Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
4 pages
1 file
The Tri-Council Policy Statement: Ethical Conduct for Research Involving Humans (TCPS) was first issued in 1998. At that time, the inappropriate exclusion of women from clinical trials was a serious problem. Currently, the TCPS is undergoing a comprehensive review and it is expected that new research guidelines will be issued in 2010. One of the problems with the current draft of the revised TCPS is that it fails to properly address the routine exclusion of pregnant women from research. We illustrate the negative ethical implications of excluding pregnant women from research and argue for changes to the research guidelines that would address these negative implications.
The American journal of bioethics : AJOB, 2018
Bioethics
Historically, there has been a reluctance to include pregnant women in research due to a fear of harming the fetus. Often mentioned in this respect are the diethylstilboestrol (DES) and thalidomide tragedies. From 1938 to 1971, DES was prescribed to an estimated 1.5 to 3 million women during pregnancy to prevent miscarriage. The drug turned out not to prevent miscarriage and was linked to several adverse complications for the offspring, including vaginal and cervical carcinomas in young women, and malformation of reproductive organs in both male and female children. 1 In the late 1950s, thalidomide was prescribed for nausea 1 Allesee, L., & Gallagher, C. M. (2011). Pregnancy and protection: The ethics of limiting a pregnant woman's participation in clinical trials.
American Journal of Law & Medicine, 1993
The barriers to women's participation as subjects in biomedical research are currently being challenged as a matter of legislative policy, medicine, and law. This Article catalogs the ways in which women have been disadvantaged by their exclusion and recent developments to redress them, and goes on to dissect the underlying rationales for excluding women from clincial trials. The author reveals the ‘fundamental misconception’ behind exclusionary rationales, and argues that research sponsors in fact have more to fear in the way of potential liability from the exclusion of women, even pregnant women and women of child-bearing capacity, than from their inclusion. Finally, the Article suggests strategies for achieving reform of these exclusionary practices.
International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 2008
Though much progress has been made on inclusion of non-pregnant women in research, thoughtful discussion about including pregnant women has lagged behind. We outline resulting knowledge gaps and their costs and then highlight four reasons why ethically we are obliged to confront the challenges of including pregnant women in clinical research. These are: the need for effective treatment for women during pregnancy, fetal safety, harm from the reticence to prescribe potentially beneficial medication, and the broader issues of justice and access to benefits of research participation. Going forward requires shifting the burden of justification from inclusion to exclusion and developing an adequate ethical framework that specifies suitable justifications for excluding pregnant women from research.
Trials
Background: Since pregnant women are severely underrepresented in clinical research, many take the position that the exclusion of pregnant women from research must be justified unless there are compelling "scientific reasons" for their exclusion. However, it is questionable whether this approach renders research with pregnant women fair. This paper analyzes and evaluates when research with pregnant women can be considered as fair and what constitutes scientific reasons for exclusion. Methods: Conceptual ethical and methodological analysis and evaluation of fair inclusion. Results: Fair inclusion of pregnant women means (1) that pregnant women who are eligible are not excluded solely for being pregnant and (2) that the research interests of pregnant women are prioritized, meaning that they ought to receive substantially more attention. Fairness does not imply that pregnant women should be included in virtually every research project, as including only a few pregnant women in a population consisting only of women will not help to determine the effectiveness and safety of a treatment in pregnant women. Separate trials in pregnant women may be preferable once we assume, or know, that effects of interventions in pregnant women differ from the effects in other subpopulations, or when we assume, or know, that there are no differences. In the latter case, it may be preferable to conduct post-marketing studies or establish registries. If there is no conclusive evidence indicating either differences or equivalence of effects between pregnant and non-pregnant women, yet it seems unlikely that major differences or exact equivalence exist, the inclusion of pregnant women should be sufficient. Depending on the research question, this boils down to representativeness in terms of the proportion of pregnant and non-pregnant women, or to oversampling pregnant women. Conclusions: Fair inclusion of pregnant women in research implies that separate trials in pregnant women should be promoted. Inclusion of pregnant women has to be realized at the earliest phases of the research process. In addition to researchers and research ethics committees, scientific advisory councils, funders, drug regulatory agencies, pharmaceutical companies, journal editors and others have a joint responsibility to further develop the evidence base for drug use in pregnant women.
Am. JL & Med., 1993
The barriers to women's participation as subjects in biomedical research are currently being challenged as a matter of legislative policy, medicine, and law. This Article catalogs the ways in which women have been disadvantaged by their exclusion and recent developments to redress them, and goes on to dissect the underlying rationales for excluding women from clincial trials. The author reveals the 'fundamental misconception' behind exclusionary rationales, and argues that research sponsors in fact have more to fear in the way of potential liability from the exclusion of women, even pregnant women and women of child-bearing capacity, than from their inclusion. Finally, the Article suggests strategies for achieving reform of these exclusionary practices. t This title is of course a tribute to the Supreme Court's astute distinction between pregnant and nonpregnant persons in Ceduldig v. Aiello. 417 U.S. 484 (1974). See infra notes 237, 252 and accompanying text.
American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology
The views expressed in this article are the personal views of the authors and may not be understood or quoted as being made on behalf of or reflecting the position of their respective institutions, member organizations, employing companies, health agencies, or one of its committees or working parties. C.G.B. participated in paid lectures for Medela on breastfeeding and COVID-19 and for Hologic on late preterm pregnancy. The remaining authors report no conflict of interest.
Newsclick, 2024
Tricolor, our National flag represents our glorious civilization and is also a direction of our future
A cuarenta años del grupo historia de la práctica pedagógica en Colombia., 2021
El presente artículo es una versión escrita modificada de una conferencia leída en la Universidad del Valle, el 29 de octubre de 2018, con ocasión del evento de celebración de años de fundación del Grupo de Historia de la Práctica Pedagógica en Colombia (GHPPC). Concebido al modo de fábula, con la figura de un acalorado debate entre “ángeles pedagógicos” y “diablos epistemológicos” en la cabeza del autor, el artículo propone un balance sobre el significado y la evolución de dos nociones fundacionales que el GHPPC ha aportado al campo conceptual de la pedagogía en el país, las nociones de saber pedagógico y de práctica pedagógica. Mediante los intercambios y contrargumentaciones, se perfilan dos posiciones antagónicas hoy en este campo: quienes sostienen la necesaria e inevitable desaparición de la pedagogía y quienes mantienen el proyecto de fortalecerla como el saber propio del oficio de maestro y como disciplina crítica de las relaciones escuela-cultura-sociedad. La fábula termina por insinuar de qué modo ambas posturas tienen razón y porqué cada una de ellas no tiene la razón.
Kompetensi adalah kecakapan yang memadai untuk melakukan suatu tugas atau sebagai memiliki ketrampilan & kecakapan yang diisyaratkan. Sedangkan kompetensi menurut Van Looy, Van Dierdonck, and Gemmel menyatakan kompetensi adalah sebuah karakteristik manusia yang berhubungan dengan efektifitas performa, karakteristik ini dapat dilihat seperti gaya bertindak, berperilaku, dan berpikir.
Consumption and Society , 2024
Περιοδικό Κοινός Τ[ρ]όπος, 2024
Maltepe Üniversitesi İnsan ve Toplum Bilimleri Araştırma Merkezi Web Sayfası , 2009
CRC Press eBooks, 1998
ACTAS XII CONGRESO INTERNACIONAL AR&PA 2022. Rethinking the Sense of Heritage Repensar el patrimonio cultural en un mundo digital y en crisis, 2022
ENDSARS MOVEMENT IN NIGERIA, 2023
DergiPark (Istanbul University), 2016
Applied Optics, 2005
Agung Prasetyo , 2024
Sustainability, 2020
Materials Research, 2020
Chinese Physics B, 2014
Correo Cientifico Medico, 2013