F., and Le Moal, M. “Drug Abuse: Hedonic Homeostatic Dysregulation,”
Science 278 (1997): 52–58.
Koob, G. F. et al. “Opponent Process Model and Psychostimulant Addiction,”
Pharmacological Biochemistry and Behavior 57 (1997): 513–521.
Koob, George F., and Volkow, Nora D. “Neurocircuitry of Addiction,”
Neuropsychopharmacology 35 (2010): 217–138.
Ladyman, James, and Ross, Don, with David Spurrett and John Collier. Everything
Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Levy, Neil. “Resisting ‘Weakness of Will,’” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 82, no. 1 (2011): 134–155.
Maté, Gabor. In The Realm of Hungry Ghosts: Close Encounters with Addiction.
Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books, 2010.
Perry, B. D., and Pollard, R. “Homeostasis, Stress, Trauma, and Adaptation:
A Neurodevelopmental View of Childhood Trauma,” Child and Adolescent
Psychiatric Clinics of North America 7 (1998): 33–51.
Perry, Bruce D. “Childhood Experience and the Expression of Genetic Potential:
What Childhood Neglect Tells Us about Nature and Nurture,” Brain and Mind
3, no. 1 (2002): 79–100.
Rapping, Elayne. The Culture of Recovery: Making Sense of the Self-Help Movement in
Women’s Lives. Boston: Beacon Press, 1996.
Ratey, John, with Eric Hagerman. Spark: The Revolutionary New Science of Exercise
and the Brain. New York: Little, Brown and Co., 2008.
Robinson, T. E., and Berridge, K. C. “The Neural Basis of Drug Craving: An
Incentive-Sensitization Theory of Addiction,” Brain Research Reviews 18, no. 3
(1993): 247–291.
Index
12 step programs, 4, 51, 125, 133, 147, anticipation, 36, 43, 119, 159,
156–9, 170 anxiety, 10, 35–6, 66, 76–7, 85,
91,122–3, 138–9, 145–6, 152–3,
A.A. (See Alcoholics Anonymous), 155, 164, 175
84, 131 apathy, 81, 95
abuse, 2, 12–14, 37–8, 42, 52, 60, Aristotle (See Self-Control), 15, 17, 24
62–4, 68, 71, 74–7, 84–9, 92–3, asymmetric dependence, 107
127, 129, 131, 138, 143, 146–8, atomic linguistic theory, 119
152, 157, 167, 169 attachment, 7, 34, 42, 63, 66, 74, 126,
activity-dependent, 122 154, 166
addiction attitudes, 8, 10, 21, 64, 81, 85, 89–90,
history of, 118,130 98, 115, 141, 157, 167, 169
culture of, 79–99 attractor Well, 144–5, 164, 167,
addicted self, 176 173, 175
addictive autonomy, 90, 174
behavior, 132, 134–8, 140–1,
145–147, 149–53, 155, 157–9, baby (See Newborn), 63, 65–6, 74, 113,
162, 164–6, 168–9, 171–4 115, 129, 139
career, 173 Bateson, Gregory, 60, 187
experiences, 126, 141 behavioral economists, 4, 54
thinking, 16, 167–71 belief, 21, 29, 60–1, 89, 93, 104,
patterns, 1, 25, 27, 33, 47, 50, 57–8, 106, 115, 119–20, 155, 158–60,
75, 113, 115, 119, 121, 128, 144, 169–70, 175
148, 150, 167, 169, 170, 172, 175 bias
personality, 95, 133 attentional bias, 170–1
Adverse Childhood Experiences better than average effect, 170
(ACE’s), 63, 65, 152 confirmation bias, 169
adolescence, 62, 64 conservatism bias, 169, 171
advertisement, 83 binge, 36, 95, 127
African American, 86, 166, 182 brain disease, 82
affluent communities, 86 brain imaging, 44, 48, 149, 185
akrasia (See Self-Control), 15–16 Buddhist monks, 149
Alcoholics Anonymous
history of, 84 caffeine, 79
alcoholism, 50–1, 53, 60, 72, 74, 84, Campril, 175
127, 130, 148, 170 cannabis (See Marijuana), 79, 81,
allergy to alcohol, 84 163–4
American culture, 16, 83, 85 capitalism, 83–4
amulets, 175 caregiver, 63, 65–7, 76, 105, 113–15,
anguish, 123 164
animal studies cause and effect, 50, 77, 103
primates, 68–9, 184 certainty, 138
rat rark, 69–70, 93
203
204 Index
cessation, 38, 44, 113, 141, 146, 148, depression, 10, 44, 77, 91, 94, 137,
155, 171, 173 139, 152, 175
childhood, 60, 62–5, 130, 152–3, 164 discounting, 54, 57
choice theory, 4, 15, 20–1, 53 discourse, 11, 19, 25, 83, 124, 173
Christian, 124 disease model, 4, 11, 14–15, 20, 35–6,
cigarettes (See tobacco), 37, 42, 80, 40–2, 46–7, 50–3, 57–8, 73, 76,
94, 97, 111, 113, 123, 132, 140, 84–5, 88, 91, 95, 99, 132
155, 167 disparity, 92
class, 81, 86–7, 95,130–1 divorce, 130, 161
cocaine, 37, 54, 70, 81, 87, 93, 96–7, desire, 17–21, 90, 119, 143, 145, 168,
106, 126, 129, 137–41 173, 175
coffee (See caffeine), 17, 61, 79–81, dogma, 98, 120, 147, 167, 169
142, 164–5 DSM (Diagnostic And Statistical
cognitive biases, 168, 170 Manual), 3, 10–14, 16, 19, 42, 48,
cognitive dissonance, 169, 171 79, 91, 99, 179
cognitive load, 128–9 dopamine, 18, 39, 42–7, 60, 63, 65,
comorbidity 67, 109, 116, 151
anxiety disorders, 77, 91, 152 drug of choice, 9, 38
bipolar, 77, 91, 175 drug policy, 92, 95
depression, 10, 44, 77, 91, 94, 137, dualism, 20–1, 33, 36, 100
139, 152, 175 dual systems, 126, 128, 130, 133–4
complex dynamic system, 6, 25, DUI, 20, 173–4
28, 33, 40, 61, 105, 126, 163, Dynamic Systems Approach, 6
173, 175 dynamical psychological approach,
confidence, 73, 123, 138, 174 137
confirmation bias, 169
conservatism bias, 169, 171 early adolescence, 64
consumer capitalism, 84 ecology, 60–1, 123
consumption, 68, 80, 83–4, 89, 146, ecology of addiction, 60, 187
149, 163 ego depletion, 17, 55, 57, 125–7, 129,
competition, 80, 170 149–50
communication, 40, 42, 102, 120, emergence model (emergent), 6–7,
160–1 23–5, 28–31, 33, 36, 61, 67, 82,
concept, 2, 6–7, 10–11, 13–14, 17–18, 100–1, 109, 121, 143, 166
20, 22–3, 28–30, 33, 35, 41, 50–2, emotional reactivity, 153, 156
82, 84–5, 87, 89, 100–1, 103–21, employment, 87, 127, 162
128–31, 137, 156, 165, 167, 173 emotional responses, 64, 114–15
crack, 87, 93, 97 entropy, 28, 30–2, 105
craving, 18, 35–6, 38–9, 45, 123, environment, 6–9, 14, 22, 24–5, 28,
146–9, 157 31–3, 44, 47–8, 57–8, 61–4, 68–77,
crystals, 175 79, 83, 86, 93, 95, 100, 105, 109,
control, 6, 9, 13–15, 17–21, 24, 36–7, 111, 114–15, 118, 121–22, 137,
40, 48, 51, 53–7, 59, 65, 71, 80, 151–2, 156, 165–8, 184, 189, 190
82–5, 87–8, 90–1, 96–7, 126–35, expectations, 42, 44, 62, 64, 114, 116,
137–8, 141–2, 149–51, 156, 118, 131, 167–8, 171
164–6, 172, 174 exposure, 3, 9, 35–8, 44, 46, 56, 62,
69, 86, 152, 167
denial, 88, 168–9 evolution, 2, 31, 66, 84, 104, 117,
Dennett, Daniel, 168 156–7, 167–8, 170, 172
Index 205
family, 88, 94, 101–2, 108, 114, 117, industry, 53, 81, 82, 84, 87, 96–7,
124, 130–1, 167, 172, 176 140
fast food, 79, 81 industrialization, 82
fate, 135 inequalities, 10
faith, 162 infant (See Newborn), 65–6, 74, 114,
fear, 4–5, 37, 66, 81, 114, 122–3, 162 164
Flanagan, Owen, 123 informational atomism, 105–6
Fodor, Jerry, 105 inhibition, 18
food addiction, 79, 97, 99 innate, 103–5
free will, 14, 21, 53 interpersonal bargaining, 132
freedom, 20, 83, 85, 102, 123, 157 intervention, 18, 36, 46, 85, 88, 144,
friends, 77, 101–3, 111, 122, 130, 152, 156, 171, 176
164, 168 intentionality, 16
fMRI (See Brain Imaging), 48–9 intentional self-control, 129
isolation, 4, 22, 60, 65–6, 77, 95,
gambling, 2, 12, 37–9, 43, 70, 88, 91, 135–6
95, 97–8, 135, 167, 174
genetics, 25, 33, 35, 58, 72–6 Korean culture, 89
gestalt, 8, 102, 117, 119–20, 156–7
gestation, 62, 74–5 labor, 79–80, 82, 93, 192
globalization, 82 language of thought, 108
God, 4, 104, 111, 124, 156, 159 lever points, 6, 172–3
guilt, 91, 94, 161–2, 175 life
life changes, 173, 175–6
habituation, 39–40, 45, 127, 144–5 life circumstances, 129
habitual behavior, 145, 169 Lifering Secular Recovery, 157, 173,
hallucinogens, 155 175–6
happy hour, 81, 95 Locke, John, 103
hedonic theory, 132 LSD, 97
healthcare, 81 Ledoux, Joseph, 37
hemp (See marijuana), 81, 182 love, 88, 107, 117, 128, 131–2, 135–6,
heritability (See genetics), 72–3 140, 153–4, 160–1, 173, 176
Heyman, Gene (See choice theory), low-income, 87
3, 13, 52, 73, 90, 117
hitting bottom, 88, 173–4 mantra, 114, 149, 158
Hume, David, 103, 111 Mate, Gabor, 75, 122, 129
hyperbolic discounting, 57 maternal care, 68
hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal marijuana, 13, 77–8, 86, 96–8
(HPA-axis), 65 meaning holism, 119–20
meditation, 11, 145, 149–51, 164,
identity, 31, 47, 83, 123 175–6
illegal drug, 85–7 mental representation, 105–6,
immigrant, 87 108, 111
imprinting, 103 memory, 37, 41, 45, 48, 64, 66, 144,
impossibility, 104 148, 150, 153
impulse Control, 37, 90, 150, 156 mereology, 22–3
incarceration, 86–7, 97–8, 162, 174 metaphysics, 6, 12, 20, 22, 26–7, 31
incentive sensitization, 38, 45–6, 123 methamphetamine, 37, 54, 92,
incentive salience phenomenon, 127 130–1
206 Index
mind, 4–7, 12, 14, 20–1, 25–9, 32, 36, poor, 10, 21, 40, 56, 80, 86–7, 89, 92,
47, 62, 99–100, 106–114, 120, 94, 97–8
149, 152, 154, 168 post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD),
mind altering chemical, 142, 147 91, 121, 152–4
miscommunication, 120 poverty, 86–7, 92, 94, 192
modularity, 49, 50 pragmatism, 105
motivation, 21, 36, 38–9, 42–6, 48, 51, prescription drugs, 81, 86, 96–7
53–6, 58, 68, 136, 143, 148, 156, price, 81, 93, 113
158, 172–4 prison, 86, 97, 118, 158, 161
protestant work ethic, 83
Naltrexone, 146, 175 profit, 46, 80, 82, 84, 97, 165
naturalism, 104, 109 prohibition, 84, 90, 98
nature, 25, 73–4, 83 prototypes, 109, 112, 115, 119,
Neil Levy, 17, 56 120, 125
nicotine (See Tobacco), 13, 37, 42–3, psychostimulants, 37, 42–3
47, 146 psychodynamic Theory, 136
necessity, 104 punctuated equilibrium, 126–7, 132
neural networks, 144 punishment, 71, 93, 174
neural systems, 2, 7, 40, 110, 144, 149
neuropsychology, 62 rage, 137, 139
neurotransmitter, 2–3, 6–7, 21–2, race, 77, 86
41, 43–4, 63, 65, 108, 144, 148, Rational Recovery, 173
151, 154 recovery, 3–4, 8, 10, 102–3, 105, 117,
normal/normality, 18, 22, 27, 42, 46, 142, 157, 159–60, 173, 175–6
64, 67–70, 90, 99, 106–7, 123, reductionism, 23, 33, 100
129–31, 137, 144–5, 153–4, Reiki, 175
162, 164 reinforcement, 43, 114, 157, 174
normative self-control, 128–9 rejection, 99, 122
nurturing, 62, 69, 114 relapse, 39, 42, 44–5, 50–1, 54, 56–7,
nutrition, 86, 94, 166, 175 62, 68, 71, 102, 121, 130, 143–4,
146–7, 150, 153, 167, 173
obsession, 95 release, 41, 63, 123
opium, 18, 37, 79–80, 93–4, 97, 137 remorse, 1, 20, 95, 102, 158
opioid manufacturers, 96 repression, 139
oxycontin, 37, 96 responsibility, 51, 84, 90–1, 125, 127,
morphine, 1, 37, 51–2, 69–70 136, 141, 157–8, 161, 166
reward
peers, 68, 77–8, 93–4, 115 reward circuit, 21, 43–4, 48, 60
perceptual apparatus, 109 reward seeking, 123, 127
personality, 73–4, 95, 132–3, 148
phenomenal authority, 124 salience, 3, 18, 33, 39–40, 45–6, 48,
phenomenology, 8, 122–3 125, 127, 136, 145
pharmaceutical, 96–7, 147 secrets, 135
philosophy, 15, 28, 99 sedatives, 139
Plato, 103–4 self-control, 17, 55–7, 126, 128–9,
plasticity, 7, 14, 41, 68, 151, 159 137, 150, 156
pleasure, 2, 37–8, 42, 44, 46–7, 63, 70, self-esteem, 167
84, 113, 115, 119, 127, 132, 138, self-medicate, 137, 139
148,158–9 self-regulation, 42, 65, 83, 153
Index 207