A New Philosophy of Darkness
By Adam Barkman
As an animal-angel hybrid, human beings have a foot in both the physical and the
spiritual realm. Insofar as human beings are angelic, they possess the magnificent
faculties of creative imagination, rational thinking and free choice. Yet, all too often, human beings demonstrate an internal schism between the scientific and the
poetic, the literal and the metaphorical. On top of this, the human being’s ability to
reason is limited to seeing only a few things in full and a few more things in part.
Finally, human will, which leads humans astray as often as it leads them aright,
almost guarantees that as humans progress in one direction, they lose their way in
another. Sadly, even in the Information Age, knowledge is not being unified as it
ought to be and proper action is not being taken as it could be, and so injustice and
violence – that is, unjust hurt – abound.
Nevertheless, in this essay, I do not want to talk about injustice or violence in
general, but rather one type of injustice or violence: injustice against darkness and
those creatures associated with the dark. Since the beginning of time, human beings have vilified darkness, and while at times this vilification has been just, all too
often darkness, and creatures associated with the dark, have been absolutely reviled, the ultimate result of which has been gross injustice not only to nature in the
form of light pollution and a certain kind of speciesism, but also to human beings
in the form of a weakened aesthetic imagination and an uncertainty about their
place on the Earth and in the universe. Consequently, drawing on insights from
science, religion, philosophy and literature, I want to examine what the human
being’s proper response to darkness and creatures associated with it should be.
Over the course of history, darkness and creatures associated with the dark have long been
vilified. Yet according to Adam Barkman, this vilification has often resulted in both aesthetic
and ethical injustice. At the root of these injustices is humanity’s constant failure both to
keep the literal and the metaphorical separate and to remember that all creation – both in its
individual parts and as a whole – was created and declared good. Thus, in this paper, Barkman
considers how we should understand, speak about and act in regard to darkness and creatures associated with the dark. Dr. Barkman, the author of C. S. Lewis and Philosophy as a Way
of Life and co-editor of Manga and Philosophy, is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Yonsei
University.
265
Christian Scholar’s Review
266
Literal Darkness and Light Pollution
According to the physical sciences, light is electromagnetic radiation of any
wavelength. More specific to human beings, light is visible radiation or electromagnetic radiation with wavelengths capable of causing the sensation of vision.
Opposed to light, and defined negatively or in terms of what it is not, is darkness,
which is simply the absence of light.
Setting aside the universe’s dependence on the mysterious substance, dark
energy, which makes up about 72% of the universe, and dark matter, which makes
up about 23% of the universe, we know that even bare darkness, insofar as it contrasts with light, is necessary for the survival of many biological creatures – both
animals and human beings.
As for animals, light acts like a powerful magnet for many nocturnal species.
Birds migrating at night are known to fly into tall, brightly lit buildings and seabirds have been known to circle marine oil platforms until they die from exhaustion. Moreover, the artificial light of the city can cause some birds to sing too early
in the day, the result of which is, among other things, overfeeding, which in turn
can cause early migration, which, of course, is disastrous for not only the adult
birds, but also their young and the entire ecosystem they inhabit. And something
similar is true for many other species, from zooplankton to moths. Sea turtles, to
take another example, prefer to lay their eggs on dark beaches since the darkness
affords the eggs, and the young hatchlings, greater protection from predators; consequently, if beaches are too bright, the sea turtle population decreases and everything that depends on sea turtles, both that which eat, and that which are eaten by,
the turtles are affected.1 In all of these cases, and in countless others, light pollution
or the absence of sufficient, natural darkness greatly harms animals.
As for human beings, not enough darkness can cause circadian disruption and
can throw off their biological clocks and sleep patterns, resulting in decreased sexual
activity and increased headaches, fatigue, anxiety, obesity and even breast cancer.2
Moreover, and perhaps even more importantly, the creative and spiritual desires
that arise in human beings as a result of their abandoning themselves to the
splendour of the heavenly bodies above is extinguished when there is not enough
darkness to contrast with the “bright shoals of stars and planets and galaxies.”3
The lack of darkness paves the way for not only aesthetic injustice through the
equalizing, blinding glare of light pollution, but also ethical injustice insofar as
human beings, being closed off from the heavens above, are tempted to think that
they are alone in the universe and the creator of their own souls. Whereas our
1
Michael Salmon, “Artificial Night Lighting and Sea Turtles,” Biologist 50 (2003): 163–168.
Scott Davis et al., “Night Shift Work, Light at Night and the Risk of Breast Cancer,” Journal
of National Cancer Institute 93 (2001): 1557-1562; Eva Schernhammer et al., “Rotating Night
Shifts and Risk of Breast Cancer in Women Participating in Nurses’ Health Study,” Journal of
National Cancer Institute 93 (2001): 1563-1566.
3
Verlyn Klinkenborg, “Our Vanishing Night,” National Geographic (November 2008): 108.
2
A New Philosophy of Darkness
forefathers felt awe to the point of worship when they looked up at the celestial
spheres, we moderns tend to see a hazy sky and feel proud to know that stars,
though we rarely see them, are merely balls of gas; as Friedrich von Schiller remarked in his poem “The Gods of Greece”: “Where lifeless – fixed afar, / A flaming ball to our dull sense is given, / Phoebus Apollo, in his golden car, / In silent
glory swept the fields of heaven!”4 In short, the health of human beings in both
their biological and spiritual capacities suffers when literal darkness, in its appropriate place, is not appreciated.
“Evil” Animals
Just now I mentioned two types of injustice that arise as a result of undervaluing literal darkness: aesthetic injustice and ethical injustice, both of which ultimately have to do with a given thing not being valued or treated as it ought to be
(though aesthetic injustice refers to matters of beauty, whereas ethical injustice refers to matters of moral conduct). In regard to darkness, I mentioned that due to a
lack of literal darkness, human beings are tempted to elevate themselves above
God or the gods. Now this is one side of ethical injustice: elevating a thing above
its proper position or assigning a given thing more value than it ought to be assigned. But there is also the other side of ethical injustice: lowering a thing below
its proper position or assigning a given thing a lower value than it ought to be
assigned. Consequently, whereas human beings, due to light pollution, often elevate themselves above God unjustly, human beings, due in large part to Darwinism, often unjustly lower themselves to, or near, the same level as animals. Both
directions lead to ethical injustice (at least given my metaphysical assumptions)
and so should be avoided.
Nevertheless, while I think it is a grave mistake to see human beings as merely
developed animals, the Darwinian impact has had at least one positive effect on
thinking in the West: injustice toward animals, particularly those associated with
the dark, is decreasing. That is, although psychologist Richard Ryder and philosopher Peter Singer go too far when they accuse most people of speciesism – that is,
an unjust bias in favour of our species above any other species5 – and primatologist Frans de Waal and philosopher Martha Nussbaum go too far in decrying the
evil of anthropodenial – that is, human beings denying that they are only animals6
– I do think that human beings, though their nature is superior to all other animals
and thus justly favor themselves above them, historically have devalued some animal species so low as to be unjust toward them. Indeed, as East Asian specialist
Thomas LaMarre has pointed out, even when one race uses zoomorphic images to
portray another race as an animal, such as the Americans did when they portrayed
the Japanese as monkeys during the second world war, people act unjustly not
4
Friedrich von Schiller, “The Gods of Greece,” in The Poems of Schiller (New York: Dodo Press,
2007), 3.1-4.
5
See Peter Singer, Animal Liberation (New York: Random House, 1975).
267
Christian Scholar’s Review
268
only toward other people but also toward animals since animals, as amoral creatures, do not have the moral flaws of humans because they do not have the moral
capabilities that humans have.7 The corrective of Darwinism, then, has been helpful, but if it is taken as more than a corrective, it leads to the errors of Ryder, Singer,
de Waal and Nussbaum.
Yet if creatures associated with the dark, to be specific now, should be neither
hunted down and killed nor treated like our equals and brothers, what is the correct view of them? I myself favor something like the view of C. S. Lewis in his
science fiction book Perelandra, wherein he claims that all creatures were made good
and insofar as we see some creatures as inherently evil, we are being tricked by
satanic philosophy; as the hero of Perelandra, Ransom, tells us upon visiting an
alien world and seeing strange creatures in it:
The creature was there, a curiously shaped creature no doubt, but all the loathing had vanished clean out of his mind, so that neither then nor at any other time could he remember it,
nor ever understand again why one should quarrel with an animal for having more legs or
eyes than oneself. All that he had felt from childhood about insects and reptiles died that
moment: died utterly, as hideous music dies when you switch off the wireless. Apparently it
had all, even from the beginning, been a dark enchantment of the Enemy’s. Once, as he had
sat writing near an open window in Cambridge, he had looked up and shuddered to see, as
he supposed, a many-coloured beetle of unusually hideous shape crawling across his paper.
A second glance showed him that it was a dead leaf, moved by the breeze; and instantly the
very curves and re-entrants which had made its ugliness turned into its beauties. At this
moment he had almost the same sensation. He saw at once that the creature intended him no
harm – had indeed no intentions at all. . . . Then, apparently not liking its surroundings, it
turned laboriously round and began descending into the hole by which it had come. As he
saw the last section of its tripartite body wobble on the edge of the aperture, and then finally
tip upward with its torpedo-shaped tail in the air, Ransom almost laughed. “Like an animated corridor train” was his comment.8
Lewis’s point is that any literal hatred or vilification of creatures associated with
darkness, such as snakes, insects and so on, is ethically unjust since such behavior
treats good things as though they were evil. Moreover, one could even take this
further and say that even indifference to creatures associated with darkness (not to
mention any creature for that matter) can be seen as, at least, aesthetically unjust
since every creature has a specific and unique nature that demands to be appreciated for its own quiddity; hence, I think Lewis is again on the right track when he
writes,
6
“To put my thesis in a nutshell: anthropodenial, a uniquely human tendency, is not simply
a pernicious intellectual position: it is a large cause of moral deformity.” Martha Nussbaum,
“Compassion: Human and Animal,” presented at Seoul National University (29 August 2008):
4.
7
Thomas LaMarre, “Speciesism, Part I: Translating Races into Animals in Wartime Animation,” in The Limits of the Human, vol. 3, Mechademia, ed. Frenchy Lunning (Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press, 2008), 76.
8
C. S. Lewis, Perelandra, in The Cosmic Trilogy (1943 reprint; London: Pan Books, 1990), 310311.
A New Philosophy of Darkness
God need not create this Nature. He might have created others, He may have created others.
But granted this Nature, then doubtless no smallest part of her is there except because it
expresses the character He chose to give her. It would be a miserable error to suppose that
the dimensions of space and time, the death and rebirth of vegetation, the unity in multiplicity of organisms, the union in opposition to sexes, and the colour of each particular apple in
Herefordshire this autumn, were merely a collection of useful devices forcibly welded together. They are the very idiom, almost the facial expression, the smell or taste, of an individual thing. The quality of Nature is present in them all just as the Latinity of Latin is present
in every inflection or the ‘Correggiosity’ of Correggio in every stroke of the brush.9
Of course, a common objection to this kind of view is to ask what, if everything is unique and purposeful, is the purpose of things like mosquitoes or the
Andromeda Galaxy? The problem inherent in this kind of question is that typically
people mean something like “What is the utility of these things for humans?” But it
does not take the Crocodile Hunter, Steve Irwin, to see that this begs the question,
for why should we think that once we agree that everything was created for a
purpose and possesses a unique nature that everything was made for human use?
Although mosquitoes do not benefit human beings (and only benefit a few natural
creatures) in terms of being a source of food, comfort and so on, the uniqueness of
the mosquito must delight its Creator and part of being aesthetically just means
learning to appreciate things as God appreciates them – that is, not just for their
utility but also for their own sake. We could take this further and argue that although human beings will probably never see the far reaches of the universe, it
does not follow that the beauty that is likely found there exists in vain. Perhaps
God made such simply for His own pleasure; or perhaps there are alien races that
are able to appreciate that beauty. While Isaiah uses the child playing with an asp
as a metaphor for the harmony found in Paradise, it can probably be taken literally
as well since if all things were created unique and good, then why would God not
want to bring all such good things together in reconciliation and delight?10
Nevertheless, while it is ethically wrong to literally hate any creature, and at
least aesthetically wrong to fail to appreciate every creature, including those associated with the dark, it does not follow that we should love or appreciate all creatures equally. Although I do not want to rank animals in terms of ontological worth,
I do think that in most cases people are perfectly just in preferring, say, a horse to a
bat, or a dog to a wolf – not because these night creatures have been associated with
both rational and irrational fears nor because they have been blamed by legends
both rightly and wrongly, but rather, or at least most importantly, because of the
tameness factor. That is, I think that a tame animal is superior to an untamed animal,
and so since horses and dogs are tamed more easily than bats and wolves, typically, though not always, people will then rightly value horses and dogs over bats
and wolves. But why is tamed better than untamed? Well, according to C. S. Lewis
(again), if the world was made to be under the benevolent authority of human
9
C. S. Lewis, Miracles, in C. S. Lewis: Selected Books (1947 reprint; London: HarperCollins,
1999), 1149.
10
Isaiah 11:8.
269
Christian Scholar’s Review
270
beings, then all those creatures below humans were made to be under human authority.11 Consequently, while we cannot attribute ethical behavior to animals, we
can say that an animal that obeys human authority acts according to its nature
(and thus, for its own happiness) and an animal that rebels against human authority acts against its nature (and thus, against its own happiness); as Aristotle wrote,
“The same holds good of animals in relation to men; for tame animals have a better
nature than wild and all tame animals are better off when they are ruled by man;
for then they are preserved.”12 Bringing this all together, we can say that the tame
animal does not mean a sterile, broken or enslaved animal but rather an animal
that enjoys its wildness and freedom within the bounds of proper submission,
wherein its true happiness lies. Indeed, Lewis even speculates that in addition to
being preserved and elevated above untamed animals, tamed animals might become qualified for a higher life than they, or we, could possibly imagine; thus, in
Lewis’s science fiction novel That Hideous Strength, Mr. Bultitude the bear “trembled
on the very borders of personality” when in the presence of its benevolent ruler
Ransom.13
What about Animal Archetypes?
As I mentioned earlier, many animals associated with the dark have developed bad reputations over time. Some of these reputations are justly given and
some are unjustly given; for instance, it is unfair to the bat to link it with vampires
since by doing so, bats are seen to be more harmful than they really are, whereas it
is not unjust to fear and attempt to remove a snake from around one’s house since
snakes really do bite anyone who startles them. However, even in the case of the
snake we should not make the move toward injustice by linking our rational fear
of snakes with the idea that snakes are somehow inherently evil, for snakes have
no evil intentions: they simply act according to their natural instincts. Moreover if
nature really has been in rebellion against humans since the time that humans
rebelled against God, it still does not follow that any part of nature should be seen
as evil, since to qualify as evil an act of the will is necessary.
Be all this as it may, I agree with the basic insight of scholars like Karl Jung,
Joseph Campbell and others when they say that human beings have access to universal archetypes which gives them genuine knowledge about some mysterious
truth. Moreover, I think that such archetypes are not merely grounded in some
original primal experience that somehow passed down through the ages in the
form of cultural generalizations; rather, I think that these archetypes are reflective
of some higher, more mysterious aspect of reality that is only partially understood
11
C. S. Lewis, The Problem of Pain, in C. S. Lewis: Selected Books (1940 reprint; London:
HarperCollins, 1999), 545-546.
12
Aristotle, Politics, 1254b10-12.
13
C. S. Lewis, That Hideous Strength, in The Cosmic Trilogy (1945 reprint; London: Pan Books
1990), 672.
A New Philosophy of Darkness
by human beings, who, as I said, are limited creatures. Of course, none of this is to
deny cultural generalizations: it is only to say that in addition to cultural generalizations, there are also genuine universal archetypes.
Now what this has to do with creatures associated with the dark should be
obvious. Most cultural generalizations about creatures associated with the dark,
such as the bat, are negative, the result of which is that such creatures are usually
treated unjustly. But what about some creatures like the snake or the dragon? Are
these creatures not archetypes of evil? Even if one were to grant that the history of
the snake and the dragon is the history of creatures associated with great evil –
hence, Satan possessed the snake in the Garden of Eden and, perhaps in connection with this, was linked with the dragon – it does not follow that snakes and
dragons are inherently evil, only that they were appropriated for evil and thus
associated with it. Thus, when the Buddha reformed, and enlisted in his service
the snake-dragon Naga, we are provided with a powerful reminder that such creatures should not be stereotyped as inherently evil. Consequently, I would deny
that the snake or dragon is an archetype of evil since according to my theory, archetypes should reflect natural, objective natures, such as the cunning of the snake,
the stealth of the bat or the majestic terror of the dragon.
Metaphorical Darkness
While I am opposed both to treating any animal as though it were inherently
evil and to equating cultural generalizations, which are often unjust, with universal archetypes which reflect true natures, I think that there are a few occasions for
linking darkness with evil.
To begin with, we must be clear about literal darkness: literal darkness is not a
thing and so is neither good nor evil in and of itself; indeed, it has no “self” since it
has no nature. The goodness of literal darkness must be seen in the context of the
created whole, where certain absences – in our case, the absence of light – are appropriate in certain places. Thus, literal darkness should be seen as a good thing
insofar as it contrasts aptly with proper light and color, an implication of which is
that light pollution is both aesthetic and ethical evil since such pollution diminishes the proper shade of the night sky, which results in both aesthetic injustice
toward the beauty of creation and ethical injustice toward the humans and animals
hurt both directly and indirectly by too much light. Of course on the flipside, when
literal darkness is present where light and color should be present, such as when
lights are kept permanently off at an art gallery, then literal darkness may be considered (at least in this case, an aesthetic) evil.
And something similar is true of metaphorical darkness. Our metaphors linking darkness and evil may be considered just metaphors insofar as they are based
on a similarity grounded in privation or unnatural lack. Thus, we could use the
metaphor of the death of a human as being like the extinguishing of a candle justly,
but we could only use this metaphor justly insofar as we meant that the extin-
271
Christian Scholar’s Review
272
guishing of a candle is an unnatural event. If we meant that the death of a human
being, which is always unnatural (in the grand scheme of creation), is like the
extinguishing of all candles – naturally or otherwise – then we would be creating
an unjust metaphor. Hence, in this case we should qualify the metaphor by saying
something like the death of a human being is like a candle extinguished by a sudden draft from an open window.
In addition to cases where darkness can be justly (and unjustly) linked with
evil in metaphors, there are also cases where darkness can be justly (and unjustly)
linked with positive good in metaphors. Focusing on situations where darkness
can be justly linked with positive good in metaphors, I want to consider two examples: the affect in the soul that Rudolf Otto calls the numinous and certain forms
of Negative Theology.
In The Idea of the Holy, Rudolf Otto examines “the Numen” or “the Holy,” which
is a technical term used to describe the sacred minus any moral or rational aspects.14 From the word Numen, Otto derives the word “numinous,” with which he
then speaks of a numinous category of value which is always present when an
individual is in a numinous state of mind. “This mental state,” Otto writes, “is perfectly sui generis and irreducible to any other; and therefore, like every absolutely
primary and elementary datum, while it admits of being discussed, it cannot be
strictly defined.”15 According to Otto, the numinous is the feeling that overcomes
the mind when the individual “is submerged and overwhelmed by its own nothingness.”16 This feeling, in turn, is always accompanied by a sense of complete
dependence on the Divine.17 However, this feeling of dependence is not merely a
natural feeling of dependence, such as insufficiency resulting from a difficult circumstance; rather, it is a mystical sense of dependence, like the dependence Abraham
felt when he pled with God for the people of Sodom: “Behold now, I, who am but
dust and ash, have taken upon me to speak unto the Lord.”18 Otto calls this kind of
dependency the “creature-feeling;”19 nevertheless, while the numinous is broadly
identified with “creature-feeling,” Otto claims that this can be divided into two
key elements: (1) the feeling of mysterium tremendum, and (2) fascination.
When an individual experiences mysterium tremendum, he feels he is in the
presence of something which is at once awful, august, majestic, overpowering,
living, urgent, different, pulsating, dark and uncanny.20 The feeling of mysterium
tremendum may “burst in sudden eruption up from the depths of the soul with
spasms and convulsions, or lead to the strangest excitements, to intoxicated frenzy,
14
Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy: An Inquiry Into the Non-Rational Factor in the Idea of the
Divine and its Relation to the Rational, trans. John W. Harvey (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1958), 6.
15
Ibid., 7.
16
Ibid., 10.
17
Ibid., 25.
18
Genesis 28:27.
19
Otto, The Idea of the Holy, 8.
20
Ibid., 13-30.
A New Philosophy of Darkness
to transport, and to ecstasy;” in itself, this feeling may be either demonic or angelic, something wild and grisly or beautiful and pure.21 Yet in whatever mode this
feeling takes, it always makes the mind shudder and the individual think of himself as less than nothing since he feels himself to be in the presence of something
that is supernatural, wholly other and yet pulsating with an energy and life more
real than his own. The dark or uncanny nature of mysterium tremendum is a vital
part of this concept since it points to the unlimited, supernatural nature of the
numinous. Otto himself compares this element of the numinous to Immanuel Kant’s
sublime, for while neither are concerned with beauty, both are concerned with the
mysterious, the maddening, the daunting, and the boundless22 (although, of course,
Kant’s sublime has to do with aesthetics, whereas Otto’s numinous has to do with
religion; hence, Otto claims that Kant’s sublime is “a pale reflexion of” the
numinous23). Consequently, the numinous can be incited by things like romantic literature, fairy stories and myths; as Otto writes, “But the fairy-story proper only
comes into being with the element of the “wonderful,” with miracle and miraculous events and consequences, i.e. by means of an infusion of the numinous. And
the same holds good in an increased degree of myth.”24
The second and final element in the numinous is fascination. This sensation
occurs in the individual as a result of his experiencing the mysterious and unknown. Awe, it is true, brings the individual to his knees, but desire to see and
understand the mystery – indeed, fascination and “love” for the dark mystery25 –
causes him to raise his eyes. And what he sees when he raises his eyes causes him
to be overcome with a kind of madness, but it is the madness of the finite looking
into the infinite,26 and in this sense, it bears resemblance to Platonic eros, which
speaks of the need for the soul to be possessed by divine eros in order to ascend into
the heavens.27 Consequently, the individual who experiences the numinous feels at
once terrified of, and attracted to, the dark, haunting mystery.
The numinous, of course, is related to Negative Theology, that is, theology that
attempts to define God or the Divine by what it is not. According to Church Father
Gregory Nyssa and later on, theologian Pseudo Dionysius, a human being’s knowl21
Ibid., 12-13.
For Kant, emotion is irrelevant to beauty, but not to the sublime. Moreover, while beauty
has to do with quality, the formed, the finite and the natural, the sublime has to do with
quantity, the unformed, the infinite and the non-rational. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York: Hafner, 1961) [2.23]. It should be noted that the division
between the sublime and the beautiful did not originate with Kant, for Kant himself derived
this idea from Edmund Burke’s On the Sublime and Beautiful (not Longinus’ On the Sublime).
However, since Otto dealt with Kant and not Burke, I have restricted my comments to Kant.
Cf. Edmund Burke, On the Sublime and Beautiful (New York, P. F. Collier & Son, 1937), 101
[3.27].
23
Otto, The Idea of the Holy, 40.
24
Ibid., 122.
25
Ibid., 41.
26
Ibid., 29.
27
Plato, Phaedrus, 249-50.
22
273
Christian Scholar’s Review
274
edge is so limited that his understanding of God, who is unlimited, often appears
to be nothing but nonsense. This nonsense is what is known as the “divine darkness,” which is a person’s feeling that the Divine is so far above his understanding
and so bright that the Divine appears dark before the light of the human mind, just
as a human’s eyes see black after staring into the sun too long.28
Consequently, it seems to me that both the numinous and certain types of Negative Theology create just metaphors to highlight natural darkness and goodness.
For instance, in the case of the numinous, the link between human ignorance and
darkness is a good one since some ignorance is natural to humans and this natural
ignorance entails natural curiosity. Or in the case of certain formulations of Negative Theology, the metaphor that links God and darkness is a good one since it is
natural that when human beings mentally stare at God in His full splendor, they
should feel confused, and hopefully, properly humbled.
Dark Delight
In conclusion, I think a proper approach to darkness and creatures associated
with the dark begins with separating literal and metaphorical darkness clearly. If
this is done, then I think it becomes apparent that literal darkness in its proper
place and all creatures associated with the dark are natural and good, and if people
want to be both ethically and aesthetically just, they need to value and appreciate
such. Nevertheless, unnatural darkness can be linked justly with evil in metaphors.
However, I would encourage people to follow Rudolf Otto, Gregory Nyssa and
Pseudo Dionysius in exploring ways to illustrate positive darkness in metaphors
not only because such is natural and right but also because this corrective (the
important word here) is badly needed in a world that largely sees darkness, and all
that is associated with the dark, as both literally and metaphorically evil.
28
Pseudo-Dionysius, The Mystical Theology, 1048a-b.