PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES
Philosophical Perspectives, 26, Philosophy of Mind, 2012
INDISCRIMINABILITY AND PHENOMENAL CONTINUA
Diana Raffman
University of Toronto
The relation of perceptual indiscriminability is widely thought to be nontransitive: there can be a series of objects (stimuli) s 1 . . . s n in which s 1 is pairwise
indiscriminable on some perceptual dimension from s 2 , and s 2 is indiscriminable
from s 3 , and s 3 from s 4 , and so forth, but s n is discriminably different from s 1 .
For example, Timothy Williamson writes that
[t]wo stimuli whose difference is below the threshold cannot be discriminated.
Since many indiscriminable differences can add up to a discriminable difference,
one can have a series of stimuli each indiscriminable from its successor, of which
the first member is discriminable from the last. Indiscriminability is a nontransitive relation. (Williamson 1994, 69)
According to some theorists, the possibility (indeed, actuality) of a phenomenal
continuum—viz., a seemingly continuous progression from an instance of one
color (pitch, loudness, etc.) to an instance of another, incompatible color—shows
that perceptual indiscriminability must be nontransitive. Here is Crispin Wright,
for example:
It is familiar . . . that we may construct a series of suitable, homogeneously
coloured patches, in such a way as to give the impression of a smooth transition
from red to orange, where each patch is indiscriminable in colour from those
immediately next to it; it is the non-transitivity of indiscriminability which
generates this possibility. (Wright 1975, 338–9)
Suppose that we are to construct a series of colour patches, ranging from red
through to orange, among which indiscriminability is to behave transitively. We
are given a supply of appropriate patches from which to make selections, an initial
red patch C1, and the instruction that each successive patch must either match its
predecessor or be more like it than is any other patch not matching it which we
later use. Under these conditions it is plain that we cannot generate any change
in colour by selecting successive matching patches; since indiscriminability is to
be transitive, it will follow that if each Ci in the first n selections matches its
310 / Diana Raffman
predecessor, [then] Cn matches C1. The only way to generate a change in colour
will be to select a non-matching patch. (Wright 1976, 344–5)
The alleged nontransitivity seems to cause trouble wherever it goes, however.
Just for example, it threatens the coherence of the ordinary idea of determinate
perceptual qualities like shades, pitches, and intensities; and it helps to generate
a particularly toxic version of the sorites paradox. In what follows I want
to begin by illustrating the kinds of problems that are created by the alleged
nontransitivity, and the lengths to which philosophers have often had to go in
order to deal with them. Then I will suggest a way of thinking about phenomenal
continua that may eliminate some of the difficulty.
I
Before going further, we need to draw two important distinctions. First, we
need to distinguish between the statistical relation of indiscriminability and the
phenomenal relation of appearing (looking, sounding, tasting, etc.) the same.
The statistical relation, employed primarily in psychology and psychophysics, is
expressed in terms of percentages of same/different comparisons in which two
physically different stimuli appear the same. Thus understood, indiscriminability
is clearly nontransitive: there can be a series of stimuli s 1 . . . s n such that, under
some constant viewing conditions (suppose even that s 1 . . . s n are all in view
simultaneously), s 1 appears the same as s 2 in (e.g.) 75 percent of same/different
trials, s 2 appears the same as s 3 in 75 percent . . . and s n−1 appears the same as s n
in 75 percent, but s 1 and s n appear the same in only 30 percent of trials. (More
intuitively, perhaps: there can be a series of stimuli such that s 1 and s 2 can be
told apart 25 percent of the time, s 2 and s 3 can be told apart 25 percent of the
time, and so forth, but s 1 and s n can be told apart 70 percent of the time.)
In contrast, virtually all philosophical discussions of indiscriminability
concern not the statistical psychophysical relation but rather the phenomenal
relation of appearing (looking, sounding, etc.) the same, in terms of which the
statistical relation is defined.1 Philosophers tend to refer to stimuli as looking the
same as if this were an invariant relation, i.e., as if stimuli that “look the same”
under certain conditions always look the same under those conditions. But there
are no stimuli that always look the same, so it can be hard to understand what the
philosophers have in mind, and interpretative decisions may have to be made. In
order to connect with the philosophical discussions, for the sake of argument, in
what follows I will bracket this worry and go along with the idea that appearing
the same is an invariant relation. I’ll suppose that it’s the latter relation whose
nontransitivity is at issue.
The second distinction, observed by at least some philosophers working in
the area (e.g., Graff 2001, 927, Mills 2002, 391), is between (in)discriminability
construed as a relationship discernible in a single pairwise same/different
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 311
comparison (often expressed by saying of two objects that we can or cannot
“tell them apart”), and looking the same construed as a more demanding,
epistemically laden relationship. Pierre Chuard explains:
[F]allibilists about looks . . . argue that . . . indiscriminable adjacent patches may
well look different, despite their perceptual indiscriminability; it’s just that we
cannot notice the relevant differences in the chromatic appearances of such
patches . . . .[V]ery small differences in chromatic appearances may be visually
indiscriminable to normal perceivers because they cannot notice them, thus
lacking perfect access to small differences in how things look to them. (2007, 162)
In what follows, I will sometimes speak inexactly to keep my discussion from
becoming cumbersome; but where the differences are important or an author’s
usage is not clear from the context, I will do my best to distinguish these varying
senses of ‘indiscriminable’ and ‘looks the same’.
As I just mentioned, the alleged nontransitivity of indiscriminability appears
to threaten the coherence of the ordinary idea of determinate perceptual
(“phenomenal”) qualities. Intuitively we want to say that objects have the same
shade or pitch or loudness just in case they are indiscriminable, i.e., just in case
they appear the same, in the relevant respect. But unlike indiscriminability, the
identity relation is transitive; so this natural way of individuating determinate
qualities is not available. Peacocke observes:
[I]t is pretheoretically tempting to suppose that . . . perceived shades s and s’
are identical if and only if s is not discriminably different from s’. The nontransitivity of nondiscriminable difference (“matching”) entails that there is
no way of dividing the spectrum into shades that meets that condition. Take
an example in which, in respect of color, x matches, y matches z, but x does
not match z. To conform to the above principle about shades, the shade of y
would have to be identical with shades that are distinct from one another. (1981,
83)
Drawing a famously radical conclusion, Michael Dummett contends that the
nontransitivity of indiscriminability renders the idea of phenomenal qualities,
and the vague predicates that ostensibly express them, incoherent:
What, then, of phenomenal qualities? . . . [W]e cannot take ‘phenomenal quality’
in a strict sense, as constituting the satisfaction of an observational predicate,
that is, a predicate whose application can be decided merely by the employment
of our sense-organs: at least, not in any arena in which non-discriminable
difference is not transitive . . . .[T]here are no phenomenal qualities, as these
have been traditionally understood; and, while our language certainly contains
observational predicates[, they] infect it with inconsistency. (1975, 324)2
Conceptualism about the representational content of perceptual experience
(e.g., McDowell 1994, Brewer 2005) has also required treatment for difficulties
caused by the alleged nontransitivity of the indiscriminability relation. According
312 / Diana Raffman
to the conceptualist, all experiential content is conceptual: we can experience,
or perceptually represent, only what we can conceptualize upon inspection. An
apparent counterexample is our experience of determinate phenomenal qualities:
surely, opponents have argued, these shades, pitches, intensities, and the rest are
too fine-grained for us to conceptualize in this way. Conceptualists reply that, on
the contrary, we do have sufficiently fine-grained concepts—viz., demonstrative
concepts such as ‘this shade’ or ‘that shade of magenta’, or ‘that flat leading tone’.
For example, McDowell contends that you possess (and deploy) a demonstrative
concept of a given determinate shade of red just in case you can tell, after your
experience of the shade is over, whether a (closely) subsequent experience as of
a shade of red is as of that same shade.
The nontransitivity problem rears its head when we try to say what
representing that same shade consists in: how does your experience represent
objects as having the same shade? The natural answer: by representing them
in such a way that they are indiscriminable with respect to hue. But there the
problem takes hold, for this natural answer attempts to define the transitive
relation of sameness or identity with respect to hue, in terms of the nontransitive
relation of indiscriminability with respect to hue.3
Disjunctivism in the philosophy of mind also runs into trouble in its appeal
to the indiscriminability relation. Bucking tradition, the disjunctivist holds that
veridical perceptions are essentially different in kind from illusions and hallucinations.4 He thinks that the mind-independent entities that are the intentional
objects of our experiences are constituents of the experiences that are veridical;
and for obvious reasons, no such constituency can obtain in the case of illusions
or hallucinations. The disjunctivist acknowledges that veridical perceptions,
illusions, and hallucinations are all experiences, but he claims that what unites
them as such is just their indiscriminability from veridical perceptions—not, as
philosophical tradition would have it, their qualitative or intentional or adverbial
properties. Specifically, a mental event is an experience as of just in case it is
indiscriminable from a veridical perception of . M. G. F. Martin explains:
Rather than appealing to a substantive condition which an event must meet to
be an experience, and in addition ascribing to us cognitive powers to recognise
the presence of this substantive condition, [disjunctivism] instead emphasizes
the limits of our powers of discrimination and the limits of self-awareness: some
event is an experience of a street scene just in case it couldn’t be told apart
through introspection from a veridical perception of the street as the street . . . .
(2004, 48)
[A] challenge to the sufficiency of indiscriminability for identity of kind of
experience comes from the alleged nontransitivity of indiscriminability for some
observable properties. Certainly, given observers on particular occasions may
fail to detect the difference in shade between sample A and sample B, and also
fail to detect the difference between sample B and sample C, and yet be able
to detect the difference between sample A and sample C. If this leads us to
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 313
the conclusion that experiences of A are indiscriminable from experiences of B,
and experiences of B are indiscriminable from experiences of C, then we face a
problem supposing that there are kinds of event which are sensory experiences of
colour shades on the disjunctivist proposal. The indiscriminability of experience
of A and experience of B would require us to suppose that these are just the same
kind of experience; likewise for the experience of B and of C. By transitivity of
identity, this requires that the kind of experience one has of A is of the same
kind as the experience one has of C, but this contradicts the observation that
the experience of C is discriminable from the experience of A since kinds of
experience are discriminable only where distinct. (2004, 76)
If I understand correctly, Martin reasons that if two stimuli are indiscriminable,
then the experiences they occasion are indiscriminable, and experiences are
indiscriminable just in case they are phenomenally identical.5 Hence if indiscriminability is nontransitive, something has to give.
Now I want to consider some of the responses that defenders of these and
other affected views have made to the alleged nontransitivity problem.
II
The most common response to the problem has been to argue that the
relation of looking the same is transitive, or at least that there is no good reason
to think it’s nontransitive, because adjacent items in an ostensible phenomenal
continuum are, after all, either discriminably different (Hardin 1988, Burns 1994,
e.g.) or indiscriminable but phenomenally different (Graff 2001, Mills 2002, e.g.).6
Proponents of the latter option claim that although we cannot tell adjacent
items apart in a pairwise same/different comparison, they are nevertheless
phenomenally different, i.e., they appear (look, sound, taste) different. Hence
there can be no phenomenal continua after all.
I haven’t yet said exactly what a phenomenal continuum is. As a first approximation, a phenomenal continuum is a series of stimuli in which neighboring items
appear the same but the endpoints appear different, at a given time, to a perceiver
who proceeds along the series, inspecting each pair of neighboring stimuli. Or
better: a phenomenal continuum is a continuous progression in appearance that
is instantiated, at a time, by a series of stimuli in which neighboring items appear
the same but the endpoints appear different at that time, etc. The phenomenology
of phenomenal continua is baffling because, even given perfectly constant viewing
conditions, the first and last items appear different and yet nowhere between the
two is any local difference in appearance discerned.
Why think adjacent items in a putative phenomenal continuum are phenomenally different? And why, if they are phenomenally different, are they
indiscriminable, as “fallibilists” (Chuard 2007) have claimed? Typically, fallibilists
construe indiscriminability as an epistemic (rather than purely perceptual) failing,
but the details are unclear. They tend to cite factors—such as the small size of
314 / Diana Raffman
the relevant stimulus differences or the slow rate of the relevant change(s) of
appearance, or failures of attention—that might explain the indiscriminability
of neighboring items but do not obviously leave room for any phenomenal
differences as these are usually understood. Eugene Mills writes:
I deny first-person infallibility for the belief that two patches look as though they
share all their color-appearance properties. But infallibility for this belief is silly
anyway. Each patch has a vast array of color-appearance properties, nested and
otherwise. It is fantastic to suppose that in comparing two patches, I could not
fail to notice a slight difference with respect to one of these (at least) thousands
of colors. (2002, 391)7
Delia Graff expresses her view this way:
Another explanation, consistent with transitivity, is that when we look (say) at
the hour-hand on a clock, although it does in fact look to change in position
over the course of twenty-second intervals, the change in appearance is too slight,
and too slow, for us to notice it. We judge the hour-hand to look still, but our
judgement about the character of our experience is mistaken. (2001, 927)
According to the fallibilist, the relation of looking the same can be transitive
because adjacent items do not in fact look the same.8 Williamson suggests
that phenomenal continua do not (cannot?) exist because physically different
samples are always “impersonally” discriminable, i.e., because some observer
in some context could tell that the samples are different. The trouble with this
response is that all that’s required for nontransitivity is that some series of stimuli
instantiate the requisite sort of progression for some observer at some time. It’s
irrelevant whether some other observer could tell the stimuli in question apart.
John Zeimbikis (2009) writes that a
distinction between phenomenal indiscriminability and phenomenal identity is
adopted by Austen Clark (1989) when he says that that there are phenomenal differences below the threshold of sensible discrimination, or ‘a qualitative difference between the sensations engendered by indiscriminable things’.
The difference could also be described as that between looking phenomenally
identical and being phenomenally identical. (357–8)
The preceding are some examples of the strategies that philosophers have
been forced to adopt in response to the alleged nontransitivity of indiscriminability. In my view, granting that stimuli that cannot be told apart in a
pairwise comparison (under normal or standard conditions, whatever exactly
these may be) may nevertheless be phenomenally different—in other words, may
look different—or that stimuli that look phenomenally identical could fail to
be phenomenally identical, is too high a price to pay for a resolution of the
problem. In the remainder of this paper I will advance a different response to
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 315
the nontransitivity problem, one that may allow us to resolve it in a less drastic
way. Specifically, rather than postulating undetectable phenomenal differences
between indiscriminable adjacent items, I will urge that some of the individual
stimuli in (a series that instantiates) a phenomenal continuum change their
appearance, change how they look, as an observer moves along the series. In
other words, instead of a difference in appearance between adjacent items, I
will propose that a change occurs in the appearance of one or more items
individually. I’ll call this proposal the ‘instability hypothesis’.9 Of course, for
a claim of nontransitivity to hold good, the stimuli in a phenomenal continuum
must remain constant in appearance throughout; the instability hypothesis must
be false. A series in which the stimuli change their appearance doesn’t show that
appearing the same is nontransitive, any more than the fact that Tom and Dick
weigh the same, and Dick and Harry weigh the same, but Tom and Harry have
different weights, shows that identity is nontransitive if we’ve weighed Tom and
Dick in 2001, and then Dick and Harry in 2002, and then Tom and Harry in 2003.
In the next section I am going to present some experimental results that
seem to support the instability hypothesis. The conclusion we should draw, I’ll
suggest, is that neighboring stimuli in a phenomenal continuum appear (look,
sound, etc.) the same, but such a continuum provides no evidence that appearing
the same, in contrast to statistical indiscriminability, is nontransitive.
III
The experiment described below was designed and run in collaboration with
Delwin Lindsey of the Psychology Department and Angela Brown of the School
of Optometry at Ohio State University.10
The stimuli were a series of 41 patches of colored light that instantiated a
phenomenal continuum (on almost all trials) between two slightly but clearly
different shades of green. The stimuli were presented on a high-resolution color
monitor in the circular arrangement shown in Figure 1. Nothing depended upon
the locations of the endpoints. About half of the stimuli were redundant: roughly
every other patch in the circle was physically identical to its predecessor.11
Neighboring physically different patches differed by less than the discrimination
threshold or just noticeable difference in hue of our most sensitive subject. (We
had established the thresholds of our subjects in an earlier experiment, requiring
correct detection on 75% of trials.) The subjects in the experiment were ten
philosophy and psychology faculty, students, and staff at Ohio State University,
including several faculty and graduate students in psychology of vision.
Each trial began with a same/different comparison of the hues of two neighboring of ‘different’ (which happened rarely), the next trial began immediately
and she was cued to judge the next pair of patches. (If the patches are numbered
#1–#41, the order of the pairs was #1/#2, #2/#3, #3/#4, etc. Consecutive
pairs always shared a patch.) If the subject made a judgment of ‘same’, a disk
316 / Diana Raffman
endpoints
Figure 1. Stimuli as presented for the same/different task on each trial. Black dots cued the
subject to judge the indicated pair. The patches marked ’endpoints’ are clearly discriminable.
Figure 2. Stimuli as presented for the adjustment task on each trial. Subjects’ task was to adjust
the hue of the central disk to match the hue of the indicated pair.
of colored light appeared in the center of the circle, as pictured in Figure 2. The
subject then adjusted the hue of the disk by moving the computer mouse back
and forth until the disk matched the hue of the two patches. (The starting hue
of the disk and the directionality of the mouse were randomized.) The disk then
disappeared and the next trial began. In this way the subject was taken around
the circle, judging each pair of patches seriatim and adjusting the hue of the disk
accordingly. Subjects went around the circle twice. At the end of the experiment
we asked roughly half of the subjects if they had noticed any changes in the
colors of the patches during the experiment. All said ‘no’.
What we found was that even though all of the patches were in view
throughout, and the members of every pair were judged ‘same’ by every subject
on almost every trial, subjects’ settings of the disk progressed more or less
systematically with the physical values (wavelengths) of the patches.12 In other
words, subjects matched the pair #2/#3 to a longer wavelength than the pair
#1/#2, the pair #3/#4 to a longer wavelength than the pair #2/#3, and so on.
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 317
Figure 3. Data from an individual subject, showing a systematic progression of the setting of
the disk on more or less every trial.
More to the point, patch #2 was matched to a different wavelength when it was
compared to #1 than when it was compared to #3; patch #3 was matched to
a different wavelength when compared to #2 than when compared to #4; and
so on. Data from one subject, which are typical, are pictured in Figure 3. On
the y-axis is the setting of the disk (in arbitrary units), and on the x-axis is
the number of the stimulus pair to which the disk was being matched. Black
triangles indicate redundant trials in which the stimuli in a pair were physically
identical; white squares indicate trials in which stimuli were physically different.
Since the graphs show the disk settings, the data points (squares and triangles)
represent all and only trials in which the members of a pair were judged ‘same’.
(The graphs contain more than 41 data points because subjects went around
the circle twice; hence pairs that were judged ‘same’ both times received two
disk settings.) The curve shows fairly steady progression of the disk settings as
subjects progressed through the pairs of patches, for both the physically identical
and physically different pairs.13
No doubt our data admit of various interpretations. But I think that at the
least they cast doubt upon the idea that neighboring patches are phenomenally
different, i.e., that they look different. If anything, the data suggest that individual
patches looked different in their different pairwise comparisons. We must proceed
with caution here, though. It is overwhelmingly likely that our subjects could not
have recognized, could not have noticed, any such change of hue. And this lack of
recognition would not be analogous to (for example) change blindness, in which
observers become aware of the change in question as soon as their attention is
drawn to it or the relevant visual disruption is removed. (Subjects who experience
change blindness fail to notice changes, often large ones, in visual scenes when
318 / Diana Raffman
the changes occur during a visual disruption such as a saccade or blink or a cut in
a film.14 For example, viewers in one experiment failed to notice that two people
in a scene had exchanged heads (Grimes 1996.) Nor would it be analogous to
attentional blindness, in which, again, subjects see a previously unnoticed aspect
of the stimulus array as soon as they start paying attention to it. In contrast, in
our experiment, making the same/different comparisons and setting the hue of
the disk required sustained conscious attention, with no visual disruption.
Nevertheless, I do want to suggest that phenomenal changes occurred in
the appearances of one or more of the patches as subjects proceeded around
the circle. But why is a hypothesis of unrecognized phenomenal changes in
individual patches more plausible than the fallibilists’ hypothesis of unrecognized
phenomenal differences between adjacent patches? I think there are at least
three reasons. First, there are circumstances, different from the ones in the
change and attentional blindness scenarios, in which these phenomenal changes
could be recognized by the subject herself (or so I predict–more on this in a
moment); second, recognition of such changes in appearance would defeat the
nontransitivity claim but leave phenomenal continua intact; third, there will be
no need to endorse the fallibilists’ counterintuitive claim that stimuli judged the
same in a pairwise comparison may nonetheless look different.
Let me illustrate what I have in mind. (I have not done an experiment to test
the hypothesis I’m about to put forward; for now I can only make a prediction.)
IV
Consider a hypothetical version of the experiment using only 6 (nonredundant) patches, arranged in a straight line, progressing from one shade of
green to another, slightly but perceptibly different one. Suppose that you perform
the experimental tasks at some time t, and you reproduce our results: you judge
adjacent patches the same and the endpoints #1 and #6 different, and your disk
settings progress steadily. How then should we characterize the phenomenology:
how do the patches look to you? Specifically, as against the fallibilists, can we
characterize how the patches look, compatibly with preserving the intuition that
objects judged the same in a pairwise comparison appear the same?
Perhaps, despite the systematic progression of your disk settings, until a
patch that is pairwise clearly different from patch #1—ex hypothesi #6—becomes
sufficiently prominent in your attentional field, all of the patches you have
observed to that point (viz., #1-#5) look the same, i.e., you have no experience
of a phenomenal progression. (Plausibly, the same/different judgment of each
successive pair of patches is made in a distinct attentional act, and you cannot
attend to all 6 patches, a fortiori all 6 pairs, simultaneously.) However, when
#6 enters your attentional field, you experience a phenomenal progression. The
question is: if #1 and #5 look the same pairwise, how does #6 get to look
different from #1 without #5 looking different from #6?
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 319
My thought is that #5 and #6 never need to look different because as soon
as #6 looks different from #1, so does #5, and maybe also #4, depending upon
how much attention #4 receives. Thus #5 (and possibly #4) undergoes a shift
in its hue appearance as you shift your attention from the #4/#5 pair to the
#5/#6 pair; #5 looks different in its two comparison pairings with #4 and #6.15
And you can notice this. I predict that if you were to scan quickly back and forth
along the series, from one end (#1) to the other (#6), you would see and notice,
would recognize, at least some of the patches between #1 and #6 subtly (very
subtly!) shifting their hues back and forth, together, now looking like #1, now
like #6, now like #1, now like #6. The result would be that you never see a hue
difference between adjacent patches. The fallibilist would contend that adjacent
patches look different to you, but unrecognizably so; in effect, he asks us to take
these phenomenal differences on faith. In contrast, on the view I am proposing,
you can recognize the kind of phenomenal change that (e.g.) #5 undergoes.
I remarked earlier that our experimental subjects probably could not have
noticed or recognized hue shifts of the kind that, if I am right, would be
recognized in (e.g.) a shorter series like #1-#6. There may be various reasons
why: for example, maybe the large number of stimuli used in the experiment, or
their circular arrangement, or the slow and halting pace of subjects’ progression
through the series, or the demands of performing two different tasks, made
the hue shifts unnoticeable. Whatever the reasons, they are compatible with the
notion that one or more individual patches in the experimental series changed
their appearance, changed how they looked, even if subjects could not notice
that.
This changing of hue appearance is what makes a phenomenal continuum
possible, enabling the first and last items to appear different although nowhere
between the two is any local difference in appearance discerned. It makes possible
the perception of an apparently smooth, continuous progression in hue. To put
the point another way, these subtle changes, not any nontransitivity, are what
make phenomenal continua possible. If this is correct, then neighboring items in
a phenomenal continuum do indeed look—“really look” (cf. Graff, 2001)—the
same in pairwise comparisons, but the instability of their appearances across
different pairings defeats the nontransitivity claim.
The picture I am proposing requires letting go of the notion that shades
of color are stable, mind-independent properties of objects, “out there” on their
surfaces. Shades are neither stable nor mind-independent nor (simply) out there.
Under normal or standard conditions (we leave open what these are), shades are
informative about what’s out there, in particular about the surfaces of objects
and the light striking them. But they are also informative about what’s “in here”–
about the state of my visual system, what I have been looking at recently, what
order I have been judging things in, and so forth.
Where then have we gotten to? I proposed the instability hypothesis as a
way of undercutting the nontransitivity claim with respect to the relation of
appearing the same, without being pushed into the counterintuitive strategies
320 / Diana Raffman
described earlier. To the extent that it succeeds, the hypothesis allows us to
(1) reject the nontransitivity claim, (2) acknowledge the reality of phenomenal
continua, and (3) preserve the intuition that stimuli judged the same in a pairwise
comparison look the same. In addition, nothing in the proposed account stands
in the way of claiming that whenever two or more stimuli look the same, they
share a look—viz., a determinate quality (shade, pitch, loudness, etc). This isn’t
yet to provide identity conditions for shades or looks; indeed, I don’t think
that such identity conditions can be formulated in terms of discriminatory
or same/different judgments. I think there is a way to do it, in terms of a
perceptual task called magnitude estimation, in which shades are identified by
their percentages of different chromatic components. For example, unique blue
is the shade containing 100% blue and 0% of any other hue; balanced orange
is the shade containing 50% red and 50% yellow; balanced red-orange contains
75% red and 25% yellow; and so on. I cannot go into the details here, but see
my 2013 for discussion.
Notes
1. As we’ll see, not everyone would accept the idea that statistical indiscriminability
is defined in terms of appearing the same.
2. See also Goodman 1951.
3. I don’t mean to suggest that the conceptualist is without a response (though
I think the present predicament is not easily escaped; see e.g. Pelling 2007 for
discussion). My present goal is just to illustrate the kinds of difficulties posed by
the alleged nontransitivity.
4. Here I ignore many significant differences among disjunctivist positions; see e.g.
Haddock and Macpherson 2008 and Soteriou 2009 for detailed surveys.
5. The notion of (in)discriminability as a relation between experiences is probably
not coherent; see Siegel 2004, 109, and my 2013.
6. Briefly, the trouble with Hardin’s and Burns’s ingenious proposals is that
nontransitivity requires only that adjacent items appear the same and the
endpoints appear different, to some individual observer on some single occasion.
7. Consider that in order for Mills’ view here to undercut the nontransitivity claim, I
must invariably fail to notice some such slight difference. Nontransitivity requires
only the possibility of a single occasion on which adjacent items in the series
look the same, to a single subject.
8. Adopting this view allows Graff (2001) to hold on to the principle that “if two
samples really do look alike then they share a look”.
9. An ancestor of the instability hypothesis is proposed, but not tested, in my 2000.
10. Lindsey.43@osu.edu, Brown.112@osu.edu. These experimental results are presented also in my 2011 and 2013, for different philosophical purposes.
11. There were 21 physically distinct stimulus values (wavelengths; but see note 9). If
we label the 21 values as a–u, their order in the circle can be specified as a, a, b,
b, c, c, and so on. Consecutive trials then involved the pairs a/a, a/b, b/b, b/c,
c/c, and so on. (The “redundant” pairs [a/a, b/b, etc.] tested for false alarms,
Indiscriminability and Phenomenal Continua / 321
12.
13.
14.
15.
viz., ‘different’ responses to identical stimuli. The latter data are irrelevant to the
present discussion.)
For convenience I use the term ‘wavelength’, but strictly speaking it is incorrect.
Rather, the stimuli were mixtures of broadband lights, and neither the primaries
nor the mixtures had a defined wavelength.
This result suggests that subjects may have been matching the hue of the disk to
the mean physical value of the two patches in each pair.
Though see Simons et al. 2000.
Note that I have said nothing about the related, difficult question of how an
unattended patch looks at any given time. For example, when you are making
a same/different judgment of the #5/#6 pair, how does #3 look? I am not
certain of the answer. One possibility is that unless stimuli are attended to at
least some significant degree, the contents of our experiences of them are merely
“determinable”, becoming determinate only when our attention focuses on them.
For instance, maybe the content of our unattended experience of #3 could be
expressed by something like ‘on the way from the green of #5 and #6 to the
slightly yellower green of #1’. I am not now in a position to develop the latter
idea further, however. While this question about experiences of the unattended
patches will need to be answered soon, I think it doesn’t need to be answered
immediately. (I will say more below about the nature of the determinate contents
of our hue experiences of attended stimuli.)
References
Brewer, B., 2005. “Perceptual Experience Has Conceptual Content”. In M. Steup and E. Sosa
(Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (Blackwell), pp. 217–230.
Burns, L., 1994. “Something to do with Vagueness”, in Spindel Conference 1994: Vagueness.
Southern Journal of Philosophy 33 [supplement], ed. T. Horgan, 23–48.
Chuard, P., 2007. “Indiscriminable Shades and Demonstrative Concepts”. Australasian Journal
of Philosophy, 85 (2): 277–306.
Clark, A., 1989. “The Particulate Instantiation of Homogeneous Pink”. Synthese, 80 (2): 277–
304.
Dummett, M., 1975. “Wang’s Paradox”. Synthese, 30: 301–24.
Graff, D., 2001. “Phenomenal Continua and the Sorites”. Mind, 110, 440: 905–935.
Goodman, N., 1951. The Structure of Appearance. Harvard University Press.
Grimes, J. 1996. “On the failure to detect changes in scenes across saccades”, in Akins, K. (Eds.),
Perception (Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science) 2, 89–110. Oxford University Press.
Haddock, A., and Macpherson, F., (Eds.) 2008. “Introduction” to Disjunctivism: Perception,
Action, Knowledge. Oxford University Press.
Hardin, C., 1988. “Phenomenal Colors and Sorites”. Nous, 22: 213–34.
Martin, M. G. F., 2004. “The Limits of Self-Awareness”. Philosophical Studies, 120: 37–89.
McDowell, J., 1994. Mind and World. Harvard University Press.
Mills, E., 2002. “Fallibility and the Phenomenal Sorites”. Nous, 36 (3): 384–407.
Peacocke, C., 1981. “Are Vague Predicates Incoherent?” Synthese, 46: 121–141.
Pelling, C., 2007. “Conceptualism and the (Supposed) Non-transitivity of Colour Indiscriminability”. Philosophical Studies, 134: 211–234.
Raffman, D., 2000. “Is Phenomenal Indiscriminability Nontransitive?”(Eds.) C. Hill Philosophical Topics 28, 1, Vagueness, pp. 69–87.
322 / Diana Raffman
Raffman, D., 2011. “Vagueness and Observationality”. In Giuseppina Ronzitti (Eds.), Vagueness:
A Guide (Springer)
Raffman, D., forthcoming 2013. “Indiscriminability, Discrimination, and Categorization”. In
Berit Brogaard (Eds.), Does Perception Have Content? Oxford University Press.
Siegel, S., 2004. “Indiscriminability and the Phenomenal”. Philosophical Studies, 120 (1–3):
91–112.
Simons, D., Franconeri, S., and Reimer, R., 2000. “Change blindness in the absence of a visual
disruption”. Perception, 29: 1143–1154.
Soteriou, M., 2009. “The Disjunctive Theory of Perception”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI, Stanford University.
Williamson, T., 1994. Vagueness. Routledge.
Wright, C., 1975. “On the Coherence of Vague Predicates”. Synthese, 30, 3/4: 325–65.
Wright, C., 1976. “Language Mastery and the Sorites Paradox”. In G. Evans and J. McDowell
(Eds.), Truth and Meaning, pp. 223–47. Clarendon Press.
Zeimbekis, J., 2009. “Phenomenal and Objective Size”. Nous, 43, 2: 346–362.