RIVISTA INTERNAZIONALE DI FILOSOFIA E PSICOLOGIA
DOI: 10.4453/rifp.2016.0025
ISSN 2039-4667; E-ISSN 2239-2629
Vol. 7 (2016), n. 2, pp. 256-263
SYMPOSIUM
Another Argument for Cognitive Phenomenology
Elisabetta Sacchi( ) & Alberto Voltolini( )
Ricevuto: 5 maggio 2016; accettato 4 luglio 2016
█ Abstract In this paper, we want to support Kriegel’s argument in favor of the thesis that there is a cognitive form of phenomenology that is both irreducible to and independent of any sensory form of phenomenology by providing another argument in favor of the same thesis. Indeed, this new argument is also intended to show that the thought experiment Kriegel’s argument relies on does describe a genuine metaphysical possibility. In our view, Kriegel has not entirely succeeded in showing that his own argument displays that possibility. We present our argument in two steps. First, we attempt to prove that there is a
cognitive phenomenology that is irreducible to any form of sensory phenomenology. Our proof relies on a
kind of phenomenal contrast argument that however does not appeal to introspection. Second, by showing that the link between this form of cognitive phenomenology, the phenomenology of having thoughts,
and sensory phenomenology in general is extrinsic, we also aim to demonstrate that the former is independent of the latter.
KEYWORDS: Cognitive Phenomenology; Irreduciblity; Independence; Having Thoughts; Grasping
Thoughts
█ Riassunto Un altro argomento in favore della fenomenologia cognitiva – In questo articolo intendiamo
corroborare l’argomento di Kriegel in favore dell’esistenza di una forma cognitiva di fenomenologia irriducibile a e indipendente da ogni altra forma di fenomenologia della sensibilità, avanzando un altro argomento a sostegno della stessa tesi. Nei fatti, questo nuovo argomento vuole anche mostrare che
l’esperimento mentale su cui poggia l’argomento di Kriegel descrive effettivamente una genuina possibilità metafisica; e tuttavia crediamo che l’argomento di Kriegel non abbia mostrato fino in fondo proprio
questa possibilità. Vogliamo presentare il nostro argomento in due passi. In un primo momento, tenteremo di provare l’esistenza di una fenomenologia cognitiva irriducibile a ogni altra forma di fenomenologia
sensoriale. La nostra prova poggia su un tipo di argomento basato su un contrasto fenomenico che non si
appella all’introspezione. In un secondo momento, mostrando che il legame tra questa forma di fenomenologia cognitiva, ossia la fenomenologia del possesso dei pensieri, e la fenomenologia sensoriale è un legame estrinseco, intendiamo dimostrare che la prima è indipendente dalla seconda.
PAROLE CHIAVE: Fenomenologia cognitiva; Irriduciblità; Indipendenza; Possesso dei pensieri; Afferramento dei pensieri
( )
Facoltà di Filosofia, Università degli Studi di Milano "Vita e Salute", via Olgettina, 58 - 20132 Milano (I)
( )
Dipartimento di Filosofia e Scienze dell'Educazione, Università degli Studi di Torino, Palazzo Nuovo,
via S. Ottavio, 20 - 10124 Torino (I)
E-mail: sacchi.elisabetta@hsr.it (); alberto.voltolini@unito.it
Creative Commons - Attribuzione - 4.0 Internazionale
Another Argument for Cognitive Phenomenology
257
█ Introduction
differential feelings of interest in us;
IN THIS PAPER, WE WANT to support
Kriegel’s argument in favor of the thesis that
there is a cognitive form of phenomenology
that is both irreducible to and independent of
any sensory form of phenomenology by
providing another argument in favor of the
same thesis. Indeed, this new argument is also
intended to show that the thought experiment
Kriegel’s argument relies on does describe a
genuine metaphysical possibility. In our view,
Kriegel has not entirely succeeded in showing
that his own argument displays that possibility. We present our argument in two steps.
First, we attempt to prove that there is a
cognitive phenomenology that is irreducible
to any form of sensory phenomenology. Our
proof relies on a kind of phenomenal contrast
argument that however does not appeal to introspection. Second, by showing that the link
between this form of cognitive phenomenology, the phenomenology of having thoughts,
and sensory phenomenology in general is extrinsic, we also aim to demonstrate that the
former is independent of the latter.
but
█ No argument from interest
In the opening part of The Varieties of Consciousness,1 Kriegel argues in favor of cognitive
phenomenology as a sui generis form of phenomenology. As he claims, cognitive phenomenology is a form of phenomenology that is
both irreducible to any other form of phenomenology, primarily sensory phenomenology, and independent of any such form.2
Kriegel initially tries to convince us of his
claim by an appeal to a «simple observation»:
«if there were no cognitive phenomenology,
life would be boring».3 To be sure, he adds that
an argument may be unpacked from this simple observation, namely:
1) If we did not have irreducible cognitive
phenomenology, the contents of our phenomenal awareness from phenomenal onset to sunset would not be disposed to elicit
2) they are so disposed; therefore,
3) we do have irreducible cognitive phenomenology.
Yet as he admits, the argument is less
convincing than the very same observation.
And pour cause. To illustrate this point more
vividly, a libertine may find premise (1) rather controversial. She may remark that,
even if she had no cognitive phenomenology,
she might spend her life passing from one
sexual adventure to another, simply finding
each adventure distinctively attractive from a
sensory point of view. No orgasm she would
feel in any of these encounters would be typologically identical with any other one, she
may crudely comment.
However, cognitive life is indisputably interesting in itself, so as to be worth experiencing even if one did not have a sensory
phenomenology. Is there another way to argue in favor of this idea?
█ The Zoe argument
Kriegel claims that there is a way to argue
that cognitive phenomenology is independent of sensory phenomenology. Since the independence claim entails the claim that cognitive phenomenology is irreducible to sensory phenomenology,4 to argue for the former is eo ipso to argue for the latter.
In putting forward his new argument,
Kriegel’s aim is to attempt to break the deadlock in the philosophical discussion on this
topic. In fact, the position that claims that
cognitive phenomenology is different from
sensory phenomenology, the so-called liberal
position,5 has been backed by several arguments. Among these arguments, the phenomenal contrast argument, the so-called
Moore-Strawson argument,6 and the one
from first-person knowability, the so-called
258
Goldman-Pitt argument,7 are the two main
varieties. Although Kriegel admittedly endorses both arguments, he claims that they
suffer from a lack of elucidation of the target
notions they involve, i.e., the notions of cognitive and of phenomenal. His new argument’s starting point consists in precisely
providing such an elucidation: «with the
right characterization of the cognitive and
the phenomenal […] one can start to imagine
the kind of scenario whose possibility would
establish the existence of primitive cognitive
phenomenology».8 To be sure, Kriegel’s new
argument is a phenomenal contrast argument
(PCA). Yet unlike the standard arguments of
this form, it does not rely on introspection, as
we will see. Notoriously, appealing to introspection is a doubtful move.
Kriegel first asks us to imagine a sensory
zombie, that is, someone who is devoid not
only of any form of sensory phenomenology,
both perceptual (linked to exteroceptive sensations) and algedonic (linked to interoceptive and proprioceptive sensations; in order
to take into account the fact that such a phenomenology includes not only pains but also
pleasures, one may perhaps better label it
alg/hedonic), but also of any form of emotional phenomenology, which is for Kriegel
at the very least grounded in sensory phenomenology. In order to imagine such a
zombie, Zoe as Kriegel labels it, one may first
imagine three partial zombies, that is, individuals who are respectively devoid of sensory, alg/hedonic, and emotional phenomenology, and second, one may fuse together such
imaginations in the imagining of Zoe, who
lacks all of these phenomenologies. Yet, continues Kriegel, Zoe’s life is not that bad as
one might suspect. For, Kriegel stipulates, on
the basis of some internal yet nonconscious
processes that still happen to her in the subpersonal perceptual, alg/hedonic and emotional implementing areas of her brain, she
still entertains an interesting cognitive life
entirely devoted to thoughts concerning
mathematical calculations. In such calculations, she inter alia realizes some important
Sacchi & Voltolini
mathematical proofs. Any such realization
involves a contrast in her cognitive life. He
infers that such a contrast is phenomenal,
thereby involving phenomenal mental states,
simply by mobilizing his characterization of
what is phenomenal, not by appealing to introspection, as standard PCAs do.9 Since by
assumption such mental states are not sensory, it follows that they are endowed with a
cognitive phenomenology. Thus, one may
overall conclude that Zoe has a cognitive
phenomenology while lacking a sensory one.
As some people have remarked, the problem with this argument is that the fact that
we can conceive of this previous story is no
guarantee that the story amounts to a logical
possibility. Indeed, we do not positively imagine this story.10 Granted, Kriegel is convinced of the opposite, for the story betrays
no trace of a contradiction.11
Yet, his opponents may reply, even if this
shows that the description of the story amounts
to a positive form of imaginability and hence to
a logical possibility, what reasons do we have to
further endorse the claim that the story is also
metaphysically possible? Is this a case for which
being logically possible entails being metaphysically possible? To this reply, Kriegel rejoins
that «it is certainly highly plausible that some
types of conceivability – including conceivability by an epistemically responsible agent in
normal or favorable circumstances – provide
prima facie, defeasible evidence for metaphysical possibility»; Zoe’s case represents one of
these types.12
Yet can we content ourselves with the absence of any defeater? What if some defeater
eventually pops up?13 In order to rule out
such a possibility, we think it is useful to look
for some other argument that strengthens
Kriegel’s credence in what he calls «cognitive-phenomenal primitivism»,14 thereby
demonstrating that Zoe’s case is indeed a
metaphysical possibility. In fact, we claim
that there is such an argument. In the next
Section, we tell another story which further
suggests that there is no internal connection
between cognitive and sensory phenomenol-
Another Argument for Cognitive Phenomenology
ogy, thus demonstrating not only that the
former is irreducible to the latter, but also
that is independent of it.
█ The Vita argument
First, we focus on the most general phenomenal contrast, the one between phenomenal life on the one hand, where what Kriegel
calls «the highest phenomenal determinable»
aka «phenomenality per se (what-it-is-like-ness
as such)»15 is instantiated, and the absence of
such a life, where no phenomenality at all occurs. Needless to say, this amounts to the contrast between being awake and being asleep
(allowing for the further assumption that no
dreaming occurs while sleeping; from now on,
let us take this specification for granted). Passing from being awake to being asleep is precisely switching from having phenomenality
per se to having no such thing at all.
This said, let us present a case that involves such a contrast, the case of Vita. Vita
is a chronic insomniac who uses all possible
techniques to fall asleep. When she goes to
bed she puts a black band over her eyes, she
switches on a radio that continuously repeats
the same sounds; she finds the most comfortable position to lie in; she covers herself with a
very soft blanket so she will stay warm, and so
on and so forth. In this condition, she manages to keep her sensory phenomenology relatively stable, so as to help her to fall asleep. In
this way, she manages to relax: she feels no
anxiety, fear or anger. Yet when it comes to
falling asleep, no way. These practices notwithstanding, she goes on thinking. Indeed,
the reason why she does not fall asleep is precisely that she cannot stop thinking.
This reason has nothing to do with any
underlying processes in her body (her brain
included), for example, not falling asleep because her heart is beating too fast. Such physiological processes, if any, may cause her not
to fall asleep, but they are not the reasons why
the phenomenal switch from being awake to
being asleep does not occur. Rather, that reason has to do with the fact that she experienc-
259
es such thoughts, that they are conscious for
her. Clearly enough, the reasons for her to
entertain that sort of phenomenal switch
have to be phenomenal as well. Indeed, she
could continue to stay awake for a variety of
phenomenally relevant reasons: e.g. because
she was anxious, or suffered from a terrible
itch, or even because she saw a ray of light.
Yet, as we have seen before, it is not her sensory phenomenology, as in all the above cases, that is responsible for her not passing into
another state where she lacks phenomenology at all.
Thus, another form of phenomenology
must be responsible. The conscious thoughts she
entertains over and above sensory phenomenology play this inhibitory role; her phenomenal life continues precisely because of them.
To begin with, this argument is a form of
PCA, for it involves considering a phenomenal
switch from being awake to being asleep. However, it has some features of its own. For, unlike
standard PCAs and like Kriegel’s Zoe argument, the point of the argument is not to focus
on different phenomenal states whose phenomenal difference is given introspectively. For
there is no introspection as regards one’s being
asleep – obviously enough, being asleep is not a
mental state, hence a fortiori it cannot be something one is introspectively conscious of. Thus,
it would be better to conceptualize the phenomenal difference the story points out as a
difference between the existence of phenomenal awareness on the one hand and the lack of
such awareness on the other.16
Moreover, it is hardly disputable that what
the argument’s story describes is a metaphysical
possibility: as a matter of fact, any of us may
find her/himself in Vita’s state. Up to now,
therefore, if we are right, we have managed to
prove that there is a cognitive phenomenology
that is irreducible to a sensory one.
Obviously enough, detractors of the liberal view of cognitive phenomenology will immediately protest that we have not proved
the above claim. For, they would say, even if
one concedes that Vita has a cognitive phenomenology that exceeds her standard senso-
260
ry phenomenology, that cognitive phenomenology may well be reduced to some other
form of sensory phenomenology; namely,
sensory imagery.17 In any such thoughts, Vita
entertains some kind of sensory imagery, typically but not exclusively visual imagery. While
thinking, say, of her work tomorrow, she has
some flashes of the building where she works;
while thinking of how to get to this building,
she auditorily imagines the noise of the traffic
around, and so on and so forth.
Yet no such imagistic phenomenology can
account for all the thoughts Vita entertains
while lying in bed. As she is very ingenious, she
has developed a technique for thinking boring,
sleep-inducing, thoughts: typically, item-counting thoughts. Yet instead of counting sheep as
normal people do, Vita counts items featuring
an even less exciting subject; namely, geometrical figures. As you know, she is a terrible insomniac. So, her enumeration proceeds: after a
while, she starts counting first a chiliagon then
a circle. Yet as we all know, no sensory imagery
distinguishes the thought of a chiliagon from
the thought of a circle. Thus, this switching in
Vita’s thoughts cannot be accounted for in
terms of sensory imagery.
Yeah, yeah – our detractor will say. Yet in
counting geometrical figures, as in any other
thought for that matter, Vita engages herself
in some inner speech, which definitely has an
aural counterpart. So, while counting a chiliagon, Vita silently says to herself (and auditorily imagines herself saying) This is a chiliagon , while counting a circle, Vita silently
says to herself (and auditorily imagines herself
saying) This is a circle , thereby letting her
switch in thought be matched by a switch in
(auditory) imagery that concerns the different
phonology and possibly also the different syntactical parsing of such sentences.18
Yet even if this were the case, it is quite
easy to figure out a continuation of the story
where Vita exploits another technique:
namely, obsessively repeating to herself in
inner speech the very same sentence endowed with both the same phonology and
the same syntax, yet meaning it now one way,
Sacchi & Voltolini
now another way. For instance, she repeats
Dionysius is Greek sometimes meaning
Dionysius the Elder, ruler of Syracuse, Sicily,
in ancient times, at other times meaning Dionysius the Younger, son of the former.
It is quite possible that in her mind, not
only she does not visually distinguish the two
men, with whom obviously she has never had
any physical contact – she sticks to the very
same mental image of a distinguished ancient
adult Greek – but she also does not aurally
distinguish the different yet both phonetically
and syntactically alike tokens of the above
sentence.19 Thus, the thought switching that
she repeatedly entertains cannot be accounted
for by any sort of sensory imagery. As Wittgenstein once masterly said in his own way:
When someone says the word cube to
me, for example, I know what it means.
But can the whole use of the word come
before my mind when I understand it in
this way?
Yes; but on the other hand, isn’t the meaning of the word also determined by this
use? And can these ways of determining
meaning conflict? Can what we grasp at a
stroke agree with a use, fit or fail to fit it?
And how can what is present to us in an instant, what comes before our mind in an
instant, fit a use?
What really comes before our mind when
we understand a word? – Isn’t it something like a picture? Can’t it be a picture?
Well, suppose that a picture does come before your mind when you hear the word
cube , say the drawing of a cube. In what
way can this picture fit or fail to fit a use of
the word cube ? – Perhaps you say: It’s
quite simple; if that picture occurs to me
and I point to a triangular prism for instance, and say it is a cube, then this use of
the word doesn’t fit the picture. – But
doesn’t it fit? I have purposely so chosen
the example that it is quite easy to imagine
a method of projection according to which
the picture does fit after all.
The picture of the cube did indeed suggest
Another Argument for Cognitive Phenomenology
a certain use to us, but it was also possible
for me to use it differently.20
Once we have so managed to show that
cognitive phenomenology is irreducible to
any sensory phenomenology, it is relatively
simple to also show that the former is independent of the latter, thereby also showing
how Kriegel’s argument may be supported by
our own argument.
As is well known, the point of Wittgenstein’s previous remarks was that meaning
something by means of an expression does
not consist in any sort of mental process that
at most accompanies meaning:
Neither the expression to mean the explanation in such-and-such a way nor the
expression to interpret the explanation
in such-and-such a way signifies a process which accompanies the giving and
hearing of an explanation.21
Now, Vita’s case shows that the very same
point can be made with regard to the relationship between sensory and cognitive phenomenology, at least as far as the phenomenology
of thought is concerned. Let us concede that
any of Vita’s thoughts is accompanied by
some sort of sensory phenomenology or other:
in actual fact, there is no thought of Vita’s that
is not accompanied by some phenomenal sensory state or other, ultimately a sensory imagery of some form or other (visual, auditory,
etc.). One might even wonder whether sensory phenomenology necessitates cognitive phenomenology, in Chudnoff’s terms: «some
phenomenal states suffice for being in a cognitive intentional state»,22 where this sufficiency
condition is a factual one: actually, being in
some sensory phenomenal state or other suffices for being in a cognitive phenomenal
state. Yet clearly enough, this relationship between the two kinds of phenomenologies is no
more intimate than that of an accompanying
or a surrounding. Yet this is to say, there is no
intrinsic relationship between a cognitive form
of phenomenology and a sensory form of
261
phenomenology.
In other terms, the cognitive phenomenology of having thoughts is independent of any
sensory phenomenology. There indeed is a
possible world in which Vita still has the
thoughts that prevent her from falling asleep
and yet has no phenomenal sensory states at
all – or in other terms, there is a possible world
in which Vita is nothing but our old Zoe.23
In order to further confirm that there is
no intrinsic relationship between cognitive
and sensory phenomenology, consider situations in which, unlike the previous one, irreducibility of cognitive phenomenal states to
sensory phenomenal states does not lead to
the fact that the former states are independent of the latter states. There indeed is a difference between the phenomenology of having thoughts, which is what we have talked
about all along, and the phenomenology of
grasping thoughts, namely that form of phenomenology that paradigmatically takes
place in experiences as of understanding,
those originally pointed out by Strawson24
among others. In such experiences, there definitely is a dependence of the cognitive phenomenology of understanding on the sensory
phenomenology of hearing or reading. One
could not understand the thought that is expressed by a sentence that by itself is dead ,
i.e., meaningless, if one did not hear or read
that very sentence, or even another such sentence that is ascribed the very same meaning
(for instance, a synonymous sentence in a
different language). For understanding presupposes interpretation of a meaningless sentence that is heard or read as such, as ambiguous sentences clearly show.
One could not understand the famous
Wildean joke To lose one parent, Mr.
Worthing, may be regarded as a misfortune; to
lose both looks like carelessness if one did not
first hear or read that sentence as a meaningless
sentence by then interpreting it in the sense
having to do with misplacing rather than in the
sense having to do with suffering from deprivation.25 Yet in having a thought, no such act of
interpretation has to be presupposed. It is not
262
the case that one mentally hears or reads a certain sentence and then understands it by interpreting in a certain way, possibly choosing one
among different theoretically legitimate interpretations.26 Rather, one immediately thinks
the thought in the only sense it has.
Thus, even if some sentence or other imaginatively heard or read in inner speech
pops up while having that thought, this sentence only accompanies the thought in an extrinsic sense: one might have thought that
very thought without silently repeating to
herself that sentence, or any other sentence
for that matter.27 In a nutshell, the difference
between the phenomenology of having
thoughts and that of grasping thoughts explains why in the former the relationship between cognitive and sensory phenomenology
is not the one holding in the latter; namely, it
is an extrinsic and not an intrinsic one,
thereby leading to the independence of the
former from the latter.28
Let us take stock. If we have managed to
show that Zoe’s case really amounts to a metaphysical possibility by illustrating how the
case of Vita, which undoubtedly is a metaphysical possibility, may ultimately coincide
with it, we have also managed to show that
there is a form of cognitive phenomenology
that is both irreducible to and independent
of sensory phenomenology.29
█ Notes
1
See U. KRIEGEL, The Varieties of Consciousness,
Oxford University Press, Oxford 2015.
2
To put things in Chudnoff’s terms. See E.
CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, Routledge,
London 2015, pp. 15-17. To be sure, Kriegel limits himself to saying that his arguments are intended to prove the fact that cognitive phenomenology constitutes a primitive and distinctive
form of phenomenology, hence that it is irreducible (in the phenomenal sense of irreducibility) to
sensory phenomenology. Yet if successful, those
arguments also show that there may be someone
who entertains cognitive phenomenology without
entertaining any sensory phenomenology.
3
U. KRIEGEL, The Varieties of Consciousness, cit.,
Sacchi & Voltolini
p. 40.
4
See E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit.,
p. 17.
5
See T. BAYNE, M. MONTAGUE, Cognitive Phenomenology: An Introduction, in: T. BAYNE, M. MONTAGUE (eds.), Cognitive Phenomenology, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, pp. 1-34, here p. 3.
6
See U. KRIEGEL, The Varieties of Consciousness, cit.,
p. 40. One can find the argument in G.E. MOORE,
Propositions, in: G.E. MOORE, Some Main Problems of
Philosophy, Routledge, London 1953, pp. 52-71, in
particular pp. 58-59 and in G. STRAWSON, Mental
Reality, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA) 1994, pp. 5-13.
7
See ibidem. One can find the argument in A.I.
GOLDMAN, The Psychology of Folk Psychology, in:
«Behavioral and Brain Sciences», vol. XVI, n. 1,
1993, pp. 15-28 and in D. PITT, The Phenomenology of Cognition, or What Is It Like to Think that
P?, in: «Philosophy and Phenomenological Research», vol. LXIX, n. 1, 2004, pp. 1-36.
8
Ivi, p. 41.
9
See ivi, pp. 30-31. To be sure, in Chudnoff’s
terms, unlike pure PCAs, Zoe’s argument is a hypothetical PCA, that is, an argument in which the imagined case is not actual. See E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., pp. 45-55. Yet this does
not undermine its non-introspective nature.
10
See A. PAUTZ, Does Phenomenology Ground Mental Content?, in: U. KRIEGEL (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2013,
pp. 194-234, in particular p. 219. For the notion of
a positive imaginability and its link to logical (and
also metaphysical) possibility, see originally D.J.
CHALMERS, The Conscious Mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1996.
11
See U. KRIEGEL, The Varieties of Consciousness,
cit., p. 56.
12
Ivi, p. 62.
13
Chudnoff’s criticism may be taken to go along
this direction. E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., p. 54.
14
U. KRIEGEL, The Varieties of Consciousness, cit.,
p. 38.
15
Ivi, p. 10.
16
In this respect, one might take our PCA as a form
of what Chudnoff labels a glossed PCA, in whose
premises one also glosses on the nature of the phenomenal difference involved. See E. CHUDNOFF,
Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., pp. 55-60.
17
See J. PRINZ, The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1, in: T. BAYNE, M. MONTAGUE (eds.),
Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., pp. 174-196, here
Another Argument for Cognitive Phenomenology
pp. 181-193.
18
See ivi; M. TYE, B. WRIGHT, Is There a Phenomenology of Thought?, in: T. BAYNE, M. MONTAGUE
(eds.), Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., pp. 326-344.
19
For similar examples, see e.g. C. SIEWERT, The
Significance of Consciousness, Princeton University
Press, Princeton 1998.
20
L. WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations
(1953), Blackwell, Oxford 2009, IV ed., I, § 139.
21
Ivi, I, § 34.
22
E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., p.
133.
23
Accepting this claim means accepting what
Chudnoff labels the Disembodied Qualia Premise:
«if there are cognitive phenomenal states, then
there should be parts of phenomenally different
total phenomenal states T1 and T2 such that:
T1 includes both sensory and cognitive states and
T2 is the same as T1 with respect to cognitive phenomenal states but lacks all sensory phenomenal
state» (E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology,
cit., p. 118).
24
See G. STRAWSON, Mental Reality, cit.
25
It may then be the case that also in the other
two cases that Chudnoff points out, namely:
grasping a mathematical proof that uses a diagram and intuiting a mathematical proof by visualizing a shape, cognitive phenomenology is
grounded in sensory phenomenology. For both
such cases are cases in which one perceives something meaningless and then ascribes an interpretation to it. See E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenom-
263
enology, cit., p. 107.
26
Perhaps interpreting that sentence amounts to
matching it with a Mentalese sentence in the brain,
Fodorians say. Yet the Mentalese sentence is not a
meaningless sentence that is first (imaginatively)
sensed as such and then interpreted in some way or
other, for it is an originally meaningful sentence.
Thus, if it is a vehicle of thinking, it is not so in the
same way as a meaningless sentence is a vehicle of
understanding.
27
Chudnoff acknowledges that there may be cases
of thoughts endowed only with cognitive phenomenology. Yet by echoing Prinz (see J. PRINZ, The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1, cit.), he
wonders whether such cases are possible (see E.
CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., p. 108). If
we are right in splitting these cases from cases of understanding in the above way, there is no problem in
accepting their being genuinely possible.
28
Thus, by drawing such a difference between
these phenomenologies, with regards to the phenomenology of having thoughts one may rebut
the argument Chudnoff labels the missing explanation argument that supposedly blocks the inference from irreducibility of cognitive phenomenology to sensory phenomenology to independence of the former from the latter. See E. CHUDNOFF, Cognitive Phenomenology, cit., pp. 117-120.
29
Although this paper was mutually conceived and
discussed, Elisabetta Sacchi is particularly responsible for sections 1 and 3, while Alberto Voltolini is
particularly responsible for sections 2 and 4.