The Logic of Quantified Statements
The Logic of Quantified Statements
The Logic of Quantified Statements
THE LOGIC OF
QUANTIFIED
STATEMENTS
3
Arguments with Quantified Statements
A given theorem says that such and such is true for all
things of a certain type.
4
Universal Modus Ponens
5
Universal Modus Ponens
The rule of universal instantiation can be combined with
modus ponens to obtain the valid form of argument called
universal modus ponens.
6
Universal Modus Ponens
Note that the first, or major, premise of universal modus
ponens could be written “All things that make P (x) true
make Q (x) true,” in which case the conclusion would follow
by universal instantiation alone.
7
Example 1 – Recognizing Universal Modus Ponens
Solution:
The major premise of this argument can be rewritten as
x, if x is an even integer then x2 is even.
8
Example 1 – Solution cont’d
• S (k).
10
Use of Universal Modus Ponens in a Proof
11
Use of Universal Modus Ponens in a Proof
Hence
Thus m + n is even.
12
Use of Universal Modus Ponens in a Proof
13
Use of Universal Modus Ponens in a Proof
15
Universal Modus Tollens
16
Universal Modus Tollens
Another crucially important rule of inference is universal
modus tollens. Its validity results from combining universal
instantiation with modus tollens.
17
Example 3 – Recognizing the Form of Universal Modus Tollens
Solution:
The major premise can be rewritten as
x, if x is human then x is mortal.
18
Example 3 – Solution cont’d
19
Proving Validity of Arguments
with Quantified Statements
20
Proving Validity of Arguments with Quantified Statements
21
Using Diagrams to Test for
Validity
22
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
Consider the statement
All integers are rational numbers.
Or, formally,
Picture the set of all integers and the set of all rational
numbers as disks.
23
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
The truth of the given statement is represented by placing
the integers disk entirely inside the rationals disk, as shown
in Figure 3.4.1.
Figure 3.4.1
24
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
To test the validity of an argument diagrammatically,
represent the truth of both premises with diagrams.
25
Example 6 – Using Diagrams to Show Invalidity
26
Example 6 – Solution
The major and minor premises are represented
diagrammatically in Figure 3.4.4.
Figure 3.4.4
27
Example 6 – Solution cont’d
(a) (b)
Figure 3.4.5
28
Example 6 – Solution cont’d
29
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
The argument of Example 6 would be valid if the major
premise were replaced by its converse. But since a
universal conditional statement is not logically equivalent to
its converse, such a replacement cannot, in general, be
made.
30
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
The following form of argument would be valid if a conditional
statement were logically equivalent to its inverse. But it is not,
and the argument form is invalid.
31
Example 7 – An Argument with “No”
Use diagrams to test the following argument for validity:
32
Example 7 – Solution
A good way to represent the major premise diagrammatically
is shown in Figure 3.4.6, two disks—a disk for polynomial
functions and a disk for functions with horizontal asymptotes
—that do not overlap at all.
Figure 3.4.6
33
Example 7 – Solution cont’d
The diagram shows that “this function” must lie outside the
polynomial functions disk, and so the truth of the conclusion
necessarily follows from the truth of the premises.
34
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
An alternative approach to this example is to transform the
statement “No polynomial functions have horizontal
asymptotes” into the equivalent form “x, if x is a
polynomial function, then x does not have a horizontal
asymptote.”
35
Using Diagrams to Test for Validity
If this is done, the argument can be seen to have the form
36
Creating Additional Forms of
Argument
37
Creating Additional Forms of Argument
Universal modus ponens and modus tollens were obtained
by combining universal instantiation with modus ponens
and modus tollens.
38
Creating Additional Forms of Argument
Consider the following argument:
39
Example 8 – Evaluating an Argument for Tarski’s World
Figure 3.3.1
40
Example 8 – Evaluating an Argument for Tarski’s World
cont’d
42
Example 8 – Solution cont’d
43
Example 8 – Solution cont’d
In this example you can see that the first premise should
remain where it is, but the second and third premises
should be interchanged.
45
Example 8 – Solution cont’d
47
Remark on the Converse and Inverse Errors
48
Remark on the Converse and Inverse Errors
49
Remark on the Converse and Inverse Errors