eScholarship
International Journal of Comparative Psychology
Title
The Mind of Organisms: Some Issues About Animal Cognition
Permalink
https://escholarship.org/uc/item/1tt1r1pd
Journal
International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 6(2)
ISSN
0889-3675
Authors
Previde, Emanuela Prato
Colobetti, Marco
Poli, Marco
et al.
Publication Date
1992
License
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 4.0
Peer reviewed
eScholarship.org
Powered by the California Digital Library
University of California
International Journal of Comparative Psychology, Vol.
6,
No.
2,
1992
THE MIND OF ORGANISMS:
SOME ISSUES ABOUT ANIMAL COGNITION
Emanuela Prato Previde
Universita degli Studi di Milano
Marco Colombetti
Politecnico di Milano
Marco
Poli
Universita degli Studi di Milano
Emanuela Cenami Spada
Universita degli Studi di Milano
Sense sure you have,
Else could you not have motion.
Hamlet,
III,
4
INTRODUCTION
The study
of animal behavior
dition, starting with
ceptions, like
Romanes
and
intelligence has a fairly long tra-
naive mentalism.
Tolman and Kohler,
With a few noble
ex-
psychological research on animals has
been dominated by the behaviorist paradigm, and only in the last fifteen
years has there been a substantial growth of interest in the analysis of
cognitive processes in animals. This renewed impetus towards a cognitive
approach, as opposed to a strict behaviorist perspective, resulted from
both internal problems and external influences: on the one hand, there
were
difficulties in explaining all instances of
ditional
S-R approach; on the
scientific respectability,
psychology and
behavior within the tra-
other, mental concepts were gaining a
thanks to the development of
human
new
cognitive
artificial intelligence.
Address correspondence to E. Prato Previde, Istituto di Psicologia, Facolta di Medicina
e Chirurgia, Universita degli Studi di Milano, via F. Sforza 23, 20122 Milano, Italy.
1992 International Society for Comparative Psychology
79
80
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
In the late sixties, the powerful influence of behaviorism on animal
psychology began to decrease, as a consequence of a variety of empirical
data, which proved difficult to explain, or even contradicted the fundamental assumptions of S-R theories. Phenomena such as autoshaping,
selective attention, conditioned learning of taste aversions, and preferential learning of some responses showed that the traditional laws of
learning were inadequate to explain every conceivable case of learned
behavior, in humans as well as in other animal species.
While learning theory continued to evolve in response to empirical
accommodate all the new findings within the clasconception through ad hoc adjustments of the accepted laws, a
growing number of comparative psychologists felt that the basic assumptions of behaviorism needed to be re-examined.
Along this line, a number of studies questioned the universality of the
S-R laws of behavior at both the intra- and the interspecific level, focusing
on the relevance of biological factors in controlling behavior. This area
of study stimulated debate on biological constraints and adaptive specializations in learning (Bolles, 1970; Hinde & Stevenson-Hinde, 1973;
Rozin & Kalat, 1971; Seligman, 1970; Shettleworth, 1972), promoting
concern for functional approaches to the study of learning (Hollis, 1984;
Staddon, 1983).
A diff'erent line of research has attempted to apply the tools of human
cognitive psychology to the study of animal behavior. In recent years, a
number of systematic attempts have been made to explore this possibility
in a comparative frame of reference. This is the case for comparative
analyses of short and long term memory (Van der Wall, 1982; Grant,
Brewster, & Stierhoff, 1983; Vaughan & Green, 1984; Roberts & Van
Veldhuizen, 1985), studies of cognitive maps (O'Keefe & Nadel, 1978;
Gaffan & Gowling, 1984; Gould, 1984, 1986), works on categorization and
concept formation (Herrnstein, 1984, 1990; Lea, 1984), studies on linguistic abilities of diff'erent species (Ristau & Robbins, 1982; Herman,
1986; Schusterman & Gisiner, 1988; Pepperberg, 1991), and research on
natural communication systems in animals (Snowdon, 1987). Although
not yet conclusive, the results of these studies are beginning to take a
coherent shape, providing important information for answering questions
about the evolution of cognition, and suggesting new and stimulating
directions for future research. It is with this approach that we are concerned here.
This paper is neither a review of all relevant work in animal cognition,
nor a complete, detailed survey of the theoretical stands taken by researchers in the field: even though the discipline is still young, a similar
endeavor would require at least a book size work. Our aim is rather to
present, analyze and discuss the basic assumptions of animal cognition,
focusing on those aspects that appear to be central today, and will presumably continue to be so in the near future. The questions are: What
challenges, trying to
sical
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
AL.
81
do those who study animal cognition intend to achieve? And why? And
how?
1, we state the main goals of those who study animal cogand argue that this discipline has an intrinsically comparative
nature. In Section 2, we delineate some classical objections to cognitivism,
show that they have been overcome by present day methodology, and
In Section
nition,
introduce the notion of representation as the basic element of cognition.
3, we introduce the view of representations as mental states,
In Section
i.e.,
states
endowed with content; an
alternative perspective, based on
the notions of form and formal manipulation, is presented in Section
Finally, in Section 5 we draw some conclusions.
1
.
4.
THE WHY AND THE WHAT OF ANIMAL COGNITION
What a piece of work is a man!
how noble in reason! how infinite
.].' The beauty of the
[.
world, the paragon of animals!
in faculty
.
Hamlet,
II,
2
While the study of human cognition arose as a clear-cut break with the
behaviorist paradigm, animal cognition, partly due to the nature of the
available data, necessarily maintains a certain degree of continuity with
the traditional methods.
The
cognitive approach brings to the compar-
ative psychologist a further set of tools for the formulation of theoretical
models of animal
intelligence. In the
words of Roitblat, Bever, and Ter-
race (1984),
Animal cognition
concerned with explaining animal behavior on the
and processes, as well as on the basis of observable variables such as stimuli and responses, (p. 1)
is
basis of cognitive states
Whatever position one may adopt towards cognitive states and proit is clear that the main reason for attributing cognition to animals
is that we, as humans, do experience a mental life. While such an attribution is in agreement with a unitary and evolutionary view of organisms,
it introduces an element of anthropomorphism, which has often motivated suspicion or rejection by scientists. However, animal cognition does
not imply a straightforward transfer to animals of models of human
thought, which would indeed be unjustified; rather, it is to be taken as
cesses,
a source of possible explanatory hypotheses about the unobservable determinants of animal behavior, which are then to be tested through a
strict empirical methodology. It is expected that by careful experimental
control the anthropomorphic
harmless
component of cognitive models can be made
— as harmless as the anthropomorphic component of concepts
like force
and energy
in classical physics.
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
82
Given that the prototype of cognition is, by definition, human thought,
animal cognition appears to be an intrinsically comparative study of
intelligence: the direction of comparison goes from humans to animals,
then back again to humans. In fact, even though the fundamental concepts of the cognitive approach originate in human psychology, we expect
that they will be substantially enriched and refined through the attempt
to apply them to other species. Although the physical continuity between
humans and the other species was accepted more than one century ago,
the problem of the continuity of mental capabilities has not yet been
satisfactorily solved.
But what are the fundamental concepts
of a comparative study of
cognition? As Roitblat says (1987),
Comparative cognition is the study of the mind of organisms and the
ways in which those minds produce adaptive behaviors. It is an approach to understanding behavior that emphasizes what animals know
and how they use that information in guiding their behavior. Comparative cognition seeks to understand how animals acquire, process,
store, and use knowledge about their world, (p. xii)
As already remarked, cognition is concerned with explaining behavior
not only through observable variables like stimuli and responses, but
also on the basis of cognitive states and processes, which are not directly
observable. Apparently, the goal has not changed since the time of Romanes. But what sounds similar need not be the same. There is no room
in contemporary "cognitivism" for naive anthropomorphism; as we shall
argue in the next section, the criticisms made to Romanes' easygoing
approach are not pertinent any more.
There are basically two orders of considerations that motivate a cognitive approach to the study of animal behavior. The first one, as we
have already suggested, arises from the limitations of behaviorism, and
views cognitive concepts as hypothetical constructs that might provide
better explanations of empirical data. From this standpoint, cognitive
science does not diff"er from any other natural science, in that it postulates
unobservable entities to explain the regularities of observable phenomena. Such entities are justified when they provide economical and general
interpretations of complex findings, and produce predictions that are
experimentally testable.
But comparative cognition has also a completely independent motivation, which is often overshadowed by the previous one. As regards the
human species, cognition is not so much an explanatory construct as a
plain matter of fact: mental states are part of subjective reality before
entering the theoretician's tool kit. But the mind is a very complex
and Darwin teaches us that any such thing stands in
need of an evolutionary explanation: Where does cognition come from?
biological entity,
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET AL
How
did
it
evolve?
Is
Homo
83
sapiens the only cognitive organism on the
earth?
two sides to cognition: it is a tool for understanding
phenomenon to be understood in its own right; and
we believe that a comparative approach should be concerned with both
So, there are
behavior, but also a
issues.
number of questions arise. Are there real methodproblems with the use of mental notions in natural science? If
not, what makes the mental different from the nonmental? How can
mental processes be described? And then: What is the adaptive value of
cognition? Are there species-specific differences in mental processes?
In the following sections, we shall consider possible answers to some
At
this point, a
ological
of these questions.
2.
NATURAL SCIENCE AND THE CONCEPT OF MIND
Behaviorism emerged as a reaction to the fuzzy, prescientific use of
mental terminology in "internal eye" psychology. Mental concepts were
regarded to be incompatible with the materialistic stand required by a
mature scientific discipline, and were viewed as uneconomical and superfluous in a science of behavior. Moreover, mental explanations were
considered to be unfalsifiable, in that it was always possible to find one
that fitted any experimental data.
As documented in the scientific literature (Sober, 1983), the revival of
mind was made possible by the overcoming of these
objections. Here we shall run quickly through this matter, focusing on a
a science of the
few points which are particularly relevant for our goals.
A first objection to the use of mental concepts in science was that
mental processes are not physical. A similar assumption is certainly part
and parcel of the Cartesian doctrine, but it is by no means a necessary
corollary of the concept of mind. As remarked by Place back in 1956, it
is perfectly sound to assume that typical mental features, like consciousness, are features of neurophysiological processes: the mind need not be
less physical than any other process studied in natural science. In talking
about the mind we must be very careful, because in ordinary language
the terms "physical" and "mental" are opposite; it is therefore up to
natural science to construe the notion of mental process so that it is a
special kind of physical process.
When we accept this assumption, we might be tempted to get com-
any notion of mind and to consider only neurophysiological
phenomena. In fact, this position is advocated by the so-called "eliminativists," like Churchland (1981). The main problem with this approach
pletely rid of
is
that
it fails
to identify the characteristic properties of the mental.
Given that mental processes are neurophysiological, not
all
neurophys-
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
84
need to be mental; but how can we find out which
we do not have an independent theory of the mind? As
iological processes
ones are,
if
remarked by Sober (1983), there
is
a big difference between explaining
the mental, and explaining it away.
It is important to note that leaving the neural level to deal with mental
states does not force us to analyze the subjective quality of conscious
experience. Phenomenological issues, put forward by Griffin as the core
of cognitive enquiry (1978, 1981, 1984), pose problems far beyond the
present possibilities of experimental research. But, as we shall see in the
following sections, cognitive science has developed concepts and methods
to deal with the mind from an objective, rather than subjective, standpoint.
The
is therefore to build an independent theory of mental proby putting forward a number of hypothetical constructs for the
explanation of behavior from an objective standpoint. As stressed by
Chomsky (1959), there is no special problem in postulating unobservable
entities in scientific theories; almost any science deals with hypothetical
entities that can only be inferred from observable events.
A frequent objection to the use of mental explanations is based on the
well-known Morgan's canon (1894), stating that:
goal
cesses,
... in
no case may we interpret an action
of a higher psychical activity,
if it
as the outcome of the exercise
can be interpreted as the outcome
of one which stands lower in the psychological scale,
However,
.
.
.
in
(p.
53)
1903 Morgan himself added that:
the canon by no means excludes the interpretation of a particular
if we already have independent evidence of the occurrence of these higher processes in the animal
under observation, (p. 59)
activity in terms of the higher processes,
Again we have a situation common to many sciences. A general theory,
accounting for a whole set of phenomena through higher level concepts,
is preferable to a theory that explains the same phenomena by lower
level processes, but requires several ad hoc adjustments to encompass
all of them. In fact, one of the goals of the study of comparative cognition
is to provide general explanations of a wide range of observable behaviors.
Perhaps a more severe objection, put forward by Skinner (1964), is
that mental explanations can always be made to fit any experimental
finding, thus dooming mental theories to be unfalsifiable. In fact, this
appears to be an actual risk for cognitive theories, that have a very
complex equipment of unobservable entities. Therefore, comparative
cognition must take great care to avoid falling into this trap. This point
will be considered in the following sections.
To summarize, the cognitive approach is based on two fundamental
assumptions. The first assumption is that cognitive processes are physical
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET AL
and
85
nervous system of
that cognitive processes can be described
biological, in that they are fully realized in the
the organism.
The second one is
at an abstract level,
making no reference
either to the specific quality of
the subjective experience of the organism, or to the processes taking
place at the neural level.
It has been argued that to keep the concept of mind in a scientific
and define instances of mind, and
to establish a set of procedures and empirical markers with some degree
of consistency; (ii) to show that the concept of mind will serve to more
efficiently integrate and organize existing information; (iii) to demoncontext
it is
necessary:
(i)
to identify
strate that the formulation permits the derivation of specific, testable
mind and its influences on
are, however, very genrecommendations
behavior (Gallup, 1982). These
formulas
for deciding if and
nor
simple
eral and contain neither reliable
predictions about the presence or absence of
when we should use
cognitive terms
when
dealing with animals.
In fact, in order to explain behavior, many contemporary comparative
psychologists use a mass of technical terms that have an intrinsic cognitive connotation, even if they are not always defined in a precise way.
A list of such terms includes cognitive map, perception, memory, concept,
representation, expectation, rule, goal, behavior plan, linguistic ability,
and intelligence.
Although these terms cover a wide range of
different ideas, they share
which, therefore, qualrepresentation,
notion
of
underlying
the common
ifies as the central concept of cognitive theories. In fact, two different
views of representations have been adopted in animal cognition. The first
approach, presented in the next section, regards representations as mental states, defined by a mode and a content, both involved in causing
behavior. Typical mental states are beliefs and desires about objects,
facts and events in the environment. According to the second perspective,
known as information processing psychology (Section 4), representations
code information about the environment, and their ability to mediate
between stimuli and responses relies upon transformations performed
by computational processes, which are sensitive to their formal structure.
3.
THE SEMANTIC MIND
A possible
ethology,
is
approach, which
is
gaining favor especially within cognitive
to regard representations as particular types of internal states,
such as beliefs and desires, that can be held by organisms. In analytic
philosophy, such states are called mental or intentional, and their characteristic property is that they are about objects and states of aff'airs in
the outside world: for example, a belief is always the belief that something
is the case, and a desire is the desire that something be the case. It is
important to note that the term "intentional," here, does not mean voluntary or purposive as in everyday English; following a tradition started
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
86
by Brentano and Husserl, and continued by a number of contemporary
it just means about something, and, therefore, has
a broader sense. What we call "intentions" in everyday language is just
one possible form of intentionality.
When representations are regarded as mental states, their essential
feature is content. Representations have a content, in that they represent
philosophers of mind,
something: objects of the external world, relationships among objects,
other words, representations hold a semantic relationship with the environment.
Mental states are made up not only by a content, but also by a mode
facts, events, etc. In
(Searle, 1983).
Examples of modes
are: to believe that, to desire that, to
Note that, in terms that should
be more familiar to comparative psychologists, holding a belief is nothing
more than possessing certain information about the environment, while
a desire is just a goal or a purpose. Two different mental states may have
distinct modes, while sharing the same content. For example, the belief
that one's offspring is safe and the desire that one's offspring be safe are
two distinct mental states, with equal content and different modes.
see that, to intend to, to fear that, etc.
The idea of a semantic relationship between representations and reality
human conscious experience: for example, the experience
we have when we see something is that there are real objects out there,
originates in
showing certain properties and relationships. In fact, consciousness is
taken as the central issue in the study of cognition by Griffin (1978, 1981,
1984), who defines cognitive ethology as the study of the mental experiences of animals.
Even
one accepts that representations presuppose conscious expenot the subjective quality of the experience itself that is under
investigation. In fact, such a subjective quality is impossible to assess:
how could we possibly know what it is like to be a bat? (Nagel, 1974)
Fortunately, the aim of a scientific study of the minds of other animals
is not to find out what it is like to be a certain type of animal, but rather
to clarify how mental states cause observable behavior. In order for
mental states to have an explanatory role, their power to produce behavior has to be a function of their constitutive features, i.e., their content
and mode. But content and mode can be defined without trying to make
the actual quality of experience explicit. Consider for example the perception of colors. The ability of an animal to discriminate objects of
different colors, plus the presence of cones in the retina, would be considered as sufficient evidence that the animal has color vision. Even if
we have no idea of the exact nature of the experience of the animal when
it is looking at a red triangle, we can take colors into account when
rience,
if
it is
describing the content of the animal's visual perceptions.
A
and desires, is
mind the definitions
characteristic property of mental states, like beliefs
that they exhibit a logic. For example, keeping in
and desire given above, from the belief that there is an intruder
near the nest, and the belief that intruders are dangerous for the offspring,
of belief
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET AL
follows the belief that the offspring
87
is
in danger.
The attribution of logical
capacities to animals
may appear
morphism. But
not necessarily the case, as simple logic does not
this
is
as a piece of unjustified anthropo-
require high level abilities, like that of reflecting upon one's own beliefs
and concepts, which might well be specific to the human species. As
Griffin (1991) reminds us, complex phenomena like self-awareness and
thinking about the process of thinking itself are by no means necessary
components of cognition: in fact, to think that they are so would be the
real anthropocentric mistake.
The view
of representations as mental states, which
is
traditional in
accepted in cognitive science. One common
criticism is that notions like belief and desire are metaphoric and, while
used in everyday "folk psychology," have little to share with real science
analytic philosophy,
is
far less
Ho^^^er, the work of philosophers like Dennett (1987) and
Searle (1983) and pioneering research in animal cognition show that
mental states, and in particular beliefs and desires, can be employed as
useful explanatory tools and undergo rigorous scientific investigation.
The fact that "belief and "desire" are part of the folk vocabulary
used to describe everyday behavior does not mean that the same terms
cannot be used technically. It is inevitable for a science of the mind to
have some overlap with everyday language. Similarly, linguists use terms
like "sentence" and "name" in a strictly technical way, and nobody thinks
that they are producing "folk linguistics"; the same is true for such terms
of physics like "force" and "energy." Furthermore, terms like "belief
and "desire" are by no means metaphors. The ascription of mental states
to an organism, in order to explain its behavior, is meant to be literal,
not metaphoric, in that it is assumed to describe at a high level of
(Stich, 1983).
abstraction
—
—
a real physical state of the organism.
Once more, there is
body moves
difference with respect to other sciences: to say that a
no
under the action of gravitational force
is
a literal statement, not a met-
a theoretical construct.
aphoric one, even
can
be
used to explain behavior, we
and
desires
before
beliefs
Clearly,
need a general theory of mental states. Here we shall consider two difif
the notion of force
is
ferent approaches: Dennett's intentional stance
and
Searle's biological
naturalism.
In the field of animal cognition, the best known approach to intentional
explanation of behavior is that proposed by Dennett (1987), under the
name "intentional stance." Essentially, the intentional stance is the
standpoint of the scientist who seeks to explain behavior as a rational
consequence of beliefs and desires ascribed to the organism.
The
how beliefs and desires interact
assumed that an organism acts in order
on the basis of its beliefs. As Dickinson says (1988),
role of rationality
determining behavior:
fulfill its
desires
In general,
if
I
is
it is
to dictate
in
to
assume that an intentional account of behavior is justified
shown to be dependent on, in the sense of being
that behavior can be
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
88
a rational consequence
(p.
of,
a set of beliefs and desires about the world,
307)
It is essential that the explanations in terms of mental states are not
simply post hoc reconstructions. As remarked by Bennett (1991), the
belief-desire-behavior triangle is, so to speak, an equation with two unknowns: one can always find many different belief-desire pairs that explain any given behavior. Therefore, we need some criterion to attribute
beliefs and desires in advance, in order to predict a forthcoming response;
the validity of the attribution will then be tested by observing the be-
havior actually occurring.
Of
not possible to give a list of observable features that
sufficient for an organism to entertain a specific belief.
However, as holding a belief means to possess certain information about
the environment, we can try to attribute certain beliefs to an animal
when they can be the result of its learning history and of its present
situation, given the characteristics of its sensory apparatus.
With desires we face a similar problem. From a functional standpoint,
desires act like motivational states in producing behavior. They differ
from simple motivations in that, having a content, they can combine
with beliefs, thus determining in a flexible way a response that fits the
situation as represented by the organism. Therefore, when we attribute
a desire we must take into account both the basic motivational states
that the animal is assumed to have, and the possibility that it combines
course,
are necessary
it is
and
with the animal's
An example
beliefs.
of this methodology can be found in Dickinson's experi-
ments on intentional behavior in rats (1988). In one of these studies,
hungry rats were trained to pull a chain in order to obtain sucrose solution, and to press a lever to obtain food pellets. By changing the motivational state from hunger to thirst, it was found that the rats preferred
pulling the chain to obtain sucrose solution, provided that they had
previous, independent experience of the different effects of sucrose solution and food pellets on the state of thirst. These results can be accounted for in terms of rats holding beliefs and desires (Figure 1), the
content of which is directly determined by the experimental conditions
in the following way:
As regards
desires, the motivational states of hunger and thirst were
produced experimentally, via food and water deprivation. Furthermore, the experimental procedure allowed the rats to learn the value
of both food pellets and sucrose solution in relieving hunger, and of
sucrose solution in relieving thirst. Therefore,
we
are justified in at-
tributing to hungry rats the desire for either food pellets or sucrose
solution, and to thirsty rats the desire for sucrose solution only.
As regards beliefs, the experimental procedure was designed to let the
rats acquire the information that pressing the level caused the delivery
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
89
AL.
/positive contingency
^
between an action
and an outcome
relevant
motivational
state
expenence
with the
outcome
desire for
belief that the action
the
C
causes the outcome
FIGURE
1.
An
outcome
D
experimental application of the intentional stance.
of food pellets,
and pulling the chain caused the delivery of sucrose
solution.
Having thus attributed
beliefs
and
desires to the animals, the principle
of rationality leads us to predict that thirsty rats will try to
fulfill
their
desire to get sucrose solution by pulling the chain. This prediction
was
confirmed by the observed behavior.
This experiment deserves a few words of comment. First, it is remarkable that even simple instrumental behavior supports an intentional
account; however, as stressed by Dickinson himself, particular care is
required in designing experiments in order to evaluate competing mechanistic and intentional explanations. Second, one should not expect that
representations spring up by themselves in the animal's mind; sufficient
experience with the relevant aspects of the world is crucial to support
the content of both beliefs and desires. For example, in the reported
study previous experience with the effects of the reinforcers was essential
to turn the pure motivational states into actual desires.
The intentional stance is by no means confined to laboratory experiments; in fact, it has more often been adopted in cognitively oriented
field research (Ristau, 1991). Indeed, we think that a number of results
reported in the literature are suitable for an intentional interpretation;
this seems to the case also for simple organisms, like honeybees.
In a series of extremely intriguing experiments on honeybee cognition,
90
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
Gould and Gould (1988) showed that the bees' ability to use their maps
beyond simple navigation. It was observed that dance attenders were not recruited by dances indicating that
flowers were located in an adjacent lake, whereas they were recruited
normally by dances indicating an equally distant location along the shoreline. A possible interpretation proposed by Gould and Gould was that
the location in the middle of the lake must, in a sense, have "sounded
of the territory apparently goes
unplausible" to the bees.
This interpretation could be easily cast into intentional terms. Given
we can assume that all bees
ready to leave the hive hold a comparable desire to reach the flowers.
What inhibits the recruitment appears to be the belief that no flowers
are to be found in the middle of lakes.
As observed by Gould and Gould, it is not easy to imagine what kind
of selective pressure might have promoted the ability to discard, on the
basis of an individually constructed map, the information obtained from
the dancers. In fact, there is no experimental evidence, and no theoretical
reason as well, supporting lying and deceit in honeybees. This problem
is related to the more general question of what might be the adaptive
value of cognitive processes. At the present stage, it is only possible to
attempt a few speculations. On the one hand, the ability to disbelieve a
message when it clashes with previously acquired information has an
adaptive value not only in case of deception, but also if messages are
prone to errors. On the other hand, it is possible that such an ability has
no value of its own, but is a consequence of selective pressure toward
the more general capacity to hold beliefs about the environment.
From a methodological point of view, Dennett's intentional stance is
an instrumentalist position, in that it is neutral with respect to such
issues as the real nature of mental states, their experiential correlates,
and their relationship with the actual causes of behavior. The instrumental nature of the intentional stance becomes especially clear if one
considers the role of the principle of rationality. Principles of this kind
are common in science. For example, predictions of the fate of physical
systems can be based on the principle of minimum energy: if a spherical
body is allowed to move freely in a concave container, sooner or later it
will stand still at the bottom of the container, having reached a state of
minimum energy in the gravitational field. The minimum energy principle thus allows one to predict the final equilibrium state in a synthetic
way, without bothering about how the state is reached. This kind of
physical explanation is clearly not causal, because there is no assumption
that a "tendency to minimum energy" is acting on the body. However,
this does not rule out the possibility of explaining the same phenomenon
causally, which can be done by taking gravitational force and friction
explicitly into account. In fact, the minimum energy principle can be
derived from the basic laws of physics: its use does not imply that one
the nature of the motivational state of bees,
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET AL
gives
up the assumption that
all
91
physical
phenomena have a
causal ex-
planation.
On
the basis of these considerations, it is natural to wonder whether
replace the principle of rationality with a causal account. According to Bennett (1991), intentional explanations are noncausal: they
we can
should be regarded as simple, synthetic tools for making predictions
about behavior; causality only makes sense at the neural level. A substantially different standpoint is taken by Searle (1983), who argues that
mental states are not only explicative tools, but rather real states endowed with causal power.
According to Searle, intentional states are a particular kind of physical
state of the nervous systems, and as such can cause other intentional
states and, eventually, behavioral responses.
What
characterizes inten-
tional causation with respect to classical physical causation
must be a
is
that there
mode and content of the
For example, thirst may cause an
certain kind of relationship between
causally related intentional states.
intentional act of drinking because thirst involves a desire to drink, which
satisfied by the act of drinking itself. This kind of explanation is
coherent with the traditional requirements of natural science. Rationality
appears to be an emergent property of intentional causation, and the
principle of rationality is therefore a derived law, like that of minimum
is
energy.
Between Dennett's instrumentalism and Searle's realism there is indeed a profound philosophical difference. But this does not necessarily
imply a comparable difference in the explanation of behavioral data.
Beliefs and desires, whether considered as instrumental attributions or
as descriptions of real physical states of an organism, lead to the same
predictions about the organism's behavior. At the present state of cognitive science, the question of which of the two approaches should be
adopted is a matter of personal philosophical position, and cannot be
settled on the basis of observable data.
However, beyond strictly philosophical matters, Searle's work on intentionally presents many ideas that might prove important for developing a general theory of cognition. In particular, two points are worth
discussing here.
The first is that although scientists can only describe the content of
mental states through language, such contents need not be realized in
linguistic form in the mind. Language is necessary for us to describe the
representations held by other organisms, but it is not necessary in order
for representations to be realized in the brain. When we say that an
animal perceives an intruder, we do not mean that the animal entertains
a mental sentence like "There is an intruder in front of me"; rather we
mean that the animal is in a neural state related to the world in a way
that an external observer can describe by the reported sentence.
The second important point is that allowing for representations in the
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
92
mind does not mean that every process going on
in the brain
is
repre-
sentational. Rather, representations presuppose a rich repertoire of non-
representational capacities as a necessary background. Let us consider
Sober's example (1983) of a dog, Fido, recovering a bone previously
hidden under a
tree. Fido's
the belief that there
is
behavior can be accounted for in terms of
a bone under the tree and the desire to get the
we assume that its mental states contain representations
Such representations are possible because Fido is
able to discriminate bones and trees from other types of objects. However,
its ability to discriminate bones and trees, which is a necessary precondition for holding representations about bones and trees, is not itself
bone. Therefore,
of a bone and a tree.
based on representations.
Searle's idea is that without a rich repertoire of such nonrepresentative
capacities, that he calls the Background, we cannot even start to form
representations about the world. After being able to recognize stones,
tables and the "on" relationship between two objects, we can entertain
the thought that a particular stone is on a given table. But the ability
to recognize a stone is not itself based on beliefs about stones.
When we attribute to Fido the belief that a bone is buried under the
tree, we give for granted that it is able to recognize a bone. As Sober
remarks, the use of the term "bone" in describing Fido's belief does not
imply that we attribute to it our knowledge of bones, e.g., that bones are
part of an animal's skeleton, that they can be used to make a tasty broth,
etc. Fido's representations must be considered to be relative to its Background, not to our Background and general knowledge.
This kind of species relativism is extended by Millikan (1986) to the
very notions of belief and desire. In commenting on Gould and Gould's
researches on honeybee cognition, she says that:
... it is unlikely that there is any distinction within the performing
bee to correspond to the distinction between belief and desire unlikely that the bee either believes or desires anything in the human
way. (p. 72)
—
it is not necessary to go this far. As we have already said, it
not the experiential quality of beliefs and desires that matters, but
rather their role in causing behavior. Fido does not possess the same
information we have about the world, but certainly it has some information; the content of its beliefs will be "doggish," but they are beliefs
Perhaps
is
after
all.
The standpoint just
outlined suggests that representations are the tip
of a nonrepresentation iceberg. It follows that cognitive science has two
concerns:
first,
the role of representations in producing behavior, which
we have discussed
in the
present section; second, the nonrepresentative
We shall come back to this point
process that generate representations.
in the next section,
psychology.
devoted to the paradigm of information processing
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
4.
93
AL.
THE COMPUTING MIND
When
dealing with representations,
it is
traditional to distinguish be-
tween content and form. While issues about content have been extensively investigated in philosophy, cognitive psychologists have devoted
their attention mainly to form.
The role of form is a central concern of information processing psychology (IPP), which regards mental processes as a flow of information
through a number of cognitive subsystems. A pioneering effort in this
direction is Broadbent's model of memory (1958). It is assumed that in
any subsystem information is coded in a suitable way, and that cognitive
processes can be regarded as transformations acting on coded information. As remarked by Yoerg and Kamil (1991),
The
task of the cognitive psychologist from an information processing
is to determine the nature and organization of the processes
which transform, encode, represent, and use information from the
external (or internal) world to produce behavior, (p. 279)
perspective
Possibly the main reason for the success of
IPP has been the
availability
of rigorous mathematical tools derived from information theory (Shan-
non, 1948).
A
further impetus
came from computer
science,
and
in par-
According to Newell and Simon (1978),
any intelligent system, either natural or artificial, is a physical symbol
system, i.e., a physical system whose states are symbolic structures, and
whose processes are computations performed on such structures. In a
physical symbol system, symbolic structures play the role of representations; however, computations are sensitive only to the form of representations, not to their content.
This version of IPP is substantially equivalent to the philosophical
position originally put forward by Putnam in 1962 under the name of
functionalism, and developed in a series of papers reprinted in Mind,
language and reality (1975). According to this view, the brain is to be
regarded as a digital computer executing a specific program. The resulting
computations transform the stimuli (input) into behavior (output),
through a series of intermediate steps. Mental states are simply states
occurring in the computations carried out by the brain according to the
program. Therefore, for any given organism the goal of psychology is to
determine the program executed by its brain. It is important to note,
however, that Putnam has not completely changed his philosophical
position (1988), reaching the conclusion that functionalism cannot shed
any light on the structure and activity of the mind.
Functionalism has become a popular approach to cognition for a number of reasons. As it reduces intelligence to computations carried on by
a machine, it is clearly a materialistic approach. The brain is viewed as
just one possible kind of machine able to carry on the required computations; functional models are abstract and independent of the neuticular
from
artificial intelligence.
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
94
rophysiology of the brain, and, therefore, the present lack of knowledge
about brain processes does not bear on cognitive modeling.
From the point of view of animal cognition, the main virtue of func-
does not presuppose any kind of subjective
present, is an epiphenomenon, in that it
does not contribute in any way to the computational process.
A typical controversy in IPP is whether particular cognitive processes
exploit pictorial or symbolic representations, i.e., whether the information is coded as a sort of mental image or rather in a sentence-like form.
Questions of this kind may be addressed either at the competence or at
the performance level (Airenti & Colombetti, 1991). In the former case,
the relevant variable is whether the subject is or is not able to perform
a certain task; in the latter, the focus is on variables like the time required
tionalism
is
perhaps that
it
experience. Consciousness,
if
produce a response.
of competence oriented research on the nature of representations is provided by the work on category discrimination by pigeons
carried on by Pearce (1988). In a number of experiments, Pearce has
to
An example
shown that pigeons
learn to discriminate visual stimuli consisting of
several bars on the basis of their absolute height, but find
it
very difficult
on the basis of the same/different height relationship.
Referring to Premack's claim (1983) that the ability to rely on relationships between stimuli is the mark of symbolic representation, Pearce
interprets the results of his study as showing that pigeons store visual
information in pictorial rather than symbolic form.
Also, performance data have been invoked to support hypotheses about
the form of representations. An interesting and well-known kind of experiment studies the ability to recognize different rotations of an image.
Shepard and Metzler (1971) showed that the time employed by human
subjects to recognize an image as the rotation of another one was proportional to the angle of rotation. This result strongly suggests that such
images are represented in pictorial form. A similar set of experiments
was carried out by Hollard and Delius (1982) using the same apparatus,
task and stimuli on both pigeons and humans. The performance of the
two species turned out to be remarkably different. As in the Shepard
and Metzler study, the latency of response by humans increased with
increasing amount of rotation. On the contrary, the response produced
by pigeons did not depend on the rotation angle. The conclusion drawn
by the authors was that pigeons and humans use different representato discriminate
tional systems.
from the preceding examples that the aim of IPP is to study
is encoded by organisms, and to analyze the transformations that operate on such coded representations. However, we think
that the very notion of mental transformation is somewhat problematic.
Consider for example Gould's researches on the visual perception by
honeybees, which are regarded by their author to "shed some light on
the nature of the mental transformations honeybees are capable of, though
It is clear
how information
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
95
AL.
how
these transformations are made." (1990, p. 87) In
particular, Gould showed that a bee trained to discriminate between two
vertically oriented artificial flowers can recognize their right-left mirror
not as yet on
image as similar to, even if difl"erent from, the original pattern; on the
contrary, bees do not exhibit the same ability when confronted with an
up-down reversal of the flower.
These results are easy to explain
one assumes that the bee's rephas to undergo
transformation
physical
the
is
analogous
to
that
a mental transformation
of the stimulus pattern. Gould's findings are then explained by assuming
that bees' images can undergo vertical, but not horizontal, mirror transformations. To account for the same results in terms of symbolic representations would be much more difficult, even if not impossible.
However, it is important to stress that within IPP there seems to be
an implicit assumption that representations necessarily have either pictorial or symbolic form. But where does this assumption come from?
Clearly from the human use of pictures and of language for representing
objects or state of aff"airs. But pictures and words are external carriers
of representations, and they do not immediately warrant the assumption
that mental representations must be of either kind. Mental representations are not external, and there is no reason to assume that they
should mimic some object of our experience.
A similar problem has already arisen in other scientific disciplines. In
Newton's times, the assumption that light was made of particles accounted for a number of optical phenomena; however, in the nineteenth
century it was discovered that light often behaved as a wave in an elastic
medium, in a way that was incompatible with the corpuscular hypothesis.
This contradiction remained unsolved until it was accepted that light
did not need to have either a corpuscular or an oscillatory nature: it
could be something different. The point is that both particles and waves
are objects of our everyday experience; but the microscopic structure of
light is beyond our direct acquaintance, and so required completely new
tools to be described.
if
resentation of the flower is pictorial: the representation
Possibly, in cognitive science
we
are facing a similar situation;
maybe
mental representations are not like pictures or sentences: they are something else. A concrete example of what they could be like is provided by
a recent approach to mental modeling known as neural networks (Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986). Neural networks are mathematical models
inspired by the structure of the nervous system: they consist of a large
set of units connected by excitatory or inhibitory links of variable strength.
Such networks encode information through the strengths associated to
the links, and represented as numerical "weights," in a way that is neither
pictorial nor symbolic. It is conceivable that a model of this kind may
account for Gould's data without resorting to any notion of transformation of representations.
It should be clear by now that contemporary research in animal cog-
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
96
nition
is
following two distinct paths: in general, interpretations in terms
of mental states are not integrated with
IPP models. This may sound
one considers that functionalism was first conceived in order
to provide a computational basis for concepts like belief and desire (Putnam, 1988, p. 73). But, in fact, the development of IPP has been largely
independent of philosophical concerns and, after all, philosophy has
often overlooked the problems of applied research. We think, however,
that it is now time to see whether the two approaches can be successfully
and usefully merged.
One of the studies considered in the previous section can provide an
example of how mental states could be related to information processing.
Let us go back to Gould and Gould's finding that honeybees are not
recruited by dances indicating that flowers are located in the middle of
a lake. We have already suggested an interpretation of this result in
terms of beliefs and desires. It is crucial to our interpretation that the
bees' representation of the home range can be viewed as a set of beliefs.
But where do these beliefs come from?
In general, there is the possibility that a belief is derived from more
fundamental ones: recall the example of the belief that the off'spring is
in danger, which could be derived from the previous beliefs that there
is an intruder near the nest, and that intruders are dangerous for the
off'spring. But then, we are left with the problem of explaining where the
previous beliefs come from. It is clear that we cannot assume that all
beliefs derive from more basic ones, lest we should face an infinite resurprising,
if
—
gression.
When a belief is not derived from more fundamental ones, it has to
be the product of some basic Background capacity to adopt Searle's
terminology. Going back to the bees' representation of the home range,
it is reasonable to assume that it is the product of a basic ability to
represent the spatial structure of the environment. Therefore, while the
representation of the home range can be regarded as an intentional state,
it has to be the result of a more fundamental, nonrepresentative process.
The problem now is how to explain such a capacity. It seems to us
that the real explanation can be given only at the neurophysiological
level (Airenti & Colombetti, 1990). But IPP can offer us a possible description of the process that highlights important properties: for example,
—
Gould (1984) presents evidence that the bee's representation of the home
range appears to work more like a pictorial map rather than like a series
of snapshots of key points along the route.
To conclude, we would like to point out that the IPP approach to the
study of animal cognition has at least two main merits. The first is that
it allowed scientists to deal with mental features in a very concrete way,
helping them to overcome a deeply rooted reluctance. The second, and
more important, is that its models are suggestive and have a strong
heuristic value: many interesting aspects of animal behavior would not
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
AL.
97
have been investigated without an information processing frame of refit should be kept in mind that interpreting mental
processes as computations is a metaphor, even if one with a great heuristic
power, and not a literal explanation. In fact, there seems to be no reason
to assume that the processes going on in the nervous system of organisms
are more computational than those occurring, say, in the growth of a
plant or in a chemical reaction.
erence. However,
5.
SUMMARY
In this paper, a
number of issues related to animal cognition have been
we have argued that:
discussed. In particular,
(1)
As
(2)
Mental processes can be described
at an abstract level, with no
appeal either to the quality of subjective experience or to neuro-
(3)
There are cases in which the behavior of organisms is amenable
to an explanation in terms of mental states, i.e., states endowed
with content about the external world. However, the existence of
mental states presupposes a rich repertoire of nonrepresentative
(4)
Even
it is formulated today, the notion of mind does not commit to
the existence of nonphysical entities, and can be investigated with-
in a rigorous scientific
framework.
physiological processes.
capacities.
if
for
nonhuman animals mental states are hypothetical conhumans their existence is a plain matter of
structs, in the case of
fact,
and the challenge
for
comparative psychology
is
to establish
their evolution.
(5)
Explanations of behavior in terms of mental states might well be
causal in nature as
(6)
(7)
it is
traditional in the natural sciences.
Information processing psychology describes neurophysiological
processes in terms of computational analogues. Basic concepts such
as mental transformations depend heavily on the tools chosen to
describe computations.
It is time to pursue an integration of the approaches based on
mental states and on information processing. A promising meeting
point could be provided by the nonrepresentative capacities underlying mental states.
While most of these points clearly have an intrinsic philosophical relevance, the standard of judgment for the success of the study of animal
cognition can only be that of the empirical sciences. A survey of the state
of the art reveals that much progress has been made in this direction,
both by
field research and by laboratory work exploiting traditional
conditioning procedures.
The comparison
of different species appears to be particularly impor-
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
98
tant.
By considering also species not closely related
to
humans
it is
easier
to overcome the danger of projecting the contents of our minds onto the
experimental nonhuman animals. Furthermore, studying different species in their natural environment allows for the investigation of the
adaptive value of cognition.
While it is generally accepted that cognition emerges from the activity
of the nervous system, we do not know how complex this system must
be to implement mental processes. It is certainly more intriguing to find
evidence of cognitive processes in honeybees than in apes, and this emphasizes the utility of investigating even simple organisms.
Since the late seventies, the term cognitive science came to denote an
interdisciplinary effort to understand cognition. Up to now, the disciplines officially pertaining to cognitive science are
human
cognitive psy-
chology, philosophy of mind, neuroscience, artificial intelligence, lin-
and cognitive ethology. We believe that it is time for animal
component of cognitive science in its own
right. To reach an integrated view of cognition, both developmental and
evolutionary aspects are essential. Animal cognition contributes to the
former, and is indeed crucial for the latter. Moreover, by studying cognitive processes in an ethological perspective, research on animals may
shed light on the coupling between a cognitive system and its environment, thus introducing into cognitive science an ecological component
guistics,
cognition to be considered a
that
is still
lacking.
REFERENCES
& Colombetti, M.
(1990). Representations for action. Actes du 4eme Collogue
Recherche Cognitive (pp. 49-64). Paris: INRIA.
Airenti, G., & Colombetti, M. (1991). Artificial intelligence and the representation problem. In M. De Glas & D. Gabbay (Eds.), Proceedings of the First World Conference
on the Fundamentals of Artificial Intelligence (pp. 17-28) Paris: (WOCFAI '91).
Airenti, G.,
de VAssociation pour
la
How
is
Bennett,
(1991).
J.
cognitive ethology possible? In C. A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive
Ethology (pp. 35-49). Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
BoUes, R. C. (1970). Species specific defense reactions and avoidance learning. Psychological Review, 77, 32-48.
Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and communication. London: Pergamon Press.
Chomsky, N. (1959). A review of B. F. Skinner's "Verbal behavior." Language, 35, 2658.
Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and prepositional attitudes. The
Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67-90.
Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: The M.I.T. Press.
Dickinson, A. (1988). Intentionality in animal conditioning. In L. Weiskrantz (Ed.), Thought
without language (pp. 305-324). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gaffan, D., & Cowling, E. A. (1984). Recall of the goal box in latent learning and latent
discrimination. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36B, 39-51.
Gallup, G. G. (1982). Self-awareness and the emergence of mind in primates. American
Journal of Primatology, 2, 237-248.
Gould, J. L. (1984). Natural history of honeybee learning. In P. Marler & H. S. Terrace
(Eds.),
Gould,
The
J. L.
biology of learning (pp. 149-180). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
The locale map of honeybees: Do insects have a cognitive
(1986).
Science, 232, 861-863.
map?
EMANUELA PRATO PREVIDE ET
AL.
99
Gould, J. L. (1990). Honeybee cognition. Co^m'fi'on, 37, 83-103.
Gould, J. L., & Gould, C. G. (1988). T/ie /loneyfeee. New York: Freeman.
Grant, D. S., Brewster, R. G., & Stierhoff, K. A. (1983). "Surprisingness" and short-term
retention in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes,
9,
63-79.
(1978). Prospects for a cognitive ethology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
527-538.
Griffin, D. R. (1981). The question of animal awareness. New York: Rockefeller University
Griffin, D. R.
4,
Press.
Griffin, D. R.
(1984).
Griffin, D. R.
(1991).
Animal thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Progress toward a cognitive ethology. In C.A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive
ethology (pp. 3-17). Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
L. M. (1986). Cognition and language competencies of bottlenosed dolphins. In
R. J. Schusterman, J. Thomas, & F. G. Wood (Eds.), Dolphin cognition and behavior:
A comparative approach. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
Herrnstein, R. J. (1984). Objects, categories, and discriminative stimuli. In H. T. Roitblat,
T. G. Bever, & H. S. Terrace (Eds.), Animal cognition (pp. 233-262). Hillsdale, NJ:
Herman,
LEA.
Herrnstein, R. J. (1990). Levels of stimulus control: A functional approach, 'ognition,
37, 133-166.
Hinde, R. A., & Stevenson-Hinde J. (Eds.). (1973). Constraints on learning. London:
Academic
Press.
Hollard, V. D., & Delius, J. D. (1982). Rotational invariance in visual pattern recognition
in pigeons and humans. Science, 218, 804-806.
(1984). The biological function of Pavlovian conditioning: The best defense
a good offense. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes,
Hollis, K. L.
is
10, 413-425.
Lea, S. E. G. (1984). Complex general process learning in nonmammalian vertebrates. In
P. Marler & H. S. Terrace (Eds.), The biology of learning (pp. 393-397). Berlin: Spring-
er-Verlag.
Millikan, R. G. (1986). Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content. Philosophical Review, 95, 47-80.
Morgan, C. L. (1894).
Morgan, C. L. (1903).
An introduction to comparative psychology. London: Scott.
An introduction to comparative psychology (2nd ed.). London:
Scott.
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435-450.
Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1978). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
Hall.
O'Keefe,
J.,
&
Nadel, L. (1978). The hippocampus as a cognitive map. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Pearce, J. M. (1988). Stimulus generalization and the acquisitions of categories by pigeons.
In L. Weiskrantz (Ed.), Thought without language (pp. 132-155). Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Pepperberg, I. M. (1991). A communicative approach to animal cognition: A study of
_ conceptual abilities of an African Grey parrot. In C. A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive ethology
(pp. 35-49). Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47,
44-50.
Premack, D.
(1983).
The codes
of
man and
beasts. Behavioral
and Brain
Sciences,
6,
125-167.
Putnam, H.
Putnam, H.
Mind, language and
reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: The M.I.T. Press.
Ristau, C. A. (1991). Aspects of the cognitive ethology of an injury-feigning bird, the
piping plover. In C. A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive ethology (pp. 91-126). Hillsdale, NJ:
(1975).
(1988).
LEA.
Ristau, C. A., & Robbins, D. (1982). Language in the great apes: a critical review. Advances
in the Study of Behavior, 12, 141-255.
Roberts, W. A., & Van Veldhuizen, N. (1985). Spatial memory in pigeons on the radial
maze. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 11, 241-260.
Roitblat, H. L. (1987). Introduction to comparative cognition. New York: Freeman.
1
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE PSYCHOLOGY
00
Roitblat, H. L., Bever, T. G.,
& Terrace, H.
S. (Eds.).
(1984).
Animal
cognition. Hillsdale,
NJ: LEA.
Rozin, P.,
&
Kalat,
J.
(1971).
Specific hungers
and poison avoidance as adaptive spe-
cializations of learning. Psychological Review, 78, 459-486.
E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA: The M.I.T. Press.
Schusterman, R. J., & Gisiner, R. (1988). Artificial language comprehension in dolphins
and sea lions: The essential cognitive skills. Psychological Record, 38, 311-348.
Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Seligman, M. E. P. (1970). On the generality of the laws of learning. Psychological Review,
77, 406-418.
Rumelhart, D.
Shannon, C. E. (1948).
A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System
Journal, 27, 379-423.
Shepard, R. N., & Metzler,
J.
(1971).
Mental rotation of 3-D
Technical
objects. Science, 171,
701-
703.
Shettleworth, S.
Shaw
(Eds.),
J.
(1972).
Advances
Constraints on learning. In D. S. Lehrman, R. A. Hinde, & E.
New York: Academic
in the study of behavior. Vol. 4 (pp. 1-68).
Press.
(1964). Behaviorism at fifty. In T. W. Wann (Ed.), Behaviorism and
phenomenology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Snowdon, C. T. (1987). A comparative approach to vocal communication. In D. W. Leger
(Ed.), Nebraska symposium on motivation: Comparative perspectives in modern psychology, 35 (pp. 145-199). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Sober, E. (1983). Mentalism and behaviorism in comparative psychology. In D. W. Rajecki
(Ed.), Comparing behavior: studying man, studying animals (pp. 113-141). Hillsdale,
NJ: LEA.
Staddon, J. E. R. (1983). Adaptive behavior and learning. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
Skinner, B. F.
versity Press.
Stich, S.
(1983).
From
folk psychology to cognitive science.
Cambridge,
MA: The
M.I.T.
Press.
Van der Waal, S. B. (1982). An experimental
cracker. Animal Behavior, 30, 84-94.
analysis of cache recovery in Clark's nut-
Vaughan, W., Jr., & Green, S. L. (1984). Pigeon visual memory capacity. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 10, 256-271.
&
I.,
Kamil, A. C. (1991). Integrating cognitive ethology with cognitive psychology. In C. A. Ristau (Ed.), Cognitive ethology (pp. 273-289). Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
Yoerg, S.