The Cambridge Dictionary of Sociology
Providing an authoritative and comprehensive overview of the classical and the
contemporary, this volume is an indispensable guide to the vibrant and
expanding field of sociology. Featuring over 600 entries, from concise definitions
to discursive essays, written by leading international academics, the Dictionary
offers a truly global perspective, examining both American and European traditions and approaches. Entries cover schools, theories, theorists, and debates,
with substantial articles on all key topics in the field. While recognizing the
richness of historical sociological traditions, the Dictionary also looks forward to
new and evolving influences such as cultural change, genetics, globalization,
information technologies, new wars, and terrorism. Most entries incorporate
references for further reading, and a cross-referencing system enables easy
access to related areas. This Dictionary is an invaluable reference work for
students and academics alike and will help to define the field of sociology in
years to come.
BRYAN S. TURNER
is Professor of Sociology in the Asia Research Institute at the
National University of Singapore, where he leads the research team for the
Religion and Globalisation cluster. Prior to this, he was Professor of Sociology
in the Faculty of Social and Political Sciences at the University of Cambridge.
Professor Turner is the author of The New Medical Sociology (2004) and Society and
Culture: Principles of Scarcity and Solidarity (with Chris Rojek, 2001), and is the
founding editor of the Journal of Classical Sociology (with John O’Neill), Body &
Society (with Mike Featherstone), and Citizenship Studies. He is currently writing a
three-volume study on the sociology of religion for Cambridge University Press.
BOARD OF EDITORIAL ADVISORS
Ira Cohen, Rutgers University
Jeff Manza, Northwestern University
Gianfranco Poggi, Universita di Trento
Beth Schneider, University of California, Santa Barbara
Susan Silbey, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Carol Smart, University of Leeds
The
Cambridge Dictionary of
SOCIOLOGY
General Editor
BRYAN S. TURNER
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo
Cambridge University Press
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521832908
© Cambridge University Press 2006
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provision of
relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place
without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published in print format 2006
eBook (NetLibrary)
ISBN-13 978-0-511-37145-5
ISBN-10 0-511-37145-4
eBook (NetLibrary)
hardback
ISBN-13 978-0-521-83290-8
hardback
ISBN-10 0-521-83290-X
paperback
ISBN-13 978-0-521-54046-9
paperback
ISBN-10 0-521-54046-1
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls
for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not
guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
To the memory of my parents Sophia Turner (née Brookes) and
Stanley W. Turner
Contents
List of contributors
page viii
Acknowledgments
x
Introduction
xi
How to use this Dictionary
xix
THE DICTIONARY
vii
List of contributors
Gabriel Abend, Northwestern University
Gary L. Albrecht, University of Illinois, Chicago
Jeffrey Alexander, Yale University
Tomas Almaguer, San Francisco State University
Patrick Baert, University of Cambridge
Jack Barbalet, University of Leicester
James Beckford, University of Warwick
Stephen Benard, Cornell University
Michael Billig, Loughborough University
Mildred Blaxter, University of Bristol
Mick Bloor, University of Glasgow
William A. Brown, University of Cambridge
Brendan J. Burchell, University of Cambridge
Stewart Clegg, University of Technology, Sydney
Elizabeth F. Cohen, Syracuse University
Ira Cohen, Rutgers University
Oonagh Corrigan, University of Plymouth
Rosemary Crompton, City University, London
Sean Cubitt, The University of Waikato, New Zealand
Tom Cushman, Wellesley College
Tia DeNora, University of Exeter
Peter Dickens, University of Cambridge
Michele Dillon, University of New Hampshire
S. N. Eisenstadt, The Jerusalem Van Leer Institute
Tony Elger, University of Warwick
Anthony Elliott, Flinders University of South
Australia
Amitai Etzioni, The Communitarian Network,
Washington
Mary Evans, University of Kent
Ron Eyerman, Yale University
James D. Faubion, Rice University
Janie Filoteo, Texas A & M University
Gary Alan Fine, Northwestern University
David Frisby, London School of Economics
Loraine Gelsthorpe, University of Cambridge
Julian Go, Boston University
David Good, University of Cambridge
Philip Goodman, University of California, Irvine
Susan Hansen, Murdoch University
Bernadette Hayes, University of Aberdeen
Chris Haywood, University of Newcastle upon Tyne
John Heritage, University of California, Los Angeles
John Hoffman, University of Leicester
John Holmwood, University of Sussex
Robert Holton, Trinity College, Dublin
Darnell Hunt, University of California, Los Angeles
Geoffrey Ingham, University of Cambridge
Engin Isin, York University, Canada
Andrew Jamison, Aalborg University
Valerie Jenness, University of California, Irvine
Bob Jessop, Lancaster University
James E. Katz, Rutgers University
Douglas Kellner, University of California,
Los Angeles
Krishan Kumar, University of Virginia
John Law, Lancaster University
Charles Lemert, Wesleyan University
Donald N. Levine, University of Chicago
Ruth Lister, Loughborough University
Steven Loyal, University College, Dublin
Mairtin Mac-an-Ghaill, University of Birmingham
Michael Macy, Cornell University
Jeff Manza, Northwestern University
Robert Miller, Queen’s University, Belfast
Jan Pakulski, University of Tasmania
Edward Park, Loyola Marymount University
Frank Pearce, Queen’s University, Canada
Emile Perreau-Saussine, University of Cambridge
Chris Phillipson, Keele University
Gianfranco Poggi, Università di Trento, Italy
Dudley L. Poston,* Texas A & M University
Stephen Quilley, University College, Dublin
Mark Rapley, Edith Cowan University
Larry Ray, University of Kent at Canterbury
Isaac Reed, Yale University
Thomas Reifer, University of San Diego
Derek Robbins, University of East London
Chris Rojek, Nottingham Trent University
Mercedes Rubio, American Sociological Association
*Dudley Poston wishes to thank the following graduate students for their assistance: Mary Ann
Davis, Chris Lewinski, Hua Luo, Heather Terrell and Li Zhang.
viii
List of contributors
Rogelio Saenz, Texas A & M University
Kent Sandstrom, University of Northern Iowa
Cornel Sandvoss, University of Surrey
Jacqueline Schneider, University of Leicester
Jackie Scott, University of Cambridge
Martin Shaw, University of Sussex
Mark Sherry, The University of Toledo
Birte Siim, Aalborg University, Denmark
Susan Silbey, Massachusetts Institute of
Technology
Carol Smart, University of Manchester
Vicki Smith, University of California, Davis
Nick Stevenson, University of Nottingham
Rob Stones, University of Essex
Richard Swedberg, Cornell University
Piotr Sztompka, Jagiellonian University, Poland
Edward Tiryakian, Duke University
Kenneth H. Tucker, Jr., Mount Holyoke College, MA
Bryan S. Turner, National University of Singapore
Jonathan Turner, University of California, Riverside
Stephen P. Turner, University of South Florida
Arnout van de Rijt, Cornell University
Ann Vogel, University of Exeter
Frederic Volpi, University of St. Andrews
Alan Warde, University of Manchester
Darin Weinberg, University of Cambridge
Andrew Wernick, Trent University, Canada
Kevin White, The Australian National University
Fiona Wood, Cardiff University
ix
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Sarah Caro, formerly Senior Commissioning Editor in
Social Sciences at Cambridge University Press, for her tireless and cheerful
commitment to this Dictionary, and her enthusiasm for the project of sociology
as a whole. Her quiet determination to get the job done provided me with an
enduring role model. More recently, John Haslam has effectively seen this
project to a conclusion. Juliet Davis-Berry of the Press worked unstintingly to
get lists, entries, and authors organized. Carrie Cheek has provided generous
and careful secretarial and editorial support in collecting entries, corresponding
with authors, overseeing corrections, and dealing with my mistakes. Without
her ongoing support, the Dictionary would not have been completed. Leigh
Mueller worked with extraordinary vigilance to correct the proofs of the
Dictionary and to impose some standard of excellence on often wayward English.
The editorial board members – Ira Cohen, Jeff Manza, Gianfranco Poggi, Beth
Schneider, Susan Silbey, and Carol Smart – contributed to the development of
the list of entries, read and re-read draft entries, and made substantial contributions of their own. Ira Cohen, in particular, wrote major entries, advised authors,
and recruited his daughter as a contributor. The authors kindly responded to
criticism and correction of their draft submissions with considerable tolerance.
Many authors struggled with major illness, family breakdown, and the sheer
cussedness of everyday life to complete entries on time. The following authors
wrote many additional and extensive essays, often at the last minute to fill
in gaps caused by entries that were missing for a variety of reasons, and I am
especially grateful to them: Stewart Clegg, Tony Elgar, Mary Evans, Susan
Hansen, John Hoffman, John Holmwood, Charles Lemert, Steven Loyal, Stephen
Quilley, Mark Rapley, Larry Ray, Darin Weinberg, and Kevin White. The Dictionary
is, in short, a genuinely collective effort. However, any remaining errors and
omissions are my responsibility.
x
Introduction
At one level, sociology is easy to define. It is the study of social institutions – the
family, religion, sport, community, and so on. We can study institutions at
the micro-level by looking at interactions between family members, for example, or we can examine macro-relations such as the family and kinship system
of a society as a whole. Below this level of minimal agreement, there is considerable dispute as to what sociology really is, and during the twentieth
century and into this century many critics of sociology have periodically
pronounced it to be in crisis or to be moribund. It is said to be prone to jargon,
or it is claimed by its critics to be merely common sense. A natural scientist at
my former Cambridge college, on hearing that I was editing a dictionary of
sociology, inquired in all seriousness whether there would be enough concepts
and terms for a whole dictionary. My problem as editor has by contrast been the
question of what to leave out. In this context of lay skepticism, a dictionary of
sociology is in part a defense of the discipline from its detractors, and in part a
statement of its achievements and prospects. It aims to give a precise, informative, and objective account of the discipline, including both its successes and
failures, and in this sense dictionaries are inherently conservative. A dictionary
seeks to give an informed guide to a particular field such that both the expert
and the student can benefit intellectually.
In many respects, part of the problem for sociology as an academic discipline
lies in its very success. An outsider to the academy at the end of the nineteenth
century, sociology is now influential in archaeology, the arts, the history and
philosophy of science, science and technology studies, religious studies, organizational theory, and in the teaching of general practice and community medicine in medical faculties, where the social dimension of everyday reality is now
taken for granted. The study of contemporary epidemics in public health,
especially the AIDS/HIV epidemic, has employed sociological insights into networks and risk taking. The management of any future pandemic will draw upon
sociological research on social networks, compliance behavior, and the impact
of such factors as social class, gender, and age on prevalence rates. Other areas
such as art history and aesthetics often draw implicitly on sociological notions of
audiences, art careers, art markets, and cultural capital. Science and technology
studies more explicitly depend on the sociology of knowledge. Dance studies
frequently adopt insights and perspectives from the sociology of the body. It is
often difficult to distinguish between historical sociology, social history and
world-systems theory. Cultural studies, women’s studies, and disability studies
have drawn extensively on debates of social construction in sociology. Activists
xi
Introduction
in social movements in support of disability groups have directly adopted sociological ideas about how disability as a social construct involves the curtailment
of social rights. Ethnomethodology – the study of the methods or practices that
are important in accomplishing tasks in the everyday world – has contributed to
research on how people use complex machinery in workplace settings. Conversational analysis has been important in understanding how conversations
take place, for example between doctor and patient. The emerging area of
terrorism studies will no doubt have a substantial input from sociologists on
recruitment patterns, beliefs, and social background. In short, there has been
a great dispersion and proliferation of the sociological paradigm into adjacent
fields and disciplines. Much of this intellectual dispersion or seepage has
practical consequences.
The danger is, however, that the sociological perspective will, as a result of
this intellectual leakage, simply dissolve into cultural studies, film studies,
media studies, and so forth. Sociological insights and approaches have been
successfully dispersed through the humanities and science curricula, but the
intellectual connections with sociology are not always recognized or indeed
understood. The contemporary enthusiasm for multidisciplinarity and interdisciplinarity often obscures the need to preserve basic disciplines. Although
this dispersal of sociology into various areas within the humanities and social
science curricula is satisfying in some respects, it is important to defend a
sociological core, if sociology is to survive as a coherent and valid discipline.
The idea of defending a “canon” has become somewhat unfashionable. In
literary studies, the problem of the canonical authority of the received great
texts has been a crucial issue in English literature since the publication of, for
example, F. R. Leavis’s The Great Tradition in 1948. The idea of a sociological
canon has been attacked by feminism and postmodernism for being too
exclusive and narrow, but a canonical tradition does not have to be unduly
narrow or parochial, and students need to understand how sociology developed, who contributed to its growth, and where contemporary concepts
emerged historically. I would contend further that classical sociology, when
generously defined, remains relevant to understanding the contemporary
world. The study of “the social” remains the basis of the discipline, where
the social is constituted by institutions. Where the intellectual roots of
the discipline are ignored, the strong program of sociology as an autonomous
discipline is eroded. A dictionary of sociology is an attempt to (re)state the
principal theories and findings of the discipline, and thereby inevitably contributes to the definition of a canon. Sociology remains, however, a critical
discipline, which constantly questions its origins and its evolution.
Of course, in many respects, sociology is not a homogeneous or seamless
discipline. It has always been somewhat fragmented by different traditions,
epistemologies, values, and methodologies. Sociological theories and ideas are
perhaps more open to contestation and dispute, precisely because their social
and political implications are radical. A dictionary of sociology has to articulate the coherence of the subject, and at the same time fully to recognize its
xii
Introduction
diversity. For example, one major division in sociology has been between the
American and the European traditions. The basic difference is that sociology
in America became thoroughly professionalized with a strong association (the
American Sociological Association), a variety of professional journals, a clear
apprenticeship process prior to tenure, and a reward system of prizes and
honors. In Europe, professional associations have not been able to establish
an agreed core of theory, methods, and substantive topics. While European
sociology defines its roots in the classical tradition of Marx, Durkheim, Weber,
and Simmel, American sociology more often sees its origins in the applied
sociology of the Chicago School, in pragmatism, and in symbolic interactionism. American sociology has favored empiricism, pragmatism, and social
psychology over European sociology, which has its foundations in the Enlightenment, the humanism of Auguste Comte, the political economy of Marx, and
the critical theory of Adorno and Horkheimer. We should not overstate this
division. There have been important figures in sociology, who, to some extent,
have bridged the gap between the two traditions – C. Wright Mills, Talcott
Parsons, Peter Berger, Neil Smelser, and more recently Jeffrey Alexander and
Anthony Giddens. W. E. B. Du Bois was trained in both American and European
traditions. Nevertheless the divisions are real and these historical differences
have been, if anything, reinforced in recent years by the fact that European
sociology has been more exposed to postmodernism, deconstruction, and
poststructuralism than has the American tradition. In negative terms, European sociology has been more subject to rapid changes in fashions in social
theory. Pragmatism, social reform, and applied sociology in America have been
seen as an alternative to the excessive theoretical nature of European thought.
While Adorno and Horkheimer saw American empiricism as the worst form of
traditional theory, the Marxist revival in the 1960s and 1970s in Europe had
little lasting impact in America. Talcott Parsons’s sociology in fact never gained
dominance in American sociology, partly because The Structure of Social Action
was too European. More recently the pragmatist revival in America – for
example in the social philosophy of Richard Rorty – has attempted to show
once more that American social theory does not need any European inspiration. Recent European debates have not had much impact on mainstream
American sociology. Two illustrations are important. The development of
cultural studies that has been influential in British sociology, around the work
of Richard Hoggart, Raymond Williams, Stuart Hall, and the Birmingham
School, has had relatively little consequence in mainstream American sociology. The debate around Ulrich Beck’s notion of risk society and the theory of
individualization has not extended much beyond Europe.
In this new Cambridge Dictionary of Sociology, I have attempted to cover both
American and European traditions by ensuring that the editorial board and
the authors reflect these different approaches, and that the entries have
afforded ample recognition of the richness of these different perspectives.
Entries therefore attempt to provide a more global coverage of sociology by
attending to these differences rather than obscuring or denying them. The
xiii
Introduction
Dictionary examines key intellectual figures in both European and American
sociology, and also reflects different substantive, theoretical, and methodological perspectives. Although there are important differences that are the
product of separate historical developments, the Dictionary also looks forward
to new influences that are the common concerns of sociologists everywhere.
What are these new developments in sociology that the Cambridge Dictionary
attempts to address? First, there is the debate about globalization itself.
Sociologists have been concerned with two significant aspects of this process,
namely the globalization of trade and finance following the collapse of the
Bretton Woods agreements and the rise of the Washington consensus, and
the development of technology and software that made possible global communication in an expanding economy. Sociologists have examined a variety
of substantial changes relating to globalization, such as diasporic communities, global migration, fundamentalism, and the rise of the global city.
Various theoretical responses to these changes are also fairly obvious. The
analysis of risk society itself can be seen as a sociological response to
the uncertain social consequences of economic globalization. Another development is the use of social capital theory to look at the social impact of global
disorganization and economic inequality on individual health and illness.
While the original foundations of globalization theory were explored in
economics and politics (for example the global governance debate), sociologists have become to some extent more interested in cultural globalization in
terms of mass media and cultural imperialism. As a result of globalization,
sociologists have been exercised by the possibility of new forms of cosmopolitanism, and whether a cosmopolitan ethic can transform the character
of sociology. These debates and concepts are fully represented in this
Dictionary.
One important aspect of globalization has been a revival of the sociological
study of religion. In the 1960s the sociology of religion was especially dominant, partly through the influence of sociologists such as Peter Berger, Thomas
Luckmann, Bryan Wilson, and David Martin. However, as the secularization
thesis became dominant, the intellectual fortunes of the sociology of religion
declined. In American sociology, the study of cults and new religious movements was important, but the sociology of religion was no longer influential in
sociology as a whole, and it was not at the cutting edge of sociological theory.
The globalization process has given rise to a revival of the sociology of religion,
especially in the study of fundamentalism. In this respect, the work of Roland
Robertson on (cultural and religious) globalization has been particularly influential. Here again, however, there are important differences between America
and Europe, because American sociology has been much more influenced by
the applications of rational choice theory to religious behavior, giving rise to
the notion of a “spiritual marketplace.” Whereas European societies have
experienced a history of religious decline in terms of church attendance and
membership, religion in America has remained an influential aspect of public
life. The “new paradigm” in American sociology of religion has taken notice of
xiv
Introduction
the “supply side” of religion, where competition in the religious market has
expanded religious choice and fostered a buoyant spiritual marketplace.
It is obvious that 9/11, and the subsequent “war on terrorism,” have had
and will continue to have a large impact on sociology. This political and
military crisis demonstrated that the largely positive views of global society
that were characteristic of the early stages of the study of globalization, for
example on world democracy and governance, were somewhat one-sided,
premature, and indeed utopian. The brave new world order had come to a
sudden end. Global uncertainty was reinforced by the Afghan war, the war in
Iraq, and the more general war on Al-Qaeda; and these world events have
opened a new chapter in the history of sociological thought – the sociology of
global terrorism. The bombings in Bali, Madrid, and London demonstrated
the global nature of modern terrorism. We might argue that the sociology of
globalization has, as it were, taken a dark turn. There is growing awareness
of the need to study the global sex industry, including pornography, child
sex abuse, sexual tourism, and the wider issues of slavery and the trade in
women. The war on terrorism has made the sociology of the media even more
prominent, but it has also demonstrated that sociology has until recently
ignored such prominent social phenomena as war, terrorism and violence,
money and exchange, and religion, human rights and law. There is also
greater awareness of the need for a new type of medical sociology that will
examine the globalization of epidemics of which HIV/AIDS, SARS and avian flu
are dramatic examples. Critics have argued that the “cultural turn” in sociology that gave rise to a new interest in cultural phenomena in everyday life
and to new interpretative methods, from discourse analysis to deconstruction
as a method of textual analysis, has resulted in the neglect of traditional but
important social phenomena – social class, poverty, inequality, power, and
racial conflict. One further consequence of 9/11 and 7/7 (the bombings in
London) has been a growing disillusionment with multiculturalism, and
many social scientists have proclaimed “the end of multiculturalism”
and have identified the rise of the “new xenophobia” in western societies.
Future research on race, ethnicity, and identity will be colored by the
despairing, bleak mood of the first decade of the new millennium.
While sociologists have been interested in the social causes of fundamentalism in general, research on political Islam has been especially prominent in
current sociological research. These recent developments have resulted
in various re-evaluations of Max Weber’s comparative sociology of religion.
The debate about the relevance of the Protestant Ethic Thesis to Islam continues to interest sociologists, and there has also been much interest in the
revival of Confucianism in Asia. There is, however, also recognition of the fact
that we need new ways of thinking about modernization, secularization, and
fundamentalism. The work of S. N. Eisenstadt in developing ideas about
“multiple modernities” offers innovative theoretical strategies for sociological research. Globalization is therefore stimulating a rich arena of research in
modern sociology, such as George Ritzer’s work on McDonaldization, Manuel
xv
Introduction
Castells on the media, Martin Shaw on global military conflict, Thomas Cushman on global human rights, and David Martin on global Pentecostalism. This
Dictionary provides substantial coverage of these issues, theories, and authors.
One major dimension of globalization is of course the expansion and transformation of media technology and information. Marshall McLuhan in the
1960s invented a variety of expressions to describe the arrival of a new age –
in particular the idea of a global village. Every aspect of modern society has
been revolutionized by these developments in communication and information – from “cybersex” and “telesurgery” to smart bombs. To understand the
social changes that made possible the information society, there has been a
revival of interest in technology. What had been rejected by Marxist sociology
as “technological determinism” has become increasingly central to the sociological understanding of how the world is changing. Research on the impact of
technology on spatial relationships, speed, and social networks can be seen in
the growing interest in the idea of mobilities, social flows, and networks in the
work of John Urry. The concern to understand technology has forced sociologists to think more creatively about how we interact with objects and networks
between objects. The development of actor network theory has brought together spatial, technological, and science studies to understand the interactional relations between human beings and the world of objects. Many
sociologists believe that these changes are so profound that a new type of
sociology is required to analyze speed, mobility, and the compression of space.
The “cultural turn” (a new emphasis on culture in modern society) was
followed by the “spatial turn” (a new preoccupation with space, the global city,
and urban design). In order to encompass these developments, the Dictionary
has included many entries on information, communications, and mass media.
Technological change in modern society often involves a combination of
information, genetics, computerization, and biomedicine. These developments in society have transformed the old debate about nature and nurture,
and raised new issues about surveillance, individual freedoms, eugenics, and
governmentality. The relationship between the human body, technology, and
society has become increasingly complex, and the emergence of the sociology
of the body can be regarded as one response to these intellectual, social, and
legal developments. The ownership of the human body has become a major
issue in legal conflicts over patients, patents, and profits. The early stages
in the evolution of the sociology of the body were closely associated with
feminism, the anthropology of Mary Douglas, and the work of Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Michel Foucault, but developments in micro-biology and information sciences are beginning to change these concerns with the body “as
organism” to the body as “genetic map.” These new challenges arising from
the implications of genetics for human aging and reproduction have given
rise to the possibility of what Francis Fukuyama has called “our posthuman
future.” This new intellectual confrontation between biology, informatics,
and sociology has also produced a considerable re-assessment of the legacy
of Charles Darwin, social Darwinism, and evolutionary thought. The social
xvi
Introduction
problems associated with the application of genetics have stimulated a renewed interest in the changing nature of reproduction, gender, and the
family. Stem-cell research, therapeutic cloning, and regenerative medicine
are changing the intellectual horizons of medical sociology, and are raising
new questions (for example, can we live forever?) – for which we have no
satisfactory answers.
A reassessment of the relationships between sociology and biology is recasting the old debate between education and endowment, and in turn forcing us
to rethink sex, sexuality, and gender. In the 1960s and 1970s mainstream
sociology often neglected feminist theory and gender. The debate about how
to measure social class, for example, often failed to take into account the class
position of women by concentrating exclusively on the class position of men
in the formal labor market. In the 1970s and 1980s, feminist analysis flourished and the work of Juliet Mitchell, Kate Millett, Germaine Greer, Ann
Oakley, and Shulamith Firestone had a comprehensive impact on sociological
research. Although feminist thought was often fragmented into materialist,
socialist, and postmodern versions, feminism gave rise to a rich legacy of social
theory and empirical work. Sociology has also been influenced by sexual
politics, debates about identity, and queer theory. These debates over gender,
sex, and sexuality were heavily influenced by the debate around social construction, perhaps first clearly enunciated by Simone de Beauvoir’s claim that
women are created by society rather than by biology. Medical technology has
transformed the conditions under which people reproduce and has produced
new methods of reproduction that do not require sexual intercourse between
men and women. These new reproductive technologies are forcing sociologists
to re-think the social relations of biological reproduction.
The emergence of gender studies, women’s studies, and gay and lesbian
studies has often meant that traditional areas such as sociology of the family
and marriage have been overshadowed by new questions and new foci of
research. While contemporary sociologists explore gay and lesbian cultures,
an older, perhaps more socially conservative, tradition, represented by the
work of Peter Laslett, Peter Willmott, Michael Young, and Elizabeth Bott in
Britain and by W. J. Goode in America, went into decline. This relative decline
of the family as a key topic of research is ironic – given the alleged ideological
dominance of heterosexuality (“heteronormativity”) in mainstream society
and in conventional sociology. We can imagine, however, that current sociological views of what constitutes gender and sexuality will have to change
radically with changes in how humans reproduce through new reproductive
technologies, surrogacy, same-sex marriages, “designer babies,” and cloning.
These developments constitute a considerable component of this Dictionary.
Alongside the sociology of the body, there has been an important development of the sociology of the emotions, where the work of Jack Barbalet has
been particularly innovative. By drawing on the legacy of William James,
Barbalet pushed the debate about emotions away from social psychology
towards seeing emotions as the link between social structure and the social
xvii
Introduction
actor. His work reminds us of the connection between contemporary theories
of emotion and the work of classical economists such as Adam Smith in The
Theory of Moral Sentiments of 1759. The contemporary analysis of emotions
needs to be understood as part of a legacy of classical sociology and the
Enlightenment.
Another way of approaching these critical debates is through the influence of
postmodernism. Because conventional sociology has been associated with the
Enlightenment tradition and modernity, postmodern theory was seen as an
attack on classical sociology. Thinkers such as Durkheim and Weber were held
up to be the epitome of modern as opposed to postmodern social theory. There
are at least two problems associated with these critical evaluations of classical
sociology. They often fail to distinguish between postmodernity as a state of
society (for example, as illustrated by flexibility in employment, the dominance
of service industries, the growth of information technologies, the rise of consumerism, and the general decline of a post-Fordist economy) and postmodernism as a type of theory (which employs textual analysis, irony, bathos, essay
form, and aphorism). We can therefore understand postmodernity without
difficulty via sociological concepts (that are related to the theory of postindustrial society) without having to accept postmodern theory. Postmodern theory in
Europe is still influential in the sociological analysis of culture and identity, and
it was influential in the expansion of new methodologies that questioned the
legacies of positivism and behaviorism. In the postwar period there was initially
a dominant focus on survey data and quantitative analysis, but there has been a
growing interest in qualitative methodologies, ethnographies, biographical research, oral history, and discourse analysis. There is also an emerging interest in
the use of electronic communication as a method of conducting research. These
movements in social theory – constructionism, postmodernism, poststructuralism, and queer theory – have been somewhat eclipsed by the growing interest in
globalization theory and awareness of the negative aspects of globalization such
as new wars, terrorism, slavery, and crime. With the impact of globalization,
new debates will emerge in sociology around the question of cosmopolitanism
and global sociology.
The Cambridge Dictionary of Sociology attempts therefore to cover these new,
important and controversial developments in sociology, but it is also concerned not to become disconnected from the sociological tradition. In developing this modern Dictionary, I have been at pains to retain a lively and
committed relationship to the diverse traditions and legacies of classical
sociology, which have shaped the sociological imagination in the last century.
Maintaining the core of sociology preserves a basis for further innovation and
creativity. The Dictionary has been developed to recognize the continuities
between classical sociology and the work of such sociologists as Ulrich Beck,
Raymond Boudon, Pierre Bourdieu, James Coleman, Anthony Giddens, and
Neil Smelser. The Dictionary attempts to be relevant to modern social theory
and changes in contemporary society, while describing these developments in
the context of the legacy of classical sociology.
xviii
How to use this Dictionary
Sociology is a critical discipline, and its concepts are typically contested.
There is no consensus over the meaning of globalization, risk, information,
culture, and society. The aim of this Dictionary has therefore been discursive.
Its entries are designed to illustrate and debate concepts, showing their
diverse origins and contested meanings. Some entries – on culture, family,
gender, genetics, globalization, health, information, mass media and communications, power, race and ethnicity, religion, science and technology studies,
social movements, and work and employment – are very long (around 5,000
words). These major entries allow authors to explore these critical issues in
depth. The variable length of entries is intended to reflect the complexity and
importance of different topics and fields in sociology. These large entries on
key aspects of society are intended to be, as it were, the intellectual backbone
of the Dictionary.
The Dictionary also contains a large number of entries on sociologists, both
classical and contemporary. While the selection of these entries will always be
somewhat arbitrary, they are intended to illustrate current debates as reflected in the work of living sociologists. This selection of contemporary
sociologists will cause some degree of annoyance to those living sociologists
who are not included. I hope they will accept my apologies for their absence,
but these choices are unavoidably eccentric to some degree. I have if anything
been overly inclusive rather than exclusive.
There is no list of bibliographical references at the end of the entries.
Because references are included in the text, the reader can get an immediate
grasp of the key bibliographical sources. The entries also contain many cross
references in bold print that allow the reader to make immediate connections
to other related entries. With foreign works, the first date in round brackets
refers to its original publication, while dates in square brackets refer to
publication dates of titles in English translation. Where possible I have referred to the English titles of translated works rather than to the original
language of the publication. There are no footnotes or endnotes. The aim
throughout has been to achieve simplicity rather than clutter entries with
scholarly conventions that are not necessarily helpful to the reader.
Finally, the authors have been drawn from many countries in a bid to
reflect the contemporary richness and cosmopolitanism of sociology. The
entries are written in a simple, discursive, and accessible language that
strives to avoid jargon or excessive dependence on a technical and arid
xix
How to use this Dictionary
vocabulary. I have encouraged authors to write in business-like, clear English.
There are relatively few diagrams, charts, or figures.
It is intended that the Dictionary will offer a lively defense of sociology as a
vibrant and expanding field of study. The more complex and difficult modern
society becomes, the more we need a relevant, critical, and energetic sociological understanding of society. This Dictionary is intended to assist that
understanding.
Bryan S. Turner
National University of Singapore
xx
A
accounts
The term account – along with the related terms
accountable and accountability – is a term of art
largely associated with ethnomethodology. However, it has come into wider usage as various
broadly ethnomethodological insights and sensibilities have drifted into mainstream sociology.
Following Marvin Scott’s and Stanford Lyman’s
article “Accounts” (1968) in the American Sociological Review, some users of the term have dwelt
primarily on accounts as linguistic devices used to
neutralize the disapproval caused by seemingly
untoward behavior. Thus, the term has been distinguished as a particular subset of the category
explanation. According to this line of argument,
accounts may be divided into two sub-types: excuses and justifications. The first device acknowledges an act to have been “bad, wrong, or
inappropriate” but denies the apparently culpable
party is fully responsible for what has occurred.
The second device denies the act was bad, wrong,
or inappropriate in the first place. Insofar as these
devices rely for their efficacy on invoking what
C. Wright Mills once called certain shared “vocabularies of motive” (1940) in the American
Journal of Sociology, they may be used as empirical
windows on the wider world of moral sensibilities
shared by a studied social group.
Ethnomethodologists use the terms accounts,
accountable, and accountability in a rather more
inclusive and fundamental way. Indeed, they
argue that it is only by virtue of its accountability
that any kind of collaborative social action is at all
possible. In its specifically ethnomethodological
sense, the accountability of social action is more
than just a matter of linguistically excusing or
justifying untoward conduct. It entails exhibiting
and coordinating the orderliness and reasonability of social action in the widest sense. Hence, the
terms account, accountable, and accountability
are used to capture various constituent features
of social action as such. Social action is accountable in this sense to the extent that its witnesses
find it non-random, coherent, meaningful, and
oriented to the accomplishment of practical goals.
Moreover, for ethnomethodologists, the accountability of social action is much more than just a
theoretical matter or one of disinterested interpretation. As social actors, we are not just accountable to one another in the sense that we can
linguistically describe each other’s actions. Rather,
the very fact that social action is describable in this
way, or that it can be accounted for, is linked to
another sense of its accountability. As social actors,
we are also accountable in the sense that we may
be held to account if our behavior fails to exhibit
orderliness and reasonability to those with whom
we find ourselves engaged. Social actors need not
linguistically describe conduct in order to find it
accountable in these senses.
Ethnomethodologists also stress that sociologists can make use of the fact that social action
is manifestly accountable to social actors themselves as a resource for making sociological sense
of what is going on in social action. In principle,
all of the various linguistic and non-linguistic
devices through which social actors make their
actions accountable to one another should also be
recoverable for use as resources in the empirical
sociological analysis of their actions.
DARIN WEINBERG
act
– see action theory.
action research
– see action theory.
action theory
“Did he jump or was he pushed?” Jumping is an
action. Being pushed is an event. Action theory is
an approach to the study of social life that is based
on the ontological premise that people jump. For
example, the flow of traffic on a busy street differs
from the flow of electrons on a copper wire. Electrons are pushed, drivers are not. From a structural perspective, we can learn a great deal about
the flow of traffic by focusing on exogenous determinants, without ever knowing much about what
drives human behavior. While few action theorists
1
action theory
would disagree with the value of structural analysis, they also see the need to look beyond the
constraints on action, to the intentions, purposes,
and goals that motivate efforts to push back.
Action theory has roots in Max Weber’s interpretative method and in Talcott Parsons’s effort
to integrate this with Émile Durkheim’s macrosocial approach. In “The Place of Ultimate Values
in Sociological Theory,” Parsons insisted that
“man is essentially an active, creative, evaluating
creature” whose behavior must be understood in
terms of the ends of action, and not “in terms of
‘causes’ and ‘conditions’” (1935). His “voluntaristic
theory of action” opposed the deterministic account of human behavior as “pushed,” whether
by Sigmund Freud’s “unconscious” or Pavlov’s bell.
Action theory informs a diverse range of
contemporary sociological theorizing, including
rational action, symbolic interactionism, conflict
theory, and hermeneutics. Conceptually, there are
two main branches – one based on interests, the
other on identity. Rational-action theory posits
instrumental pursuit of self-interest, which can
include an interest in public as well as private
goods and an interest in social approval and avoidance of sanctions. Using mathematical formalism, the theory can generate testable predictions
from a relatively small number of assumptions.
However, the scope of the theory is limited by
heroic assumptions about perfect information
and unlimited calculating ability. Even versions
based on “bounded rationality” are limited to
actions intended to maximize utility, which excludes expressive and enthusiastic behavior and
actions motivated by normative obligation and
moral righteousness.
That void has been addressed by theories of
action based on identity rather than interest. For
identity theorists, “interests are only the surface
of things. What is beneath the surface is a strong
emotion, a feeling of a group of people that they
are alike and belong together,” according to Randall Collins in Sociological Insight (1992: 28). Individuals order the social world by carving out
cognitive categories through interaction with
others, leading to stereotyping, in-group favoritism, and out-group prejudice. Social and moral
boundaries are defined and affirmed by punishing
deviants. Punishment is not calibrated to deter
deviance; rather, it is unleashed as an expression
of indignation at the violation of normative
boundaries, even when this may excite opposition
rather than suppress it.
Interest and identity theories of action both
emphasize the dynamics of interaction among
2
action theory
autonomous but interdependent agents. However,
they differ in how this interdependence is understood. Interest theory posits strategic interdependence, in which the consequences of individual
choices depend in part on the choices of others.
Game theorists (see game theory) model this interdependence as a payoff matrix defined by the
intersection of all possible choices of the players,
with individual payoffs assigned to each cell. For
example, the payoff for providing favors depends
on whether the partner reciprocates. Peer pressure
is also an example of strategic interdependence
created by the application of sanctions conditional upon compliance with expected behavior.
Identity theorists point instead to the cognitive
interdependence of agents who influence one another in response to the influences they receive,
through processes like communication, persuasion, instruction, and imitation. Action theory
poses three related and perplexing puzzles: the
problem of social order, the tension between structure and action, and the problem of free will and
determinism. Contemporary research on complex
dynamical systems has enriched action theory by
providing plausible solutions to each of these
puzzles, based, in turn, on the principles of selforganization, emergence, and deterministic chaos.
Macrosocial theories of social order posit a
structured system of institutions and norms that
shape individual behavior from the top down. In
contrast, action theories assume that much of
social life emerges from the bottom up, more like
improvisational jazz than a symphony orchestra.
People do not simply play roles written by elites
and directed by managers. We each chart our own
course, on the fly. How then is social order possible? If every musician is free to play as they
choose, why do we not end up with a nasty and
brutish cacophony, a noisy war of all against all?
Parsons addressed the “Hobbesian problem of
order” by positing a set of shared norms and
values that secure the cultural consensus necessary for social systems to function. Yet this is not a
satisfactory solution. In effect, society remains a
symphony orchestra in which the musicians must
still learn their parts, except that now the Leviathan needs to carry only a thin baton, and not a
lethal weapon.
An alternative solution was anticipated by Parsons’s student, Niklas Luhmann. Luhmann bridged
the gap between action theory and systems theory
by placing individual actors in a web of communicative interaction with others. His rather abstruse
ideas on autopoietic systems of interaction find
clearer expression in complexity theory. The
action theory
emergence of order out of local interaction in
complex systems has come to be known as “selforganization” according to S. Kaufman in Origins
of Order (1993). The archetype is biological evolution, but there are parallels across the sciences,
cases in which surprising (and often quite exquisite) global patterns emerge from interactions
among relatively simple but interdependent processes, in the absence of central coordination, direction, or planning. These include flocks of birds,
traffic jams, fads, forest fires, riots, and residential
segregation. There is no leader bird who choreographs the dance-like movement of a flock of
geese. There is no supervisor in charge of a riot.
There is no conspiracy of banks and realtors who
are assigning people to ethnically homogeneous
neighborhoods. These processes are examples of
complex systems in which global order emerges
spontaneously out of a web of local interactions
among large numbers of autonomous yet interdependent agents. Emergence is a defining feature
of complex systems and is ultimately responsible
for the self-organization we find beneath the apparent chaos of nature (Coveney and Highfield,
Frontiers of Complexity, 1995).
Emergent properties are not reducible to the
properties of the individual agents. The idea of
emergence was anticipated by one of the founders
of sociology, who established this as a fundamental rule of the sociological method. “The hardness
of bronze is not in the copper, the tin, or the lead,
which are its ingredients and which are soft and
malleable bodies,” Émile Durkheim wrote in The
Rules of the Sociological Method, “it is in their mixture.” “Let us apply this principle to sociology,” he
continued; “[Social facts] reside exclusively in the
very society itself which produces them, and not
in its parts, i.e., its members” (1986: xlvii).
Structuralists have reified Durkheim’s theory of
social facts as emergent properties, leaving individual actors as little more than the incumbents
of social locations and the carriers of structural
imperatives. Heterogeneity in preferences and
beliefs affects only which individuals will fill
which “empty slots,” the origin of which lies in
processes that operate at the societal level.
In The Structure of Social Action (1937), Parsons
also argued for the emergent properties of social
systems, but believed Durkheim went too far in
concluding that these “social facts” are entirely
independent of individual consciousness. Parsons
corrects the hyperstructuralist interpretation of
Durkheim by incorporating an essential insight
of Joseph Schumpeter’s “methodological individualism,” the idea that societal patterns emerge
action theory
from motivated choices and not from social facts
external to individuals. Methodological individualism can be taken to imply that social facts are
but the aggregated expression of individual goals
and intentions. For example, residential segregation reflects the preferences of individuals for
living among people similar to themselves. In contrast, structuralists assume that individual differences in ethnic identity affect who will live where
in segregated neighborhoods but are not the cause
of neighborhood segregation, which emanates
from societal processes like red-lining and patterns
of urban development.
Action theory is often most effective when it
steers between these extremes. A classic example
is Thomas Schelling’s model of neighborhood segregation in his “Dynamic Model of Segregation”
in the Journal of Mathematical Sociology 1971 (1).
Schelling challenged the macrosocial assumption
that segregation is imposed from the top down,
through institutional means like “red-lining.” At
the same time, his famous experiment also
challenged the microsocial assumption that
segregation floats from the bottom up, through
the aggregation of individual prejudices against
ethnic minorities and outsiders. Schelling randomly distributed red and green chips on a large
checkerboard and moved individual chips to
empty locations if the number of in-group neighbors fell below an individual’s threshold of tolerance. He discovered that extreme segregation
can emerge even in a population that tolerates
diversity, as agents relocate to avoid being in the
minority. This surprisingly strong tendency towards neighborhood segregation is an emergent
property of the population, generated by local
interactions among large numbers of interdependent but autonomous agents, even when every
individual is tolerant of diversity.
Action theory explains social life by identifying
the reasons for action (whether instrumental interests or symbolic meanings). As Anthony Giddens
put it in The Constitution of Society, “I propose simply
to declare that reasons are causes” (1984: 345). Yet
most people now accept that everything in the
universe is physically determined. How can this
determinism be reconciled with a voluntaristic
theory of action? Consider a sunbather who
moves his/her towel to fend off a late afternoon
shadow. Meanwhile, next to the towel, a heliotropic plant turns to follow the sun’s trajectory,
thereby maximizing its access to an essential resource. Even the most dedicated Cartesian would
not suggest that a sunflower is a purposive agent
whose actions can be explained by the plant’s
3
action theory
need for photosynthesis. How do we know that the
sunbather is any different? One answer is that
the sunbather could have chosen to remain in the
shadow, while the sunflower could not. However,
it is trivial to construct a stochastic sunflower that
“chooses” to move, based on a probability distribution given by the location of the sun. A better
answer is that the sunbather can tell you that
the desire for sunlight is the reason for the action,
while the sunflower will tell you nothing of
the kind. Plants cannot provide reasons for their
behavior, humans can. But does this mean that the
sunbather is right? Is it possible that the sunbather,
like the sunflower, is simply responding to physical stimuli that induce heliotropic movement,
and, unlike for the sunflower, this movement is
accompanied by the epiphenomenal feeling of
choosing?
There is mounting evidence from neuroscientists and experimental psychologists that supports
that possibility. In 1983, Benjamin Libet found
that “cerebral neural activity (‘readiness potential’) precedes the subject’s awareness of his/her
intention or wish to act by at least 350 msec”
(“Commentary on ‘Free Will in the Light of
Neuropsychiatry,’” 1996). More recently, in The
Illusion of Conscious Will (2002), Daniel Wegner
reported substantial evidence to support the hypothesis that “conscious will” is largely an illusion, useful to help us remember our authorship
of actions whose causes lie elsewhere. These and
other studies point to the possibility that our intentions are formed in the course of initiating
action, but in a separate cognitive subsystem
that assigns authorship after the fact. If so, then
perhaps humans are unique in the ability to provide rational accounts for our actions, but we have
no more free will than does a sunflower.
The theory of complex systems suggests an alternative possibility – that free will is compatible with
determinism. Even relatively simple dynamical
systems can require exponential amounts of computing power for every additional input into the
system, until the number of bits required to predict
system behavior, even in the near term, can exceed
the number of particles in the universe. Thus, a
highly nonlinear deterministic system like the
brain can be indeterminable, which leaves open a
window for intentional choice that is not reducible
to system determinants (James P. Crutchfield,
“Complexity: Order Contra Chaos,” 1989).
Meanwhile, a growing interest in complex
adaptive systems has opened up action theory to
“backward-looking” approaches in which intentionality is empirically variable rather than
4
actor network theory
presupposed. In backward-looking models, the
ends of action attract the behaviors that produce
them, whether or not the agent intended the outcome or is even aware of its existence. From a
forward-looking perspective, this idea appears
hopelessly teleological since the ends of action
are located in the future and cannot reach back
through time to attract the choices needed to
bring them about. Models of complex adaptive
systems avoid this problem by pointing backward,
not forward – attributing action to outcomes that
have already occurred. In agent-based evolutionary models, outcomes of a given action alter the
population distribution of agents who engage in
that action. In learning models, outcomes of a
given action alter the probability distribution of
actions within the repertoire of any given agent.
Either way, the link between action and outcome
is a set of experiences, not intentions. Agents look
forward by holding a mirror to the past. They
jump when they are pushed.
MICHAEL W. MACY
actor network theory
Actor network theory (ANT) is a family of approaches to social analysis that rests on six core
assumptions. First, it treats institutions, practices,
and actors as materially heterogeneous, composed
not only of people but also of technologies and
other materials. Second, it assumes that the elements making up practices are relational, achieving
their shape and attributes only in interaction with
other elements. Nothing is intrinsically fixed or
has reality outside the web of interactions. Third,
it assumes that the network of heterogeneous relations and practices is a process. If structures,
institutions, or realities are not continuously
enacted then they disappear. Fourth, it therefore
assumes that realities and structures are precarious in principle, if not in practice. Fifth, this
implies that the world might be different, a suggestion that opens up interesting political possibilities. And sixth, it explores how rather than why
realities are generated and maintained. This is
because even the most obvious social causes are
relational effects and therefore themselves subject
to change.
ANT developed initially in the 1980s in Paris
with the work of such authors as Michel Callon,
Bruno Latour (Science in Action, 1987), and John Law
(Organizing Modernity, 1994). It grew (and grows)
through empirical studies of technologies, science
practices, organizations, markets, health care,
spatial practices, and the natural world. Indeed it
is not possible to appreciate ANT without exploring such case studies. Philosophically, it owes
adaptation
much to Michel Serres (1930–5) and is generally
poststructuralist in inspiration. It thus shares
with the writing of Michel Foucault an empirical
concern with material–semiotic patterns of relations, though the patterns that it discerns are
smaller in scope than those identified by Foucault.
The approach is controversial. First, since it is
non-humanist it analytically privileges neither
people nor the social, which sets it apart from
much English-language sociology. Second, since
it offers accounts of how rather than why institutions take shape, it is sometimes accused of
explanatory weakness. Third, political critics
have suggested that it is insensitive to the “invisible work” of low-status actors. Fourth, it has been
accused in some of its earlier versions of a bias
towards centering, ordering, or even managerialism. And fifth, feminists have observed that it has
shown little sensitivity to embodiment (see body).
Whether these complaints are now justified is a
matter for debate. Indeed, ANT is probably better
seen as a toolkit and a set of methodological sensibilities rather than as a single theory. Recently
there has been much interchange between ANT,
feminist material-semiotics (Donna J. Haraway)
and postcolonial theory, and there is newer
“after-ANT” work that is much more sensitive to
the politics of domination, to embodiment, to
“othering,” and to the possible multiplicity and
non-coherence of relations. A key issue remains
politics. Such “after-ANT” writers as Annemarie
Mol (The Body Multiple, 2002) and Helen Verran
argue that relations are non-coherent and enact
overlapping but different versions of reality, so
there is space for “ontics,” or an “ontological politics” about what can and should be made real. This
means that alternative and preferable realities
might be enacted into being or made stronger:
reality is not destiny.
JOHN LAW
adaptation
– see evolutionary theory.
addiction
In its original usage, addiction meant simply to be
given over to someone or something. It was a term
used widely to describe passionate investments in
various sorts of activities, as can be seen in Shakespeare’s Othello where we read “Each man to what
sport and revel his addiction leads him.” Well into
the nineteenth century the concept of addiction
was used to describe a diverse assortment of
human fixations. But as Temperance movements
grew in the mid nineteenth century, the term
was increasingly considered as a medical or
addiction
quasi-medical term of art and its scope was delimited to describing an individual’s seeming
enslavement to alcohol or drugs. A multitude of
efforts have been made to provide biological explanations for some people’s apparently pathological attachment to alcohol or drug use but
each has met with rather serious conceptual obstacles. In response to these difficulties, most medical lexicons have now dispensed with the term
addiction in favor of the presumably less conceptually troubling concept dependence. However,
the term addiction continues to be found in both
clinical and popular discourse regarding alcohol
and drug problems and has indeed been extended
to new forms of apparently compulsive behavior
including over-eating, gambling, compulsive
sexual behavior, and others.
In sociology, addiction has been approached
from several distinct theoretical vantage points.
Regrettably, the term has often been used interchangeably with other terms including deviant
drug use, drug misuse, and drug abuse. Such imprecision results in a confusion of questions concerning the social approval of various sorts of
alcohol or drug use with questions concerning
whether this use is voluntary. Much of the history
of social policy concerning alcohol and psychoactive drugs has been predicated, at least ostensibly, on the claim that these substances possess
unusual powers over people and must be regulated to protect citizens from their own personal
proclivities to succumb to addictive use. If we are
not able to distinguish claims regarding the putative morality of alcohol or drug use from claims
regarding people’s ability to control their use, we
are poorly equipped to evaluate effectively the history of policies predicated on the notion that
people need protection from putatively addictive
substances. We are also poorly equipped to evaluate social research which either endorses or rejects
this idea. If it is to have any meaning at all, the term
addiction cannot be considered as synonymous
with terms denoting voluntary substance use.
The earliest sociological research concerned
specifically with addiction was conducted by
Alfred Lindesmith under the tutelage of Herbert
Blumer at the University of Chicago. Lindesmith
noted that, whereas users who acquired heroin on
the street were often vulnerable to addictive patterns of use, those who had been administered
opiates in hospital settings were not so vulnerable. He explained this by suggesting that,
whereas both hospital and street users experience
physiological withdrawal symptoms upon cessation of use, only street users are consciously aware
5
addiction
of the fact that the source of their distress lies in
their heroin deprivation. Lindesmith argued that,
by using drugs specifically to alleviate withdrawal, mere drug users were transformed into
genuine drug addicts. This theory was attractive
to sociologists in the twentieth century because it
insisted the symbolic meanings actors found in
their drug experiences were essential elements of
the addiction process. While Lindesmith’s theory
remains the classic canonical benchmark for contemporary sociological theorizing on addiction, it
has been subject to several rather serious critiques. Most fundamentally, his theory presumes
that physiological withdrawal distress is a necessary prerequisite for the onset of addictive patterns of behavior. In the wake of the so-called
crack cocaine “epidemic,” theories of addiction
predicated on the experience of physiological
withdrawal distress have been undermined. Because they do not involve gross physiological withdrawal symptoms, crack cocaine addiction, along
with nicotine addiction and behavioral addictions
like those to eating, gambling, and sex, have cast
doubt on the generalizability of Lindesmith’s
theory and have even put in question its validity
with respect to opiates themselves.
During the mid twentieth century, structural
functionalists offered a variety of theoretical accounts for apparently addictive behavior that
departed in important ways from Lindesmith’s seminal work. Seeking wholly social structural explanations, these theories shared in common a
departure from Lindesmith’s presumption of a necessary physiological component to addiction. In
his famous essay “Social Structure and Anomie”
(1938, American Sociological Review), Robert K.
Merton suggested that chronic drunkards and
drug addicts might exemplify the retreatist adaptation, one of his five modes of adjustment
whereby social actors adopt ostensibly deviant patterns of action. According to Merton, the addict
could be understood as an individual who believes
in the propriety of both cultural goals and the
institutionalized procedures society affords for
achieving those goals but who cannot produce
the desired results by socially sanctioned means.
The result of this failure is a retreat from social life
into “defeatism, quietism, and resignation.” This
proposition was developed by Richard Cloward
and Lloyd Ohlin in their book Delinquency and
Opportunity (1960) in what became their fairly influential “Double Failure” hypothesis regarding addictive behavior. In contrast to Merton, Cloward
and Ohlin suggested addicts were not opposed to
adopting illegitimate means of achieving legitimate
6
addiction
cultural goals, but rather were incapable of using
even these means for securing social rewards.
Hence, addicts were double failures in the sense
that they failed to achieve by either legitimate or
criminal procedures. Heavy drug use was held to
alienate the putative addict from both mainstream
and delinquent subcultures, thus further minimizing their opportunities for social success. Some
structural functionalists moved beyond explanations of the distribution of addicts across social
structural positions to consider the social psychological processes that motivated addictive patterns
of alcohol or drug use. The best-known of these was
normative ambivalence theory, according to which
dysfunctional substance use will arise when agents
are bombarded with competing normative orientations to their use. According to functionalists, apparently addictive behavior patterns were to be
regarded as eminently rational, if painful and socially notorious, adaptations to social structural
deprivation. The functionalist approach tended to
stereotype addicts as necessarily socially disadvantaged and sometimes to confuse the trappings of
poverty with the trappings of addiction. But it had
the virtue of freeing sociological research from the
presumption of a brute biological basis for addiction and of allowing sociologists to entertain the
possibility that people might experience alcohol or
drug problems simply as a result of the ways they
had learned to use these substances to cope with
the social structural circumstances of their lives.
Structural functionalist approaches were rivaled by approaches to addiction (and deviant
substance use more generally) proffered by ethnographers broadly allied with symbolic interactionism. As part of a more general critical turn
against structural functionalism in the second
half of the twentieth century, many of these sociologists distanced themselves from what David
Matza, in his book Becoming Deviant (1969) dubbed
the “correctional” perspective found in structural
functionalist theories of addiction and deviant
substance use, and moved towards what he called
an “appreciative” analytic stance towards such
putatively deviant behavior. Noting that modern
societies were a good deal more pluralistic and
conflicted than structural functionalists had generally allowed, these researchers advocated an agnostic moral regard for putatively dysfunctional
or deviant behavior and an effort to empathize
with putatively deviant individuals and subcultures. No longer was it assumed that behavior
reviled in mainstream culture was necessarily
viewed negatively by those who themselves engaged in the behavior. Nor was it any longer
addiction
assumed that the social mechanisms according to
which these behaviors were produced and sustained need reflect a functional breakdown of
either the individual or his or her society. Indeed,
many of these studies highlighted the existence of
subcultural prestige hierarchies, wherein the use
and sale of illicit substances was valued as a
mark of adventurousness and other subculturally
valued characteristics. Substance use was depicted
as a source of meaning in the lives of users. Hence
studies focused on such matters as drug slang or
argot, the settings of drug-related activity, the
norms and practices characteristic of drug and
alcohol using subcultures, and the careers
through which drug users passed as they moved
from initiates to seasoned veterans of drug- or
alcohol-using social worlds. The concept of career
has also been used by researchers to emphasize
the important influence exercised by labeling on
putatively addictive behavior patterns.
More recently, the topic of addiction has been
taken up by leaders in rational choice theory who
have properly recognized it as an apparent counterexample to the axiomatic proposition that
social action is necessarily rational action. Some
of these theorists have sought to reconcile empirical instances of addictive patterns of behavior
with core propositions of rational choice theory.
Others have concluded that addiction is essentially
irrational and more thoroughly rooted in neurological dysfunction than micro-economic decisionmaking mechanisms. While these efforts have
produced some interesting technical refinements
of rational choice theory itself, they have done less
to shed new sociological light on why some people
seem to experience rather severe levels of difficulty
refraining from the use of alcohol or drugs, even
after repeated negative experiences with them.
Another more recent line of theoretical work on
addiction hails from attribution theory. Attribution theorists turn their attention away from why
certain people fall into apparently addictive behavior patterns and instead consider social and psychological explanations for why people attribute
behavior to addictions. Attribution theory properly
highlights the fact that objective characteristics of
social behavior and efforts to explain that behavior
are intimately linked to one another. In addition
to research that considers why certain activities
are so addictive for certain people, fruitful insights
can come from the study of why the concept of
addiction is itself so compelling for certain people
acting in certain social contexts.
To date, sociologists have illuminated various
important dimensions of problematic substance
addiction
use but have recurrently found it almost impossible to validate the concept of addiction without
recourse to biological accounts of physiological
dysfunction. Those who have taken the idea of
involuntary substance use seriously have overwhelmingly incorporated reference to biological
mechanisms as indispensable elements of their
own sociological theories. In contrast, the vast
majority of those who have not drawn from biology have found it difficult to account for the apparently involuntary aspects of addiction. In his
book The Alcoholic Society (1993), Norman Denzin
develops a theory of “the alcoholic self” which
takes important theoretical strides towards a
more thoroughly sociological explanation by incorporating his more general approach to the sociology of emotions into his theory of addiction.
While an undeniably important contribution,
Denzin’s research on the emotionality of addiction
exhibits consequential ambiguities that make it
difficult to square fully with the claim that addictive patterns of behavior are genuinely involuntary.
In a series of essays including “The Embodiment of
Addiction” (2002, Body and Society), Darin Weinberg
has drawn upon the growing literature on the
sociology of embodiment to reconcile the phenomenology of addiction as involuntary affliction
with the longstanding sociological claim that
people might acquire problematic patterns of substance use simply by virtue of the ways they have
learned to use these substances to cope with the
social structural circumstances of their lives. He
argues that the sociology of embodiment allows
us to appreciate more fully that not all meaningful, or socially structured, behavior is behavior
that we deliberately choose or with which we
self-identify. This work suggests a fruitful interface between the sociology of embodiment, the
sociology of moral inclusion, and sociological
work on the boundaries of human agency.
Rather predictably, most contemporary sociological research on drugs and alcohol focuses on
questions pertaining to the various social problems that arise from either substance use itself or
the social policies in place to control substance
use. No doubt these questions will, and should,
continue to occupy the attentions of social scientists, whether or not they require use of a concept
of addiction. But the sociology of addiction as
such also holds promise as a valuable empirical
test case for social theories concerned with the
relationship between much more general sociological themes, including nature/culture, structure/agency, rationality, emotion, embodiment,
and social exclusion. This type of research will
7
Adorno, Theodor Wiesengrund (1903–1969)
certainly require a vigilant enforcement of the
conceptual distinction highlighted earlier – that
between addiction per se and voluntary activity
that is merely deviant.
DARIN WEINBERG
Adorno, Theodor Wiesengrund (1903–1969)
Born in Frankfurt, Germany, on September 11,
1903, into an upper-class bourgeois family, the
son of a German Jewish father and Italian Catholic
mother, Adorno studied philosophy, psychology,
and musicology at the University of Frankfurt
where he received his PhD in 1924. With the rise
to power of Hitler’s fascism, Adorno first emigrated to England and then joined the Institute
for Social Research in exile at Columbia University
in New York.
During the 1930s, he became closely connected
with the Institute’s attempt to develop a critical
theory of society. This involved Adorno in one of
the first attempts to develop a Marxian critique of
mass culture, which Adorno and the Institute discerned was becoming ever more significant as an
instrument of ideological manipulation and social
control in democratic capitalist, fascist, and communist societies. Working with the “father of mass
communications,” Paul Lazarsfeld, at the Princeton Radio Project and then at Columbia University, Adorno participated in one of the first
sustained research projects on the effects of popular music. Later, Adorno was also to work on one
of the first attempts to develop a critical analysis
of television, producing an article on “How to
Look at Television” in 1954.
Adorno was a key member of the interdisciplinary social research projects at the Institute and
worked on their studies of fascism and anti-Semitism. Adorno and Institute director Max Horkheimer went to California in the early 1940s,
where they worked closely on the book that
became Dialectic of Enlightenment (1948 [trans.
1972]). In Minima Moralia (1974) and other essays
of the period, Adorno continued the Institute’s
studies of the growing hegemony of capitalism
and the integration of the working class as a
conservative force of the capitalist system. In
such a situation, deeply influenced by his sojourn
in New York and California, Adorno only saw the
possibility of individual revolt. He also feared,
however, the resurgence of authoritarianism in
the United States and collaborated on a groundbreaking collective study of The Authoritarian
Personality (1950) with a group of Berkeley
researchers. The project embodied the Institute’s
desire to merge theoretical construction with
empirical research and produced a portrait of a
8
aesthetics
disturbing authoritarian potential in the United
States. Adorno was responsible for elaborating
the theoretical implications and helped design
the research apparatus.
In the early 1950s, Adorno returned with Horkheimer to Germany to reestablish the institute in
Frankfurt. Here, Adorno continued his studies in
sociology and culture, though he turned primarily
to philosophy in the last years of his life. During
the 1950s, he participated in the Institute’s sociological studies of education, students, workers,
and the potential for democracy. Adorno wrote
many sociological essays at this time and participated in the debates published in The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology (1976). In these debates,
Adorno defended the Institute’s conception of dialectical social theory against positivism and the
“critical rationalism” defended by Karl Popper
and other neopositivists.
Increasingly critical of communism and skeptical of Marxism, Adorno primarily engaged in
cultural criticism and studies of philosophy and
aesthetics during his last decade. As he died suddenly of a heart attack in 1969, his magnum opus,
Aesthetic Theory, was published posthumously
(1984).
DOUGLAS KELLNER
aesthetics
A notion invented in the eighteenth century in
the German-speaking world, the term aesthetics
was bequeathed to the history of ideas with philosopher Alexander Gottleib Baumgarten’s Aesthetica (1750–8). As developed by Baumgarten,
aesthetics was the study of the beautiful. He conceived of this project as a science of “sensuous
cognition,” and from its inception aesthetics was
concerned with the effects of art works on their
recipients, perhaps most famously illustrated in
Immanuel Kant’s (1724–1804) concept of the sublime and the idea of purposeless, transcendental
art works. In the English-speaking world, aesthetics was subsumed under a concern with the philosophy of taste and is represented in the work of
John Locke (1632–1704) and David Hume (1711–76).
As the century waned, British and continental
theories of aesthetics were increasingly preoccupied with notions of beauty and unity in the arts,
pointing to structural correlates between music
and the plastic arts in terms of their effects, and
fueling more general notions of unity in the arts
and sciences, notions that would continue to develop in the following century. As part of the
general rise of interest in aesthetics, Aristotle’s
Poetics was translated into English in 1789. During
the second half of the eighteenth century, an
affirmative action
affirmative action
acquaintance with the science of aesthetics was
often considered to be part of an individual’s
equipment for social life, and it is here that the
initial conception of aesthetics as the science of
beauty and its effects began to provide seeds for
subsequent critical considerations of the role of
the arts in relation to social classification. Concurrently in the late eighteenth century, the arts
flourished, stimulated by burgeoning publics, urbanization, and the status-seeking strategies of
increasingly professionalized artistic workers in
London, Paris, Vienna, and other European cities.
During these years, new aesthetic hierarchies
were articulated by artistic workers and appropriated by arts consumers as a resource for status
creation and maintenance.
Many sociologists of the arts have described
how aesthetics (understood as beauty and value)
and taste in the arts have been resources for social
boundary work. Pierre Bourdieu, for example,
sought to turn Kant on his head in Distinction
(1979 [trans. 1984]), by arguing that aesthetics
could never be disinterested but was rather linked
to lifestyle and position in social space. More recently, scholarship in environmental and social
psychology, arts sociology, and cultural geography
has returned to the original focus of aesthetics,
albeit from an empirical and pragmatically
oriented perspective, highlighting the concept of
aesthetic ecology and aesthetic agency, and developing theories of what may be afforded by art
works and aesthetic materials broadly construed.
TIA DENORA
affirmative action
Affirmative action, or positive discrimination as it
is known in the United Kingdom, entails the provision of various types of advantages to members
of groups who have been systematically oppressed
for their membership in that group. The term
stems from the legal understanding of affirmative
or positive remedies which compel wrong-doers to
do something in addition to merely refraining
from the wrong-doing itself. Affirmative action
policies can be found throughout the world.
Though they can focus on any group that has
suffered systematic discrimination, affirmative
action policies tend most often to concern ethnic
groups historically oppressed within a given society, and women. They tend to provide advantages
in the domains of education, employment, health,
and social welfare.
Affirmative action first became a topic of serious debate in the wake of the civil rights movements of the 1960s when it was discovered that
legal proscriptions against historical wrong-doings
were not wholly successful in creating equal opportunities for members of historically oppressed
groups. Activists began suggesting that, in addition to the negative remedies proscribing discrimination against historically oppressed groups, it
would be necessary to implement affirmative or
positive strategies to correct past wrongs. Various
approaches have been taken to distributing affirmative action advantages. Some societies have
favored quota systems that require the ratio of
recipients of certain scarce resources, like state
building contracts or university admissions, to
resemble the ratio found in the larger society
between majority and minority groups. Others
have favored a less restrictive entitlement to consider issues of ethnicity and gender in deciding
how best to distribute scarce resources. But, regardless of approach, affirmative action policies
have very often met with rather fierce resistance,
primarily from members of historically privileged
groups who resent what they call reverse discrimination. Much more rarely, resistance has come
from members of the groups presumed to benefit
from affirmative action on the grounds that affirmative action policies sustain racial, ethnic, or
gender antagonisms and/or prove demoralizing to
their beneficiaries.
Sometimes, particular affirmative action policies have been critiqued on the grounds that
they tend to benefit only the most privileged
among historically oppressed groups and fail to
remedy the much more devastating hardships
and inequalities suffered by what William Julius
Williams (The Truly Disadvantaged: The Inner City, the
Underclass, and Public Policy, 1987) has called the
“truly disadvantaged.” In addition to failing to
help the most disadvantaged segments of historically oppressed groups, it has been suggested that
such policies discredit affirmative action as such
by giving benefits to people who neither deserve
nor need them. In place of ethnicity- and genderbased affirmative action policies that are insensitive to the comparative hardships suffered by
their recipients, some have suggested policies
more explicitly pegged to actual disadvantage.
These kinds of arguments have met with vigorous
counterarguments suggesting that race- and
gender-based affirmative action remain crucial to
the project of institutionalizing a more egalitarian society. Many high-profile former recipients of
affirmative-action advantages, including former
American Secretary of State Colin Powell, have
come out in favor of such policies despite political
pressures not to do so.
DARIN WEINBERG
9
affluent society
African-American studies
affluent society
The Affluent Society is the title of an influential book
originally published by the American economist,
John Kenneth Galbraith (1908–2006) in 1958 (there
have been numerous subsequent editions). As a
work of political economy, it begins with a critique of classical political economists (such as
Adam Smith [1723–90] and David Ricardo [1771–
1823]) who had emphasized above all the primacy
of increasing production and the requirement for
a minimum of public consumption (that is, low
taxes) if this was to be achieved. This he labeled as
“conventional wisdom,” better adapted to historic
conditions than to the realities of the contemporary United States, which had become, after World
War II, an “affluent society,” one whose productive
capacities could easily meet the needs of its citizens. Indeed, under conditions of affluence, production could be increased only through the
creation of new desires and needs via advertising
and marketing, which succeeds because of the development of a “culture of emulation.” Moreover,
the lack of investment in public goods (schools,
parks, roads and refuse disposal) had created a
world of “private affluence and public squalor,”
in which, for example, increasingly elaborate private cars clog increasingly inadequate public
roads. Galbraith argues for increased expenditure
on public goods, and that the “social balance” between the allocation of resources to private and
public goods must be created by political organizations. He also identifies the emergence of a new
class (see social class) of educated labor, for whom
work itself is considered to be a source of recreation, and for whom the maximization of income
is not a primary goal. The expansion of this class
will also contribute to an improved social balance.
ROSEMARY CROMPTON
affluent worker
The argument that sections of the working class
had experienced embourgeoisement became popular in the 1950s and 1960s, to explain changing
values and political allegiances among manual
workers. Increasing affluence was seen to underpin a move from working-class to middle-class
lifestyles and values, so that such workers became
middle-class. This argument was challenged, both
theoretically and empirically, by J. Goldthorpe
and colleagues, in The Affluent Worker in the
Class Structure (1969). They agreed that important
changes had occurred in the market and work
experience of affluent manual workers, but argued
that related changes in lifestyles (privatism) and
political attitudes (instrumentalism) remained
10
distinctively working-class. Partial convergence
with white-collar workers should not be conflated
with assimilation to the middle class.
This neo-Weberian analysis challenged presumptions about the necessary decline of trade
unions and the United Kingdom Labour Party,
just as union membership was growing and the
Labour Party regained electoral success. Instead,
these authors portrayed a movement from a “traditional solidarity” working class to an increasingly
“instrumental collectivist” working class. In turn,
however, the adequacy of this contrast and projection was widely challenged, as shifts in forms of
working-class class consciousness and organization were found to be more varied, uncertain,
and contested, for example by F. Devine in Affluent
Workers Revisited (1992). This encouraged more
complex accounts of the relationships between
working-class experience, forms of consciousness,
and politics, undermining strong claims for links
between specific class locations and forms of consciousness and action, which had been shared by
many currents in British studies of social class.
TONY ELGER
African-American studies
This field of interdisciplinary studies charts the
experiences of people of African descent in black
Atlantic societies including the United States, the
Caribbean, and Latin America. It studies the social
structures and cultures that African people in the
diaspora have created. More specifically, it studies
the social, cultural, and political processes that
have shaped the experience of people of African
ancestry. There are a large number of study
centers and research institutes providing interdisciplinary programs in higher education in the
United States. Many of these centers, such as the
University of California Los Angeles Center for
African American Studies (1969), date from the
1960s. The National Association of African American Studies was founded by Dr. Lemuel Berry Jr. at
the Virginia State University at Ettrick, Virginia,
in 1992 and it held its first annual conference in
1993. African-American studies draws some of its
intellectual inspiration from the work of black
American intellectuals such as W. E. B. Du Bois,
and the Institute for Afro-American Studies at
Harvard University (1975) is named after him.
There are several academic journals that cater
to this interdisciplinary field, including the Journal
of Black Studies (1970), The Black Scholar (1969), the
Western Journal of Black Studies (1977), and Womanist
Theory and Research (1994) from the Womanist
Studies Consortium at the University of Georgia.
age
African-American studies is part of a significant
expansion of interdisciplinary studies since the
1960s dealing with justice issues, such as Latino
studies and women’s studies.
While African-American studies is not confined
to sociology, sociologists have made important
contributions to the field, including Paul Gilroy
whose Black Atlantic (1993) has been influential.
African-American studies has not had a significant
impact on the study of race and ethnicity and
racism in the United Kingdom or Europe. In sociology, the study of “race relations” in the United
Kingdom has been critically discussed by scholars
influenced by feminism or Marxism for its failure
to analyze politics and power. African-American
studies has not flourished in the United Kingdom
for the obvious reason that black British citizens
are also from India, Pakistan, and Bangladesh, as
well as the Caribbean and Africa. For similar
reasons, critical race theory has not been a dominant paradigm in British sociology. British radical
sociologists have been influenced more by Franz
Fanon than by DuBois, more by Stuart Hall and
Paul Gilroy than by African-American academics,
and have in recent years drawn more from Pierre
Bourdieu’s studies of Algeria, migration, and
poverty in The Algerians (1958) [trans. 1962] and
The Weight of the World (1993) [trans. 2000] than
from American social science. While racism is a
common problem in the United States and Europe,
the sociological study of race has taken rather
different directions.
BRYAN S. TURNER
age
The study of age in sociology covers influences
affecting individuals across all phases of the lifecourse, as well as the specific period known as old
age. In practice, although findings on the longterm impact of changes in early and middle
age have begun to emerge, most research focuses
still on “older” or “elderly” people. Matilda White
Riley, an influential figure in American sociological research, refers to the interdependence of
aging on the one side and society on the other.
She argues in On the Significance of Age in Society
(1987) that, in studying age, we not only bring
people back into society, but recognize that both
people and society undergo process and change:
“The aim is to understand each of the two dynamisms: (1) the aging of people in successive cohorts
who grow up, grow old, die, and are replaced by
other people; and (2) the changes in society as people
of different ages pass through the social institutions that are organized by age.”
age
Sociological perspectives on age adopt a contrasting approach to other social science disciplines. The sociologist starts from the view that
old age is interesting because – although it is an
enduring human phenomenon handled differently by different societies – it is at the same
time changing and influencing human behavior.
The sociologist is concerned to explore the processes involved and how they are being interpreted by men and women, from different social
classes, ethnic groups, and cultural settings. This
approach contrasts with social policy and government interests in old age. In these contexts, old
age is often regarded as a problem (for the economy or the health service, to take two examples),
hence the need for some analysis and collection of
data. This approach has its own validity and justification but may lead to a distorted view of social
aging, together with a limited selection of topics
to be analyzed and discussed.
The experience of aging has been influenced by
shifts in the patterning of the life-course over the
past 100 years. Changes in the demography of
aging and in patterns of work and retirement
have been especially important in shaping contemporary aspects of later life. On the first of
these, improvements in life expectancy have
been crucial in creating “middle” and “old” age
as significant phases in the life-course. In 1901,
life expectancy at birth was around forty-five years
(for men) and forty-nine years (for women), with
many people (especially those from working-class
backgrounds) dying before they reached what
would now be recognized as old age. With life
expectancy at birth in the United Kingdom (in
2001) seventy-six years for men and eighty-one
years for women, survival past middle age is
normal, even if frequently accompanied by
heightened awareness of the aging process and
of future mortality.
Changes in the organization of work and employment have also been consequential in reshaping the life-course. In general terms, the
period from 1945 to the mid-1970s confirmed the
emergence of a “standardized” life-course built
around initial education, work, and leisure. This
period is associated with the creation of retirement as a major social institution, with the
growth of entitlements to pensions and the gradual acceptance of an extended period of leisure
following the ending of full-time work. In fact this
model of the life-course lasted a relatively short
span of time in historical terms, with the period
from 1945 to 1975 defining its outer limits.
11
age
From the late 1970s a number of changes can be
identified, arising from the development of more
flexible patterns of work and the impact of high
levels of unemployment. These produced what
may be termed the reconstruction of middle and
old age, with the identification of a “third age” in
between the period of work and employment (“the
second age”) and a period of mental and physical
decline (“the fourth age”). An aspect of these new
features of social aging is the ambiguity and flexibility of the boundaries of the third age, at both its
lower and upper ends. Both of these now involve
complex periods of transition, with the move
away from employment, and with the blurring of
dependence and independence in late old age.
Age is a marker of a number of changes affecting
older people – these reflecting a mix of physiological, social, and biographical factors. First,
changes associated with poor health are highly
significant for many older people. For example, it
is estimated that, among those people aged eightyfive and over, one in five will have dementia and
three in five a limiting longstanding illness such as
osteoarthritis or osteoporosis. Second, changes in
social relationships are also substantial, with the
loss of close friends and relations a striking feature of later life. Third, age may exacerbate rather
than reduce inequalities experienced earlier in
the life-course. Social class remains a stronger
predictor of lifestyle than age, and older people
are likely to have more in common with younger
people of their own class than they will with older
people from other classes.
As well as social class, age is also affected by
social divisions associated with gender and race
and ethnicity. The gender imbalances of later life
are now well established. Because women outlive
men by an average of five years, there are around
50 percent more women than men among those
sixty-five and over. The gender imbalance is even
more marked in late old age: among those aged
eighty-five and over, women outnumber men by
three to one. Sara Arber and Jay Ginn in Connecting
Gender and Aging (1995) conclude that: “The fact
that over half of older women are widowed,
whereas three-quarters of older men are married,
has consequences for gender, identity, relationships, and roles in later life.”
Race and ethnicity are another important division running through age-based relationships.
In the early part of the twenty-first century, there
will be a significant aging of the black community
as the cohorts of migrants of the late 1950s
and 1960s reach retirement age. Older people
from minority ethnic groups are likely to have
12
age
distinctive experiences in old age, these including:
first, increased susceptibility to physical ill-health
because of past experiences, such as heavy manual
work and poor housing; second, great vulnerability to mental health problems, a product of racism
and cultural pressures; third, acute financial
problems, with evidence of elderly Asians being
at a particular disadvantage. The problems faced
by ethnic elders have been defined as a form of
“triple jeopardy.” This refers to the fact that
ethnic elders not only face discrimination because
they are old; in addition, many of them live in
disadvantaged physical and economic circumstances; finally, they may also face discrimination
because of their culture, language, skin color, or
religious affiliation.
The above divisions have led Joe Hendricks in
Structure and Identity (2003) to conclude that:
“People do not become more alike with age; in
fact the opposite may well be the case . . . Their
heterogeneity is entrenched in disparate master
status characteristics, including membership
groups and socioeconomic circumstances, race,
ethnicity, gender, subcultural, or structural conditions on the one hand, and personal attributes on
the other.”
Research on social aspects of age focus on the
norms, values, and social roles associated with a
particular chronological age. Sociologists emphasize the way in which ideas about different phases
in the life-course – such as childhood, mid-life,
and old age – change over time and across cultures. John Vincent in Old Age (2003) suggests that
even if the experience of a life-cycle in which an
individual feels a sense of loss when they have
passed their “prime” is a universal, it says nothing
about the timing, meaning, and cultural content
of the social category of old age: “The variety of
ways of being ‘old’ are as different as the ways of
being in one’s ‘prime’. A re-evaluation of old age
in the West requires an appreciation of the variety
of ways it is possible to live one’s ‘old age’ and an
escape from culturally bound stereotypes.”
From a social perspective, age may be viewed as
constructed around various social practices and
institutions. It is associated in particular with the
regulation of movement through the life-course.
Western societies standardize many aspects of
public life on the basis of chronological age. Social
institutions control access and prescribe and proscribe certain behaviors by age. In consequence,
birthdays have social as well as individual significance. Legal rights and duties are commonly
associated with particular ages, with access to a
range of institutions moderated through age-based
age
criteria. The various responsibilities associated
with citizenship are strongly associated with
age, notable examples including the right to
vote, military service, and duty to serve on a jury.
Age is also constructed through the phases associated with pre-work, work, and post-work. Western societies have come to define old age as
starting at sixty or sixty-five, ages associated with
receipt of a pension following retirement. This
development can be seen as a twentieth-century
invention, consolidated with the rise of the welfare state. Other markers of old age are, however,
possible and increasingly likely, given further extensions in life expectancy. With pressures to
extend working life, retirement at seventy would,
for example, present a new boundary at which
“old age” would begin.
Social relationships built around family and
friends remain crucial for understanding many
aspects of the lives of older people. Most older
people are connected to family-based networks,
which provide (and receive from the older person)
different types of support. Relationships with
peers, and friendship in particular, has also been
shown to be central to well-being in later life, with
research pointing to the value of a “special relationship” or confidant in adjusting to the stresses
and strains of later life. Overall, the research evidence would point to an increase in the importance of friends in the lives of older people. In the
early phase of retirement, and even (or especially)
into late old age, friends will be significant in
maintaining morale and self-identity. For many
older people, faced with reduced income and
poor health, the loss of close friends may pose
acute problems of adjustment and threats to the
integrity of the self.
Processes and experiences associated with age
have been examined in a number of sociological
theories drawing on functionalist, symbolic interactionist, and neo-Marxist perspectives. Functionalist approaches to the study of age such as role
theory (formulated in the early 1950s) focused
on the impact of losing work-based ties – this producing, it was argued, a crisis of adjustment
following retirement. Advocates of this view,
such as Ruth Cavan and Robert Havighurst, took
the position that morale in old age was enhanced
through involvement in new roles and activities,
notably in relation to work and leisure. “Disengagement theory” (as developed by Elaine Cumming
and William Henry) was another functionalist perspective (developed in the late 1950s) that took an
opposing view, suggesting that withdrawal from
mainstream social responsibilities was a natural
age
correlate of growing old. Old age was viewed as a
period in which the aging individual and society
both simultaneously engage in mutual separation,
with retirement in the case of men and widowhood
in respect of women.
Through the 1960s, and for a period in the
1970s, activity and disengagement theory set the
parameters of debates within social gerontology.
“Activity theory” stimulated the development of
several social psychological theories of aging, including “continuity theory” (by Robert Atchley)
and theories of “successful aging” (by Rowe and
Kahn). Drawn from “developmental” or “life-cycle
theory,” continuity theory asserts that aging
persons have the need and the tendency to maintain the same personalities, habits, and perspectives that they developed over their life-course.
An individual who is successfully aging maintains
a mature integrated personality, which also is
the basis of life satisfaction. As such, decreases
in activity or social interaction are viewed as related more to changes in health and physical
function than to an inherent need for a shift in
or relinquishment of previous roles.
Increasingly, however, through the 1970s, concern came to be expressed about the individuallevel focus of theories of aging and their failure to
address the impact of social and economic factors
on the lives of older people. Riley’s “age stratification theory” was an early example, exploring the
role and influence of social structures on the process of individual aging and the stratification of
age in society. One dimension of this theory is the
concept of “structural lag,” which denotes that
social structures (for example policies of retirement at age sixty-five) do not keep pace with
changes in population dynamic and individual
lives (such as increasing life expectancy). The implications of the theory are that human resources in
the oldest – and also the youngest – age strata are
underutilized, and that excess burdens of care and
other responsibilities are placed upon groups in
the middle years.
Another important approach which moved
beyond individual adjustment to aging, and
which was also influenced by the age stratification
model, has been the life-course approach (as initially developed by Glen Elder). Here, aging individuals and cohorts are examined as one phase of
the entire lifetime and seen as shaped by historical, social, economic, and environmental factors
that occur at earlier ages. Life-course theory
bridges macro–micro levels of analysis by considering the relationships among social structure,
social processes, and social psychological states.
13
age
Passuth and Bengston in Sociological Theories of
Aging (1996) suggest that the key elements of the
approach are that: “(1) aging occurs from birth to
death (thereby distinguishing this theory from
those that focus exclusively on the elderly); (2)
aging involves social, psychological and biological
processes; and (3) aging experiences are shaped by
cohort-historical factors.”
From the early 1980s, neo-Marxist perspectives
such as political economy theory became influential within studies of aging. Beginning in the late
1970s and early 1980s with the work of Carroll
Estes and Alan Walker, these theorists initiated
the task of describing the respective roles of capitalism and the state in contributing to systems of
domination and marginalization of older people.
The political economy perspective is distinguished
from the dominant liberal-pluralist theory in political science and sociology in that political economists focus on the role of economic and political
systems and other social structures and social
forces in shaping and reproducing the prevailing
power arrangements and inequalities in society.
In the political economy perspective, social policies pertaining to retirement income, health,
and social service benefits and entitlements are
examined as products of economic, political, and
socio-cultural processes and institutional and individual forces that coalesce in any given sociohistorical period. Social policy is an outcome of
the social struggles, the conflicts, and the dominant power relations of the period. Policy reflects
the structure and culture of advantage and disadvantage as enacted through class, race/ethnicity,
gender, and age relations. Social policy is itself a
powerful determinant of the life chances and conditions of individuals and population groups such
as older people.
Another important approach is that of cultural
and humanistic gerontology, sometimes referred
to as moral economy or more broadly as cultural
gerontology. This perspective, first developed by
Thomas Cole and Harry Moody, has gained popularity, as the classical theoretical opposition of
structure versus agency and culture versus structure has given way to an appreciation of the interplay and “recursive” relationships of culture, and
agency and structure. Cultural gerontology is part
of the trend towards theories that reject the sole
determinacy of economics in explaining social institutions such as the state and old age policy. The
approach provides a re-formulation of the unidirectional causality implied in the classical base/
superstructure (see ideology) model of Marxism.
What has followed is an intensified focus on
14
age
addressing issues relating to meaning and experience in later life, with critical questions raised
about the efficacy of western culture in providing
adequate moral resources to sustain the lives of
older people.
Biographical perspectives have also emerged as
a significant stream of work within gerontology.
Biographical or “life history” research has an extensive pedigree in the social sciences (building on
the work of W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki,
The Polish Peasant in Europe and America, 1918–20).
Some of the key researchers in the field of aging
using biographical and life history techniques
have included James Birren, Joanna Bornat,
Peter Coleman, Paul Thompson, and Gary Kenyon.
Birren’s influential edited collection Aging and
Biography (1996) took the view that biographical
approaches could contribute towards understanding both individual and shared aspects of aging
over the life-course. Examining reactions to personal crises and turning points could, it was
argued, provide researchers with unique insights
into the way individuals construct their lives.
Equally, however, studying lives provides a perspective on the influence of social institutions
such as work and the employment and the family.
Biographical data thus help in understanding
what Ruth and Kenyon (Biography in Adult Development and Aging, 1996) refer to as the possibilities
and limits set by the historical period in which
people live.
Finally, theories of aging drawn around issues
relating to identity and the self have also gained in
importance. Mike Hepworth and Mike Featherstone in The Body (1991) have developed the view
that aging can be best explained as a mask. Here,
physical processes of aging, as reflected in outward appearance, are contrasted to a real self
that remains young. This theory, which has come
to be known as the “mask of aging,” holds that
over time the aging body becomes a cage from
which a younger self-identity cannot escape. The
body, while it is malleable, can still provide access
to a variety of consumer identities. However, as
aging gathers pace, it becomes increasingly difficult to “re-cycle” the failing body, which simultaneously denies access to that world of choice.
Simon Biggs in The Mature Imagination (1999) suggests that the struggle between inner and external
worlds may result in older people being at war
with themselves, in a battle between a desire for
youthful expression and the frailties generated by
an aging body.
Globalization is another significant issue
affecting both theories of aging and the daily lives
age differentiation
of older people. An important development at a
macro-level arises from the interplay between
demographic change (notably longer life expectancy) and the trends associated with political and
cultural globalization. Awareness of living in an
interconnected world brings to the fore questions
of cultural diversity, different understandings
about what it means to grow old, and the issue
of who we take to be an older person.
The tendency in studies of aging has been to use
western models of development to define old age,
these taking sixty or sixty-five as the boundary set
by conventional retirement and pension systems.
But in some continents (notably sub-Saharan
Africa), old age may be more meaningfully defined
as starting from fifty (or even earlier). Access to
pension systems to mark the onset of old age is
itself a culturally specific process. Relevant to
western contexts (though changing even here
with privatization), it has little resonance in countries such as China where, out of 90 million people
aged sixty-five plus, just one-quarter have entitlement to a pension. In a number of senses the
traditional formulation of “aging societies” is unhelpful, given global inequalities. Global society
contains numerous demographic realities – aging
Europe, to take one example, as compared with
increasingly youthful United States, and falling
life expectancy in Russia and sub-Saharan Africa.
Such contrasts create significant variations in the
construction of growing old – national, transnational, subcultural – producing, as a result,
new questions and perspectives for research in
the field of aging.
CHRIS PHILLIPSON
age differentiation
– see age.
age group
– see age.
ageism
– see age.
agency and structure
Beginning in the 1970s, the expression “agency
and structure” has been employed to thematize
the relationship between the enactment of social
practices on the one hand and large-scale and
historically enduring social phenomena on the
other. Language is often used to illustrate several
important issues in agency–structure relations.
On the one hand, language exists as an observable
reality only when actors use language (converse,
read, or write) in specific ways at particular
agency and structure
moments in local settings. On the other hand,
from a structural point of view, a given language
exhibits general patterns (for example, syntax, semantics, grammar) that are never fully realized in
any single conversation or piece of writing, although they are presupposed by all of them. In
the case of language, the problem of agency and
structure focuses on the relationship between the
enactment of linguistic practices on the one hand
and the large-scale structure of language on the
other.
In terms of the agency–structure problem,
agency implies enactment rather than autonomy
or empowerment, which in other contexts the
term sometimes implies. The term structure is
used in several different ways. Language is only
one example of cultural structures, a category
that also comprises culinary cultures, religious
cultures, cultures of dominant and subaltern
groups, and so on. Material structures are relevant
as well. For example, a capitalist market, no matter
how extensive and dynamic it may be, exists only
so long as traders engage in acts of exchange of
material resources. If acts of exchange were to
cease, say following the collapse of the value of
instruments of credit, then even the most massive
and structured market would come to a halt and
ultimately cease to exist. Fields of the distribution
of scarce resources can be framed in terms of the
agency–structure problem as well. For example,
the practice of continuous reinvestment of profits,
about which Max Weber wrote, enables entrepreneurs and investors to accumulate large quantities of capital. Skillful reinvestment can
ultimately concentrate large amounts of capital
under the control of a very small group while the
majority of a population is not very prosperous.
But if profits are not skillfully reinvested in practice, then the structure of inequality may change.
Finally, social networks and other patterns of articulated social relationships may be understood
in terms of the agency–structure problem as well.
For example, the networks of weak ties at the
center of Mark Granovetter’s well-known research
may be understood as a set of casual, intermittent
interactions among acquaintances, during which
useful information is discussed and thus transmitted. Each link in the network is an enacted set of
conversational practices, and the form of the
network is produced one link at a time as these
conversations occur.
To appreciate the specificity of the agency–
structure problem, it must be understood in contrast to the problem of the relationship between
the individual and the collectivity. This second
15
agency and structure
problem, which is one of the oldest and most
intractable dilemmas in social theory, restates in
sociological terms the philosophical conundrum
of free will versus determinism. Are individuals so
constituted and constrained by their structural
circumstances that they have little or no free
will at all, as Émile Durkheim, for example, maintained? Or are social structures merely the epiphenomenal consequences of what actors do as
they each pursue their personal interests and desires, as can be inferred, for example, from the
writings of Adam Smith (1723–90)? The dilemma
here is that the sociologist is virtually compelled
to assume a reductionist position. Either individuals are epiphenomenal to structures or structures are epiphenomenal to individuals. The
agency–structure problem does not compel the
sociologist to reduce one phenomenon to another.
This is because, from an agency–structure point of
view, the individual is no longer a counterpoint to
structure. Instead, the counterpoint to structure is
social praxis, that is, the enactment of forms of
social conduct or behavior. Enacted forms of behavior generate (that is, construct or produce) the
realities of social life, whether they be cultural,
economic, distributional, or network patterns.
The same cannot be said of individuals. Individuals may want to act in certain ways in order to
achieve their interests or wants, but they may lack
the competence or resources to do so. In other
words, individuals in a given setting may not be
able to enact certain practices, even if motivated
to do so. Conversely, actors may generate aspects
of social reality (for example, cultural domination
as Pierre Bourdieu suggests) though they are unaware they exercise agency in this regard.
How is the agency–structure problem amenable
to non-reductive solutions? To begin, consider not
a single locally enacted practice, but rather a single
form of practice, which is to say a form of practice
that may be enacted each day by numerous actors
in different settings and may be enacted as well by
successive generations of actors. Now we can
introduce the idea of social reproduction, which
is to say the recurrent reenactment of similar
forms of practice. Of course, no two instances of
enactment are entirely the same: for example,
when conversing, people make grammatical and
syntactical mistakes, or engage in creative wordplay rather than speaking in conventional forms.
Nonetheless, over many instances, people use language in broadly similar ways, and this is what it
means to say that forms of linguistic practice are
reproduced. But, as previously mentioned, no
single form of practice can generate a large-scale
16
agency and structure
structure such as an entire language or market.
Large-scale structures are generated when many
different forms of practice are reproduced. Since
this reproduction takes place over some duration
of time in a variety of different locales, sociologists can analyze structures best by abstracting
structural properties of praxis they find to be
associated with one another. Indeed, the same
set of interactions may help to generate a number
of different structures. For example, a capitalist
market is generated in ongoing sequences of commercial practices and economic exchange. But the
same practices generate a network of business
acquaintances. Practices may also result from
the use of a common language or dialect, and so
on. Which of these structures is of interest is an
analytical choice on the part of the sociologist.
We now can see how structured practices (practices that are reproduced in broadly similar forms)
can sustain large-scale structures, but what part
do these structures play in the enactment of practices? The issue here turns on social competencies.
Babies and newcomers to a culture or society do
not arrive knowing how to speak a given language
or how to execute a market trade. Individuals gain
agency (the ability to enact given practices) as they
learn how to perform the forms of conduct that
are a matter of routine in a given group. From this
point of view, the structured form of social practices precedes and shapes how that practice is
performed. Looked at from a broader perspective,
the set of practices that form a language or a
capitalist market or a network of weak ties precedes any given round of social reproduction. In
the end what we have is what Anthony Giddens
terms in The Constitution of Society (1984) a “duality
of structure.” That is to say, there is an ongoing
reciprocal relationship between structure and
agency. Structural circumstances provide the
means to reproduce social practices, but when
social practices are reproduced they perpetuate
the structure, making it a social reality in a new
historical moment. In very stable social groups,
for example tradition-bound villages, this reciprocal relation between structure and agency in
social reproduction may go on for generations.
Reductionism may not be inevitable when social
life is conceived in terms of the connection between agency and structure, but it is still a potential pitfall. Symbolic interactionists, for example,
sometimes reduce structures of all kinds to the
practices through which they are produced without regard for the structural properties of practices that have been reproduced many times over
in the past. Structure, in effect, is reduced to
agency and structure
enactment. It is symptomatic of this problem
that symbolic interactionism stresses the prospect
of creativity in interaction and other social
processes. In a more balanced view, the structural
conditions of praxis, including all necessary competencies and resources needed to engage in social
conduct, both enable actors to perform actions in
certain ways and thereby also limit actors to performing according to their competencies. However, creativity and resistance to established ways
of doing things are not thereby ruled out. Indeed,
many practices, especially those found in the
modern era, permit and sometimes require some
degree of innovation. This is vividly illustrated in
the fine arts, where structured practices (for
example, techniques for painting, musical composition, dancing, and so forth) are employed to
produce novel works, or, more radically, new artistic genres. Similar possibilities exist in many walks
of life, including, of course, politics, where resistors and rebels may resist oppressive practices to
oppose and replace the powers that be.
It is also possible to reduce agency to structure.
This happens when practices are conceived as so
completely derived from structural conditions
that their social reproduction is inevitable. This
form of reductionism can be observed in the
works of Bourdieu. Bourdieu often investigated
how it happens that groups of actors who are
disadvantaged and subordinated to others somehow participate in the reproduction of their own
disadvantages and subordination. He conceives
the practices in which they engage (key elements
of their habitus; see habitus and field) as unselfconsciously reproducing a field of inequality. It is
symptomatic of Bourdieu’s structural reductionism that he conceives very few opportunities for
actors to resist or rebel or, for that matter, even to
recognize the ways in which they reproduce the
structural conditions of their own inequality.
While agency only denotes the enactment of practices in the agency–structure duality, it leaves
open the possibility, given the proper situation,
that actors may seize the moment to devise new
practices that improve the conditions in which
they live.
Giddens’s structuration theory as expressed in
The Constitution of Society (1984) and discussed in Ira
Cohen’s Structuration Theory (1989) is widely regarded as the most thoroughly developed set of sociological concepts that pivots on the relationship
between agency and structure. Giddens’s work
has influenced numerous empirical works, and
new, substantively oriented innovations in structuration theory are currently under development
alienation
by the British sociologist, Rob Stones. Giddens’s
structuration theory has also attracted a great
deal of criticism, most extensively from another
British sociologist, Margaret Archer. She argues,
inter alia, that Giddens is guilty of a peculiar form
of reductionism in which structure and praxis are
inextricably linked. She believes that structure
and practices must be distinct objects of sociological analysis. However, in her main criticisms,
in Realist Social Theory (1995), Archer appears to
misconstrue the level of analysis on which Giddens addresses the agency–structure link. Giddens
writes in ontological terms, that is, in terms of
how the duality of structure and agency generates
social life at large. Archer seems to make an epistemological argument in which she calls for separate sociological analyses on the structural and
praxiological levels. If this is taken into account,
Archer’s position may differ from those of Giddens’s less than may at first appear.
A more difficult problem, for Giddens and
others who theorize in terms of agency and structure, is what to do about the individual’s wants
and interests that they originally set aside. Giddens and Bourdieu, along with most others who
theorize along these lines, rely on tacit and unconscious motives to account for social reproduction. But it is empirically demonstrable that at
least some segments of social actions are consciously driven by actors’ interests, desires, and
attachments to others. Where do these motives
come from? Are they freely chosen or are desires
and interests socially derived and reproduced?
Here the problem of individual versus collectivity
reemerges. In the future, theorists may feel challenged to find a way to address the problem of
agency and structure and the problem of individualism and collectivism from an integrated point of
IRA COHEN
view.
aging
– see age.
alienation
The process whereby people become estranged
from the world in which they are living, the concept is associated with Karl Marx’s early works,
especially Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts
(1844) and his critique of W. G. F. Hegel and
Ludwig Feuerbach (1804–72). For Hegel, people
created a culture, which then confronted them
as an alien, objectified force. Human activity was
the expression of Spirit, of Geist, whose creations
were not self-transparent to their creators,
17
alienation
although they would become so at the end of
history. The work of Feuerbach, a “Young Hegelian”
was also significant. Ludwig Feuerbach (1804–72)
criticized what he called Hegel’s reduction of
Man’s Essence to Self-consciousness, and developed
a critique of religion as “self-alienation.” Rejecting
Hegel’s idealistic philosophy and advocating materialism, Feuerbach emphasized the individual,
purely “biological” nature of humans, in which
thought was a purely reflective, contemplative
process. But in religion, the human potential for
love, creativity, and power were alienated into the
mythical deities to which such powers were attributed. In The Essence of Christianity (1843), Feuerbach
claimed that God is the manifestation of human
inner nature; religion is the “solemn unveiling” of
human hidden treasures, the avowal of innermost
thoughts, the open confession of the secrets of
human love. But this image of perfection becomes
the source of rules that are reimposed on people’s
lives as regulations and self-denial.
Both the Hegelian and Feuerbachian use of
alienation were important for Marx. He accepted
much of Feuerbach’s critique, but took issue with
the notion of a human essence projected onto
God. Human self-alienation is not psychological,
but social and historical, and specifically arises
from the system of production. Marx’s use of the
concept was critical and in some ways ironic, in
that he was taking a term that was widely used by
Hegelian philosophers and subjecting it to parody
(a point generally missed in debates about
whether the concept continues to inform Marx’s
later works). Marx insisted that it was human
labor that created culture and history but that
Hegel had substituted a mystical substance –
Mind – for the real subject of history. For Marx it
was practice rather than thought that changes the
material world and practice is a process of objectification, whereby the products of labor are manifest in material forms. This process is part of
human “species being,” that is, a potential creativity essential to being human. This enables people
to affirm themselves by objectifying their individuality in objects and enabling others to enjoy
the products of their labor. It is thus a social and
affirmative process. However, in conditions of commodity production, this becomes distorted – no
longer a free affirmation of life but, on the contrary, an alienation of life, since workers must
work in order to live. What could be the basis
of creative human self-expression is reduced in
bourgeois society to the most profound form of
alienation in wage labor. Wage-workers sell their
labor (in Capital this is refined to labor power, the
18
alienation
capacity to work for a determinate period) to satisfy basic needs for food, shelter, and clothing,
while capitalists own the labor process and dispose
of the products of labor for profit.
In The Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts,
Marx discussed four types of alienation. The first
was alienation from the product, where the means
of production are owned by capitalists who appropriate and exchange the products of labor. These
then take on a life of their own, separate from the
needs and wishes of the producers; thus, workers
“build palaces but live in hovels.” Second was
alienation from productive activity, where work
becomes external to the lives of workers, who “feel
freely active” only when eating, drinking, and
procreating – activities that humans share with
animals. Third was alienation from “speciesbeing”, such that creativity, an essentially human
capacity for objectifying ourselves through work,
is degraded in systems of production that are exploitative and where work becomes drudgery.
Finally, there was alienation of “man from man”
where community is dislocated, all social relations
are dominated by economics, and hostile classes
are formed. The fundamental injustice of capitalism is that it targets for exploitation precisely what
differentiates humans from other animals, namely
our capacity for productive creativity, which will
be fulfilled in a future, emancipated society.
In later works the concept of alienation appears
less often, although similar ideas are found in
Marx’s theory of commodity fetishism. The domination of commodities in our society is so pervasive that it seems to be an inevitable, natural state
of affairs. All our achievements, everything we
produce, appear as commodities. Capitalism is
the first system of generalized commodity production, in which the commodity has become a universal category of society as a whole. Yet the
commodity is “mysterious” in that value and price
appear to be properties arising from the process of
circulation on the market (as relationships between things rather than people). Commodities
acquire social characteristics because individuals
enter the productive process only as the owners of
commodities. It appears as if the market itself
causes the rise and fall of prices, and pushes
workers into one branch of production or out of
another, independent of human agency. The
impact of society on the individual is mediated
through the social form of things. However, Marxist analysis attempts to show that these apparent
relations between things are really social relations
of production in which value is created through
the exploitation of wage laborers.
Althusser, Louis (1918–1990)
Marx’s theory seems to assume a relatively timeless “human nature,” although this was a concept
he elsewhere rejected. He did, however, assume
that people would be most fulfilled when engaging freely in creative labor, famously depicting
in The German Ideology (1845) non-alienated existence in a future communist society as one “where
nobody has one exclusive sphere of activity but
each can become accomplished in any branch
he wishes, . . . to hunt in the morning, fish in the
afternoon, rear cattle in the evening, criticise
after dinner, . . . without ever becoming hunter,
fisherman, herdsman or critic.” But this does raise
the question of whether alienation can be eliminated in modern societies characterized by complex divisions of labor and inequalities. In later
works, Marx was more circumspect, suggesting
that the co-ordination and division of labor probably cannot be eliminated. Similarly, there is the
question of the extent to which social processes
in complex societies can be self-transparent or
whether opacity is inevitable. With the decline
of interest in Marxist theory since the collapse
of Soviet Communism, interest in the concept of
alienation has waned too.
LARRY RAY
Althusser, Louis (1918–1990)
Althusser was one of the best-known Communist
Party theoreticians of the twentieth century, who
latterly became associated with Eurocommunism.
Three influential works were For Marx (1965 [trans.
1969]), Lenin and Philosophy (1965), and Reading Capital (1967 [trans. 1970]). Key concepts associated with
his philosophy are “the problematic” (texts were
understood as effects of an underlying matrix of
concepts that could be revealed through “symptomatic reading”), “epistemological break” (between humanism and science), “overdetermination” of a
“conjuncture” in which revolutionary change
might occur, and interpellation. He attempted to
reconcile Marxism with structuralism, an intellectual fashion with which Althusser and his student
Michel Foucault were associated. This theory
stressed the persistence of “deep structures” that
underlie all human cultures, leaving little room for
either historical change or human initiative.
Althusser rejected the positive content of empirical
knowledge entirely. Althusser asserted that Essence
is not to be found in Appearance, but must be
discovered through “theoretical practice,” in which
objects appear not as real-concrete objects but as
abstract-conceptual objects. Althusser further rejected the concept of contradiction in Karl Marx and
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, which he saw in
structuralist terms as “over-determination” – where
ancient society
outcomes have multiple simultaneous causes that
together create a “conjuncture”, the resolution of
which is unpredictable. This is part of a wider rejection of much of Marx’s work, which had to be read
critically and rigorously to separate the “humanism” from scientific theorization of capitalist society. “Humanism” in this context referred to belief in
the self-realization of the human species through
creative agency.
In 1980 Althusser murdered his wife and was
confined to a psychiatric unit until his death.
LARRY RAY
ancient society
This term has a broader and a more restrictive
denotation, the two of which are analytically distinct, though deployed so much together and so
much in the same context that they are often
confused. The former is almost as old as Christian
reflection on the Old Testament, but it has its first
official social scientific usage as the nineteenthcentury register of an anthropological and evolutionist distinction between human society from
its primitive beginnings forward to the advent of
industrialism and human society as it had come
to be in the aftermath of industrialization. In just
such a usage, it can serve as the title of the compendious treatment (Ancient Society, 1877) by Henry
Lewis Morgan (1818–81) of material cultural evolution from the foraging band to the alphabetically literate city-states of pre-Christian Greece and
Rome. The crucial divide that lay for Morgan between ancient society and its counterpart – the
“modern society” – was the divide between a preindustrial and an industrial economy. Karl Marx
and Friedrich Engels were the most notable of
classical social theorists explicitly to engage Morgan’s theorization of the “savage,” “barbaric,” and
“civilized” stages of social evolution, but Spencer,
Weber, and Durkheim could agree that the great
divide between the ancient and the modern was
as Morgan would have it be. The lexical and theoretical tradition of a distinction between “ancient
preindustrial” and “modern industrial” society
survives today, but, like the distinction between
the “primitive” and the “modern,” is vulnerable
to Johannes Fabian’s critique of the “denial of
coevalness” in Time and The Other (1983).
In its more restrictive usage, the term is a
philological-historical category. Its exemplary
denotata are precisely the city-states of pre-Christian Greece and Rome. It is the fulcrum of a debate
dating from the Renaissance over the extent to
which the ancient past is culturally continuous
with the modern present (and, if not continuous,
19
Annales School
the extent to which it is more or less virtuous than
the modern present). Since the later nineteenth
century, social theorists have consistently emphasized the discontinuities between the two, if to
incompatible critical ends. Champions of progress such as Spencer, for example, construe the
gap as that between a form of society whose survival and growth depend essentially on war and a
higher form whose survival and growth can at last
rest in cooperation and the increasingly universal
pursuit of enlightened self-interest. Such occasional Romantics as Weber, in contrast, might
construe the gap instead as that between a form
of society still capable of sustaining a public
sphere unified in its commitment to a common
store of transcendent values and a depleted form
in which the gods themselves are perpetually at
war and Homo economicus reigns in their stead. The
spirit, if not the letter, of Spencer’s position has
more contemporary representatives in both Jürgen Habermas and Niklas Luhmann. Echoes of
the Weberian position continued in the twentieth
century in the anti-populist republicanism of such
political theorists as Hannah Arendt.
JAMES D. FAUBION
Annales School
A movement of French historians founded by
Lucien Febvre (1878–1956) and Marc Bloch
(1886–1944) with their journal, Annales: Economies,
Societies, Civilizations, the school reacted to the
prevailing narrative method of history and its concentration on political and diplomatic events –
whose exemplary exponent was Leopold von Ranke
(1795–1886) – by broadening both the content and
the methodological approach of history. This included: (1) extending the historian’s purview to
broad areas of human behavior and activity generally neglected by traditional historians, by drawing
on a variety of other disciplines including sociology, anthropology, psychology, linguistics, and
geography; (2) the use and development of new
methods of historical investigation, including
qualitative and quantitative methodological approaches in addition to standard archival resources; (3) examining the longue durée or broad
long-term persistence of structures within history.
The Annales approach was in no way unified
and included a number of divergent standpoints
within the group. According to Peter Burke in The
French Historical Revolution (1990), the school can be
divided into three phases covering three successive generations of historians. The first generation, which existed from the 1920s to 1945,
included Bloch and Febvre. Heavily influenced by
20
anomie
Émile Durkheim’s sociology, Bloch examined the
prevalence of the medieval belief that the king
could cure scrofula by touching people afflicted
by this skin disease in The Royal Touch (1924). However, his most influential work is undoubtedly his
two-volume study Feudal Society (1939–40), which
dealt not only with the juridical and political
dynamics of medieval society, but with its whole
worldview and culture. These books showed
Bloch’s concern with characteristic features of
the Annales movement: collective representations, the history of mentalities, and long-term
problem-based comparative historical analysis. In
contrast to the influence of sociology on Bloch,
Febvre was heavily influenced by the historical
geographical approach of Paul Vidal de la Blanche
(1845–1918), but he also focused on collective
mentalities. In his major work, The Problem of Unbelief in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais
(1939), he argued for the impossibility of atheism
in the sixteenth century.
The emphasis on geographical factors continued
in the work of the second generation of writers,
whose most prominent representative, and perhaps the most influential of all the Annales
scholars, was Fernand Braudel (1902–85). In his
doctoral dissertation, later published as The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World, in the Age of
Philip II (1949), Braudel pursues a “total history” in
which he examined the geography and economic,
social, and political structures of the Mediterranean world, as well as outlining its political, diplomatic, and military history. He stressed the
important effect that geohistorical structural constraints had on shaping states and economies, as
well as events and individuals.
Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie (1929– ), whose most
noted work is Montaillou (1975 [trans. 1979]), and
Jacques Le Goff (1924– ), who has written widely
on the Middle Ages, most acutely in Medieval Civilization 400–1500 (1988), were the most prominent
of the third generation of historians who emerged
after 1968.
The writings of the Annales movement provided
an important intellectual resource for many Marxist historians, as well as having a bearing on the
work of Michel Foucault. Its work continues in
the Fernand Braudel Center at Binghampton,
which was founded in 1976 and whose director is
Immanuel Wallerstein.
STEVEN LOYAL
anomie
From the Greek a-nomos, meaning without laws,
mores, and traditions, in sociology, the concept
refers to absence of norms and of the constraints
antiglobalization movements
these provide. In The Division of Labor in Society (1893
[trans. 1960]) Émile Durkheim describes how the
division of labor fails to produce solidarity or
social cohesion through an absence of proper
regulation of relations or a type of regulation
not in keeping with the development of the division of labor. He calls this condition the anomic
division of labor. In Suicide (1897 [trans. 1951]),
anomic suicide results from inappropriately low
levels of social regulation. Economic crises, both
depression and excessive growth, are held to be a
source of anomie. Curiously, the regulation of
marriage has contrasting consequences for men
and women, according to Durkheim: unmarried
men are susceptible to anomic suicide, whereas
the regulation of marriage has the reverse effect
on women (married women are more likely to
commit suicide than unmarried ones). For Durkheim, anomie is a feature of social structure
not of individual persons. David Riesman in The
Lonely Crowd (1950), on the other hand, regards
anomie as a psychological feature of individuals.
Robert K. Merton, though, distinguishes in Social
Theory and Social Structure (1968) between the
source and the experience of anomie, acknowledging the psychological impact of anomie but
denying it has a psychological source. Merton advances Durkheim’s account in two ways: he sees
the conflict of norms and not merely their absence as a source of anomie, and he recognizes
the creative potential of anomie as well as its
destructive side.
JACK BARBALET
antiglobalization movements
– see globalization.
Archer, Margaret (1943– )
Professor of Sociology at the University of Warwick and Co-director of the Centre for Critical
Realism, Archer is best known for her contributions to sociological theory. She was President of
the International Sociological Association (1986–
90). Her early work was on the development of
educational systems in Social Origins of Educational
Systems (1974). She developed the analysis of
human agency through a study in cultural sociology in Culture and Agency: The Place of Culture in
Social Theory (1988), in which she defends the separate causal importance of culture and social
structure. Her work is closely associated with a
realist epistemology which she has explored in
Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach
(1995). She has therefore contributed to the analysis of agency and structure, where she has been
critical of the absence of any causal account of
Arendt, Hannah (1906–1975)
structure in the work of Anthony Giddens. There
are broadly two versions of the notion of “structure.” The first, favored by Giddens, treats structure as generative rules and resources, and
emphasizes the voluntary nature of social action.
The second version defines structure as organized
patterns of social relationships that are causally
efficacious. Archer supports this second interpretation, which incorporates the idea of the causal
priority of structure over agency, but she defends
the importance of the reflexivity of social actors in
Structure, Agency and the Internal Conversation (2003).
She has, with Jonathan Tritter, also brought her
perspective into the debate about rational choice
in Rational Choice Theory (2000).
BRYAN S. TURNER
Arendt, Hannah (1906–1975)
Born in Hanover, Germany, Arendt was, from 1967
until her death, a university professor of the
Graduate School at the New School for Social Research in New York, and editor of Schocken Books
(1946–48). Arendt was one of the leading political
philosophers of her time and a critic of the social
sciences, whose language she found pretentious
and obfuscating. In an important debate with
David Riesman, starting in 1947, she argued that
sociology had failed to explain the unprecedented
rise of totalitarianism. Riesman countered that
Arendt exaggerated the capacities and competencies of totalitarian leaders and their bureaucracies, and that no adequate political theory could
be developed without an adequate sociological
theory of society. This debate was seminal in defining the relationship between the concepts of
the social and the political.
Having completed her thesis on Love and St Augustine (1929 [trans. 1996]) under the supervision
of Karl Jaspers (1883–1969), she escaped from Germany to work with Zionist organizations in
France and eventually settled in the United States,
becoming a citizen in 1951. She became famous
initially for her work on The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951). Although this work is clearly a contribution to political theory, it has important
implications for sociologists, because she argued
that people in modern society are forced out of a
shared public life into a lonely, isolated, and interior existence. In their isolation, there are pressures towards uniformity that undermine their
autonomy, and as a result they are psychologically
exposed to the totalitarian social forces of a mass
society. The clear distinction between private and
public life in the classical world has been confused
in modern times by the emergence of “the social.”
In contemporary society, people are connected
21
Aron, Raymond (1905–1983)
together, but these common threads are, paradoxically, their private consumer desires. In a mass
society, the social becomes the basis of mass conformity and the ethical calling of the political
sinks into mundane petty politics.
Her most influential philosophical work was The
Human Condition (1958) in which she divided
human activities into labor, work, and action.
She argued that human life can only be meaningful if people can engage effectively in the public
sphere. This view of politics and her critique of the
social were further expanded in On Revolution
(1963), Between Past and Future (1961), and Men in
Dark Times (1970). In her report on the trial of
Adolf Eichmann in 1961 in Eichmann in Jerusalem
(1963), she coined the expression “banality of evil”
to describe the impact of bureaucratic norms on
personal responsibility for the Holocaust. Her
essays on personal morality and collective responsibility were edited as Responsibility and Judgement
(2003).
BRYAN S. TURNER
Aron, Raymond (1905–1983)
A French journalist, political philosopher, and sociologist, Raymond Aron studied at the École Normale Supérieure and spent some time in Cologne
and Berlin. He was Professor in Sociology at the
Sorbonne from 1954 until 1968. In 1970 he was
elected to a Chair at the Collège de France.
Amongst his many publications are German Sociology (1935 [trans. 1957], Introduction to the Philosophy of History (1938 [trans. 1961]), and two volumes
of Main Currents in Sociological Thought (1960, 1962
[trans. 1965, 1967]). He contributed to the study of
industrial society in Eighteen Lectures on Industrial
Society (1963), and to the sociology of war in Peace
and War; A Theory of International Relations (1961),
The Century of Total War (1951), and Clausewitz; Philosopher of War (1976). He positioned himself in the
French liberal tradition, stretching back to Baron
Charles de Montesquieu and Alexis de Tocqueville.
Aron introduced Max Weber to French sociology
and political science. He was particularly sympathetic towards Weber’s political stance and his
methodology of history. Aron insisted that the
positivist view was inapplicable to the analysis of
social phenomena. He took issue with the tendency of Émile Durkheim and some Marxists to
embrace holism and to explain social processes
by a “prime mover.” For Aron, the search for a
single primary cause, whether it is economic or
cultural, does not do justice to the complexity of
social life. An opponent to Marxism, Aron insisted
that we should never abandon our aim for objectivity in the social sciences, even if it can never be
22
arts
obtained. He was highly critical of utopianism and
regarded Marxism as a dangerous route to totalitarianism. These views made him unpopular
amongst the generation of May, 1968, but he has
since been rehabilitated. Jon Elster and Raymond
Boudon worked under his supervision.
PATRICK BAERT
arts
The field of (the sociology of the arts) deals with
art works, forms, and genres in social, political,
and historical context. It has shifted, over the past
five decades, from a concern with the arts and
society, to a concern with the social shaping of
the arts, to, more recently, a focus on how the
arts may provide conditions for action and organization in various social milieux. In all of these
projects, notions of the autonomy of the arts, of
absolute artistic worth, and of the isolated genius
creator are replaced by considerations of arts
occupations, organizations, and institutions, by a
focus on material and technical resources, and by
studies of reception and use of the arts.
This empirical focus has distinguished arts sociology since the mid-1970s from earlier theoretical
and philosophical approaches (most notably the
perspective of Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno)
that adopt an evaluative stance in relation to
styles, genres, or epochs within the arts. It is also
different from semiotic readings of art works characteristic of scholarly research on the arts within
literature, and from art and music history, in that
it tends either to evade the question of meaning
or to explore that question through the responses
and actions of artistic consumers. Various surveys
of the field have detailed this shift, such as Vera L.
Zolberg’s Constructing a Sociology of the Arts (1990)
and, more recently, Victoria Alexander’s Sociology
of the Arts (2003).
During the 1980s, arts sociology centered on
three main foci – the production of culture or art
worlds perspective, a focus on taste-as-classification, and the study of individual and collective
arts consumption.
Within the first area, Howard Becker’s Art
Worlds (1982), Janet Wolff’s Production of Art
(1981), and Richard A. Peterson’s edited collection
The Production of Culture helped set the agenda.
These works described perspectives for grounding
arts sociology, albeit at different levels, in empirical research and drew it away from earlier models
of arts sociology, most prevalent in the classical
canon (for example, Max Weber’s essay on The
Rational Foundations of Music, 1958, or Pitrim Sorokin’s study of Social and Cultural Dynamics, 1937, in
arts
which he contrasted the vision of ideational with
sensate cultures). These contributions emphasized
abstract parallels between form or structure in art
works and social structures writ large. While the
concept of the art world drew upon Howard Becker’s classic American Sociological Review article “Art
as Collective Action” (1974), and conceptualized
the arts in terms of networks and conventions,
the approach associated with the term production of culture brings into relief institutional
arrangements and contextual factors that shape
individual art works, styles, and patterns of
distribution/reception.
The focus on the connection between taste in
and for the arts and social status has been most
closely associated with the work of Pierre Bourdieu, such as Distinction (1979 [trans. 1984]). In
Bourdieu’s vision, the arts function as signs of
social location and, owing to the various codes of
artistic appropriation associated with arts consumption, as boundary tools. This perspective
has been developed through various studies of
arts patronage and cultural entrepreneurship, for
example by William Weber (Music and the Middle
Class, 1974) and Paul DiMaggio (“Cultural Entrepreneurship in Nineteenth-Century Boston,” 1982,
in Media, Culture and Society), and criticized through
comparative and empirical studies of geographical
regions outside France, most notably in the
United States, where high socioeconomic status
has been associated with broad cultural and artistic consumption (the “omnivore” concept) as opposed to a concern for exclusive distinction, as in
Richard A. Peterson and Albert Simkus’s work on
taste and social status (“How Musical Tastes
Mark Occupational Status,” 1992, in Cultivating
Differences).
Beginning in the late 1970s with, most notably,
work by members or associates of the Birmingham
Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies, focus
on the arts was used as a means for understanding
the social mechanisms of group membership and
identity formation. Here was one of the first explicit attempts to focus on the links between the arts,
the meanings that the arts hold for their recipients (here conceived as consumers), and social
formation. Equally significantly, the focus on artistic works or products dispensed with the high/
popular distinction in favor of eclectic, user-driven
classification systems, via, for example, the concept of articulation first developed by Stuart Hall.
This perspective, illustrated in work by Paul
Willis and Simon Frith, and by Dick Hebdige’s
Subculture and the Meaning of Style (1979), bound
together anthropological attention to collective
Asian-American studies
representation, identity formation, and arts sociology, whether focused on fashion, decoration, or
music consumption, in ways that have bequeathed
important methodological tools to more recent
work in arts sociology.
In the early 1990s, the call for a “return to
meaning” in arts sociology began, taking various
forms, from a concern with cultural structures,
cognition, repertoires, and new institutionalism,
to a focus on situated contentions of artistic
meaning and value.
More recently, work in sociology of the arts,
once somewhat marginal to the discipline of sociology as a whole, has been linked to a range of
areas. In the work of Tia DeNora (After Adorno,
2003) and Antoine Hennion (“Taste as Performance,” 2001, in Theory, Culture and Society), music
has been explored as an exemplar for various
forms of identification work, from self-identity to
emotional work. It has also been explored by Ron
Eyerman and Andrew Jamieson (Music and Social
Movements, 1998) as a social movement activity.
Depictions of the body in the plastic arts have
been examined in connection with gender politics
and sculpture, in particular high-profile public
works, and have been considered in relation to
the formation and stabilization of collective
memory and from the perspective of “technologies of memory” (Robin Wagner-Pacifici, “Memories in the Making,” 1996, in Qualitative Sociology).
New work, at the interstices of sociology and
social psychology, is emerging on aesthetic agency
and environmental aesthetics, in organizational
contexts and in the public sphere; and studies of
arts production and arts distribution technologies
have been linked to the historical and situated
formation of subjectivity. Boundaries between
“arts sociology,” other sociologies, and work in
cultural geography, community music therapy,
social psychology, philosophy, and work in the
arts and performing arts are continuing to blur,
in ways that decant the once specialist concern
with the arts into the realm of everyday life and
social institutions and bring to the fore a concern
with the aesthetic dimension in areas seemingly
far removed from the arts, traditionally conceived.
TIA DENORA
Asian-American studies
From their historical roots as one of the smallest
and most geographically concentrated racial
groups, massive international migration since
the passage of the Immigration Act of 1965 has
made Asian Americans the fastest-growing segment of the United States population. According
23
Asian-American studies
to the US Census (2000), from 1960 to 2000 the
population of Asian Americans grew from fewer
than 1 million to over 10 million, raising their
share of the US population from less than 1 percent
to over 4 percent. While Chinese, Japanese, and
Filipinos made up the overwhelming share of the
Asian-American population before the 1960s,
the Asian-American population today is characterized by tremendous ethnic diversity, resulting
from massive migration from nearly all parts of
Asia. The ethnic diversity of Asian Americans has
been matched by their class diversity. While laborers dominated the earliest waves of Asian immigration before the 1920s, contemporary Asian
immigration has been characterized by significant
class diversity, including large numbers of highly
trained and educated professionals as well as unskilled workers, political refugees, and undocumented immigrants who face severe economic
disadvantage and social marginalization. For the
Asian-American poor and the working class, the
prevailing “model minority” image that depicts
all Asian-Americans as economically successful
and highly educated functions to mask their
plight.
In addition to these social characteristics, Asian
Americans, as a racial term, represents one of the
most important and instructive lessons on American race relations and racial categorization. On
the one hand, as Michael Omi and Howard Winant
show in Racial Formations in the United States (1994),
the term Asian American highlights the dominant
role of the state in the creation of racial categories. Most notably, through successive federal legislations and court decisions, the term Asian
American found its most politically powerful
meaning as an externally imposed legal category
to deny Asians from South and East Asia the right
to become citizens under the Naturalization Act
of 1790 that originally limited naturalized citizenship only to “free whites.” The denial of naturalized citizenship was joined through various state
laws to exclude Asian Americans from ownership
of land, to subject them to anti-miscegenation laws,
and to justify exclusion from immigration. This
de jure discrimination did not end until the civil
rights movement of the 1960s. On the other hand,
the term Asian American has served to organiz
internally the political activities and social life of
this group in powerful ways. In electoral politics,
as Yen Le Espiritu demonstrates in Asian American
Panethnicity (1992), the Asian-American banner
creates a much more potent political presence
than can be achieved through ethnic-specific
organizing. In this sense, Asian American has
24
assimilation
become a category of empowerment. In addition
to strategic deployment in politics, Asian American is increasingly becoming an important term
for explaining a wide range of social behaviors and
cultural formations, ranging from residential and
marriage patterns to literary and cultural productions that shape collective action and personal
identity. Perhaps the most important sociological
lesson of Asian American is to show that all racial
categories are socially constructed and their significance and meaning are constantly undergoing
change and transformation.
EDWARD PARK
Asiatic mode of production
– see Karl Marx.
assimilation
Originally developed by the Chicago School, assimilation refers to the process by which outsiders
(especially migrants) give up their distinctive culture and adopt the cultural norms of the host
society. This was typically thought to occur among
second-generation migrants. There is no single
model of assimilation but the concept was closely
related to the “melting pot” metaphor used by
Robert Park in relation to the United States, an
anticipated result of which was a diminution of
ethnic and racial divisions. Although often
regarded as a “one-way” process, assimilation actually attempted to understand how heterogeneous
societies develop though the reciprocal cultural
interpenetration and adaptation of many different
groups. The end result would then be a society in
which a uniform cultural identity (for example
“the American”) would reflect the merging of diverse cultural and religious ingredients. Modern
forms of organization, including urbanization,
the market, mass culture, and universal education, were driving assimilation. Later theories in
the 1960s developed more nuanced models.
Gunnar Myrdal emphasized the contrast between
American ideals of equality and the practice
of racial discrimination, which he hoped would
be overcome through the democratic political
process. Milton Gordon developed a model of
seven types of assimilation (cultural, structural,
marital, identificational, attitudinal, behavioral,
and civic) that need not always coincide. More
recently the theory has been criticized on many
grounds. These include failing to address structural racism, a deterministic and unilinear evolutionary logic, the persistence of religious and
ethnic differences in modern societies, and existence of globalized transnational communities.
LARRY RAY
associative democracy
associative democracy
The relationship between voluntary associations
and democracy is one of the most enduring issues
in social theory. While modernity is often defined
as the process which eliminates all intermediate
associations and affiliations between the individual and state or society, the actual unfolding of
modernization has been much more complicated
than this image implies. Rather, voluntary associations were the fundamental elements of the vitality of democratic life without which modern
democratic states could not function. That this is
the case is the starting point of theories of “associative democracy,” especially as put forward by
Paul Q. Hirst in Associative Democracy: New Forms of
Economic and Social Governance (1994) and Can Secondary Associations Enhance Democratic Governance?
(1995). Hirst argued that an associative democracy
model would address the recurring dilemmas of
social democratic models that rely on the state,
which create forms of dependency and pluralist
democratic models that rely on voluntary initiatives, which create individualism. That such theories were put forward clearly indicates that those
social theorists in the nineteenth century, notably
Émile Durkheim in The Division of Labor in Society
(1894 [trans. 1984]), who had foreseen the increased polarization of democratic life between
the individual and the state, were indeed prescient. Throughout the twentieth century, the rise of
the social welfare state and then its rapid retrenchment and withdrawal have illustrated these
intractable dilemmas of the right measure of
balance between individual and social responsibility. Those who argued for associative forms of
democracy highlighted the importance of voluntary associations and social groups in democratic
life, fostering both individual and social responsibility. Others have argued more generally that,
without fostering an associative culture, democratic states would become increasingly dominated by politics as professional expertise and the
society as professional administration. The possibilities of associative democracy remain one of
the most vital and lively questions of social and
political theory.
ENGIN ISIN
attitude
This concept has a long, if sometimes controversial, history in sociological research. An attitude is
generally defined as a learned disposition or belief
that allows us to predict behavior. If, for example,
we discover that an individual holds a positive
attitude (learned disposition or belief) towards a
presidential candidate we should, all other things
audience
being equal, be entitled to predict s/he will vote
(behavior) for that candidate. Research based on
assessments of people’s attitudes is sometimes
held in higher scientific esteem than other types
of survey research on the grounds that well-established attitude scales are said to have a higher
level of validity and reliability than other types
of survey research instruments. Attitudes are usually understood to occur on several different
measurement continua, including those moving
from highly favorable to highly unfavorable;
stronger to weaker levels of intensity; and higher
to lower levels of resolution or stability. Hence, we
may hold a highly favorable attitude towards a
presidential candidate, more or less intensely. If
our attitude is less intense we may be less likely to
act on it than if it is more intense. Likewise we
may hold a highly favorable attitude towards a
presidential candidate, more or less resolutely.
This means that our attitude might be both highly
favorable and highly intense but also highly subject to change based on new evidence. Attitudes
that are held with high levels of intensity and
high levels of stability are said to be those that
offer the best grounds for predicting behavior.
DARIN WEINBERG
attitude scales
– see scales.
audience
While earlier forms of cultural studies focused on
textual analysis and the production of culture,
beginning in the 1960s a variety of individuals
associated with the Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies began paying close
attention to audience use of media, and the concept of audience studies became a key part of
Cultural studies. The Birmingham group argued
for an active audience that was able to dissect
critically and make use of media material, arguing against the media manipulation perspective.
Rooted in a classic article by Stuart Hall entitled
“Encoding/Decoding” (1980), British Cultural studies began studying how different groups read
television news and magazines, engaged in consumption, and made use of a broad range of media.
In Everyday Television: Nationwide (1978), Charlotte
Brunsdon and David Morley studied how different
audiences consumed TV news; Ien Ang (Watching
Dallas, 1985) and Tamar Liebes and Elihu Katz
(A World Connected, 1990) investigated how varying
audiences in the Netherlands, Israel, and elsewhere consumed and made use of the US TV series
Dallas; and John Fiske (Understanding Popular
25
audience research
authoritarian personality
Culture, 1989; Power Plays, Power Works, 1993) wrote
a series of books celebrating the active audience
and consumer in a wide range of domains.
Some critics believed that audience studies
went too far in valorizing an active audience and
called for mediation between theories like those
of the Frankfurt School that posited that the
media were all-powerful instruments of manipulation, and theories like those of Fiske that emphasized the autonomy of audiences and their power
of resistance. Since the mid-1980s, there has
been a proliferation of how different audiences
in various parts of the world use media according
to their gender, race and ethnicity, social class,
and ideology. In addition, media industries have
always been interested in audience studies, and
so the audience has entered the center of a wide
range of communication, cultural, and social
theories in the contemporary moment.
DOUGLAS KELLNER
audience research
– see audience.
Austro-Marxism
The term Austro-Marxism was coined before
World War I to describe a group of young Marxist
theorists in Vienna – the most prominent being
Max Adler, Otto Bauer, Rudolf Hilferding, and Karl
Renner. They expounded a form of Marxism that
was rigorous yet undogmatic and that (unlike the
revisionism of the German Social Democratic
Party) remained revolutionary. Most had been involved in the Austrian socialist student movement
and remained politically active in the Austrian
Social Democratic Party. Their influence declined
after the annexation of Austria to Nazi Germany
in 1934, although neglect of their ideas underestimates their significance for Marxist theory. Austro-Marxists were interested in the development
of Marxism as an empirical social science and
were influenced by other intellectual currents in
Vienna at the time, notably logical positivism and
neo-Kantianism. The specific ideas of the AustroMarxists are illustrated by the four major studies
undertaken by Adler on the philosophy of science,
Bauer on nationality and nationalism, Hilferding
on finance capitalism, and Renner on social functions of law (see law and society). Much of Adler’s
work was devoted to the clarification of the theoretical foundations of Marxism and to its re-presentation as an empirical social science. He drew on
both neo-Kantian and positivist philosophies to
claim that the Marxist concept of “socialized
humanity” was a conceptual a priori that made
26
the investigation of causal regularity possible.
Adler’s view of Marxism as a sociological theory
was broadly shared by other Austro-Marxists and
in turn influenced the development of sociology
in Austria up to 1934. Over three decades AustroMarxists analyzed the profound changes in capitalism the most significant of which is characterized by Hilferding as Finance Capital (1910). This
work was concerned with problems of circulation
and capitalist production and addressed the
theory of money, growth of joint-stock companies,
monopoly capital, economic crises, and imperialism. Hilferding argued that there had been a structural change in capitalism with the separation
of ownership from control in the joint-stock
company. This enabled small numbers of people
to acquire control over a large number of companies in which a central role was played by the
credit system and banks (“finance capital”). But
technological progress makes ever-larger quantities of capital necessary, so the volume of fixed
assets increases, the rate of profit falls and competition is curtailed through the formation of cartels
and monopolies. This in turn changes the role of
the state, which increasingly engages in conscious
rational organization of society. The aim of socialist politics is, then, not the abolition of the state
but the seizing of state power in order to bring
this rationalization and direction of social life to
fruition. However, a further aspect of this closer
relationship between state and cartels is the
emergence of imperialist politics, involving a
struggle over world markets and raw materials.
In this context, socialism will not arise from any
inevitable breakdown of capitalism but through
the political organization of working-class political parties creating a rational economic system.
These ideas are reflected in Renner’s theory of the
relative autonomy of law and Bauer’s theory of
nationalism as the ideology of imperialism.
LARRY RAY
authoritarian personality
World War II was followed by the rapid development of social scientific analyses of prejudice and
racism. One of the most influential but controversial of these was The Authoritarian Personality (1950),
the result of research undertaken by Theodor
Adorno, Else Frenkel-Brunswick, Daniel Levinson,
and R. Nevitt Sanford as part of the Berkeley
Public Opinion Study and for the Institute of
Social Research, also known as the Frankfurt
School. The Authoritarian Personality used two psychodynamic tests, the A (authoritarianism) and F
(fascism) scales, and was based on interviews with
authoritarianism
authority
émigré Germans in the postwar United States. It
examined the connection between deep-rooted
personality traits and prejudice, and analyzed
the formation of the “potentially fascistic individual.” This authoritarian personality type displayed
characteristics of “authoritarian submission” –
disliked giving orders but had an uncritical attitude towards idealized moral authorities of the ingroup; “authoritarian aggression” – a tendency to
seek out and condemn people who violate conventional attitudes; anti-intraception – opposition
to imagination and creativity; superstition and
stereotyping – would believe in superstition
and think in rigid categories; power and toughness – identification with powerful figures; cynicism – generalized hostility and belief in
conspiracies; projectivity – projecting onto stigmatized groups unconscious emotional impulses;
and preoccupation with sex and concern with
“goings-on.” This personality type will become
anxious and insecure when events upset their
previously existing worldview. The personality
type was associated particularly with (what the
authors saw as) the highly sexually repressed
lower middle class, a group that felt threatened
by both large corporations and socialism and was
predisposed to support authoritarian politics.
LARRY RAY
authoritarianism
The term authoritarianism indicates a political
regime in which government is distinguished by
high-level state power without legitimate, routine
intervention by the populace governed, for
example through binding procedures and practices of popular consent-formation, public opinion, free speech, and government accountability.
Citizens’ appeal against the decisions of the ruler
is discouraged and, eventually, repressed by coercive means. A wide array of nation-state societies
have historically been governed by such regimes.
Although authoritarian rule is usually deployed as
a shorthand for oppressive measures, it can also
(but not wholly without coercion at some point)
feature as paternalistic benevolence. Authoritarian rulers hold themselves responsible (but not
accountable) for the ruled subjects’ well-being
and may enforce strict conformity “for the subjects’
own good.”
In the political sociology of Max Weber, the
term also occurs in the characterization of
the transition between authority systems in the
West. Traditional differs from modern (that is rational-legal) authority in that, by character, law in
the authoritarian regime is particularistic, both
formal and substantive inequality before the
law exist, and the ultimate purpose of law as
coherent body is not well elaborated. According
to Weber’s differentiation of ideal-typical regimetype activity, non-authoritarian regimes are characterized by adjudication (highly rationalized law)
rather than administration. They emphasize
rights, including social rights, and political authority is impersonal and impartial, with sovereigns serving citizens to maintain and develop
their rights.
In comparative-historical method and macrosociology, the authoritarian regime-type is commonly differentiated from totalitarian and
democratic systems. Whereas there is wide consensus over the general distinction between democratic regimes on one hand and authoritarian and
totalitarian on the other, there is much disagreement over the difference between authoritarian
and totalitarian regimes in history. There are two
camps, one arguing that totalitarianism is a more
extreme form of authoritarianism, and a second
arguing a categorical difference between the two.
The regime-type distinction became particularly
important in a practical sense to international
relations during and following the Cold War
period, because it allowed governments to argue
it would be ethically unproblematic for them to
interact with authoritarian nations charged with
human-rights violations, because these nationstates would be capable of political reform and
therefore should not be isolated – unlike totalitarian ones. Authoritarian and totalitarian regimes
are usually compared with regard to their degree
of subordination of their political subjects’ lives.
The full control of the citizenry and the enforcement by terror under both fascism and Stalinism
are two well-documented examples of totalitarian
regimes in the twentieth century. One outstanding analysis of the parallels of these two regimes
was delivered by Hannah Arendt in The Origins of
Totalitarianism (1951), in which she emphasized
that totalitarian ideologies are marked by the purposeful, radical liquidation of any freedom,
thereby denying any space for action and thought,
as well as aiming at changing human nature.
Another defining criterion is the extent to which
regimes are revolutionary or conservative –
authoritarian regimes are argued to be the latter,
while totalitarian regimes are said to transform
the basic structure of society.
ANN VOGEL
authority
The concept of authority has a long and rich history within western political philosophy, where it
27
authority
has been often coupled and contrasted with liberty and other significant concepts. It has not had
the same resonance within sociology, where it
often appears in the same context as the power
concept. The relationship between the two concepts, however, is construed in rather different
ways.
Sometimes authority is categorically contrasted
with power. For instance, Robert Nisbet, in his
influential work The Sociological Tradition (1967),
has argued that, with the advent of modernity,
the power phenomenon has displaced authority.
This displacement has happened in a particularly
dramatic manner in the course of the second
of the “twin revolutions” – the industrial one
with its main site in England, and the political
one breaking through in France. Much in the
sociological tradition, he suggests, constitutes a
critical reflection on the power phenomenon, and
compares it unfavorably with “authority.” The
latter was a very significant aspect of pre-modern
European society, where it was enmeshed in, and
structured, magnified, justified, and bounded by,
such forces as religion, the family, law, and tradition. Power, instead, de-coupled itself from these
phenomena, and sought to control and modify
society through sheer, factual force, first and
most signally exhibited in all its brutality in the
“terror” phase of the French Revolution.
The nostalgia for the premodern order which
Nisbet considers intrinsic to the whole sociological tradition expressed itself also in its reverence for authority. This is much in evidence in the
response of Edmund Burke (1729–97) to the revolutionary events themselves, in the proto-sociology of French Restoration thinkers, and later in
Alexis de Tocqueville’s worried reflections on the
penchant of democratic societies for a new form
of despotism. Among later social theorists, Nisbet
emphasized Émile Durkheim’s hankering for authority, especially in the form of laws and other
public arrangements which would restrain the
ruthless greed of the over-individualized, atomized members of modern society.
In these conceptualizations, authority is characterized by the sense that it speaks from above
individuals, with a voice at the same time forbidding and benevolent, whose commands evoke respect and create in their addressees a sense of
obligation. But if here authority is contrasted
with power, other sociological renderings of the
concept juxtapose it to power. For instance, in
the context of recurrent arguments about the respective conceptual provinces of power, force, coercion, influence, manipulation, and authority,
28
authority
the latter is sometimes seen as exemplified by
the phenomenon banally characterized as
“doctor’s orders.” Here, authority typically seeks
to induce subjects to actions they would not
engage in on their own, but does so because it is
grounded on another subject’s superior knowledge of the circumstances and expresses its concern with the interests of the former subjects. The
benevolence component of the first understanding is strongly stressed. To simplify these complex
conceptual relations, we might say that a further
use of “authority” subordinates it conceptually to
“power.”
This variant needs closer reflection, because it
has lent itself to much elaboration by social theorists. Let us begin with Max Weber’s concept of
power (Macht) which sees power present, within a
social relationship, if and to the extent that one
party to it is in a position to realize its own interests, even against the (actual or virtual) opposition of the other party. Weber himself remarks
on certain liabilities of this understanding of
power, such as the fact that it can be applied to
relations of no great significance, and that within
a given relation “power” so understood may easily
shift from one party to the other, and then vice
versa, as the issues vary. Given this difficulty, it
is preferable, in sociological discourse, to make
use chiefly of a concept narrower than power,
characterizing situations where power asymmetries are particularly marked, and affect and
structure larger and relatively durable contexts
of interaction. This may happen, in particular,
when power is “legitimate.”
For legitimate power, Weber proposes the concept Herrschaft. This term means literally “lordship,” but it has seemed appropriate, to the
English translators of Weber, to employ a different expression. One of the alternative translations
proposed, besides “rule,” “rulership,” and “domination,” is “authority.” In this capacity, that is in its
conceptualization as “legitimate power,” authority has acquired much currency in English sociological discourse. It was put forward in 1947 as the
translation of Herrschaft by Talcott Parsons and A.
M. Henderson in The Theory of Social and Economic
Organization, their edition in English of the first
part of Weber’s Economy and Society (1922 [trans.
1968]), which for about two decades held sway
in the English-speaking world. Furthermore, even
the later, complete, and much better edition of
Economy and Society by Guenther Roth and Claus
Wittich (1968), while making some use of an alternative version of Herrschaft (domination) continued to use “authority” in rendering Weber’s
authority
final statement of his typology of Herrschaft –
widely recognized as one of his most significant
contributions to sociology and political science.
What follows refers chiefly to that typology.
First, what does “legitimacy” mean? According
to Weber, it constitutes a significant qualification
of a relationship where commands are routinely
issued which evoke obedience. They can do so,
however, on rather different grounds: because
the addressees of commands are totally accustomed to automatic, unreflected submission; as a
result of those addressees’ calculation of the respective probabilities and effects of obedience
versus non-obedience; finally, because the addressees sense that, as moral beings, they owe obedience
to those commands, that these ought to be obeyed
because they have been duly issued by people
entitled to issue them.
In this last case, commands can be said to be
legitimate. This entails that they are more willingly
and reliably obeyed, that sanctions (see norm[s]) for
disobedience are less likely to be called for, that
the whole relationship – while remaining, at
bottom, a relationship of power – is rendered
more stable, durable, wide-ranging, and effective.
These advantages of authority, that is of power
endowed with legitimacy, have long been recognized – for instance, in a statement from JeanJacques Rousseau (1712–78) in his Social Contract
(1762): “the strongest person is never sufficiently
strong to be always master unless he converts his
strength into right, and obedience into duty.”
Weber imparts an original twist to this generalization. If a power relationship turns into one of
authority insofar as it is grounded on an argument, however implicit, to the effect that those
in power are entitled to issue commands, and
those receiving commands are duty-bound to
obey, then one may differentiate the various types
of authority by referring to the contents of that
implicit argument.
Weber then argues that, at a high level of abstraction, where the whole range of historical
reality can be encompassed conceptually by few
ideal-typical constructs, that argument has always
had one or the other of three contents, each
characterizing a distinctive kind of authority.
Traditional authority. This rests on reverence for
the past, on the assumption that what has always
been the case is sacred and deserves to persist.
Thus, what makes a command rightful is the
extent to which it echoes previous, time-hallowed
commands; the rightful power holder is the descendant of a former power holder (typically, a
patriarch); the appropriate sentiment towards
authority
him of those subject to his power is that of filial
devotion; and so on.
Charismatic authority. Here, the commands are
issued by a person to whom transcendent forces
have imparted a “gift of grace,” enabling that
person to perform extraordinary feats that bear
witness to the power of those forces and benefit
those who follow the person in question. These
feats may be victories obtained through unprecedented military action and leading to wide-ranging
conquest and much booty; or the proclamation of
new beliefs and values, opening up novel understandings of the meaning of existence and
avenues to after-worldly salvation. Accordingly,
those commands are intrinsically innovative,
break with tradition instead of reasserting it,
and are to be obeyed because they express the
unchallengeable will of the person in question.
Legal authority. Here, single commands constitute correct instantiations of rules of lesser or
greater generality, valid in turn because they
have been formed and enacted according to certain procedural rules. These establish which individuals are entitled to issue which commands in
which circumstances, and thus constrain the
impact of the personal interests of those individuals on the content of the commands. In turn,
obedience does not express the personal subjection of those practicing it to those issuing the
commands, but constitutes, however implicitly,
the dutiful observance of an entire system of rules
which justifies and orients those commands.
What Weber thus typifies are at bottom cultural
realities, sets of understandings, and justifications which can be, and sometimes actually are,
advanced in the context of discourses. On this
account, his typology has sometimes been interpreted idealistically, as if in Weber’s mind the
nature of its legitimacy determined all significant
features of an authority relation.
This is not an acceptable interpretation. As we
have seen, the reference to legitimacy serves to
differentiate conceptually a phenomenon which
presents aspects of a very material nature, in
particular those relating to the exercise or the
threat of violence as the ultimate sanction of
commands, or the arrangements made to provide
those in command with material resources. Furthermore, legitimacy itself often emerges, in one
configuration or another, only over time, as a byproduct of those or other material aspects of the
authority relationship. Figuratively, one might
say that authority develops as naked power,
over time, clothes itself in legitimacy – a development that in turn has considerable consequences
29
authority
for the nature and the effects of those very
aspects.
For instance, the extraction from the economy
of resources to be made available to those in a
position of power, can be facilitated by the emergence and the consolidation of a feeling, within
the collectivity, that the commands through
which such extraction is carried out appeal to
the dutiful submission of subordinates to their
legitimate superiors. Furthermore, the extraction
process will vary in its forms, tempo, intensity,
predictability, according to the nature of the legitimacy vested in those superiors. Those features of
it will in turn have distinctive effects on other
aspects, both of the authority relation and of
social life in general.
In fact, Weber’s typology of authority, while
privileging the varying nature of the legitimacy
as a way of partitioning conceptually that phenomenon, subsumes under the resulting partitions a whole range of further components, such
as the arrangements for the judicial settlement of
disputes and punishment of crime, the typical
ways in which those in authority present and represent themselves and those subject to their commands, and above all the arrangements made for
administration.
In other terms, some of the most significant
concepts produced by Weber’s thinking about politics, such as those of patriarchalism, patrimonialism, feudalism, administration by notables, or
bureaucracy, are framed within his typology of
authority, and are among his most important legacies. They convey the expressly sociological
nature of that thinking, for in his judgment other
approaches to the concept of authority, particularly philosophical and juridical ones, had not
paid sufficient attention to the day-to-day aspect
of authority, such as administration itself. It
seemed very important, to him, to create typologies of the ways in which administrators are recruited, trained, instructed, deployed, monitored,
controlled, or rewarded, as well as the “strategies
of independence” vis-à-vis the rest of the polity
which these very arrangements made possible for
the administrators themselves. In this manner
30
autopoiesis
Weber’s treatment of authority and its variants
opens itself to a consideration of the dynamics of
the whole authority phenomenon.
GIANFRANCO POGGI
automation
This concept indicates machinery-driven processes
of production in which human intervention is
intentionally minimized to ensure predictable
and standardized outcomes. Automation can
refer to linkages between different machine
devices (robot machine tools) to produce a continuous intervention-free flow of production, to
automatic control over production, or to the full
computerization of production.
Historically, automation has been associated
with assembly-line production and Taylorism but
it is not exclusive to the economies of scale and
mass production connected to Fordism (see postFordism). The post-Fordist era of capitalism is characterized by a refinement of automated processes
in the area of assembly-line and off-line assembly
production. Automation can be part of the integration, via the computerization of the total production chain, that also reaches into areas of
distribution. As a result of the historical development of the automobile industry, and later of a
broad range of consumer goods industries, automation is mainly associated with manufacturing,
but in the service sector of the economy it can also
be observed in the form of technologies and
ideologies that are deployed to minimize human
intervention.
Automation is a key phenomenon in industrial
sociology because it not only affects relations between workers and their production tools, and
thus the intrinsic meaning of human work, but
also influences social relations in work organizations and thus participation in the production
process. Automation has been an empirical referent in sociological theory with respect to such
prominent themes as alienation, deskilling, and
ANN VOGEL
the labor process.
autopoiesis
– see Niklas Luhmann.
B
Bales, Robert Freed (1916–2004)
Barthes, Roland (1915–1980)
An important figure in the growth of the study
of group dynamics, Bales received his PhD from
Harvard University, becoming Harvard Professor
of Social Relations (1945–86). He spent the entirety
of his academic career at that institution.
During the 1950s and 1960s when the study of
small groups was at its height, Bales was a major
figure in exploring the dynamics of group life. His
1950 book, Interaction Process Analysis: A Method for
the Study of Small Groups, is considered a classic
work, particularly in its development of a twelvecategory coding scheme for direct observation and
coding of verbal statements and nonverbal acts in
both natural and laboratory groups. This method
permitted social psychologists to explore systematically behavior in collective settings.
Bales was a close associate of the Harvard social
theorist Talcott Parsons, and was one of the contributors to Parsons’s project for the development
of a general theory of social action. Consistent
with the interests of many of his Harvard colleagues, Bales maintained a lively involvement in
psychoanalysis, a theory that affected both his
research and his teaching.
Later in Bales’s career, he extended the
model of interaction process analysis into a threedimensional coding system, eventually termed
SYMLOG (SYstem for the Multiple Level Observation of Groups). Towards the end of his career, Bales
became more involved in consulting, applying
his models of group life to social problems,
and eventually created a consulting group for his
SYMLOG system.
Bales may have been particularly well known
for the self-analytic group course that he ran at
Harvard for over a quarter-century, which became
a model for similar courses throughout the United
States. In these courses, students were trained
to analyze their own group communication,
while simultaneously learning theories of group
dynamics. These groups also served as a training
tool for graduate students under Bales’s direction.
Widely hailed as one of the most important
French intellectuals of the postwar years, Roland
Barthes’s semiological approach to the study of
society sought to demonstrate how cultural production reproduces itself through the signs it
creates (see cultural reproduction). We live in a
world pulsating with signs; and each sign in the
system of cultural production has meaning,
according to Barthes, only by virtue of its difference from other signs. In elaborating this semiological vision of society, Barthes drew from an
eclectic range of theorists, including Ferdinand
de Saussure, Roman Jakobson, Émile Benveniste,
Mikhail Bakhtin, and Jacques Lacan. His entire
theoretical edifice (less a coherent system than a
kind of ongoing conceptual crossreferencing)
sought to decode the signs our society generates.
Barthes made two principal contributions to
sociological categories of analysis. First, in Writing
Degree Zero (1953), he inverted Saussure’s claim
that linguistics is part of the broader discipline
of semiotics, through demonstrating that the
field of signs is, in fact, part of the more general
domain of linguistics; the language of signs, says
Barthes, always overflows with meaning, exhausts
itself. Second, in Mythologies (1957), he demonstrated how cultural production is always veiled
by its signifiers, through penetrating readings of,
for instance, wrestling, the Tour de France, as well
as a celebrated cover of Paris-Match.
Among his other works are Elements of Semiology
(1965), The Fashion System (1967), Roland Barthes by
Roland Barthes (1977), Empire of Signs (1983), and The
Pleasure of the Text (1990).
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
GARY ALAN FINE AND KENT SANDSTROM
base/superstructure
– see ideology.
Baudrillard, Jean (1929– )
Currently Professor of the Philosophy of Culture
and Media, European Graduate School, Saas-Fée,
Switzerland, Baudrillard taught at the University
of Nanterre, Paris, between 1966 and 1987. He is
31
Bauman, Zygmunt (1925– )
closely associated with postmodernism. He moved
from an early political involvement with Marxism
and the situationists to focus on symbolic forms of
exchange in The Object System (1968). His work on
simulation argued that consumer culture is dominated by hyperreality and the cultural elevation
of irony and fatality in The Mirror of Production
(1973), Simulacra and Simulation (1994), and America
(1989). The notion of intrinsic value that was the
inspiration of radicalism was portrayed as defunct
and the conventional distinction between reality
and illusion was compromised. He held that there
are no historical agents capable of transforming
history. Consumption and sign value were portrayed as replacing production and use value.
Baudrillard’s fascination with the United States
reflected his assessment of it as the most fully
developed consumer culture in the world in
America.
Reception of his work was assisted by globalization, the internet, and deregulation. Each provided metaphors for the virtual universe that
Baudrillard’s theoretical work postulated. His
theory of simulation renewed the specter of AdMass world produced by mass society theory in
the 1950s and 1960s. But it dehumanized the
notions of control and manipulation by proposing
that no social formation is capable of authoritative engagement with simulation.
His work was important for exposing the dogma
of many fossilized positions in social theory between the 1970s and 1990s. However, his epigrammatic style and provocative theses are subject to
the law of diminishing returns. Analytically, his
thought is best seen as a colorful contribution to
the renewal of the sociology of fate. C H R I S R O J E K
Bauman, Zygmunt (1925– )
Born in Poland and educated in the Soviet Union,
Bauman held academic posts in various countries
(including Poland, Israel, and Australia) before
taking up the chair of sociology at the University
of Leeds – where he is now Emeritus Professor. A
leader of the cultural turn in sociology as far back
as the 1970s, his first book in English, Between Class
and Elite (1972), took the British labor movement as
its field of investigation. In following years, in
books such as Culture as Praxis (1973), Socialism:
The Active Utopia (1976), and Memories of Class
(1982), he established himself as an erudite
analyst of the connections between social class
and culture. His master work, Modernity and the
Holocaust (1989), is a dark, dramatic study of
Enlightenment reason and its possible deathly consequences. Auschwitz, in Bauman’s view, was a
32
de Beauvoir, Simone (1908–1986)
result of the “civilizing” mission of modernity;
the Final Solution was not a dysfunction of
Enlightenment rationality but its shocking
product.
Various intellectual spinoffs followed, including Modernity and Ambivalence (1991), Life in Fragments (1995), Liquid Modernity (2000), and Wasted
Lives (2004). In these books, Bauman moved from
a concern with the historical fortunes of the Jews
in conditions of modernity to an analysis of the
complex ways in which postmodern culture increasingly cultivates us all as outsiders, others,
or strangers. As a result of this provocative
critique, Bauman’s sociology on the traumas of
contemporary life has become renowned.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
de Beauvoir, Simone (1908–1986)
Born in Paris, the elder of two daughters of bourgeois parents, de Beauvoir’s intellectual abilities
were apparent from an early age; the loss of her
family’s secure economic status allowed her to
follow a career as a secondary-school teacher of
philosophy. This radical departure from bourgeois
convention was accompanied by de Beauvoir’s long
partnership with Jean-Paul Sartre, documented in
the four volumes of de Beauvoir’s autobiography
(Memoirs of a Dutiful Daughter, 1958; The Prime of Life,
1960; Force of Circumstance, 1963; and All Said and
Done, 1972). De Beauvoir worked with Sartre on
the articulation of the philosophical movement
which was to become known as existentialism;
de Beauvoir, in her essays Pyrrhus and Cineas
(1944) and The Ethics of Ambiguity (1948), discussed
the implications for individuals of existential
tenets. The same theme informed de Beauvoir’s
first published novel (She Came to Stay, 1943).
These works, in which philosophical ideas are
illustrated through literature, were overshadowed
by the publication, in 1949, of The Second Sex, the
work for which de Beauvoir became world-famous.
The study developed out of de Beauvoir’s previous
preoccupations, in particular the status of the
other in human relationships. For de Beauvoir,
women are the other in all aspects of social life;
men are the norm of human existence and women
are judged in terms of how they are not men. The
most famous dictum of The Second Sex is “women
are made and not born.” This comment opened
numerous theoretical possibilities for the study of
gender differences, from ideas about sexual socialization to the thesis of Judith Butler about
the “performance” of gender. But this specifically
feminist interest in de Beauvoir’s work was to
emerge some years after the initial publication
Beck, Ulrich (1944– )
of The Second Sex; it was second-wave feminism
that encouraged a rethinking of de Beauvoir’s
work. Throughout the decades following the
publication of The Second Sex, de Beauvoir continued to publish novels (the best-known of which,
The Mandarins, won the Prix Goncourt in 1955),
volumes of autobiography, and a lengthy study
of old age.
From the end of World War II, de Beauvoir had
taken a prominent part in left-wing politics in
France and was a vehement critic of French policy
in Algeria and that of the United States in Vietnam. In the last two decades of her life, as a
younger generation of readers discovered her
work, she became closely associated with feminist
campaigns (especially around issues of reproductive rights) but consistently rejected the position of
other French feminists on the essential difference
of male and female thinking and language. Although the concept of the binary difference of
male and female was central to de Beauvoir’s
work, she remained consistent in the view that
the process of the accumulation of knowledge
was not gendered. Nevertheless, a recurrent
theme in her work is that of loss, a theme she
elaborated in her account of the death of her
mother (A Very Easy Death) and the short stories
published under the collective title A Woman Destroyed. De Beauvoir increasingly identified with
feminism in the last years of her life, and she
retains iconic stature as a person who chose, entirely self-consciously, to devote herself to
intellectual life and, in so doing, helped to shape
our understanding, and the politics, of gender
difference.
MARY EVANS
Beck, Ulrich (1944– )
Professor of Sociology at the University of Munich,
Beck is famous for developing the notion of risk
society and reflexive modernization in his Risk
Society. Towards a New Modernity (1986 [trans.
1992]). His argument is that late modernity increases uncertainty, hazard, and risk. The result
is a new type of society involving reflection, expert
opinion, knowledge systems, and internal critique. Beck has criticized mainstream sociology
for retaining an implicitly utopian or at least
optimistic view of modernization without examining its unintended, negative consequences. In
his Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk (1995), he
applied this approach to the problems of environmental pollution and green politics. In his more
recent work, he has more closely associated his
analysis of risk to theories of globalization in The
Reinvention of Politics. Rethinking Modernity in the Age
Becker, Howard S. (1928– )
of Global Social Order (1997) and World Risk Society
(1999). Although Beck is now specifically identified with the debate about risk and environmental
politics, his theory of individualization examines
the breakdown and fragmentation of the institutions that were integral to industrial capitalism,
such as the family and love, in The Normal Chaos
of Love (Beck and Elisabeth Beck-Gernsheim, 1990
[trans. 1995]). Individualization should not be
confused with neo-liberal individualism but with
the “disembedding” of individuals from social
structures. Individual identities are no longer defined by the secure structures of social class,
social status, family, and neighborhood. This perspective is applied to a variety of social phenomena in Beck and Beck-Gernsheim, Individualization
(2002). In his most recent work, he has considered
the possibility of cosmopolitanism in relation to
globalization.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Becker, Howard S. (1928– )
Becker’s work has spanned symbolic interactionism, deviance, sociology of the arts, occupations,
education, medical work, and the techniques of
writing. Perhaps most popularly known for his
work on deviance in Outsiders (1963), Becker’s
studies were conducted at the University of Chicago where, taught by Everett Hughes (1897–
1983), he was part of the second generation of
the Chicago School. Taking inspiration from
Georg Simmel, as well as Robert E. Park and
Hughes, Becker’s perspective treats social life as
the result of the work people do. This focus deals
with learning, cooperation, and convention.
In his article “On Becoming a Marijuana User”
(1953, American Journal of Sociology), Becker pushed
this approach into the study of embodied perception, emphasizing the role that learning plays
in structuring the psychosomatic experience of
a drug’s effects and perceived value. His 1982
work, Art Worlds, tapped his own experience as a
jazz pianist and applied the focus on collective
action to the making and valuing of artistic products, proposing artworks and their reputations as
the outcome of networks of personnel, conventions, organizational patterns of distribution,
funding and consumption, materials and technologies. In emphasizing this middle level of
social organization – networks – Art Worlds inaugurated a new mode of inquiry in arts sociology
and simultaneously provided a model for how to
investigate creative work in other areas such as
science. In these respects Becker’s work has affinities with Bruno Latour’s work on science, such as
Science in Action (1987).
TIA DENORA
33
behaviorism
behaviorism
An explanation of behavior, this perspective goes
back at least to René Descartes (1596–1650),
for whom animals were machines responding
automatically to pleasurable or painful stimuli.
Similarly, David Hartley (1705–57) noted, in Observations on Man (1749), that “the fingers of young
children bend upon almost every impression made
upon the palm of the hand, this performing the act
of grasping, in the original automatic manner.” In
the modern era, behaviorism is classically associated with lvan Pavlov’s (1849–1936) dogs salivating
at the sound of a bell. They are responding, machine-like, to a stimulus associated with food.
This view of behaviorism has been challenged.
Burrhus Frederic Skinner (1904–90), the psychologist most associated with behaviorism, argued that
the study of observed behavior needed to penetrate
beyond mere reflexes. A person is a “locus,” a point
at which biological and environmental conditions
combine to produce a behavioral effect. Factors
within the organism (including, most importantly,
learning processes) combine with environmental
stimuli to generate behavior.
George Herbert Mead (1863–1931) is usually
considered the prime social behaviorist. He
insisted on recognizing social interactions and
the distinctive mental and linguistic capacities of
humans. Language and gestures within a social
group intervene between stimulus and response,
interaction making human identity.
Behaviorism has therefore moved beyond a
simple stimulus–response model to include learning behaviors, interaction, and internal behavioral propensities. It remains, however, an
example of empiricism, resisting theories seen as
speculative and insufficiently based on evidence.
For these reasons, it resists theories of the self (for
example, those of Sigmund Freud) which argue for
underlying, but not directly experienced, structures to human nature. Similarly, behaviorism
underplays the influence of social structure and
power on individual behavior.
PETER DICKENS
Bell, Daniel (1919– )
Bell’s extensive body of work has made a major
contribution to many areas of sociological inquiry, including social change and modernity,
the evolution of capitalism, and the dynamics
and conflicts within western culture. Born in
New York, he is a graduate of City College, and
became a prominent Harvard academic and social
commentator. He is probably best known as a
theorist of postindustrial society, and as someone
34
Bell, Daniel (1919– )
who anticipated many contemporary economic
and cultural trends associated with postmodernism. His best-known works are The End of Ideology
(1960), The Coming of Post-Industrial Society (1973),
and The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism (1976).
The End of Ideology advanced the notion that a
historical epoch dominated by grand ideological
conflict had come to an end as a result of the
successes of western democratic politics and capitalism. This reflected an epoch of optimistic confidence that seemingly intractable conflicts that
had dominated the nineteenth and much of the
twentieth century could and had been overcome.
Neither Karl Marx’s prognosis of endemic class
conflict (see social class) nor Max Weber’s discussion of the iron cage of rationalized bureaucratic
domination had come about.
Criticized for complacency and exclusion of
Third World perspectives, Bell responded to the
social changes and upheavals of the late 1960s
and early 1970s with two more critical contributions to sociological analysis. In The Coming of
Post-Industrial Society, subtitled A Venture in Social
Forecasting, he diagnosed a shift from an industrially based to an information-driven, serviceoriented postindustrial society. This elevated the
role of knowledge and knowledge-holders as new
and dominant elements within structures of
power and social stratification. Professionals
rather than entrepreneurs occupied the key positions in the new social order. This argument
marked an early and influential statement of
what became known as new class theory. Bell did
not invent the idea of postindustrial society,
which had been around throughout the twentieth
century; rather he gave this concept a greater
focus and analytical rigor. Similarly, his emphasis
on knowledge and social structure, while drawing
on earlier thinkers like C.-H. Saint-Simon and
Weber, was less speculative and better grounded
in empirical complexities than that of his
predecessors.
The newly emerging postindustrial structure,
investigated further by Bell in The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism, pursued the theme of the
evolving social structure and cultural formations
of western nations. A key idea here was that of a
profound cultural cleavage between the realms of
production and consumption. While the former
depended on the work ethic and deferred gratification, the latter elevated hedonism and personal
fulfillment as the overriding values. This argument disputed the contention, associated with
Talcott Parsons, that western social systems could
bell curve
be integrated around a relatively stable set of
normative frameworks. For Bell, by contrast, the
moral foundations of capitalism would remain
shaky and uncertain. In this way, Bell anticipated
certain postmodern arguments against the unitary
nature of social order.
ROBERT HOLTON
bell curve
– see intelligence.
Bellah, Robert N. (1927– )
Elliott Professor of Sociology Emeritus at the University of California, Berkeley, and born in Los
Angeles, Bellah attended undergraduate and
graduate school at Harvard University, receiving
his PhD in Sociology in 1955. He taught at Harvard
in 1957–67, moving thereafter to his position at
Berkeley.
Bellah’s work has centered on the sociology
of religion and cultural sociology. His earliest
book, Tokugawa Religion (1955), explored Japanese
religion in a comparative framework. In Beyond
Belief (1970), he wrote on a variety of religious
traditions, viewing religion not as an objective
set of timeless truths, but as an attempt to find
meaning in the modern world. In The Broken Covenant (1975), a very controversial work, Bellah
discussed the idea of civic religion in the United
States. He argued that abstract but shared
religious values give American ideas such as
the republic and liberty a sacred dimension.
Critics accused him of collapsing the distinction
between religion and politics, a criticism rejected
by Bellah.
Bellah has continued his concern with the
moral life of Americans in his recent works, Habits
of the Heart (1985) and The Good Society (1991), both
written with Richard Madsen, William Sullivan,
Ann Swidler, and Steven Tipton. Bellah finds that
American democratic institutions are threatened
by a powerful and widespread belief that selfinterest and self-expression are the essence of freedom. He thinks that Americans have difficulty
grasping the interdependency of the contemporary world and the complexity of many of their
basic values, including the meaning of success,
freedom, and justice. Bellah states that many
Americans have trouble conceptualizing and acting on these issues because they assume that
individuals are isolated from their social and
cultural contexts. For Bellah, this is a fiction.
Most Americans are profoundly involved in social
relationships that entail community and caring,
yet they lack a language that articulates the
richness of their commitments to one another.
Bendix, Reinhard (1916–1991)
Bellah states that Americans lack such insight
into their communal obligations and experience
because they have privileged their individualistic
cultural beliefs over other aspects of their cultural
life and traditions. Yet these communal themes
run deep in American history. He labels these
communal traditions republicanism – which advocates a society based on political equality and
participatory self-government – and the biblical
tradition – which posits a good society as a community in which a genuinely ethical and spiritual
life can be lived. Bellah calls for a resurrection and
rethinking of the biblical and republican traditions, which he sees manifested in Americans’
desire for meaningful work, their wish to make a
difference in the world, and their devotion to
family and friends which often overshadows their
commitments to work. For Bellah, these traditions
represent an ideal of a community of participatory
individuals who have strong ethical bonds with
one another. American institutions, from work to
government, must change so that people do not
view them as hindrances to self-development. Individuals must be able to grasp the interconnection
of personal and public welfare, so that they can
actively participate in shaping their lives.
KENNETH H. TUCKER
Bendix, Reinhard (1916–1991)
A German-born sociologist who emigrated to the
United States in 1938, Bendix taught at the University of Chicago from 1943 to 1946, and then,
following a short stint at Colorado, at Berkeley.
Bendix’s work on political theory and historical
and comparative sociology fused theoretical depth
with expansive empirical detail. He wrote three
major historical-comparative books: Work and Authority in Industry (1956), which examined the role
of bureaucracy; Nation Building and Citizenship
(1964), which followed T. H. Marshall’s arguments
concerning working-class incorporation into
modern society; and Kings and People (1978), which
expanded on Weber’s famous distinction between
feudal and patrimonial authority. He was, however, most well known for his penetrating intellectual biography of Max Weber (1960), which
provided an alternative reading to the then dominant Parsonian interpretation of the German
thinker.
In Social Science and the Distrust of Reason (1951)
and later works such as the two-volume Embattled
Reason (1988–9) and From Berlin to Berkeley (1986), he
advocated responsible partisanship which balanced scientific scholarship with humanistic
ideals. He also edited two influential books with
35
Benjamin, Walter (1892–1940)
Berger, Peter L. (1929– )
Seymour M. Lipset: Class, Status and Power (1953)
and Social Mobility in Industrial Society (1959).
masses, the phenomenal life of the commodity,
and the transformations in perception of things.
STEVEN LOYAL
DAVID FRISBY
Benjamin, Walter (1892–1940)
Berger, Peter L. (1929– )
Although not a sociologist and initially recognized
more as literary critic and philosopher, the
German theorist Walter Benjamin has had a significant impact upon aspects of sociology in recent
decades. Perhaps most widespread has been the
debate upon and extension of his reflections on
“the work of art in the age of its mechanical reproducibility.” In his essay of that title (1969; 2002)
[1936] and elsewhere, Benjamin argued that,
whereas the traditional work of art possessed auratic qualities, the result of its uniqueness and authenticity, mechanical reproduction of images and
art works removed their auratic qualities and potentially opened up democratic possibilities. Benjamin’s interest in the technologies of image and art
work reproduction led him to explore the media of
film, photography, radio, and new modes of operating with existing media such as modern drama
and the press. This interest in images accords
with his assertion that an important feature of
modernity is the huge proliferation of images.
More recently, the translation of his massive,
unfinished prehistory of modernity, the Arcades
Project (1999), on which he worked for over a
decade collecting images, descriptions and evidence, has been influential. This project focused
in a radical manner upon Paris as capital of the
nineteenth century and was intended as an excavation of modernity that would be crucially relevant to our contemporary experience. Defining
modernity as a world dominated by illusion and
fantasy (“phantasmagorias”), and especially the
illusion of the “new,” Benjamin maintained that
the origins of modernity lay embedded in the
nineteenth century. Their excavation was to be
approached methodologically through attention
to the fragments, the refuse of the past in our
present, through the construction of dialectical
images that would force the past into our present,
through a critique of the dream-world of historicism, and through awakening from the illusions
of modernity. The investigation of the origins of
modernity were to be undertaken by the partly
metaphorical figures of the archaeologist / critical
allegorist, the collector/ragpicker, and the flâneur/
detective. The new reading of the city as text
revealed the transformations in experience of
modernity through a rich construction of the
city, commencing with its arcades, and moving
through to its streets, the bourgeois interior, the
Born in Vienna, Berger moved to the United States
after World War II and is currently a professor at
Boston University. Berger’s contribution to sociology is prolific and extensive but he is most renowned for his writings on religion and
secularization, and for the phenomenological
understanding of social life articulated in The
Social Construction of Reality (1966), coauthored
with Thomas Luckmann. In this highly influential
book, Berger emphasized what today might seem
an obvious point – that society is a product of
human design – but which in the 1960s, a time
when sociologists primarily emphasized the determining power of large-scale impersonal social
structures (for example, capitalism) and processes
(for example, modernization), was highly innovative. Berger’s focus on everyday life and the pragmatic constraints of living in the “here and now”
was quite radical. It made scholars and students
alike pay attention to the small but potent ways in
which ordinary people get on with, make sense of,
organize, and find meaning in the everyday reality
that confronts them. Berger’s emphasis on the
thoroughly social foundation of institutions, and
the possibility that institutional and social change
emerges when the taken-for-granted institutional
routines no longer make sense in a particular
social context, opened up an emancipatory view
of human (social) agency, but one, clearly, that
recognized that humans as social beings – the
products too of society – are always in interaction
with socially institutionalized ways of organizing
collective life, for example, language. The dialectic
by which humans engage the objective, socially
created external world, and in turn internalize
and act on that external reality provides a highly
dynamic model of the interactive power of institutional structures and individual consciousness
and meaning in the construction of social life.
One of Berger’s core interests has been how the
religious domain, itself the product of human
design rather than divine blueprint, allows individuals to impose order on the chaos of everyday
reality. Religion provides like-minded individuals
who interact together within a symbolic universe
of shared beliefs, symbols, and meanings with an
overarching Sacred Canopy (1967), which facilitates
the plausibility of their sense-making and thus
enhances their social integration. But, as Berger
noted, in modern society – with its rationally
36
Bernstein, Basil (1924–2000)
differentiated institutional spheres and cultural
processes – religion is but one of many competing
universes of meaning; science and art, for
example, are other (often conflicting) sources of
shared meaning in society. Within the religious
sphere, moreover, Berger argued, the plurality
of denominations and choices available reduces
the plausibility or the certainty of any one
individual’s beliefs (or choices).
Berger was a leading proponent of secularization, seeing it as an inevitable and global phenomenon of modernization and the necessary loss of
domination of religious institutions and symbols
over social institutions, culture, and individual
consciousness. Although he acknowledged that
secularization did not proceed uniformly across
all societies or across all sectors of society, he
nonetheless argued that any continuing symbolic
power of churches would necessarily rest on
churches becoming more secularized themselves.
In recent years, however, Berger has revised his
earlier thesis in Christian Century (1997), stating
that most of the world today is not secular but
very religious. Berger’s Invitation to Sociology (1963)
remains an influential and accessible introduction to sociology.
MICHELE DILLON
Bernstein, Basil (1924–2000)
Within the British tradition of empirical sociology,
Bernstein was unusual in being open to the philosophical currents in “continental” thought. His
early reading of Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945), Benjamin Whorf (1877–1957), Lev Vygotsky (1896–1934),
and Alexander Luria (1902–77), and his knowledge
of the work of Émile Durkheim, caused him to
become primarily concerned with how cultural
and linguistic frames of thinking mold our experience of the world. Before and after studying at the
London School of Economics after World War II,
Bernstein had experience of working and teaching
in socially deprived parts of east London. His combination of theoretical interest with concrete experience of non-traditional or non-academic
contexts fostered the research which he undertook and inspired at the Sociological Research
Unit at the Institute of Education of the University
of London from 1963 until his death. During this
period he was responsible for the production of a
series of studies under the general title of Class,
Codes and Control (1971, 1973, 1975). Both the first
and the third volumes of this series reprinted his
seminal article entitled: “On the Classification
and Framing of Educational Knowledge.” Bernstein was responsible for drawing attention to
the correlation between class difference and the
biologism
capacity of people to draw upon “restricted” or
“extended” linguistic codes. He was necessarily
interested in pedagogical practices, and it is
significant that his research provided a basis
for examining sociologically the function of
schooling, at a time when thinking about education was still dominated in the United Kingdom by
philosophers, and when opposition to schooling
was expressed in the de-schooling movement.
DEREK ROBBINS
bias
Bias refers to those aspects of the social research
process that may skew the findings in some way.
The main identified sources of bias concern the
researcher or informant, the measurement instruments or methods, and the sampling procedures.
Biased measures fail to do a good job of measuring
the things they are purported to measure and
therefore lack validity. Biased samples are not
representative of the relevant population or set
of cases they are meant to reflect.
The issue of whether or not one can eliminate
bias is contested. Some argue that to eliminate all
sources of bias is to purge research of human life.
From this viewpoint, the task of the researcher is
not to eliminate bias but to be reflexive about
potential distortions of accounts. Others disagree
and stress that it is the researcher’s duty to make
every effort to eliminate or minimize distortion in
the research process.
The dispute arises because the meaning of bias
is ambiguous. The notion that bias is a systematic
deviation from a true score is problematic because
concepts such as “truth” or “objectivity” sit uneasily with the study of the social world, where
“truths” differ across time and place. It is less
problematic to define bias as systematic errors
that distort the research process. The main safeguard against such systematic distortions is that
others in the community of scholars will challenge biased research. For example, feminist
scholars have played an invaluable role in challenging pervasive sexism in sociological concepts and
JACKIE SCOTT
measures.
biological reductionism
– see biologism.
biologism
In its strongest form, this perspective suggests
that the social position of social classes or ethnic
groups (see ethnicity) largely stems from genetically inherited levels of intelligence. Similarly, the
high levels of child-care or domestic work
37
biopolitics
conducted by women are an expression of their
innate caring capacities. As with social Darwinism,
such arguments clearly suggest that power and
inequality are mainly a product of an inherent
human nature. Criminality too is sometimes
seen as a product of biological inheritance.
Biologism, in its crudest forms, is a thinly veiled
ideology in which white males have exercised
power over women, nonwhites, and others. Such
pseudoscience is clearly unacceptable. On the
other hand, blank rejection of the natural sciences
by sociologists runs the risk of throwing out the
biological baby with the bathwater. Humans, like
all animals, remain a natural datum. Their biological structures and potentials must be related,
however loosely and distantly, to their behaviors,
social positions, and identities. Biological and
psychic mechanisms are certainly overlaid with,
or “overdetermined” by, social relations, but this
cannot mean that biological mechanisms can
never offer explanatory purchase. Social institutions and social structures may be realizing or
suppressing biologically based structures and capacities in complex and varied ways which are not
well understood.
Sociologists are therefore right to criticize extreme forms of biologism. But they must also
guard against charges of “sociologism,” a denial
of biological or psychic bases to human behavior
and/or crude assumptions about the plasticity of
the human body and human nature. Neither sociology nor biology can offer total explanations, and
dogmatic charges of “biologism” could result in
the premature closure of transdisciplinary analysis. Despite a legacy of suspicion, sociology must
remain open to contributions from the natural
sciences.
PETER DICKENS
biopolitics
A general term referring to the way biology intersects with politics, commerce, the law, and morality; more specifically, the term refers to the
contentious politics and conflicts concerned with
nature and the environment. Environmentalism
and animal rights are two social movements
whose cognitive and political praxis can be characterized as forms of biopolitics.
The term has a more specified meaning in what
is called the “transhumanist movement.” The
phrase was first coined by James Hughes, an
American professor, to refer to a pro-technological
outlook which takes the Luddites as its polar opposite. As a form of biopolitics, transhumanism is
a movement towards a posthuman or cyborg society. Leading social theorists associated with the
38
biotechnology
concept are Michel Foucault, Donna Haraway,
and Peter Singer.
RON EYERMAN
biotechnology
This term is used to describe a process through
which biological materials are modified. Specifically, it refers to the use or development of
techniques employing living organisms, such as
cells and bacteria, in industrial or commercial
processes.
The field of biotechnology not only integrates a
number of disciplines, drawing on molecular
biology, biochemistry, cell biology, microbiology,
genetics, immunology, and bioinformatics, it also
employs a range of different techniques and technologies including, among others, DNA sequencing, the polymerase chain reaction, and microand macro-injection. Although interventions such
as the selective breeding of plants and animals
and the use of yeast to make bread have been
taking place for centuries, the term biotechnology
is associated with more recent developments, such
as the late twentieth-century breakthroughs in molecular biology, genetic engineering, and the current convergence of science and technology aided
by bioinformatics.
The birth of modern biotechnology is generally
dated to the early 1970s when American scientists
developed recombinant DNA techniques. This is a
method for transferring genes from one organism
to another unrelated organism. Since then, a
number of other technologies have been developed
leading to innovations such as genetically modified foods, stem cell research, and gene therapy.
A new industry sector has been built up around
biotechnology. This sector is playing a critical role
in knowledge transfer, where knowledge from
universities is transferred into commercial applications, and contributing to the emerging, global
knowledge-based economy. Biotechnology companies tend to be recent start-ups established by
researchers from universities or research institutes, funded by venture capitalists, and having
extensive networks of research alliances and collaborators. They are usually built up around a
single idea backed up by patents, with few, if any,
products on the market. Biotech firms often initiate drug development, selling their products to
large pharmaceutical companies which continue
with the process of bringing the drug to market.
In drug development, biotech firms commonly
rely on continual investments from venture capitalists and bankers for an eight- to ten-year period
before the products are realized or larger pharmaceutical companies acquire the firm.
biotechnology
Since the first biotech firms were established in
the late 1970s, the industry has expanded rapidly.
The subsequent successful production of cloned
genes for producing proteins that enabled the
production of new pharmaceutical drugs and agricultural applications prompted massive governmental investments in the United States, Europe,
and emerging markets around the world.
As with recent developments in genetics, biotechnology has been heralded by scientists, policymakers, and the business world as having the
potential to bring about new and revolutionary
changes for both society and the global economy.
A system of intellectual property rights, and
global regimes to protect them, has been deployed
in relation to biotech discoveries. A number of
sociologists have drawn attention to both the
ever-increasing blurring of boundaries between
the private and public sectors, and the propensity
for biotechnological development to be subject to
excessive hyperbole. Notions of a biotechnology
revolution underpinned by scientific, governmental, and regional policy initiatives designed to
bring about the twin objectives of wealth and
health creation have generated widespread expectations about the rapid impact of biotechnology. Sociologists highlight the ways in which
promoters of new technologies build expectations
through the creation and citation of technological
visions. Social scientists Paul Nightingale and
Paul Martin demonstrate in their article “The
Myth of the Biotech Revolution” (2004, Trends in
Biotechnology), that, counter to expectations of a
revolutionary model of innovation, biotechnology
innovation is instead following a historically
well-established process of slow and incremental
change. These commentators note that most research fields can be seen to move through various
cycles of hype and disappointment, expressing
tensions between generative visions on the one
hand and the material “messiness” of innovation
on the other.
While governments worldwide are pursuing
ambitious and competitive programs to foster
bioscience-based industries, the prominence of
biotechnological processes and innovation has
prompted sociologists to grapple with the associated myriad social, political, and ethical issues.
Issues such as the impact of biotechnologies on
individuals and society, the altering of boundaries
between nature and culture, and questions about
human nature have all captured sociologists’ attention. Risk in the form of the consequences of
genetic engineering or genetic modification of
human and other living organisms has also been
biotechnology
a subject of substantial debate for scholars. The
concept of a risk society, as argued by Ulrich Beck,
has been drawn on by some sociologists analyzing
such risks.
There is also concern that genetic engineering of
humans in the form of gene therapy, where faulty
genes are either repaired or replaced, might alter
the germline cells (those cells that have genetic
material that may be passed on via reproduction
to a child) and irreversibly change the genetic
make-up of future generations. In The Future of
Human Nature (2001), Jürgen Habermas, for
example, argues that genetic engineering, along
with other forms of genetic enhancements, should
be forbidden, as such alterations undermine what
it is to be human. Other scholars have argued that
decisions about whether or not to pursue such
developments should be premised on democratically accountable mechanisms. Others again have
been more optimistic about the potential biotechnology provides to move beyond a nature/culture
opposition and develop life-enhancing reconfigurations that provide the means to overcome
our biological, neurological, and psychological
limitations.
Controversies over genetically modified foods,
cloning, and stem cell research have become
major flashpoints in the political and public
arenas. Sociologists, particularly those specializing in science and technology studies, have drawn
attention to the contested and uncertain nature
of science. Public opposition to genetically modified foods has furthered debates on public understanding of science, the role of democracy, and
the necessity for governance and regulation.
While policymakers and scientists frequently suggest such opposition is based on a public deficit of
scientific knowledge, social scientists refute this.
For example, Brian Wynne in his article “Public
Uptake of Science: A Case for Institutional Reflexivity” (1993, Public Understanding of Science), claims
that the public understands only too well the
provisional nature of scientific knowledge and
are aware that problems can emerge in the future
that are in the present unknown. More recently,
in response to a perceived breakdown in the public’s trust in science, attempts have been made by
science-funding agencies, policymakers, and governmental bodies to adopt public engagement
strategies. These strategies are often presented as
part of a more inclusive democratic process of
government and entail such activities as setting
up citizens’ juries and carrying out surveys and
public consultation exercises. Such work is often
undertaken by sociologists and other social
39
Birmingham Centre
scientists. Some scholars suggest that this is evidence of the emergence of new forms of biological
or scientific citizenship and represents a more
participatory or deliberative form of democracy.
Others are more skeptical and claim that such
exercises are designed to stave off the kind of
public opposition that has thwarted the deployment of genetically modified foodstuffs in Europe
and other western countries. O O N A G H C O R R I G A N
Birmingham Centre for Contemporary
Cultural Studies
Opened in 1964, the Centre for Contemporary
Cultural Studies (CCCS) was founded at the University of Birmingham by Richard Hoggart. Stuart
Hall was recruited as Hoggart’s partner to manage
the day-to-day affairs of the Centre. His contribution rapidly made the climate of work in the
Centre more theoretical and political. CCCS was
an anti-elitist, postgraduate teaching and research
institution. Initially, it was organized intellectually around a tripartite division between literary, historical-philosophical, and sociological
research. However, the historical–philosophical
and sociological elements soon took precedence,
especially after 1970 when Hoggart left to take up
a post in UNESCO.
Under Hall’s leadership, work gravitated towards the central issue of the articulation of
power. This was chiefly examined at the cultural
level by the attempt to fuse native traditions of
“culturalism” with continental “structuralism.”
Culturalism was a version of cultural materialism
committed to examining “the whole way of life”
of a social class. In contrast to elitist approaches,
it emphasized the “ordinary” character of culture.
Politically, it was a variant of left-wing humanism.
During the Birmingham heyday, while their work
differed in many important particulars, the chief
representatives of this tradition were recognized
as Raymond Williams, Edward Thompson, and
Richard Hoggart. Hall’s reservations about culturalism centered on its tendency to privilege agency
over structure, its neglect of questions of reflexivity, its under-developed interest in the positioning
of agency, and its general anti-theoreticism. The
most ambitious and defining project in Birmingham lay in the attempt to graft continental structuralism, embodied above all in the work of
Antonio Gramsci, Louis Althusser, and Karl Marx,
on to the native tradition of culturalism. Structuralism was held to offer theoretical determinacy,
an emphasis on totality, and a recurring interest
in the articulation of ideology through praxis.
40
Birmingham Centre
This project was developed along several fronts.
Arguably, the work on British state formation, the
formation of ideology, schooling as cultural resistance, policing and the drift to the law and order
society, encoding and decoding in mass communications, and the politics of hegemony was of most
enduring influence.
In 1979 Hall left to become Professor of Sociology at the Open University. Although the Centre
continued, it never regained the public profile or
intellectual prominence that it achieved under
his leadership. Despite maintaining a sound
record of student recruitment, it was closed by
the University in 2002, allegedly in response to
a disappointing performance in the national Research Assessment Exercise.
The principal achievements of the Centre are
threefold. At the theoretical level, it synthesized
a rich range of native and continental traditions
to examine cultural articulations of power. In
doing so, it broke decisively with elitist perspectives on culture and related the question of articulation to divisions of class, gender, and race and
ethnicity. The sophisticated use of culture to elucidate praxis was seminal in the emergence of cultural studies.
At the political level, it twinned culture with
politics. Hall’s model of intellectual labor was
borrowed from Gramsci’s concept of the organic
intellectual, that is, an individual who set out to
operate as a switch-point between cutting-edge
ideas and political activism. Following Althusser,
the state was identified as the pre-eminent institution of normative coercion. The analysis of the
historical role of the British state in managing
dissent and the consistent analytic relation of
the state’s “war of maneuver” to ordinary cultural
forms and practice was compelling and moldbreaking. This work was crucial in developing
the model of authoritarian populism that Hall
developed in the 1980s to explain working-class
support for Thatcherism.
At the pedagogic level, the emphasis on collaborative research between staff and postgraduates,
and the self-image of developing the curriculum
of Cultural studies, provided a compelling nonhierarchical, dialogic model of teaching and research. The Centre was one of the major training
grounds for the study of culture in the twentieth
century and has some claim to be regarded as
pivotal in the development of Cultural studies
and the cultural turn in sociology. Among its
alumni are Charlotte Brundson, Paul Gilroy, Lawrence Grossberg, Dick Hebdige, Gregor McLennan,
Angela McRobbie, David Morley, and Paul Willis.
black economy
The major figures in the Birmingham diaspora
retain a powerful global influence in protecting
and enhancing the heritage and perspectives developed in the 1960s and 1970s.
The weaknesses of the Birmingham tradition
inversely reflect its achievements. Conceived as a
series of projects located at the periphery of the
academy and elite culture, the work of the Centre
gradually migrated to the core. It set agendas of
discourse and research rather than critically responding to them. This exposed underlying faults
in the project.
First, in opening up the subjects of culture and
articulation to serious academic enquiry, the
Centre progressively surrendered a tenable political focus. Tensions with feminist students in the
late 1970s raised awkward questions about the
limitations of reflexivity and persistence of ideology in the Centre’s ordinary activities. The reaction was to be more responsive to feminist and
psychoanalytic traditions. This invited criticism
that the Centre was over-willing to embrace
intellectual fashion and added to the confusion
about the practical political objectives of the Birmingham project.
Second, the engagement with popular culture
became so entwined with questions of theoretical
relevance that the analysis became forbiddingly
abstract. Key concepts, such as articulation, conjuncture, enunciation, hegemony, and ideology,
were often used inconsistently and with different
inflections. The Centre’s work became vulnerable
to the charge of conceptual slippage and intellectual incoherence. These criticisms were intensified by Hall’s work after the 1980s, in which the
notion of unity in difference became prominent.
Many commentators have found this to be elusive
and obscure.
Third, the balance of cultural articulation was
heavily skewed to the roles of the state and social
divisions of class, race, and gender. The Centre
evinced a remarkable failure to investigate the
culture of the corporation, and its analysis of
the mass media never extended beyond encoding,
decoding, and media amplification. Although
Hall and his associates accurately predicted the
rise of the New Right in Britain, they failed to
anticipate the significance of globalization for
critical analysis.
CHRIS ROJEK
black economy
– see informal economy.
black studies
– see African-American Studies.
Blumer, Herbert (1900–1987)
Blau, Peter M. (1918–2002)
A prolific sociological theorist and researcher,
Blau made important contributions to exchange
theory, and to the study of complex organizations
and social stratification. Born in Vienna, he narrowly escaped Nazi Europe on the last civilian
boat to leave France, arriving penniless in New
York in 1939. Blau studied for a doctorate at Columbia University with Robert Merton. He was professor at the University of Chicago from 1953 to
1970, then at Columbia University from 1970 to
1988. He held numerous distinguished visiting
positions and was President of the American
Sociological Association in 1974.
Blau’s Dynamics of Bureaucracy (1955) developed
Merton’s approach to functionalism, showing how
innovation occurred in the enactment of rules of
formal organizations. This was followed by a
major work in the comparative theory of organizations, coauthored with Richard Scott, Formal Organizations (1963). With functionalism under
criticism for its neglect of concrete individual
actors, Blau turned to the micro-foundations of
structural analyses in Exchange and Power in Social
Life (1964). He acknowledged the criticism that
exchange theory was frequently narrowly utilitarian, elaborating normative principles of reciprocity and justice alongside rationality and
marginal utility in order to understand both conflict and integration within social relationships.
Together with Otis Dudley Duncan, he produced a
landmark study of stratification, American Occupational Structure (1967). This combined a sophisticated theoretical model of social status
attainment with innovative techniques of data
analysis to study trends in social mobility; it is a
classic of American empirical sociology. He continued to work on micro–macro theory in the later
part of his career, publishing Structural Contexts of
Opportunities (1994), in which he reformulated exchange theory to allow emergent properties of
social structures that constrained opportunities.
JOHN HOLMWOOD
Blumer, Herbert (1900–1987)
Though Blumer was theoretically a symbolic interactionist, his major writings were in the areas of
race relations (see race and ethnicity), labor and
management conflict, urbanization, and popular
culture, represented in his Selected Works (2000),
which were appropriately subtitled A Public Philosophy for Mass Society. Empirically, he remained
true to the Chicago style of ethnographic study
(see Chicago School): his forte was the detailed
empirical observation of the ways in which
41
body
body
whatever subjects were under scrutiny went about
sustaining and negotiating meaning. For Blumer,
people act on the basis of the meanings that they
impute to situations, which they build up over
time by the use of language in social interaction
with others. In this way, they develop a sense both
of their self and the other, often through the
process of seeing themselves as the other might –
taking the role of the other. Just as social interaction is processual, the sense of the self that one
has is also built and changed processually: there is
no inherent identity – only that which the self
makes up in interactions with others. Blumer did
not see the meaning of any act as inherent in
the act itself but as socially constructed by the
responses that such acts elicit and the flow of
interaction in anticipation of future acts. Thus,
while meaning may attach to quite tangible
phenomena, such as a building or a river, or
to something quite intangible, such as justice or
discrimination, what that meaning is constituted
as being is always an effect of the meanings that
society sustains, contests, and frames over time.
STEWART CLEGG
body
From the 1980s, there has been growing interest in
the sociology of the body as illustrated by B. Turner
in The Body and Society (1984), M. Featherstone,
M. Hepworth, and B. Turner in The Body. Social
Process and Cultural Theory (1991), and C. Shilling
in The Body and Social Theory (1993). Over a longer
period, there was an erratic interest in the body
among sociologists such as Erving Goffman in
Stigma (1964), and Norbert Elias in The Civilizing
Process (1939 [trans. 1978]) in which Elias explored
the regulation of bodily practices. However, contemporary interest appears to be driven by significant changes in society relating to consumption,
cultural representations, medical science, and
health. Scientific and technological advances, particularly the new reproductive technologies (see
reproduction), cloning techniques, and stem-cell
research have given the human body a problematic legal and social status. The social world is
being transformed by genetic and medical technologies that reconstruct social, especially kinship, relationships, and create the possibility of
genetically modified bodies and “designer babies.”
In particular, assisted reproduction is changing
the generative connections between parents and
children, and reconstructing the family as an institution of reproduction. In addition, aging (see
age), disease, and death and dying no longer
appear to be immutable facts about the human
42
condition, but contingent possibilities that are
constantly transformed by medical sciences. The
development of regenerative medicine and the
use of stem cell research to offset the negative
side-effects of aging and chronic disease hold out
the utopian promise of living forever, or at least
extending life expectancy considerably.
The emergence of the body as a research topic in
the humanities and social sciences is a response to
these technological and scientific changes, and to
the diverse social movements that are associated
with them, such as gay and lesbian movements,
environmentalism, and anti-globalism on the one
side, and religious fundamentalism, pro-life movements, and conservative cultural politics on the
other. More importantly, the human body, or
more specifically its genetic code, is now a key
factor in economic growth in a wide range of
biotech industries. In a paradoxical manner, the
pathology of the human body is itself a productive
factor in the new economy. Disease is no longer
simply a constraint on the productivity of labor,
but an actual factor of production. The body is
increasingly a code or system of information
from which economic profits can be extracted
through patents, rather than merely a natural
organism. In his Our Posthuman Future, Francis
Fukuyama (2002) has claimed that the biotechnology revolution will transform the nature of
politics by changing human life.
Different philosophical and sociological traditions have shaped contemporary approaches to
the body. Firstly, the body is often discussed as a
cultural representation of social organization. For
example, the head is often used as a metaphor
of government, and the word “corporation” to
describe the modern company has its origins in
such bodily metaphors. In this sociological tradition, research on the body is concerned to understand how the body enters into political discourse
as a representation of power, and how power is
exercised over the body. This approach to the body
is associated with Michel Foucault, whose work on
the discipline of the body in Discipline and Punish.
The Birth of the Prison (1975 [trans. 1977]) gave rise
to research on the government of the body in
schools, prisons, and factories. This approach to
the body was therefore concerned with questions
of representation and regulation in which diet, for
example, is a method used in Turner’s Regulating
Bodies (1992). The Foucauldian perspective is not
concerned with understanding our experiences of
embodiment; it is not concerned with grasping
the lived experience of the body in terms of a
phenomenology of the body. The starting point
body
for the study of the “lived body” has been the
research of the French philosopher Maurice
Merleau-Ponty in Phenomenology of Perception (1945
[trans. 1982]), which examined how the perception
of reality always occurs from the particular location of our body. Merleau-Ponty showed how our
cognition of the world is always an embodied
perception. In short, phenomenology was a critique of the dualism of the mind and body, in
which the body is passive and inert. Research inspired by this idea of the lived body has been
important in showing the intimate connections
between body, experience and identity.
In addition, there is an influential anthropological tradition, which examines the body as a
symbolic system. The dominant figure in this tradition is the British anthropologist Mary Douglas,
whose Purity and Danger: An Analysis of Concepts of
Pollution and Taboo (1966) shaped subsequent research. Douglas showed how notions of pollution
were associated with uncertainty and danger.
The body provides human society with metaphors
of social stability and order by defining areas of
ambiguity. In this sense, we use the body as a
method of thinking about society. In anthropology, there is another tradition, however, that has
examined how human beings are embodied and
how they acquire a variety of cultural practices
that are necessary for walking, sitting, dancing,
and so forth. The study of embodiment has been
the concern of anthropologists who have been
influenced, in particular, by the work of Marcel
Mauss, who invented the concept of “body techniques” in the Journal de Psychologie Normale et
Pathologique (1935). This anthropological legacy encourages us to think about the body as a multitude of performances. These anthropological
assumptions have been developed in contemporary sociology by Pierre Bourdieu in terms of the
concepts of hexis and habitus, by which our dispositions and tastes are organized. For example,
within the everyday habitus of social classes,
Bourdieu showed in Distinction: A Social Critique of
the Judgement of Taste (1979 [trans. 1984]) that the
body is invested with symbolic capital (see social
capital) whereby the body is an expression of the
hierarchies of social power. The body is cultivated
within the particular habitus of social classes, and
it thus expresses the aesthetic preferences of different class positions. This form of distinction is
illustrated by the different types of sport which
are supported by different social classes, and
which require different types of embodiment. Obviously bodies that are developed for rugby may be
inappropriate for tennis, and these bodies express
body
the taste (the organization of preferences in a
habitus) of different social strata.
This development of interest in the body has
also involved a recovery of philosophical anthropology, especially the work of Arnold Gehlen
(1904–76). In Man: His Nature and Place in the World,
Gehlen (1940 [trans. 1988]) argued that human
beings are “not yet finished animals.” By this
notion, he meant that human beings are biologically poorly equipped to cope with the world into
which they are involuntarily born. They have no
finite or specific instinctual equipment for a given
environment, and therefore require a long period
of socialization in order to adapt themselves to
their social world. Human incompleteness provides an anthropological explanation for the
human origins of social institutions. Gehlen’s
work has been important in the development
of contemporary sociology, especially in, for
example, Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann’s
The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the
Sociology of Knowledge (1966).
The contemporary sociology of the body has been
further influenced by twentieth-century feminism.
Simone de Beauvoir’s The Second Sex (1949 [trans.
1972]) was indirectly a major contribution to the
study of the body, and in particular to the patriarchal regulation of the female body. She argued
that women are not born, but become women
through social and psychological processes that
construct them as essentially female. Her research
on human aging in Old Age (1970 [trans. 1977]) drew
attention to the social invisibility and powerlessness of older women. Her work inaugurated a tradition of research on the social production of
differences in gender and sexuality. Feminist theories of the body have been associated with social
constructionism, which posits that the differences
between male and female (bodies), that we take for
granted as if they were facts of nature, are socially
produced. Germaine Greer’s The Female Eunuch
(1971), Kate Millett’s Sexual Politics (1971), and Ann
Oakley’s Sex, Gender and Society (1972) were important in demonstrating the difference between
biologically determined sex and the social construction of gender roles and sexual identities.
The underlying theory of gender inequalities was
the idea of patriarchy, and much empirical research in sociology has subsequently explored
how the social and political subordination of
women is expressed somatically in psychological
depression and physical illness. Much of the creative work in this field went into research on anorexia nervosa, obesity, and eating disorders, such as
Susan Bordo’s Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western
43
body
Culture and the Body (1993). The popular literature
on this issue was influenced by Susan Orbach’s Fat
is a Feminist Issue (1984). More recently, there has
been increasing interest in the question of men’s
bodies and masculinity, for example in R. W. Connell’s Masculinities (1995).
Critics argue that one paradoxical consequence
of this feminist legacy has been that the emphasis
on the social construction of women’s bodies has
led to the absence of any concern with the lived
body and embodiment. For example, Judith
Butler, drawing on the work of the Marxist philosopher Louis Althusser, has argued in Bodies That
Matter (1993) that, in a social world dominated by
heterosexuality, bodies that matter are ones that
materialize in terms of this regulatory norm.
She argues that we must pay attention then to
the dominant discourses that interpellate
men and women into hierarchical positions in
society. In this approach, the body becomes
merely an element in the rhetorical construction
of gender relations in which the lived experience
of embodiment in daily practices is neglected.
The basic notion that the “naturalness” of the
human body is a social product has been applied
to an increasingly large array of topics. For
example, the sociological analysis of the body
has played a major role in the development of
the “social model” in disability studies in order
to make a distinction between disability and impairment in W. Seymour, Remaking the Body (1998) and
C. Barnes, G. Mercer, and T. Shakespeare, Exploring
Disability (1999). The sociological focus on the body
has also begun to transform the sociology of aging,
in, for example, C. A. Faircloth, Aging Bodies: Images
and Everyday Experience (2003). The sociology of the
body has also influenced dance studies, theories of
popular culture, and the study of sport, where
ethnographic studies have produced a rich collection of empirical studies of the body in society in,
for example, H. Thomas and J. Ahmed, Cultural
Bodies: Ethnography and Theory (2004).
By treating the body as a representation, discourse, or text, it becomes difficult to develop an
adequate sociology of performance. For example,
where dance studies have been influenced by
postmodernism and by the French philosopher
Gilles Deleuze (1925–95), there is little interest in
the ethnographic study of movement and performance, despite Deleuze’s emphasis on movement and event. From the perspective of
postmodern theory, bodily practice and action
become irrelevant to the understanding of the
body as cultural sign. For example, if sociologists
wanted to study ballet as performance rather than
44
Boudon, Raymond (1934– )
as representation, they would need to pay attention to the performing body. Richard Shusterman
in Performing Live (2000), drawing on the work of
Bourdieu and developing a pragmatist aesthetics
(see pragmatism and aesthetics) has argued that
an aesthetic understanding of performance such
as hip hop cannot neglect the embodied features
of artistic activity. The need for an understanding
of embodiment and lived experience is crucial in
understanding performing arts, but also for the
study of the body in sport. While choreography is
in one sense the text of the dance, performance
takes place outside the strict directions of the
choreographic work, and has an immediacy, which
cannot be captured by the idea of the body as text.
It is important to re-capture the intellectual contribution of the phenomenology of human embodiment in order to avoid the reduction of bodies
to cultural texts. The social differences between
men and women are consequences of culture,
but understanding two people doing the tango
requires some attention to bodily performances.
We might conclude therefore that there are two
dominant but separate traditions in the anthropology and sociological study of the body. There is
either the cultural decoding of the body as a
system of meaning that has a definite structure
existing separately from the intentions and conceptions of social actors, or there is the phenomenological study of embodiment that attempts to
understand human practices, and is concerned to
understand the body in relation to the life-course
(of birth, maturation, reproduction, and death).
Bourdieu’s theory of practice offers a possible solution to this persistent tension between meaning
and experience, or between representation and
practice. Bourdieu’s notions of habitus and practice in Outline of a Theory of Practice (1972 [trans.
1977]) and Logic of Practice (1980 [trans. 1990]) provide robust research strategies for looking simultaneously at how social status differences are
inscribed on the body and how we experience
the world through our bodies that are ranked in
terms of their cultural capital. The analytical reconciliation of these traditions can be assisted by
distinguishing between, first, the idea of the body
as representation, and, second, embodiment as
BRYAN S. TURNER
practice and experience.
Bogardus scale
– see scales.
Boudon, Raymond (1934– )
A professor at the University of Paris, with François Bourricaud, Boudon edited the Critical
Bourdieu, Pierre (1930–2002)
Dictionary of Sociology (1982 [trans. 1989]), and
made important contributions to rational choice
theory in The Logic of Social Action (1979 [trans.
1981]) and (with Tom Burns) The Logic of Sociological
Explanation (1974). He worked with Paul Lazarsfeld
and they edited a collection of essays on the empirical problem of causal mechanisms in sociological explanations in L’analyse empirique de la
causalité (1966). One of his key interests is the
exploration of The Unintended Consequences of Action
(1977 [trans. 1982]). He has written extensively on
the classical tradition in sociology (with Mohamed
Cherkaoui) in The Classical Tradition in Sociology
(1997). He has also examined inequality, social
mobility, and educational opportunity in Mathematical Structures of Social Mobility (1973) and Education, Opportunity and Social Inequality (1974). He
has consistently addressed the question of social
change, for example in Theories of Social Change
(1984 [trans. 1986]). He has been a critic of cultural
relativism in The Origin of Values (2000) and The
Poverty of Relativism (2005). His study of Alexis de
Tocqueville has appeared as Tocqueville for Today
(2006).
BRYAN S. TURNER
Bourdieu, Pierre (1930–2002)
Bourdieu’s work was always concerned with the
relationship between the ordinary behavior of
people in everyday life and the discourses constructed by social scientists to explain that behavior. Bourdieu made important contributions to
the philosophy of the social sciences, but he
insisted that these were meant to be practically
useful rather than abstract. Methodologically, he
argued for a dialectic between theory and practice, claiming that, too often, social theory was
divorced from social enquiry and, equally, that
too much empirical research proceeded as if
it were possible to operate a-theoretically. The
titles of some of his texts are indicative of this
orientation: The Craft of Sociology with J.-C. Passeron
and J.-C. Chamboredon (1968 [trans. 1991]), Outline
of a Theory of Practice (1972 [trans. 1977]), The Logic of
Practice (1980 [trans. 1990]), and Practical Reason. On
the Theory of Action (1994 [trans. 1998]).
Born in southwestern France, Bourdieu studied
in 1950–4 at the Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris.
His early social trajectory embodied a tension between the indigenous cultural influences of his
family (what he was to call habitus) and the culture which he needed to acquire (what he was to
call cultural capital, allied to social capital) in
order to communicate successfully in the field
of Parisian intellectual exchange. As a student,
he was influenced by phenomenology, historians
Bourdieu, Pierre (1930–2002)
and philosophers of science, and Maurice MerleauPonty. He served as a conscript in the French Army
in Algeria in the early years of the Algerian War of
Independence (1956–8) before gaining a post as an
assistant at the University of Algiers. He wrote
three books in which he presented the findings
of research carried out in Algeria. These showed
evidence of the influence of Claude Lévi-Strauss
but, on returning to France in 1961, he became
secretary to the research group that had been
established by Raymond Aron. He ceased to present himself as a social anthropologist and
became initiated as a “sociologist” in the 1960s,
but he always retained the sense that scientific
explanation, offered in whichever discourses, ran
the risk of being conceptually colonialist in a way
which was analogous with the French presence in
North Africa. During the 1960s, he carried out
research in relation to education and university
life. Working with J.-C. Passeron, this led to the
publication of The Inheritors (1964 [trans. 1979]) and
Reproduction in Education, Society and Culture (1970
[trans. 1977]). In the same decade, he also carried
out research on cultural production and reception, leading to the publication of Photography: A
Middle-Brow Art (1965 [trans. 1990]) and The Love of
Art: European Art Museums and their Public (1966
[trans. 1990]). As a result of the translations into
English of his educational research, he was at first
primarily associated with the sociology of education, but the analyses of photography and art
museums were the prelude to work on aesthetics
and taste which was most clearly presented in his
Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
(1979 [trans. 1986]).
It was in the early 1970s that Bourdieu began to
define his intellectual position most clearly. He
revisited his Algerian fieldwork and reinterpreted
it in Outline of a Theory of Practice (1972 [trans. 1977]).
The original French text offered a critique of the
structuralism of his earliest articles, whilst the
English “translation” modified the original in
order to point towards the benefits of poststructuralism. Bourdieu outlined a working epistemology by suggesting that there should be three
forms of theoretical knowledge. The primary
form corresponds with the knowledge of their
situations held unreflectingly by social agents. It
could be said to be pre-logical or pre-predicative
knowledge. This category is explicable in terms of
the ontology of Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), as
well as of the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl
(1859–1938). It is the kind of taken-for-granted
knowledge which ethnomethodology endeavored
to elicit. Following the historical epistemology of
45
Bourdieu, Pierre (1930–2002)
Gaston Bachelard (1884–1962), Bourdieu argued
that scientific knowledge has to be deliberately
differentiated from such primary knowledge. If
primary knowledge is subjective, scientific knowledge is a form of constructed objectivism. It
operates in accordance with rules of explanation
which are socially and historically contingent. So
that contingent explanations should not be taken
to be absolutely true, Bourdieu contended that
there had to be a second “epistemological break,”
whereby the conditions of production of objectivist structuralism should be subjected to a secondlevel sociological analysis. This was the origin of
Bourdieu’s commitment to “reflexive sociology,”
outlined in An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology
(1992 [trans. 1992]). For Bourdieu, poststructuralism was not anti-structuralism. Poststructuralism was able to derive benefit systematically
from the insights of both ethnomethodology and
structuralism.
Bourdieu did not advocate an armchair reflexivity. By encouraging everyone to reflect on their
own situations and to analyze the provenance of
the conceptual framework within which they
undertook that reflection, Bourdieu believed that
he was encouraging a form of “socio-analytic encounter” which would enable people to become
equal, participating members of social democracies. After publishing his Homo Academicus (1984
[trans. 1988]) in which he analyzed the social conditions of production of the field of Parisian
higher education and of his own work within
that field, Bourdieu began to deploy his accumulated “cultural capital” within the political
sphere. Responding tacitly to the work of Louis
Althusser, Bourdieu analyzed sociologically the
construction of a “state apparatus” in his The State
Nobility (1989 [trans. 1996]) so as to encourage, in
contrast, the emergence of new sources of political power, located in social movements. From the
mid-1990s until his death, Bourdieu was an influential public figure in France, and his disposition
to favor the cause of the underprivileged gained
for him a following in an international political
context as well as in the field of international
social science. His socio-analytical method and
his political engagement were both demonstrated
in the project which he directed that was published as The Weight of the World: Social Suffering in
Contemporary Society (1993 [trans. 1999]). To these
last years belong engaged texts such as Acts of
Resistance (1998 [trans. 1998]), but it was his last
course of lectures as professor at the Collège de
France, Science de la science et réflexivité (2003), which
best represents the balance of his intellectual and
46
British Marxist historians
social project. His work has been influential across
a variety of sociological subjects, irrespective of
the canonical status of areas of research enquiry.
His Pascalian Meditations (1997 [trans. 2000]), for
example, contributed importantly to the sociology
of the body.
DEREK ROBBINS
British Marxist historians
This label refers to a diverse cohort of Marxist
writers who, from the 1930s onwards, individually
and collectively contributed to the development
of social history and historical materialism. There
are a number of disparate members within the
group, working in a number of distinct fields of
historical inquiry – ancient, medieval, and from
the sixteenth to the nineteenth century. The core
of the group includes: Maurice Dobb, whose
Studies in the Development of Capitalism (1946) began
a protracted debate on the transition from feudalism to capitalism; Rodney Hilton, whose analysis
of feudalism in The Decline of Serfdom in Medieval
England (1969) focused on the English experience
of the peasantry; Christopher Hill, who, in The
World Turned Upside Down (1972), examined the
English Revolution and the ideas which arose
from it; E. P. Thompson, whose The Making of the
English Working Class (1963) outlines the historical
importance of working-class agency (see social
class), experience, and the processual nature of
class; and Eric Hobsbawm, who, in a monumental
four-volume study, the Age of Revolution (1962), the
Age of Industry (1968), the Age of Capital (1975), and
the Age of Empire (2000), provided an expansive
survey of social and political changes throughout
the world. Other, more peripheral figures within
the category include John Saville, V. G. Kiernan,
Geoffrey Ste. de Croix, George Rudé, and Perry
Anderson.
Many of these thinkers developed their political
commitments during the rise of fascism and after
the onset of World War II. Their related intellectual perspective arose in response to Whig and
non-Marxist interpretations, including those of
Max Weber, R. H. Tawney, and Werner Sombart,
as well as against Soviet-sanctioned readings of
Marxism. With reference to the latter, they maintained an ambiguous and tense relationship with
the British Communist Party, especially after the
Soviet invasion of Hungary in 1956.
Despite their internal differences, as a collective
entity their work, as Harvey Kaye in The British
Marxist Historians (1984) shows, shares a number
of characteristics. First, there is a rejection of economic and technological determinism: all these
scholars, though to different degrees, have seen
burden of dependency
the Marxist explanatory use of the theory of base/
superstructure (see ideology) as highly restrictive
and problematic. Instead, they argued for the important and irreducible role that culture, ideas,
and beliefs played in shaping the historical process
without, however, relapsing into idealism. Second,
a number of them were concerned with the transition from feudalism to capitalism. Third, drawing
on a tradition of people’s history, they consistently
emphasized the actions, struggles, and point of
view of the lower classes; that is, they wrote from
a “history-from-below” perspective. Finally, they
reasserted the importance of class struggle, experience, and consciousness as crucial factors in
understanding the historical process.
Both individually and collectively, their work
has had an important influence on the interpretation of historical materialism, of the political
implications of history, and how history is taught
and understood. It also had a bearing on the development of cultural studies. A number of the
group’s theoretical and empirical contributions
to history are contained in the journal Past &
Present, which they founded.
STEVEN LOYAL
burden of dependency
– see age.
bureaucracy
While bureaucracy as a practice stretches back
into antiquity (especially the Confucian bureaucracy of the Han dynasty), and while Max Weber
in Economy and Society (1922 [trans. 1978]) explored
its traditional origins (see tradition), the modern
rational-legal conception of bureaucracy emerged
in France in the eighteenth century. Indeed, the
word is French in origin: it compounds the French
word for an office – a bureau – with the Greek word
for rule. In the nineteenth century, Germany provided the clearest examples of its success. Weber
realized that the modern German state’s success
had been possible only because of the development of a disciplined bureaucracy and standing
army – inventions that became the envy of
Europe. In the military, nothing exhibited bureaucratic discipline better than goose-stepping, which
the Prussians invented in the seventeenth
century. The body language of goose-stepping
transmitted a clear set of messages. For the generals, it demonstrated the absolute obedience
of their recruits to orders, no matter how painful
or ludicrous these might be. For civilians, the
message was that men drilled as a collective
machine would ruthlessly crush insubordination
and eliminate individualism. Not surprisingly,
bureaucracy
nineteenth-century German industrial organizations incorporated some of the forms of rule
whose success was everywhere around them.
While the workers did not goose-step into the
factory, they were drilled in obedience to rules.
Bureaucratic organization depended, above all
else, on the application of what Weber termed
“rational” means for the achievement of specific
ends. Techniques would be most rational where
they were designed purely from the point of view
of fitness for purpose. Weber’s conception of rationality was not purely instrumental: relating a
set of means as mechanisms to achieve a given
end was only one version of rationality, albeit
one which Weber believed would become dominant in the twentieth century.
Weber defined bureaucracy in terms of fifteen
major characteristics: (1) power belongs to an
office and not the officeholder; (2) authority is
specified by the rules of the organization; (3) organizational action is impersonal, involving the
execution of official policies; (4) disciplinary
systems of knowledge frame organizational
action; (5) rules are formally codified; (6) precedent and abstract rule serve as standards for organizational action; (7) there is a tendency
towards specialization; (8) a sharp boundary between bureaucratic and particularistic action defines the limits of legitimacy; (9) the functional
separation of tasks is accompanied by a formal
authority structure; (10) powers are precisely delegated in a hierarchy; (11) the delegation of powers
is expressed in terms of duties, rights, obligations,
and responsibilities, specified in contracts; (12)
qualities required for organizational positions
are increasingly measured in terms of formal credentials; (13) there is a career structure with promotion by either seniority or merit; (14) different
positions in the hierarchy are differentially paid
and otherwise stratified; and, finally, (15) communication, coordination, and control are centralized in the organization.
Weber identified authority, based on rationallegal precepts, as the heart of bureaucratic organizations. Members of an organization will obey its
rules as general principles that can be applied to
particular cases, and that apply to those exercising authority as much as to others. People will
obey not the person but the officeholder. Members
of the organization should “bracket” the personal
characteristics of the officeholder and respond
purely to the demands of office. Weber’s view
of bureaucracy in From Max Weber was that
“Precision, speed and unambiguity, knowledge
of the files, continuity, discretion, unity, strict
47
bureaucracy
subordination, reduction of friction, and of material and personal cost . . . are raised to the optimum
point in the strictly bureaucratic administration”
(1948).
Weber saw modern bureaucratic organizations
as resting on a number of “rational” foundations.
These include the existence of a “formally free”
labor force; the appropriation and concentration
of the physical means of production as disposable
private property; the representation of share
rights in organizations and property ownership;
and the rationalization of various institutional
areas such as the market, technology, and the
law. The outcome of processes of rationalization
will be the production of a new type of person: the
specialist or technical expert. Such experts will
master reality by means of increasingly precise
and abstract concepts. Statistics, for example,
began in the nineteenth century as a form of
expert codified knowledge of everyday life and
death, which could inform public policy. The statistician became a paradigm of the new kind of
expert, dealing with everyday things but in a way
that was far removed from everyday understandings. Weber sometimes referred to the results of
this process as disenchantment, meaning the
process whereby all forms of magical, mystical,
traditional explanation are stripped from the
world, open and amenable to the calculations of
technical reason.
Bureaucracy is an organizational form consisting
of differentiated knowledge and many different
forms of expertise, with their rules and disciplines
arranged not only hierarchically in regard to each
other, but also in parallel. If you moved through
one track, in theory, you need not know anything
about how things were done in the other tracks.
Whether the bureaucracy was a public- or privatesector organization would be largely immaterial.
Private ownership might enable you to control the
revenue stream but day-to-day control would, however, be maintained through the intermediation of
48
Burgess, Ernest W. (1886–1966)
experts. And expertise is always fragmented. This
enables the bureaucracy to be captured by expert
administrators, however democratic its mandate
might be, as Roberto Michels argued in Political
Parties in his famous “iron law of oligarchy” (1911
[trans. 1962]).
STEWART CLEGG
bureaucratization
– see bureaucracy.
Burgess, Ernest W. (1886–1966)
A member of the Chicago School of sociology,
urban sociologist, and sponsor of community
action programs, Burgess was born in Tilbury,
Ontario, Canada. He received his PhD from the
University of Chicago in 1913, where the Department of Sociology under Albion Small had pioneered the idea of social research in pursuit of
reform. He returned to the department in 1916,
where he spent the rest of his academic career,
becoming its chair in 1946. He was elected president of the American Sociological Society (the
forerunner of the American Sociological
Association) in 1934.
Cautious and meticulous, he came under the
influence of the charismatic Robert Park, with
whom he wrote An Introduction to the Science of
Society (1921).
His early research focused on the urban ecology
of Chicago. Together with Park, he developed the
concentric zone theory of spatial organization in
The City (1925). They pioneered research into race
and ethnicity, supporting a large number of doctoral students in this area. Burgess’s research
interests included the spatial distribution of
social problems and led to his involvement with
a number of community programs, especially
those concerned with the family and young
people. His papers have been collected in Donald
Bogue (ed.), Basic Writings of E. W. Burgess (1974).
JOHN HOLMWOOD
C
Canguilhem, Georges (1904–1995)
He is known mainly as the intellectual éminence
grise lurking behind some of the most influential
post-World War II French social theorists, notably
Michel Foucault and Pierre Bourdieu. Although he
was an influential teacher and thinker, he published few major texts and, to date, these are not
readily accessible in English translation. Born in
southwest France, he was taught in Paris by the
philosopher Émile Cartier (1868–1951), otherwise
known as Alain, before entering the École Normale
Supérieure in the same year, 1924, as Raymond
Aron, Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80), and Paul Nizan
(1905–40). He wrote a postgraduate thesis on
Auguste Comte under the supervision of Célestin
Bouglé (1870–1940) and taught philosophy at
Toulouse from 1936 to 1940 while commencing
medical studies. He was active in the Resistance
in the Auvergne during the Vichy regime and
resumed teaching at Strasbourg in 1944. He submitted his doctoral dissertation in medicine in
1943. This was published in 1950, and republished
many times after 1966 as On the Normal and the
Pathological – famously, in 1978, with an introduction by Foucault (whose dissertation on madness
and unreason had been examined by Canguilhem
in 1960). He succeeded Gaston Bachelard (1884–
1962) as Professor of Philosophy at the Sorbonne
in 1955 and retired in 1971. He specialized in the
history and philosophy of science, with particular
reference to the life sciences, publishing Ideology
and Rationality in the History of the Life Sciences (1977
[trans. 1988]). He made important contributions to
epistemology and his discussions of health and
disease relate as pertinently to the societal as to
DEREK ROBBINS
the individual condition.
capitalism
The study of capitalism represents a classical topic
in sociology. Both Karl Marx and Max Weber were,
for example, deeply interested in capitalism and
made it their main focus of research. During
much of the twentieth century, on the other
hand, sociologists have tended to take capitalism
for granted, often neglecting to discuss it in their
analyses of society. Exceptions exist, and there
are also some signs that capitalism is currently
enjoying a comeback as a central topic in sociology. We are, for example, witnessing an increasing number of studies on the theme of “varieties
of capitalism.”
This revival of the study of capitalism will be
reviewed later on in this entry. First, however,
the question “What is capitalism?” needs to be
addressed. There will also be a presentation of
what the classics have to say about capitalism
(Marx, Weber, and Joseph Alois Schumpeter).
Their works are still unsurpassed, and they also
constitute the foundation for much of the current discussion.
In order for human beings and societies to survive, the economy has to be organized in a special
manner, of which capitalism is only one. There
has to be production; what is produced has to be
distributed; and what has been distributed has to
be consumed. There exist different ways of organizing these three processes of production, distribution, and consumption. According to a wellknown argument, the key distinction when it
comes to economic organization is between
“housekeeping” (Haushalten) and “profit-making”
(Erwerben). As Weber argued in his General Economic
History (1922 [trans. 1978]), you either produce
for consumption or for profit. Marx in Capital
(1867 [trans. 1996]) referred to the same distinction when he spoke of “use value” versus “exchange value,” and so did Aristotle when he
contrasted oekonomia (household management) to
chrematistika (money making).
Karl Polanyi in Trade and Market in the Early
Empires (1957) further elaborated the distinction
between housekeeping and profit-making when
he introduced his well-known typology of the
three different ways in which an economy can
acquire unity and stability: reciprocity, redistribution, and exchange. Each of these three terms,
Polanyi explains, expresses a form of social
action, but also answers to an institution. For
exchange, the equivalent institution is the
market; for redistribution, it may be the state
49
capitalism
capitalism
Figure 1 Ways of organizing economic process, including capitalism
or a political ruler; and for reciprocity, the tribe,
the kin group, or the family.
While exchange and the market answer to the
category of profit-making, it should be noted that
Polanyi’s real innovation was to introduce two
categories for housekeeping: reciprocity, and redistribution. Based on this idea by Polanyi, we see
that the process of the economy can actually be
organized in primarily three different ways. First
of all, we have the kind of economies where redistribution is central; and where what is produced is
distributed via, for example, the state, before it is
consumed. Second, there are economies where
reciprocity constitutes the social mechanism
through which production is distributed for
50
consumption. Here we may think of the way that
the economy of a modern family is organized.
Last – and this is where we come to capitalism –
there is the situation which is characterized by the
fact that what is being produced is distributed via
the market. Here, however, all does not go to
consumption; and what drives the process just as
much as consumption, is the search for profit (see
Fig. 1).
Capitalism, in brief, can be defined as an economy which is organized in such a way that what is
being produced for consumption is distributed via
exchange in the market and where some portion
of what is being produced also goes to profit. The
more of the economy that gets drawn into this
capitalism
type of organization, the more the economic
system can be characterized as capitalistic. There
also has to be a constant reinvestment of the
profit into production, for the capitalist process
to become permanent.
From this model, we also understand why it is
valuable not only to study middle-range phenomena in sociology, as mainstream sociology tends
to do today, but also to look at the macro level. In
a capitalist economy, the three processes of production, distribution, and consumption are all
closely linked to one another. What is being produced has to be sold, which means that production and consumption are deeply influenced by
the market. Consumption and production, to
phrase it differently, cannot be studied in isolation from the profit motive and its organization.
We may also take a concept such as production
and further subdivide it into, say, factors of production (land, labor, capital, technology, organization). If we do this, we soon see how these are all
oriented to the market and the necessity to produce profit. Labor, for example, needs to be socialized and educated in order to survive on the labor
market. Technology cannot simply be developed
according to the criteria of what is the most efficient, but has to be produced in such a way that it
can be sold on the market, and so on.
While such important institutions in modern
society as law (see law and society), politics, and
culture are not included in the model of capitalism that has just been presented, it can be suggested that each of them will either speed up, slow
down, or block the process of accumulation in the
capitalist economy. One may, for example, argue
that certain types of legislation (say bankruptcy
law, corporate law, and contractual law) are important for an advanced capitalist system to exist.
The same is true for certain types of political institutions, such as the rational state. That a country’s
general culture can be important for its development was something that Charles-Louis Montesquieu and Alexis de Tocqueville had already
commented on.
Polanyi’s categories of reciprocity, redistribution, and exchange also allow us to capture the
phenomenon that all real economies consist of a
mixture of different sectors. A modern capitalist
economy, for example, usually has a considerable
state sector that operates via redistribution (pensions, subsidies, welfare, and so on). Households
are often organized according to the principle of
reciprocity (even if we also know that this reciprocity is closely influenced by stratification (see
social stratification) according to gender and age).
capitalism
We may therefore speak of three main economic
sectors in modern capitalist society: the market
economy, the state economy, and the household economy.
Some countries also have a developed non-profit
economy (foundations, private universities, voluntary associations, and so on). This sector operates
according to a mixture of Polanyi’s three types of
distribution.
While sociologists hold that the notion of a
single inventor is something of a myth and that
all discoveries tend to be “multiple discoveries,” it
is nonetheless possible to single out Marx as the
one who invented the theory of capitalism. In
Capital and related writings, Marx was also
the first to theorize capitalism in analytical terms
as a distinct system of its own. This system is
socioeconomic as well as dynamic in nature.
What characterizes capitalism as a distinct
socioeconomic system, according to Marx, is that
money is used as capital and not simply as money.
In the latter case, we have the situation where
an individual sells a commodity (C) in order to
buy some other commodity with the money (M).
This process Marx writes as C-M-C. The capitalist,
in contrast, uses money to produce commodities
that are sold for profit; and here we have instead
M-C-M1 (where M1 equals M plus some fraction
of M).
According to Marx, it is crucial to understand
how money can become something more than
itself (M1), and instead of ascribing this process
to the successful selling of some commodity on
the market (as economists tend to do), Marx suggests that there exists one very special commodity
that has the capacity to produce more value than it
costs. This is human labor, and the extra value
that it creates Marx terms surplus value. Marx’s
theory of surplus value consequently stands at the
very center of his theory of capitalism as well as
his theory of exploitation. To Marx, in other
words, what happens in production (where surplus value is created) is more important than
what happens in the market (where surplus value
is just given a monetary form). The market, Marx
specifies, is indeed central to capitalism – but its
key role in capitalist society is primarily one of
mystification since it is precisely the fact that commodities are bought and sold on the market, at
what seems to be their “right” price, that makes it so
hard for those who are exploited in capitalism to
understand that labor is always underpaid in
capitalism.
While Marx presented an analytical model of
the capitalist process and, on the basis of this
model, theorized how the economy would develop
51
capitalism
in the future, he also pioneered a deeply historical
and empirical study of capitalism. Few readers of
Capital will fail to have noticed this, and one may
cite Marx’s powerful descriptions of life in the
factories or the process of enclosures that set off
capitalism in England.
Capitalism, as Marx sees it, is not restricted to
some special area or sphere of society, as economists see it today, but constitutes its very foundation. The economy, as a result, influences not only
what goes on in the workplace but also a host of
other phenomena, such as law, politics, literature,
philosophy, the household, and the relations between the sexes. There is, in brief, no separate
economic sector, according to Marx.
It may finally be mentioned that Marx also criticizes past and present economists for their view of
capitalism. They often do not mention the existence of classes (see social class), and, if they do,
they do not see exploitation. Most importantly,
however, according to Marx, economists simply
take capitalism for granted and think that categories such as “capital,” “labor,” “profit,” and so
on are universal and given, once and for all. They
fail, in brief, to understand that capitalism is a
deeply historical phenomenon. And as a result,
they produce ideology rather than a scientific
theory about capitalism.
There exist many critiques of Marx’s theory of
capitalism and little needs to be added to these. It
is, for example, clear that capitalism does not
operate according to “Natural Laws” which “work
with iron necessity towards inevitable results,” to
cite the preface to Capital. There is much controversy over what is alive and dead in Marx’s analysis, for example, in Jon Elster’s An Introduction to
Karl Marx (1986). It deserves nonetheless to be
emphasized, when one discusses Marx’s view of
capitalism, that Marx has relatively little to say
about corporations and other key capitalist institutions, such as the market, the stock exchange,
and so on. For Marx, capitalism was grounded in
production, and since production typically takes
place inside the modern factory, this is also where
it primarily should be studied.
Weber was deeply influenced by Marx and his
analysis of capitalism. Like Marx, Weber, for
example, saw capitalism as the defining feature
of contemporary society and also as an ominous
force for humanity. While Weber was well aware
of capitalism’s capacity to advance the material
aspects of civilization, he also – like Marx – felt
that there was something deeply non-ethical
and inhuman about the system. The reader may
recall Weber’s famous metaphor of “the iron cage”
52
capitalism
(stalwarts Ghettoes), which has taken on a life of its
own in contemporary social science. Weber himself, however, used this metaphor to indicate that
life in modern capitalist society is unbearably
harsh. One reason for this has to do with the
unrelenting demand that everybody works all
the time; there is also the fact that life in modern
capitalist society lacks a deeper meaning.
But even if there exist parallels between the
views of Marx and Weber on capitalism, they
also differ on several important points. One may
single out five such points of profound difference.
First of all, while Marx saw capitalism as centered around production, Weber saw it as centered
around the market. Second, while Marx argued
that there only exists one type of capitalism,
Weber disagreed and suggested that there are several such types. Third, Marx and Weber differed in
the way that they conceptualized the role that
law, politics, and culture play in modern capitalism. Fourth, Weber’s theory of the origin of capitalism differed from that of Marx. And finally,
Weber introduced the concept of meaning into
the analysis of capitalism – a concept that does
not exist in Marx.
That Weber saw capitalism as centered on the
market, as opposed to production, comes out very
clearly in his general view of capitalism. From
Weber’s The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilizations
(1909 [trans. 1976]), one may cite what is probably
the most succinct definition of capitalism that
can be found in his work: “where we find that
property is an object of trade and is utilized by
individuals for profit-making enterprise in a
market economy, there we have capitalism.”
Second, while Marx argued that there was no
capitalism in Antiquity and that capitalism could
only be found in the West, Weber sharply disagreed. As opposed to Marx, Weber in Economy and
Society (1921–2 [trans. 1978]) suggested that there
are three major types of capitalism: political capitalism, rational capitalism, and traditional-commercial
capitalism. Political capitalism can be found where
profit-making is directly dependent on politics,
say where merchants operate under the direct
protection of an imperialist power or where business contracts can only be secured through the
mediation of state officials. Political capitalism,
according to Weber, existed in Antiquity, in the
West, and elsewhere, and can also be found in
modern society. Rational capitalism, in contrast,
is a uniquely western product, and first came into
full being from the time of the Reformation and
onwards. It is characterized by a strongly methodical approach to all economic matters and by the
capitalism
use of institutions such as the modern firm,
rational technology, and capital accounting.
Traditional-commercial capitalism can be found
in all societies, far back in history as well as
today, and it consists of small trade in goods and
currencies.
Third, while Marx conceptualized the role
of law, politics, and culture in capitalism as all
being influenced by economic forces in a decisive manner, Weber had a different approach.
In principle, the causality can go both ways. He
also argued that, as society develops, so do its
various spheres – such as the economic sphere,
the political sphere, the religious sphere, and so
on. Each of these spheres has its own internal
dynamic and autonomy vis-à-vis society as a whole
(Eigengesetzlichkeit). How clashes between spheres
will be solved is an empirical question and cannot
be predicted in advance. Basically, however, politics and law need to be predictable and reliable
for rational capitalism to thrive.
Fourth, Weber and Marx differed on the historical origin of western capitalism. Both saw capitalism as the result of a long evolutionary history
and not as the result of one critical event or factor
(for Marx on this point, see Capital; for Weber,
General Economic History). Still, while Marx singled
out the enclosures in England as extra important
in this development, Weber did the same with the
creation of “the spirit of capitalism” during the
Reformation and onwards. Whether Weber was
correct or not in his thesis that certain Protestant
ideas (especially the notion of work as a vocation),
helped to jumpstart modern capitalism is still a
much-debated question as Gordon Marshall demonstrates in his In Search of the Spirit of Capitalism
(1982).
The last point on which Marx’s and Weber’s
analyses of capitalism differ importantly from
one another has to do with the concept of meaning (Sinn). While Marx was very interested in
understanding the relationship between capitalism and culture, he nonetheless never addressed
the issue of the meaning that the actor attaches to
his or her actions. By explicitly including this
aspect, Weber can be said to have opened up the
analysis of capitalism in many directions that
remained closed to Marx.
Schumpeter was deeply influenced by the works
of Marx and Weber, including their analyses of
capitalism. While he admired both authors, he
also regarded Capital, as well as The Protestant Ethic
and the Spirit of Capitalism (1905 [trans. 2002]), as
having serious flaws. He was not impressed by
Weber’s argument that a qualitative change had
capitalism
somehow taken place in the mentality of western
capitalists at the time of the Reformation, and he
disapproved of most of the economics that Marx
had used in his argument. Schumpeter in his
Essays (1961) saw capitalism as gradually evolving
from Antiquity or “early capitalism” to contemporary times or “the modern phase,” that is,
“1898 and today,” traversing in the process “mercantile capitalism,” from the sixteenth century till
the end of the eighteenth century, and “intact
capitalism,” during the nineteenth century. He
emphasized continuity, and he saw no reason to
refer to primitive accumulation or Luther’s ideas
about Beruf (vocation).
Schumpeter nonetheless deeply admired Marx’s
idea that the economy is not something that only
responds to influences from the outside, as in conventional equilibrium analysis. He also tried to
construct his own theory of capitalism on this
insight by Marx, although he picked a different
central actor: the entrepreneur rather than the
capitalist. The entrepreneur, Schumpeter argues,
can be defined as an economic actor who, by
piecing together a new combination of already
existing factors, creates innovations and economic
change. Stimulated by the huge profit that an
entrepreneur makes, a number of imitators will
appear, till there is no more room for making a
profit, and the economy starts to slide downwards.
The business cycles that always accompany capitalism are, according to Schumpeter, basically caused
by the entrepreneur and the wave of imitators that
follows in his or her footsteps.
Something must also be said about Capitalism,
Socialism and Democracy (1942) when it comes to
Schumpeter’s analysis of capitalism. He here
comments on a period of the history of capitalism
when Marx and Weber were not alive, namely the
interwar period. Like Weber, however, Schumpeter singles out the giant corporations with their
huge bureaucracies as the key actors – and also as
being deeply problematic. Indeed, Schumpeter
was so fearful of these giant corporations that he
saw them as a major reason why capitalism was
bound to go under and be replaced by socialism.
Like Marx, Schumpeter was convinced that capitalism one day would disappear, but in contrast to
Marx he thought that this would be caused by
its success and not by its failure. Many factors
were involved in this process, including the quality of the capitalists. With the success of capitalism, he argued, capitalists would eventually turn
complacent and lose their desire to counter the
attacks of socialists and intellectuals – and
this failure to respond would slowly undo “the
53
capitalism
capitalist civilization,” including its otherwise
well-functioning economic system.
Socialists more or less monopolized the use of
the term capitalism from around 1900 – when
Werner Sombart (1863–1941) popularized it in
Der moderne Kapitalismus (1903) – till something
like the 1970s. From this point on, however, it
has been as much embraced by economists, liberals, and the right wing as by social democrats
and the left wing. The theory of capitalism that
can be found among economists today is also no
longer restricted to theories of how prices are set
through the interplay of demand and supply; it
also includes reflections on the institutions that
give structure to capitalism, including the state.
To discuss the various models of capitalism that
can be found among twentieth-century economists would demand a longer essay than this,
and the reader is referred to the works of people
from J. M. Keynes to Milton Friedman (1912– ), and
John Kenneth Galbraith (1908–2006). A few words
must nonetheless be said about the economists’
creation of what may be termed the neo-liberal
theory of capitalism, since it is this way of looking
at capitalism that has come to dominate the
current discourse on this subject.
The neo-liberal theory of capitalism has deep
roots in the nineteenth century and was given an
early and theoretically sophisticated expression
in the works of Austrian economists Ludwig von
Mises (1881–1973) and Friedrich von Hayek (1899–
1992). These two thinkers insisted on the decentralized, spontaneous nature of capitalism and
that the state must stay out of the economy – for
example, Friedrich von Hayek, Individualism and
Economic Order (1948), and Ludwig von Mises, The
Anti-Capitalistic Mentality (1956). Prices carry
enough information for the entrepreneur to
know what to do; and while legal and political
institutions are necessary for the market to work
properly, they must under no circumstances be
allowed to interfere with its workings or to counter its results through welfare measures. The
market will produce liberty and wealth if it is
left alone; and this is what matters.
Since the 1980s, when Margaret Thatcher and
Ronald Reagan came to power, this vision of
neoliberal capitalism has become the official economic ideology of the West, and it is still as strong,
if not stronger. As applied to the situation of the
economy in developing countries, neoliberalism is
known as “the Washington consensus” and has
come to expression in official statements by the
International Monetary Fund, the US president,
and so on.
54
capitalism
Other academics besides liberal economists
have produced important scholarship on capitalism during the post-World War II period. Leaving
aside Andrew Shonfield’s pioneering Modern Capitalism (1965) in order to continue with the theme
of the neo-liberal vision, a mention should be
made of the idea of disorganized capitalism which
emerged in the 1980s. It is here argued that the
attempt to organize capitalism at the top (via
cartels, monopolies, and the like) and at the
bottom (via trade unions, cooperatives, and so
on) is about to come to an end – for example in
Scott Lash and John Urry, The End of Organized
Capitalism (1987). The result of this process will
be strife and disorganization, and will work out
differently depending on the country in question.
During the 1990s a novel approach to the study
of capitalism emerged, which also is opposed to
neoliberalism. This is the school of varieties of
capitalism, which is close in spirit to the French
regulation school (see regulation theory) and
the so-called economics of conventions. All of
these approaches work in the tradition of political
economy and draw on a mixture of heterodox
economics and political science. Their focus is on
capitalism in individual countries, and comparisons are often made between various countries,
as well as between groups of countries. A central
task that the varieties-of-capitalism approach
has set for itself is to show that non-liberal and
heavily regulated economies work just as well as
neoliberal and de-regulated economies. Sweden
and Germany, for example, have capitalist economies that are as efficient as, say, the United Kingdom and the United States (see, for example, Colin
Crouch and Wolfgang Streeck, Political Economy of
Modern Capitalism, (1997) or Peter Hall and David
Soskice, Varieties of Capitalism, (2001). In analyzing
the way that capitalism is organized in different
countries, much emphasis in this type of literature is also laid on the mode of governance. And in
doing so, many more actors are usually taken
into account than in conventional economics, including chambers of commerce and other business associations. Much attention is finally also
paid to different types of regulations, from legal
systems to the many rules that are produced in
modern society.
An attempt has also recently been made to draw
on the tradition of economic sociology in analyzing capitalism (for example Victor Nee and Richard Swedberg, The Economic Sociology of Capitalism,
2005). This approach is heavily indebted to Weber
and Schumpeter and primarily attempts to outline the social structure of the various economic
capitalist mode of production
institutions that are at the core of capitalism,
from firms and markets to entrepreneurship
more generally. Proponents of this approach are
closer to New Institutional Economics than to the
tradition of political economy. They also center
their analyses around the notion of interest, and
view institutions as embodying interests or as
channeling interests rather than as a set of rules –
for example, in Richard Swedberg, The Concept of
Interest (2005).
It may finally be noted that, according to Marx,
capitalism is always revolutionizing itself in its
attempts to seek new profits. This means that the
analysts of capitalism are looking at a target that
is moving very rapidly, something that tends to
cast them in the unhappy role of the famous owl
of Minerva, always arriving too late. Nonetheless,
since capitalism is at the center of modern society,
and since it constitutes “the most fateful force in
our modern life” (Weber), it is absolutely crucial
that it also remains at the center of social science.
RICHARD SWEDBERG
capitalist mode of production
– see Karl Marx.
carceral society
– see Michel Foucault.
care
The social implications of care have been highlighted by sociologists whose work has emphasized the often unseen work that is performed
(largely in the household). The study of care has
been responsible for the “denaturalization” of
those responsibilities (looking after children, the
ill, the infirm, and the elderly) which were once, if
not assumed to fall to, then at least assigned to,
women. A generation of sociologists (including
Hilary Graham, Miriam David, Clare Ungerson,
and Hilary Land) asked questions about who cared
for those not able to function as independent and
autonomous adults and found that the answer
was largely, although not exclusively, women. As
a result of these studies, “caring work” has been
recognized in much of Europe as work that merits
economic payment.
There is another sense, however, in which the
extension of the understanding of the term work
has enlarged our perception of care. It lies in
the development of what has become known
as the “ethic of care.” In 1982, Carol Gilligan
(1936– ) argued, in A Different Voice, that women
approached moral choices in terms of the implications of their actions for others. Gilligan – and
career
other later writers – have defined this attitude as
that of an ethic of care which prioritizes the needs
of others, rather than abstract and ideal moral
systems, in making moral and ethical choices.
The recognition of the giving of care has also
created the social recognition of “carers,” those
millions of people (largely female) whose lives
are ruled by the dependence of others. For aging
societies, the issue of care and carers has become
central to welfare policies, since for many people
the traditional expectations surrounding care
have become unacceptable, not least in the assumption that caring for others will always be
willingly, and voluntarily, accepted. M A R Y E V A N S
career
In commonsense usage, this is the progression of
an individual through an occupation via a series
of predefined institutional gateways which secure
standing in the community, increasing levels of
seniority within the occupation, and increasing
levels of pay. The hierarchal structure of a university career provides a good example: from tutor, to
lecturer, senior lecturer, associate professor, and,
finally, professor. Max Weber argued in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1905 [trans.
2002]) that the development of the career as a
calling or vocation was a secular solution to the
problem of salvation in Protestantism, providing a
secular form of salvation through service to the
community. Sociologists, particularly those in the
symbolic interactionist tradition, have focused on
the temporal sequencing of a career and particularly the problems that arise for organizations
when individuals become blocked in their career
aspirations. More broadly then, the concept of
career can be applied to any ongoing sequences
of changes of social status over time. Thus, the
sequencing of the events that go to make a family
can be conceptualized as a career. While careers
are usually taken to be positive life experiences, as
in a career in the professions, they can also be
negatively evaluated. Erving Goffman drew attention to the negatively evaluated “moral career” of
the mentally ill patient, who through a series of
degradation ceremonies – the loss of an autonomous adult identity, the replacement of street
clothing with institutional garments, and boundaries around their ability to interact with others –
experienced a stigmatizing career. In criminology,
there is also the notion of a “criminal career” in
which an offender passes through a series of
stages towards full-time criminal activities.
Contemporary sociologists have focused on the
changing nature of work in postindustrial society,
55
case study
which makes the possibility of a life-long career
increasingly unlikely as work becomes more fragmented and discontinuous, because companies
downsize and outsource functions previously
undertaken by long-term employees: such as, for
example, IBM outsourcing its computing functions to India. Under the impact of neoliberalism
in the state sector, the idea of a career in the
public or civil service is also on the wane as
the state out-sources many of its functions to
the private market. Richard Sennett has, in The
Corrosion of Character (1998) and Respect (2003),
claimed that, with the decline of career in the
modern economy, there is a corresponding transformation of personality, namely an erosion of
KEVIN WHITE
character.
case study
The term case study refers both to methodological
strategy and subject of study. Social scientists use
the case-study approach as a methodological strategy when they wish to provide rich descriptions
and analyses of a single case, or a small number of
cases. This approach allows researchers to develop
a detailed view of processes, interactions, and
meaning systems in a way they would find difficult if they were examining dozens or hundreds
of cases. A case-study research project is limited
in its capacity to support universalizing sociological generalizations but its advantage is that
it can reveal more meaningful data about a
case. Case-study data can yield specific insights
that form the bases for hypothesis testing (see
hypothetico-deductive method) in studies that
use large datasets. Many researchers in this tradition use the comparative method, wherein close
examination of two or three targeted cases allows
them to isolate the causes and consequences of
particular case features and dynamics. Qualitative
field researchers, and historical, comparative, and
quantitative methodologists all use the case study
approach.
A case-study project might take as its subject
work organizations, social movements, communities, political regimes, schools, and myriad
other case types. The particular population from
which a researcher draws his or her case follows
from the theoretical and substantive goal. For
example, if a sociologist wishes to know whether
and why social inequality persists in organizations
that are committed to democratic, progressive
social change, she or he might study workerowned cooperatives or feminist, peace, and other
VICKI SMITH
social movement organizations.
56
Castells, Manuel (1942– )
Castells, Manuel (1942– )
A Spanish-born sociologist, Castells has roots in
urban sociology and the sociology of social movements, which are examined in his The Urban
Question (1977), City, Class and Power (1978), and
The City and the Grassroots (1983). Between 1967
and 1979 he taught at the University of Paris,
first on the Nanterre campus and, after 1970, at
the École des Études en Sciences Sociales. In 1979
he was appointed Professor of Sociology and Professor of City and Regional Planning at the University of California, Berkeley. In 2001 he became
a research professor at the Universitat Oberta de
Catalunya, Barcelona. In 2003 he joined the University of Southern California, Anneberg School
of Communication as Professor of Communication and Technology. Castells’s work climaxed
with a number of cross-cultural studies on the
information age and global (see globalization)
network society that Anthony Giddens compared
in significance to Max Weber’s Economy and Society. These were The Rise of Network Society (1996),
The Power of Identity (1997), and The End of the
Millennium (2000). A more telling comparison
might have been with Karl Marx’s Capital (1867).
For Castells operates in the neo-Marxist tradition
to explore the theme of the perpetual revolutions
under capitalism, technology, production, power,
and experience. He ultimately links the purpose
of sociology to the goal of human liberation.
Employing powerful comparative and historical
methods of analysis (see comparative method), he
demonstrates how a new type of production has
emerged in the West (based around information),
with a new type of society (network society) and a
new form of identity politics (critical pluralist/
virtual).
Castells demonstrates how “replaceable generic labor” has been repositioned through the
casualization of employment, with considerable
discontinuity in careers and personal crises, illnesses, drug/alcohol addiction, loss of assets, and
negation of distinction. He posits three fateful
cleavages in network society: (1) skills-based divisions between information and communication
workers and deskilled labor; (2) obsolescent citizens,
divided between laborers who are defined as
surplus to the requirements of the system and
what might be called the “stakeholders” in civil
society; and (3) intensified alienated labor, divided from stakeholders. His work constitutes a
magisterial account of the many-sided restructuring of capitalism in the twenty-first century.
CHRIS ROJEK
causal explanation
causal explanation
– see explanation.
causal inference
– see explanation.
causal modeling
– see modeling.
causality
In sociology, disputes over the notion of “causality” reflect deep divisions in the discipline. With
the success of eighteenth-century Newtonian
science – and the postulation that there are laws
of nature which can be discovered through empirical research – came the ideal of a science of
society with its own laws. This was the inspiration
for Auguste Comte to propose a wholly secular
explanation of social life, through what he called
the positive method (hence positivism) that restricted explanation to observable facts. Combined
with the development of evolutionism – of the
idea of the development of complex social forms
from preceding primitive ones, and the idea of
social structure (developing out of the analysis
of the state in the work of Thomas Hobbes
[1588–1679], John Locke [1632–1704], and JeanJacques Rousseau [1712–78]) – the scene was set
for postulating the lawful progression of societal
types based on empirically observable facts. Émile
Durkheim defined the subject of sociology as the
study of social facts. These are objective, existing
independently of any individual’s consciousness
of them, are external to the individual, and coerce
the individual to behave in specific ways. As
Durkheim puts it, social facts such as the family,
the legal system, or marriage, for example, “will
be felt to be real, living active forces, which because of the way they determine the individual,
prove their independence of him” (Suicide, 1897
[trans. 1951]). Thus in Durkheim’s approach
society is a causal factor in determining how individuals act. Durkheim’s approach, which claims
that the social sciences are pursuing general
knowledge of society, is, nomothetic, in seeking
to produce causal-explanatory knowledge. However, the position that there are causal relationships in social life was hotly disputed in
the Methodenstreit – the debate over whether
the methods of the natural sciences were useful
in the social sciences – in German history at
the end of the nineteenth century. Wilhelm
Dilthey (1833–1911) and Wilhelm Windelband
(1848–1915) both argued that because the subject
matter of the social sciences was the conscious
causality
subject – unlike the inert nature studied in the
natural sciences – the social sciences had to develop their own unique methods of study in which
the goal was interpretation and understanding
rather than explanation and prediction. Furthermore, the social sciences are idiographic, because
they could only ever provide knowledge of the
specific situation. To achieve this, the social science researcher had to be able to understand
empathically the subjective meanings attributed
by social agents to their actions. This method was
called Verstehen, or interpretive sociology. However, it was also a form of intuitionism, and
according to Max Weber we could never be secure
in our knowledge of whether we had got our subject’s position “right.” He proposed to resolve
the antimony between the objective search for
the laws of society and the subjectively driven
origins of social action in the individual actor.
As Weber put it in Economy and Society (1922
[trans. 1968]), “sociology is a science concerning
itself with the interpretive understanding of
social action and thereby with a causal explanation of its course and consequences.” He (in
Roscher and Knies: The Logical Problems of Historical
Economics, 1903–6 [trans. 1975]) defines causality
in the same way as David Hume (1711–76): “the
idea of an effect, the idea of a dynamic bond . . .
between phenomena qualitatively different from
each other . . . [and] the idea of subordination to
rules.” Like Hume he rejects empirical correlation
as evidence of causal relationships. A causal claim
is that an event x, coming first, will cause an outcome y on every occasion. According to Hume, in
his famous critique of causality, a causal link
cannot be demonstrated between x and y. Rather,
the most that can be said is that x and y are a
succession of occurrences which, because they
always follow each other, we come to expect to
be together. However, in Hume’s argument, we
cannot prove that they cause each other. Unlike
Hume, Weber argues that a form of causal explanation is achievable in the social sciences, that is, to
establish the elective affinity between events. This
causal explanation is to be produced not by empathy (as in Dilthey) but through understanding
why it is that an actor gives meaning to what they
do in the context of a culturally specific situation.
Thus, in his account of the Protestant Ethic and the
Spirit of Capitalism (1905 [trans. 2002]), Weber does
not seek to “enter” the mind of his subjects, but,
through constructing an ideal type of how someone faced with the metaphysical impact of Protestantism would make sense of their situation and
act, provides a causal account of their attempts to
57
cause
establish for themselves that they were saved (to
save wealth as a sign of salvation) and an explanation of the empirical correlation with the
development of capitalism (the accumulation of
capital) in Protestant countries.
Later debates in the social sciences about causality have been rendered under the rubric of the
agency and structure debate, that is the relationship between intentional action and social structures. In the works of Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory
of Science (1975), Rom Harré and E. Madden, Causal
Powers (1975), and Anthony Giddens, The Constitution of Society (1984), the task is to examine how
enduring social structures, which predate the individual, and in which s/he has no choice but to
participate, can at the same time be transformed
in social practices.
While these debates have had echoes in
American sociology, particularly in the European-originated works of Alfred Schutz and his
development of phenomenological sociology, in
general it has been dominated by a simple integration of Durkheimian ontology (social facts
exist and have the force to make individuals
act in specific ways) with a naive positivistic
empiricism (that these social facts are demonstrated by probabilistic statistics and evidenced
in correlations).
KEVIN WHITE
cause
– see causality.
census
The process of collecting demographic, social, and
economic data from all members of a population,
censuses are distinct from surveys, which are
focused on data from a subset, or sample, of a
population. Censuses have a long history, and
were first used in ancient Rome. In their modern
form, censuses are used to justify the allocation of
resources by the state. Thus, the ways in which
censuses categorize and count ethnic and other
minority groups, including transient and indigent
populations, has become a matter of some concern and debate – as these may have a direct
bearing on the resources available to members of
these groups. This controversy has been the catalyst for the introduction of sampling methods in
order to achieve a more accurate census of the
true numbers of such systematically undercounted groups.
Samples of anonymized records (SARs) are
samples of de-identified individual-level data
extracted from censuses. SARs are distinct from
58
charisma
commonly available census outputs in that they
have not been aggregated into pre-determined
tables. In fact, SARs more closely resemble survey
data, in that they contain a separate record for
each individual. The very large sample sizes of
SARs distinguish them from most surveys, as
SARs allow for the analysis of data by sub-groups
and by regional areas.
As microdata sets, SARs permit multivariate
statistical analysis at the individual level. SARs
may be used in the investigation of a broad
range of social issues including the composition
of households, ethnicity, health, education, and
employment.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
charisma
For Max Weber charisma is first a matter of
authority and its legitimacy. A charismatic leader
is not, as he explains in Economy and Society (1921
[trans. 1968]), merely forceful and strong but one
whose authority is based on supporters’ “devotion to the exceptional sanctity, heroism or exemplary character of an individual person, and
on the normative patterns or order revealed or
ordained by him.” This Weber contrasts with rational and also traditional grounds of authority,
in which obedience is respectively owed to the
impersonal order and to the person occupying a
traditionally sanctioned position. Charismatic
authority, then, unlike rational and traditional
authority, is particularly vulnerable to attack: a
challenge to the incumbent of charismatic authority necessarily brings the legitimacy of the
authority of the social order into doubt. This
situation does not arise with either rational or
traditional authority.
An additional element of charismatic authority
contributes further to its instability. What is decisive for the validity of charisma, according to
Weber, is recognition from those subject to it
that the charismatic individual possesses exceptional powers or qualities. Such extraordinary
powers can be revealed to followers or disciples
only by their demonstrable exercise. Thus, in the
necessarily emotional relationship between authority incumbent and followers, it is necessary
that the leader constantly prove that his divine,
magical, or heroic powers have not deserted him.
The charismatic leader is thus compelled constantly to reaffirm the legitimacy of his authority
in order that he may continue to hold it. One
consequence of this noted by Weber is the incompatibility of charismatic authority and continuous
economic activity devoted to regular income and
Chicago School of Sociology
economizing. Plunder and extortion, Weber says,
are typical means of provision under charismatic
rule.
Because it is based on the personal qualities of
the individual incumbent, charismatic authority
is contrary to routine and offers no solutions to
the problem of succession or the movement from
one leader to another. Within charismatic communities that persist there is therefore a tendency
towards routinization of charisma. Weber treats
routinization in terms of the development of both
succession mechanisms and means to appropriate
or select charismatic staff. Mechanisms of succession include: (1) search for a new leader possessing
certain qualities; (2) revelation by oracle or
priestly technique; (3) designation by prior charismatic leader or by his administrative staff; (4)
hereditary; and (5) ritual transmission of charisma
from one person to another. The transformation
of the charismatic mission into an office, by routinizing charismatic staff, is also achieved
through a number of possibilities associated with
different bases of selection and remuneration.
Elements of charismatic authority may be
found with other forms of rule. Weber mentions
plebiscitary presidential regimes and cabinet government as two instances in which charisma and
legal rational authority may coexist.
Edward Shils in The Constitution of Society (1982)
developed a non-Weberian account of charisma.
Charismatic properties of central institutions satisfy a need for order, and roles that are associated
with such institutions enjoy derivative charisma,
leading to relations of deference, even in egalitarian societies.
JACK BARBALET
Chicago School of Sociology
The Chicago School of Sociology was a body of
social research associated with a group of professors and their students affiliated with the Sociology Department of the University of Chicago.
The School emerged around 1915, and lasted until
about 1935. Its most prominent members included Robert Park and W. I. Thomas, alongside
such figures as Ernest Burgess and Ellsworth
Faris. In the later period of the School, the sociologists Herbert Blumer and Louis Wirth continued
its research tradition. The School was the first
group of sociologists to practice a systematic research agenda in the United States. It influenced
the development of the symbolic interactionist
tradition, and the emphasis on social psychology,
qualitative research, participant observation,
and ethnography associated with this theoretical
orientation.
Chicago School of Sociology
The Chicago School focused on a wide variety of
social processes, such as social organization and
disorganization, urban sociology, social change,
immigration, deviance, race relations, and social
movements. It often analyzed these processes in
the context of the city of Chicago, developing a
lasting influence in urban sociology through such
concepts as ecology and succession. Its researchers
helped establish the importance of empirical investigation into social issues through analyzing
documents and conducting interviews, as well as
engaging in first-hand observation of various
groups. Two of its most important studies include
The City (1925), a selection of essays by Park, Burgess, and R. D. McKenzie, and The Polish Peasant in
Europe and America (1918–20), a five-volume work
by Thomas and Florian Znaniecki. Other works
include Nel Anderson’s The Hobo (1923), Wirth’s
The Ghetto (1928), Harvey Zorbaugh’s The Gold Coast
and the Slum (1929), E. Franklin Frazier’s The Negro
Family in Chicago (1931), and Paul Cressy’s The TaxiDance Hall (1932). Park and Burgess also wrote an
introductory text, Introduction to the Science of Sociology (1921), which helped popularize the School’s
approach.
The Chicago School linked thought and action,
positing that ideas and attitudes are tied to the
social and historical conditions in which they
arise and are situated. The School’s focus on social
issues such as crime and deviance was tied to the
reformist impulse of many of its researchers, who
were concerned with solving social problems in
the pre-World War I Progressive era in the United
States. Its reformist orientation was strengthened
by the ties to journalism of one of its members,
Robert Park. Yet the Chicago School advocated an
objective and scientific study of society, and its
members attempted to implement a disinterested
sociology.
The Chicago School supported the use of the
ethnographic methods of anthropologists, arguing that the same methods could be employed to
investigate social processes within the United
States as were used to study non-western cultures. But the School was much more diverse
than this characterization. Its researchers did
assume that individuals could not be studied in
isolation from one another and were influenced
by the groups that encompassed them, and that
social change developed through the interaction
of individuals and groups with one another. Yet
many of the School’s scholars, such as William
Ogburn, embraced versions of quantitative analysis, such as survey research. Researchers did not
engage in mindless empiricism, however. They
59
Chicago School of Sociology
always approached their data with a theoretical
interest in mind.
The Chicago School emphasized that the social
and historical context in which one lived dramatically influenced social processes. But individuals
were not passive products of their environment.
Social structure and individual agency could not
be separated from one another. People could
change the social structures in which they lived,
but these economic, social, and cultural conditions
influenced their attitudes and actions. Indeed, the
actions of individuals often had unintended consequences. Social structure and geographic location
accounted for much of social behavior. Researchers
often wrote of natural, relatively predictable
processes of history and geography, shaped by the
similar social location and traditions that groups
shared, and the arrangement of commercial
establishments and residential housing in a particular area. Such concerns led to the study of
social organization and disorganization, the
latter considered to be the main cause of social
problems.
Much of their work focused on Chicago. In Park,
Burgess, and McKenzie’s The City, Park encouraged
his students to engage the denizens of the city,
“become acquainted with people,” to “nose
around” those groups that they were interested
in studying. For Park, one could only be impartial
by understanding the point of view, the subjective
experience, of other people. Thus, the social life of
the city could be understood through intense
fieldwork in particular neighborhoods. The study
of urban life should investigate a city’s culture,
occupational structure, and physical organization. The social profile of the city was conditioned
by structural factors such as its economic and
geographical conditions, including its location
on transportation and trade routes. The sociological imagination must combine these two dimensions, the structural and the subjective, into a
coherent study.
For Park, integrated city neighborhoods progressively broke down as secondary, impersonal
relationships increasingly based on the market
and law (see law and society) replaced the primary relationships of family and ethnicity. Cities
created more contacts for individuals, and offered
them an array of different lifestyles, but these
contacts tended to be transitory. The city also
allowed deviant individuals, from the genius to
the criminal, to flourish in its heterogeneous
environment.
Burgess took a somewhat different approach to
the study of urban life. He too saw cities as
60
Chicago School of Sociology
characterized by heterogeneous, diverse occupations, employing a large percentage of young and
middle-aged individuals, and occupied by a high
percentage of foreign-born immigrants. Burgess
focused on processes of growth and expansion in
the cities, viewing them as natural adaptations to
new types of social organization. He analyzed
urban expansion through his theory of concentric
zones. An inner industrial zone was surrounded
by zones consisting of the ghetto, working-men’s
homes, and at the outmost region more suburban
residential areas. Each inner zone expands as it
invades an outer zone, a process Burgess labeled
succession. This expansion involves simultaneous
processes of decentralization and concentration
of people and industries. Burgess also utilized
the notion of urban ecology to study the social
life of cities. Drawn from biology, the concept of
ecology emphasizes the interdependence of urban
life, and how an individual relates to his or
her environment. Processes of competition and
accommodation influence the development of
the urban milieu, as a community expands or declines as economic development waxes or wanes.
The differentiation and segmentation of urban
populations accompany such social changes.
Park and Burgess contended that the American
city could not be understood apart from immigration. The major work on immigration produced by
this School, and the study that contributed most
prominently to its research reputation, was
Thomas and Znaniecki’s The Polish Peasant in Europe
and America. The Polish Peasant examined Polish immigrant adaptation to the United States, focusing
on their experiences in Chicago. Thomas and
Znaniecki’s study encompassed much more than
an examination of Polish immigrants. They
explored immigration within the context of
modernization, utilizing systematic qualitative
methods (see qualitative research). Their research
emphasized the social psychological needs of the
peasant immigrant, how his attitudes and values
interacted with those of the larger society, and the
ways in which the ethnic community helped
shape the immigrant experience. They placed immigrant experiences with social change at the
center of their analysis.
Thomas and Znaniecki focused on the formation of the Polish ethnic community rather than
on individual assimilation. They viewed the Polish
community as tightly integrated and insular, its
economic and social life characterized more by
shared, reciprocal values than the profit motive.
The ethnic community was a novel American creation, and it was a positive development which
Chicago School of Sociology
encouraged adaptation to American society.
The ethnic community emerged in a particular
geographical environment, its development influenced by processes of segregation and integration
within the city. The immigrant community inherited from Europe could not survive intact in
its new American context, however. Over time, the
ethnic community began slowly to disintegrate,
and its resulting social disorganization diminished the influence of shared social rules on individuals. More contacts with the world outside of
the community and increases in individual decisionmaking and freedom overshadowed the
importance of family and traditional ethnic ties
in shaping individual identity.
There were clear limitations on the Polish peasant studies as an exemplar for the study of immigrant communities. The authors concentrated on
the urban experience of immigrants, and did not
examine how immigrants fared outside of cities.
They also downplayed the roles of religion and
discrimination in the formation of the ethnic
community. Workplace issues and questions of
political power also did not occupy a central place
in the study.
The Polish Peasant helped popularize the assimilation thesis that, over time, immigrant ethnic
groups became incorporated into the Anglo
mainstream. Yet the study demonstrated the problems associated with assimilation, including the
difficulties that an ethnic community faces in
adapting to American mores, the complex process
of the loss of immigrant ethnic solidarity and its
reconstitution in the American context, and the
continued importance of the family and other
primary groups as ethnic groups assimilated
into the American mainstream. In criticizing any
simple assimilationist model, The Polish Peasant
posited that distinctive ethnic communities
contribute to the pluralism of the United States.
The Polish Peasant was influential in the subsequent history of the sociology of immigration.
Early American research on immigration had an
assimilationist bias, interpreting The Polish Peasant
as an argument for assimilation to an Anglo community. This was a misinterpretation, as Thomas
and Znaniecki’s study emphasized the reshaping
of the mainstream as new ethnic communities
became part of American society. Moreover,
Thomas and Znaniecki studied the perceptions of
the United States developed by the immigrant,
stressing an active view of the immigrant experience. They also emphasized that both material
and cultural factors were important in the formation and maintenance of ethnic communities.
Chicago School of Sociology
Contemporary pluralist studies which celebrate
ethnic communities have returned to Thomas
and Znaniecki’s emphasis on immigrant agency,
but with a greater awareness of the power of,
and constraints on, immigrant communities. The
most recent and influential book on US immigration, Remaking the American Mainstream: Assimilation
and Contemporary Immigration (2003), by Richard
Alba and Victor Nee, returns to The Polish Peasant’s
emphasis on the active immigrant who seeks a
better life in the United States. Alba and Nee see
assimilation resulting from the interaction of different ethnic groups, which transforms and blurs
any simple notion of a mainstream culture. They
also argue that geographic context is central to
processes of immigration and assimilation, which
are also constrained by the power of existing
institutions.
By the 1930s, the influence of the Chicago
School was in decline, replaced by the new fascination with statistical methods associated with
Paul Lazarsfeld of Columbia University, who engaged in opinion polling and market research. His
concern with predicting consumer and voting behavior left little room for theory and the vagaries
of history and social interaction. Yet after World
War II a “second Chicago School” emerged, as
researchers such as Howard Becker and Erving
Goffman continued the qualitative and theoretical orientation of the School, examining issues
from deviance to the rituals of everyday life from
complex ethnographic angles.
The Chicago School remains an important influence on sociology. Contemporary sociologists
and studies influenced by this tradition include
Herbert Gans, The Urban Villagers (1962), Gary Alan
Fine, Gifted Tongues: High School Debate and Adolescent
Culture (2001), and Kitchens: The Culture of Restaurant
Work (1996), and more theoretical works by
authors such as Andrew Abbott, in his Time
Matters: On Theory and Method (2001), among many
others. Though its researchers are known primarily as ethnographically inclined, its proponents advocated a variety of research methods,
depending on the particular problem under study.
The School also offers a distinctive interactionist
theoretical alternative to the quantitative research position that views people as isolated individuals whose ideas and attitudes can be captured
through statistical instruments such as surveys.
For the Chicago School, social interaction shapes
group and individual identity. Researchers must
immerse themselves in the group that they are
studying in order to grasp how perceptions of
self and society arise within these complex
61
Chicano studies
social relations, and in turn are impacted by social
structure.
KENNETH H. TUCKER
Chicano studies
These studies had their origins in the student
activism, identity politics, and intellectual
foment of the civil rights movement of the
1960s. Like the other nationalist movements
of the era, it emerged as a field of scholarly inquiry that placed special emphasis on linking
academic research with the politics of social
justice. It made explicit that link between
activism and scholarship through terms like
action research and consciously sought to improve the educational, social, and political status
of the Mexican-origin population in the United
States.
The founding moment of Chicano studies occurred in spring 1969 when a group of Chicano/
Chicana activists and educators met at the University of California, Santa Barbara, to draft El Plan de
Santa Barbara. This foundation document called
for the creation of Chicano studies departments
devoted to a curriculum and scholarship that
addressed the unique historical experiences and
contemporary condition of people of Mexican descent. It recognized the central role of knowledge
in the reproduction of social inequality within our
communities but also in producing meaningful
strategies of social change and community
empowerment.
The initial focus of the emerging field was on
recovering the historical experience of the Chicano population in the southwestern United
States and contesting previous interpretations of
that history. Special emphasis was placed on the
legacy of community organizing and labor activism in various industries in which the Mexican
American population had toiled under onerous
working conditions. Rodolfo Acuna’s Occupied
American: The Chicano’s Struggle Toward Liberation
(1972) and Mario Barerra’s Race and Class in the
Southwest: A Theory of Racial Inequality (1979) were
emblematic of this early historical recovery project. Both works drew upon various theoretical
perspectives – Marxism, political economy, internal colonialism, and labor market segmentation – to advance a revisionist Chicano history in
the American southwest. Professional associations
such as the National Association for Chicano and
Chicana Studies, founded in 1972, further advanced the explicit connection between scholarship and activism and the importance of
ideological struggle in the academy.
62
Chicano studies
From the very beginning, Chicana activists
and scholars ensured that the experience of
women of Mexican descent was central to both
the scholarship and activism in Chicano studies.
The male-centered, masculinist, and “heteronormative” underpinnings of early works in the field
were rapidly accompanied by a more complex
rendering of those experiences and the multiplicity of social identities within the Chicano
population. Cherrie Moraga’s Loving in the War
Years (1983) and Gloria Anzaldua’s Borderlands /
La Frontera: The New Mestiza (1987) were emblematic of this de-centering of the Chicano male
subject and the move towards a more complex
and nuanced construction of the Chicana subject. While revisionist histories continued in
importance, works such as these were more interdisciplinary and literary in approach and drew
upon feminism, postmodernism, poststructuralism, and cultural studies in reframing the Chicana subject and other marginalized identities.
They challenged not only the masculinist production of knowledge in the field, but also the paradigms, methodologies, and pedagogy inherited
from traditional academic disciplines and area
studies.
More recently, issues pertaining to the social
construction of gender, sexuality, gay/lesbian subjectivities through literature and popular culture,
as well as globalization, transnationalization, and
migration processes, have reached center stage in
Chicano studies. The field is increasingly constructing a more complex and situated rendering
of the Chicano/Chicana subject and, in the process, exploring the multiplicity of identities in
all their myriad and hybrid forms.
At the present time, there are over 35 million
Latinos in the United States (65 percent of whom
are Chicano or of Mexican descent). Latinos have
now surpassed African Americans as the largest
minority group in the United States and play an
increasing and undeniably important role. For
example, one-third of California’s population is
of Mexican descent and nearly one-half of the
school-age children in the state are from this background. For these demographic reasons alone,
Chicano studies will increasingly become an important area of academic inquiry for anyone interested in race relations and the diversity of
modern life in the United States. As in its inception, political activism and the ongoing struggle
for social justice will continue to play a central
role in the evolution of Chicano studies in the
future.
TOMAS ALMAGUER
childhood/children
childhood/children
Sociology as a discipline did not display much
interest in children until the end of the twentieth
century (A. James and A. Prout, Constructing and
Reconstructing Childhood, 1990). Childhood was perceived as being mainly in the domain of psychology, education, or perhaps history, and children
themselves rarely appeared as sociological actors
who could influence events or who might matter
particularly. Traditionally, the sociological interest in children was embedded in the notion of
socialization. Thus, one of the main functions
of the family was seen to be the socialization of
children into the next generation of workers,
or parents, or even criminals. The experience of
being a child was not an issue of sociological enquiry, although the question of what children
might become when they reached adolescence or
adulthood was important. Thus children were
important in terms of their future as adults, not
in terms of what they might “be” or “do” as
children.
It is perhaps accurate to suggest that, while
sociology had little interest in children per se, it
did have more of an interest in childhood because,
like parenthood, or the family, or the education
system, childhood was conceptualized as a social
institution rather than a naturally occurring phenomenon. The work of the social historian
Philippe Ariès in his Centuries of Childhood (1962)
was highly significant in challenging any naturalistic assumptions about childhood by showing
how the institution changed at different moments
in history, and by revealing how our ideas of what
a child might be (including what a child could and
should do) have changed dramatically according
to time and place. Other historical studies which
have compared nineteenth-century childhood
with contemporary childhood, or working-class
childhood with middle-class childhood, have managed to show that there can be a huge variation
in cultural expectations of children (for example
Eric Hopkins, Childhood Transformed, 1994). Even
defining what a child is, or when childhood starts
and finishes, is open to contestation. The boundaries between the infant, the toddler, the child,
the adolescent, the teenager, and the young adult
blur as cultural norms and material circumstances change. For example, it was traditionally
assumed that a child became an adult on reaching
puberty (for girls in nineteenth-century England
this might have been as late as sixteen or eighteen). However, modern lifestyles and diets (in the
West at least) have affected physical rates of
childhood/children
growth so that puberty comes earlier (for example
ten or eleven years for girls). This means that
traditional indicators of maturity become less
relevant and it is less sensible to rely on the body
to act as the visible marker of transition from
childhood to adulthood.
Ariès pointed to the lack of differentiation between “the adult” and “the child” under the ancien
régime, and the very strict differentiation between
the generations that grew up in the Victorian era
– especially for middle-class children. For Ariès
childhood is a modern invention. This challenge
to the idea of childhood as a natural state has
given rise to sociological debates about whether
contemporary cultures are now molding childhood in problematic ways. For example, some
recent work on childhood has started to document the end of childhood, and to argue that
modern society is truncating childhood. The endof-childhood thesis points to such factors as the
premature sexualization of children, the growth
of children’s fashions and styles of dress which are
similar to adult styles, the rise of the child as a
consumer in capitalist societies, and of course the
impact on children of the media, which are seen
to introduce them to adult realities such as violence long before it is necessary. Ranged against
the end-of-childhood thesis is an alternative perspective which points to the way in which developed welfare states now almost refuse to let
children become adults. This is achieved through
policies which enforce prolonged economic dependence on parents, extend full-time education
to eighteen or even twenty-one years, and apply
restrictions on access to such things as paid employment, birth control, abortion, or alcohol.
These policies which keep young adults in a state
of dependency are, it is argued, exacerbated by an
over-protectiveness in parents which means that
children are escorted by an adult wherever they go
(for example school, friends’ houses, playgrounds,
and so on). Modern children, it is argued, are kept
in a state of emotional and economic dependency
for longer than previous generations.
These analyses of childhood are, of course, derived mainly from wealthy industrialized societies. They do not reflect the material realities,
nor social meanings, of childhood as it may be
experienced in countries such as Thailand, China,
or Japan, or in African countries. Moreover, they
may not even reflect all childhoods found in
western societies because of the tendency to overlook the different forms that childhood might
take in minority ethnic or religious communities,
63
Chodorow, Nancy (1944– )
or among refugees, or among traveler families.
For this reason, it has become increasingly important to think in terms of the diversity of childhoods
which may co-exist locally and globally.
Alongside this expansion in sociological understandings of childhood(s) (for example Chris
Jencks, Childhood, 1996) we have witnessed the
growth of what is increasingly referred to as the
“standpoint” of children (Berry Mayall, Towards a
Sociology for Childhood, 2002). There is an interest in
the experience of being a child and a parallel
concern to try to appreciate social reality from
the point of view of children themselves. This has
given rise to many empirical projects which allow
children to express their own understandings of
the social world – rather than relying on teachers
or parents to convey what children might think or
feel. This shift towards including the standpoint
of children has started to produce a conceptual
change in the discipline, comparable to the way in
which the introduction of the standpoint of
women transformed sociology in the 1980s. As a
discipline, sociology is starting to appreciate how
“adultist” it has been and, just as it has had to
come to terms with other neglected aspects of
power relations, such as racism, sexism, ageism,
and heteronormativity, so it has started to analyze
more systematically power that is exercised between the generations.
CAROL SMART
Chodorow, Nancy (1944– )
Obtaining her BA from Radcliffe College and then,
in 1975, her PhD from Brandeis University, Nancy
Chodorow is currently Professor of Sociology at
the University of California, Berkeley.
Chodorow’s The Reproduction of Mothering (1978),
was a feminist rethinking of Sigmund Freud’s version of childhood development. Because of his
patriarchal environment, Freud did not understand how females develop a gender identity. Chodorow reformulates Freud’s theory of female
socialization. She argues that the infant’s relationship to the mother, rather than the father, is the
crucial bond in an infant’s life. Gender identity is
rooted in the infant’s relationship to the mother
because in most families mothers have responsibility for child rearing. Girls have a more continuous relationship with their mother than do boys.
Accordingly, they develop a more complex gender
identity in which nurturing, caring, and sensitivity are more important than the rigid ego
boundaries and competition important to males.
Chodorow contends that most societies value
these male traits more than female values, so
64
church–sect typology
that women’s distinctive psychology and culture
are undervalued.
Chodorow’s work has influenced the work of
many feminist thinkers, from Lillian Rubin’s Intimate Strangers (1983) to Carol Gilligan’s In a Different Voice (1982). Chodorow has been criticized for
generalizing the experience of middle-class white
women to all women, and neglecting cultural
factors in psychological development. In her
most recent work, Femininities, Masculinities, Sexualities (1994) and The Power of Feelings (1999), she
addresses these criticisms, arguing that culture
intersects with psychological development in
complex ways, and that researchers should be
wary of universal generalizations about gender
differences.
KENNETH H. TUCKER, JR.
church–sect typology
This typology derives from Max Weber and was
also popularized by the Christian theologian,
Ernst Troeltsch, who was interested in elaborating
different types of religious experiences. Weber’s
ideal-typical distinction in Economy and Society
(1922 [trans. 1978]) between church and sect was
part of his theoretical analysis of the rationalization of different forms of legitimation and authority. Weber identified four characteristics of a
church: (1) a professional priesthood; (2) claims
to universal domination, such as the elimination
of ethnic or national barriers; (3) the rationalization of doctrine and rites; and (4) compulsory
membership by birth, all of whom (whether believers or not) are subject to the church’s charisma
and discipline. Distinctive to a church is the separation of charisma from the person and its linkage instead to the institutional office (hierocracy),
an office charisma (or grace) of which the church
is the universal expression and trustee.
By contrast, a sect is a voluntary association or
community of personally charismatic individuals
whose charisma or qualification must be publicly
demonstrated (for example through rebaptism for
Baptists). In Weber’s definition, a sect is a select
group whose associational claims in essence preclude universality and require the free consent of
its qualified members; it is not a group that splits
off from another because of persecution or condemnation. Sects typically reject office charisma,
adhering instead to a democratic model whereby
authority lies in the congregation, who, through
daily knowledge of the individuals in the community, are qualified to determine who among them
is visibly deserving of sect membership. Although
sect membership is voluntary, based on individual
Cicourel, Aaron Victor (1928– )
choice rather than ascribed by birth, admission
and continued participation is contingent on
the individual’s consistent adherence in everyday
life to the sect’s religious beliefs and moral
standards.
The sect community functions as a selection
apparatus for separating the qualified from the
unqualified, and for ensuring that qualified
members interact with each other rather than
with nonmembers. Although a negative consequence of this boundary maintenance is that it
encourages withdrawal from, rather than engagement or accommodation with, the nonqualified, a
positive function is the solidarity and social
integration that sects provide their members,
especially necessary for blunting the anomie and
alienation found in highly mobile modern societies and among diasporic religions (such as Judaism). Moreover, Weber argued, the high moral and
ascetic standards typically associated with sects
means that their business interests thrive, because
members and nonmembers alike trust their
economic security to them. Although the small
congregation is best suited to monitoring sect
members’ behavior, Weber emphasized that a
sect is not a small group; as he noted, the Baptists
are one of the most typical sects and also one of
the largest Protestant denominations in the world.
The contrasting universal and compulsory
claims of a church against the selective and voluntary nature of a sect are particularly useful in
understanding how different emphases on freedom and especially on freedom of conscience
filter into public debates and assumptions about
the relation between church and state. Whereas a
church would typically argue for the universal
applicability of its moral teachings to human society, a sect would typically argue in favor of a
differentiation between religious and political
matters.
MICHELE DILLON
Cicourel, Aaron Victor (1928– )
An American sociologist, who contributed seminal work to cognitive sociology and ethnomethodology, Cicourel received his BA and MA
from the University of California, Los Angeles, in
1951 and 1953 respectively, and his PhD from
Cornell University in 1957. Cicourel has taught
all over the world but primarily within the
University of California system, and is currently
Research Professor of Cognitive Science, Pediatrics, and Sociology at the University of California,
San Diego. Cicourel has made important contributions to the sociology of education, law and
citizenship
society, medical sociology, methodology, and
sociological theory. The bulk of his research has
focused on the nature and function of tacit knowledge in social interaction, particularly in institutional settings. His fundamental interest has been
to reveal the internalized interpretive schema
that govern how social actors assign meaning
and relevance to objects in their environments
and how they discern the relevance of social
norms and social roles in specific practical situations. More specifically, his research explored
how tacit knowledge and tacit social competences
underlie and inform language use, practical
inference, and the application of standardized
procedures in different social organizational contexts. Cicourel is particularly well known for a
series of groundbreaking articles and books including “The Use of Official Statistics” (1963,
Social Problems, with John Kitsuse), Method and Measurement in Sociology (1964), and Cognitive Sociology
(1974), wherein he articulates a foundational critique of sociological research methodologies that
fail to attend adequately to the tacit presuppositions and social competences that underlie
their application in actual instances of empirical
research.
DARIN WEINBERG
citizenship
The notion of citizenship can be traced back to the
Greek polis that tied rights to membership of the
city, excluding women and slaves. The modern
version of citizenship is connected to the twin
processes of nation building and industrialization
following the American and French Revolutions.
Freedom of contract and protection of property
rights were important elements, and the growth
of markets contributed to breaking down traditional hierarchies and to fostering equality and
opportunity.
Citizenship has become a key concept at the
center of policy debates within and across national borders. T. H. Marshall, in Citizenship and
Social Class (1950), first developed a modern framework for the notion of citizenship based upon
principles of freedom, equality, and solidarity.
Since then citizenship has had a double focus: as
a vision of equal rights and respect, and as a tool
to analyze the social and political development of
modern societies.
In social science, citizenship has become a
key concept, and studies have focused both on
social rights (in sociology) and on participation
(in political science). Citizenship has different
meanings, institutional designs, and patterns
65
citizenship
cross-nationally. The definition includes three different dimensions: (1) individual rights and obligations; (2) political participation including the
right to vote; and (3) belonging to a nation-state.
Modern citizenship has proved to be Janus-faced:
it can express both exclusionary and inclusionary
state practices and be a basis for discipline as well
as resistance.
Today immigration, globalization, and Europeanization have challenged the meaning and
practice of citizenship and new forms of claimsmaking by minority groups have widened the
content of citizenship. This has raised questions
about what a good citizen is, whether citizenship
can be transferred from the nation-state to the
transnational level, and whether it is possible to
combine citizenship rights tied to the nation-state
to global citizenship and human rights?
In Marshall’s seminal work, citizenship was defined as “a status bestowed on those who are full
members of a community.” All citizens should
have the same rights and duties. Marshall’s work
was based on a vision of equal rights for the
working class in capitalist society inspired by the
evolution of civil, political, and social rights in
Britain from the eighteenth to the twentieth
century.
Citizenship is part of the two major political
traditions of civic republicanism and liberalism.
Liberalism has been preoccupied with the defense
of the freedom of individuals and civil rights vis-àvis the state, and has given priority to the private
virtues of individuals over public virtues. This
understanding has been criticized, because it
tends to underestimate the need for an active
state to defend political liberty and for a political
community that can defend individual freedom.
Civic republicanism has been preoccupied with
the creation of a just society, and it has given
priority to the creation of solidarity between citizens tied together in a political community. This
understanding has been criticized because it
underestimates civil rights and tends to subsume
individuals under the needs of the political community. Communitarianism has a strong emphasis
on belonging to the political community and
can be understood either as a form of civic
republicanism or as a separate tradition.
Marshall’s framework has become a key reference for analysis of contemporary citizenship
from a cross-national context and has also been
taken up by marginalized social groups. It has
been criticized for its Anglo- and Eurocentric bias
as well as for its male bias, because it was premised upon the reality and vision of a British model
66
citizenship
and on the second-class citizenship of women and
minorities.
A number of scholars have tried to rethink the
framework of citizenship from a historical and
comparative perspective. One example is Bryan
Turner who, in his article “Outline of a Theory of
Citizenship” in Sociology (1990), introduced a
model that aims to identify political dynamics as
well as variations in citizenship regimes: (1) an
active/passive dimension that expresses how citizenship rights became institutionalized in
modern democracies “from above” by the involvement of the monarchy or “from below” through
revolutionary movements; (2) a public/private dimension that expresses whether citizenship rights
and norm(s) are associated with the public or
private arena.
The first differentiates between an active, participatory republican model and a model with
institutionalization “from above.” The second differentiates between a liberal model – with an
emphasis on private, individual rights and a passive state – and a model that emphasizes public
virtues and an active state.
Another example is Richard Bellamy, Dario
Castiglione and Emilio Santoro’s recent study,
Lineages of Citizenship: Rights, Belonging and Participation in Eleven Nation States (2004). It gives an
overview of the different legal traditions and historical contexts which have contributed to creating various liberalisms and republicanisms. This
study differentiates between a “polity” dimension,
which specifies the territorial and functional
spheres – seeing the subjects either as passive
or active – and a “regime” dimension, which refers
to the political arrangements and styles of governance, the scope of intervention in private life.
The three main European traditions – the
German, the French, and the British – correspond
to some extent to the three legal citizenship traditions: the ethno-cultural definition of nationality
(jus sanguinis), the romantic definition of nationality (jus soli) and the English common law. Since the
1990s, political developments in relation to immigration and asylum have moved the three closer
together.
Marshall’s focus was on the social and political
inclusion of the working class in society, while
post-Marshallian frameworks raise new issues
and debates. Gender and marginalized social
groups represent a major challenge for the universal framework of citizenship to respect diversity.
This tension between equality and difference/diversity has inspired alternative frameworks,
models, and designs.
citizenship
Carole Pateman, in The Sexual Contract (1988),
presented one of the first feminist approaches to
citizenship. She analyzed the dilemma of Mary
Wollstonecraft (1759–97) that illustrates that
women in modern societies are caught between
a strategy focusing on equality and inclusion of
women as equal citizens that tends to deny their
particularity “as women,” and a strategy focusing
on inclusion of their difference and particularity
that tends to reproduce inequality. Ruth Lister, in
Citizenship: Feminist Perspectives (1997), has noticed
that the tension between the universalistic ethic
of justice and the particularistic ethic of care that
gives equal status to women and men in their
diversity is a creative tension that can be overcome by a “differentiated universalism.”
Another influential approach has introduced
models that link the inclusion of women with
marginal social groups. One example is Iris Young,
who, in Justice and the Political Difference (1990), emphasizes inclusion and empowerment “from
below.” Another example is Anne Phillips,
who, in The Politics of Presence (1995), emphasizes
inclusion “from above” through a change of the
institutional design.
In the development towards multicultural societies, ethnicity tends to become an independent
factor explaining differentiation in citizenship
rights. Ruud Koopman and Paul Statham, editors
of Challenging Immigration and Ethnic Relations Politics. Comparative European Perspectives (2000), have
introduced an institutional model with two dimensions that is used in comparisons between different
ethnicity regimes. One is the formal and legal
basis for citizenship – the vertical dimension – that
places a regime between an ethno-cultural – jus
sanguinis – and a territorial – jus soli – pole. The
other is a political-cultural – horizontal – dimension, that places a regime between cultural
monism (assimilation) and cultural pluralism.
Multiculturalism has also inspired normative
models that stress minority rights. One example
is in Will Kymlicka’s Multicultural Citizenship (1995),
which introduced the notion of multicultural citizenship based on group rights of minorities. He
differentiates between rights of autonomy for
national minorities, for example aboriginals;
poly-ethnic rights such as financial support and
legal protection of ethnic and religious groups;
and rights of representation involving, for instance, guaranteed seats to ethnic and national
minorities. The multicultural approach has initiated a debate about multiculturalism and gender
equality, and, in a famous article, Susan Moller
Okin (1999), in the volume edited by J. Cohen,
citizenship
M. Howard and M. C. Neusbaum on Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?, considers whether multiculturalism is incompatible with gender equality.
Sexual and ecological citizenship are examples
of new meanings of citizenship. In Citizenship: Feminist Perspectives, Lister defines sexual citizenship as
the claims for sexual autonomy by women, lesbians, and gays. The politics of citizenship thus
promotes the citizenship status of sexual minorities and articulates new claims to “sexual rights,”
understood as “a set of rights to sexual expression
and consumption.” Ecological citizenship refers
both to rights and responsibilities of citizens
and to their relationship to nature and the wider
environment, for example green activism.
Finally, globalization and European integration
have inspired a notion of post-national citizenship. Marshall’s framework was tied to the
nation-state, but membership of a community
allows for a broader discourse about local and
global levels of citizenship. It is contested whether
the vision of a global citizenship can become a
reality and what kind of model of global citizen
should indeed prevail. Skeptics argue that the
state has the power to exclude outsiders through
the policing of the boundaries of citizenship and
residence. Optimists (such as Derek Heater in
World Citizenship, 2003) have argued that globalization could become the basis for a multi-layered
conceptualization of citizenships that would embrace the notion of global citizenship and the use
of international human rights law.
One key issue in the current debate about
cosmopolitanism is whether it is possible to transform the values of responsibility, individual
rights, and democracy associated with nationstate citizenship to the international level?
The globalization of rights and responsibilities
can be seen as the essence of a globalization of
citizenship. David Held and Anthony McGrew in
Globalization/Anti-globalization (2002) differentiate
between a strategy for cosmopolitan democracy
aiming to develop a set of democratic institutions
at the global level and a strategy for radical democracy aimed at forming a global civil society
“from below,” through which social movements
and nongovernmental organizations can pursue
their goals across national borders.
Global governance has created both problems
and opportunities for democracy. Markets are
hard to control, but political globalization may
be used to expand democracy and human rights
through the “human rights regime” – that is,
an international framework for the protection of
human rights. The international movement for
67
city
women’s rights as human rights is one example of
an expansion of the scope of human rights to
protect women.
It is contested whether the discourse of human
rights is more appropriate once we live outside
the confines of the nation-state? Bryan Turner in
his “Outline of a Theory of Human Rights” in
Sociology (1993) has argued that there is a need
for a sociological theory of human rights as a
supplement to the theory of citizenship. There is
also a need for a global concept of citizenship that
can contribute to focusing the responsibilities of
the more affluent nation-states vis-à-vis those societies in the “developing world” that lack the resources to translate the development of human
rights, as defined in the UN Covenant, into effective citizenship rights.
Another main issue is the dilemma connected
to EU citizenship. The European Union has given
citizens new rights, for example attached to paid
work, but many scholars find that the European
Union is an elitist project of nation-building
where rights are the entitlements of subjects
rather than citizens. On the one hand, the European Parliament has obtained more power,
but on the other hand there is a democratic
deficit, and political identities are still tied to
local, regional, and national communities rather
than to transnational politics. There have been
developments in EU citizenship, and the antidiscrimination doctrine of the Amsterdam Treaty
that incorporates race, ethnicity, and sexual
preference in anti-discrimination law may suggest a more inclusive definition of rights and
protection in the European Union.
Globalization and migration have made new
claims from minorities for recognition and respect for diversity into a contested question for
nation-states and the global community. At
the analytical level, it is a challenge to develop
institutions that may help to bridge the tension
between equality and respect for diversity. At the
normative level, it is a challenge to develop a vision
for an inclusionary and multi-layered citizenship
that is able to reconcile national belongings with a
transnational notion of citizenship.
BIRTE SIIM
city
Given the dramatic increase in urbanization in the
nineteenth century and the claim of much social
theory and sociology to be an analysis of contemporary societies, it is surprising that the nature of
contemporary cities was not deemed worthy of
wider study. F. Engels’s 1844 study of the urban
68
city
working class in Manchester and elsewhere and
his writings on the housing question must be set
against Karl Marx’s neglect of cities in his analysis
of capitalism, despite his statement that the division between town and country is one of great
historical importance. Of the major sociologists
around 1900, only Max Weber provided a historical analysis of the rise of towns and cities.
Although many of the analyses of dimensions of
contemporary society by Weber, Émile Durkheim,
Ferdinand Tönnies, Werner Sombart, and others
clearly presupposed a metropolitan modernity,
this was seldom reflected upon in any detail.
Only Georg Simmel made the modern metropolis
one of the sites of modernity.
Beyond the confines of sociology, there was an
increasing interest in the nature of the modern
city and its populations. This concern took the
form of early ethnographies such as the studies
of London by Henry Mayhew (1812–87), and, later,
the London survey by Charles Booth (1840–1916),
and W. E. B. Du Bois’s study of segregation in
Philadelphia. Both the state and local city authorities also increasingly devoted attention to their
populations, as evidenced in population surveys
and other statistical compilations and modes of
governance. By the late nineteenth century in Germany, for example, which experienced one of the
greatest urban expansions since its unification in
1870, the issue had arisen as to what constituted a
city. The statistically expedient but by no means
unproblematic solution was to declare an urban
concentration with 100,000 or more inhabitants
as a city, while a world city or metropolis had a
population of 1 million (in 1900, only Berlin
achieved this status).
In part influenced by Simmel’s concern with
modes of “sociation” in the city, the Chicago
School of the early twentieth century had a major
impact upon the study of the city. Yet its key
figures Robert Park, Ernest Burgess, and Louis
Wirth did not have a unified research program.
Rather, their focus upon the city was diverse,
ranging from studies of land use and social segregation, through the city as a social laboratory,
programs of social reform, the ecology of the
city, and urban ethnographies, to the urban
way of life in modernity. It could be argued that
the ethnographic tradition is what has remained
significant for later study of the city.
In more recent decades, the turn to the political
economy of cities has been in evidence, whether it
be as sites of collective consumption and the local
state (Manuel Castells, The Urban Question, 1977),
city
the production and reproduction of urban capital
(David Harvey, Social Justice and the City, 1973, and
Consciousness and the Urban Experience, 1985), or,
more recently, global cities and their networks
(Saskia Sassen, Global Cities, 2001). The city has
also been examined in a more differentiated
manner, somewhat belatedly exploring gendered
urban spaces. This has been accompanied since
the mid-1980s by explorations of new dimensions
of the modern/postmodern city (David Harvey,
The Postmodern Condition, 1989; Michael J. Dear,
The Postmodern Urban Condition, 2000; Nan
Ellin, Postmodern Urbanism, 1999); the space of
flows in the information economy and the emergence of the dual city and changes in the occupational structure (Manuel Castells, The Informational
City, 1989); postcolonial cities in the world economy; the uneven development between and
within cities, including gentrification and economies of consumption; transformations of the
public sphere within cities; cybercities (Christine
M. Boyer, Cybercities, 1996); and the disjunction
between suburbanization and the metropolis.
Many of these transformations have been associated with the supercession of place by space as
the focus of analysis. In part, this coincided with
a focus upon urban space, prompted by Henri
Lefebvre (1901–91) and others. Modifying
Lefebvre’s tripartite conceptualization in The Production of Space (1991) into the production of urban
space, the representations of urban space and
spatial practices also drew attention to the representations, images, and imaginaries of the city, as
well as how the city is negotiated and contested in
everyday practices (as in Michel de Certeau’s analysis of taking a walk [The Practice of Everyday Life,
1984]).
The study of representations of the city is indicative of wider interest in images of the city that
were already present, if often only implicitly in
earlier characterizations of the city. The city has
been variously viewed, for instance, as a moral
and political order, as a social and medical problem, as an aesthetic object, as a work of art, as
ensemble of communities, as absent community,
as utopian site, as dystopia, as apocalyptic site.
The significance of cultural dimensions of economic aspects of the city and the problems of
reading the city have been given fresh impetus
in the reception of writers such as Walter
Benjamin, whose work seems at some distance
from urban sociology. His treatments of the city
as text, as narrative, as dream-world, as site of
collective memory / collective forgetting, as
civic culture
spectacle, as visual regime, recognize the city as
not merely an agglomeration of silent built structures, as a concentration of producers and consumers, but also as imaginary, as aspiration. The
often fragmentary experiences of the city, the
shaping of everyday life in the city, everyday practices and the constitution of images of the city,
contested spaces and boundaries, and modes of
resistance are also consistent elements in understanding the contemporary city.
DAVID FRISBY
civic culture
Also referred to as political culture, this is the
culture, beliefs, and values that direct a political
system, but the study of such cultures also involves attending to the institutions that bring
about political socialization. The term became influential in political sociology following the publication of Gabriel Almond and Sydney Verba’s The
Civic Culture (1963) in which they argued that the
success of stable democracy was the result of civic
institutions promoting democratic participation
and creating opportunities for commitment and
trust. The idea of political culture is thus closely
connected with the idea of civil society. Almond
and Verba undertook a comparative study of five
countries – the United States, Italy, United Kingdom, Mexico, and West Germany. For various
historical and structural reasons, the United
States and the United Kingdom have vibrant civic
cultures because these societies have many local
and national channels whereby ordinary individuals can participate in political processes such
as voting, registering opinions, selecting political
leaders, and influencing political opinion. Their
research has been criticized in methodological
terms by Robert Dowse and John Hughes in Political Sociology (1986) on the grounds that surveys
and questionnaires cannot easily tap into political
cultures. Another criticism is that each social
class will have its own political culture
and therefore, where social class divisions are significant, it would be misleading to presuppose a
unified civic culture. In other words, Almond
and Verba did not take into account the issue of
internal variations in political cultures. Another
critical response, which was developed by Michael
Mann in Consciousness and Action among the western
Working Class (1973), has been to argue that liberal
democracies survive because the working class
have a “pragmatic acceptance” of their place
in capitalism and because there is a general lack
of any consistent commitment to values in
the society.
BRYAN S. TURNER
69
civil religion
civil religion
This is a term initially used by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78) and reintroduced to sociology
by Robert N. Bellah in a highly influential essay
published in the mid-1960s, “Civil Religion in
America” (1967). Extending Émile Durkheim’s
understanding that all things in society can be
classified as either sacred or profane, Bellah developed the idea that, quite apart from institutionalized church religion, American society also
has a publicly articulated and institutionalized
civil or civic religion that anchors the civic culture.
In the United States, Bellah argued, the “American
way of life,” the core founding values and ideals of
the republic, are given a sacred meaning in and of
themselves, and are given an added religious dimension by their intertwining with specifically
religious motifs, most usually drawn from biblical
archetypes. In pluralistic societies wherein religious denominational beliefs may have a sectarian
function, the affirmation of the nation’s civil religion serves social integration rather than fragmentation. A civil religion blends sacred cultural
ideas and symbols with religious affirmations and
is invoked to unify the nation and strengthen the
shared communality of its people, to provide an
“imagined community” out of diversity. A society’s
civil religion is most evident during highly ceremonial public rituals – presidential inaugurations, parliamentary convocations, and other
symbolically rich public events (assemblies, protests) that take place at the country’s sacred (civic)
places. The complexity of a civil religion lies in the
tension between appealing to sufficiently broad
(nonsectarian) religious symbols and to the
society’s high ideals (for example equality), while
simultaneously not being appropriated in a
sectarian manner to legitimate public policies
that in practice may threaten rather than enrich
social solidarity.
MICHELE DILLON
civil rights
– see rights.
civil rights movement
– see social movements.
civil society
An expression that became influential in eighteenth-century theories about the individual,
social contract, and the state, this denotes an
area of social consensus based on agreements
about norms and values. Whereas the state requires some level of force, civil society implies a
degree of freedom. The concept was used by Adam
70
civil society
Ferguson (1723–1816) in his An Essay on the History
of Civil Society (1767) to make a contrast between
the civilization of western Europe and the despotism of the East. The connection between “civil
society” and “civility” and “civilization” was
made clear in Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s
The Philosophy of Right (1821 [trans. 1942]), where
the German term is bürgerliche Gesellschaft. He recognized civil society as a specific area of ethical
life, which exists or mediates between the family
and the state. The word family was originally associated with oikos or “household,” and the word
economy originally referred to the running of a
household. In short, Hegel saw civil society as
existing between the state (a coercive institution)
and the economy (an institution based on selfinterest). The freedom of the individual and the
enjoyment of rights were made possible by
the historical evolution of civil society as a manifestation of bourgeois civilization.
The adjective bürgerlich means “civil, civic” and
also “middle-class, bourgeois.” Civil society is thus
an area of social life that contrasts the world of
the bourgeoisie from those of the nobility and
clergy. These notions are also closely connected
with the idea of citizenship.
Gesellschaft or “society” derives from Geselle or
“companion.” Sociology is the scientific study
of society or Gesellschaftwissenschaft. It became commonplace in sociology to distinguish between
affective social ties and more abstract social
relations. Thus Ferdinand Tönnies made an
important distinction between organic communities (Gemeinschaft) and mechanical association
(Gesellschaft) in his Community and Association (1887
[trans. 1957]).
The concept of civil society was shared by both
liberalism and socialism, albeit with different significance. For John Locke (1632–1704) in the Two
Treatises of Government (1690) the social contract
was necessary to protect the individual and property rights, and it was this contract that created
civil society in contrast to the “state of nature.”
Liberal civil society requires limited government,
the separation of powers, the rule of law, and rule
by representative government. These political institutions are important for securing civil society,
but Locke argued that a primary responsibility of
government was the protection of property. Locke
has been attacked by, for example, C. B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism
(1962), for providing a crass defence of capitalism.
In contrast, John Dunn, Western Political Theory in
the Face of the Future (1979: 39), argues that, in the
language of his day, Locke treated “property” and
civil society
“right” synonymously, and hence Macpherson’s
criticism represents a translation error.
Karl Marx was critical of Hegel’s understanding
of civil society and, in his Economic and Philosophical
Manuscripts (1844 [trans. 1964]), he argued that
bourgeois society was characterized by economic
self-interest and the struggle between social
classes. Civil society was not an arena of civilized
co-operation, but the epitome of bourgeois culture
which merely masked the objective struggle
between irreconcilable classes.
The idea of civil society was revived in the twentieth century by the work of the Italian Marxist
revolutionary Antonio Gramsci, who argued that
the state was a mixture of force plus consent, or
hegemony with coercion. While political society
organizes force, civil society is that set of social
institutions that provides consent. The leadership
of the working class by intellectuals requires the
transformation of civil society by political education if the dominant hegemony is to be challenged. Gramsci recognized that, because the
Roman Catholic Church was influential in providing moral leadership in Italy, it was necessary
to provide a moral alternative at the local level.
This tradition of analysis of civil society has been
continued, for example, by Norberto Bobbio,
Democracy and Dictatorship (1980 [trans. 1989]).
The notion of “civil society” continues to be
important in contemporary sociology because
the vitality of civic institutions is seen to be essential for sustaining democracy. Civil society is also
the public sphere within which opinions are
formed, developed, and exchanged. This arena of
debate is important in the minimal sense that it
permits lively criticism of government policies
and ministers. One function of bourgeois society
was that it created social spaces in which conversation, debate, and criticism could take place. The
idea that the transformation of mass media and
communications by the monopolistic ownership
of newspapers, radio, TV, and film has seriously
curtailed the possibility of critical dialog and argument was put forward by Jürgen Habermas in
his The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere
(1962 [trans. 1989]).
Habermas’s pessimistic view of modern society
has in turn been challenged by sociologists, partly
influenced by the idea of network society in
Manuel Castells, who claim that modern electronic technology – such as cell phones and computers – has created new opportunities for debate
and dialogue. These technologies make possible a
new global civil society which cannot be easily
controlled by the state, and they allow rapid,
civilization
cheap means of political discussion. If the coffee
house was the principal site of Habermas’s traditional bourgeois public sphere, where newspapers could be read and debated over coffee,
the cyber café is the location of the new forms of
information exchange.
BRYAN S. TURNER
civilization
A concept referring to an advanced stage or condition of organized social life and social development, often used in distinction to primitive
societies, the most important contribution to an
understanding of civilization comes from Norbert
Elias. In The Civilizing Process (1939 [trans. 2000]),
Elias examines the sociogenesis and the social
function of the concept. He argues that the term
was formed in the second half of the eighteenth
century, replacing the concepts of politesse or civilité which, before its arrival, had formed the same
function: to express the self-image and specific
kind of behavior of the European upper class, in
relation to others whom its members considered
simpler or more primitive. One of its earliest
usages is found in the work of the Comte de Mirabeau, Honoré-Gasriel Riqueti (1749–91), who reformulated the concept of Homme civilisé while
simultaneously drawing on the progressivism
and reformism prevalent in the Parisian circles
of court society. Like the Physiocrats, he believed
that social events followed laws, and that a knowledge and understanding of these laws could be
used as a progressive force by kings in their rule.
Civilization stood between barbarism and a false
“decadent” civilization engendered by a superabundance of money.
Mirabeau’s approach was extended by Enlightenment thinkers, such as Anne-Robert Jacques
Turgot, Baron de l’Aulne (1727–81), and P. H. T.,
Baron d’Holbach (1723–89), who also called for
the improvement of institutions, education, and
law, equally within a reformist framework.
Though society had reached a stage on the road
to civilization, it remained partial and incomplete since the masses remained uncivilized.
This essentially middle-class idea for reform and
the liberation of the broader sections of the population from all that was irrational in existing
conditions, including class restrictions on the
bourgeoisie, became fused with the aristocratic
belief, which was pervasive in court society, that
all others outside this sphere were uncivilized or
barbaric with reference to morals, manners, and
lifestyle.
Though it did not play a considerable role in the
French Revolution, following the revolution it was
71
civilization
used to justify French national expansion and
colonization. Whole nations henceforth began to
consider the process of civilization as completed
within their own societies – while forgetting the
social conditions of its emergence – and came to
see themselves as superior standard-bearers of an
expanding civilization and architects of colonial
conquest. Elias argues that civilization came to
express the self-consciousness of the West: “It
sums up everything in which western society of
the last two or three centuries believes itself superior to earlier societies or ‘more primitive’ contemporary ones” (2000: 5). This pride could be
related to its level of technology, its type of
manners, its development of scientific knowledge,
or to its religious ideas and customs.
However, the term did not mean the same thing
to different nations. The French and English use of
the concept could be contrasted with the German
term, Zivilisation, which, although referring to
something useful, only had a secondary value. It
was the concept of Kultur which expressed the selfimage of the Germans in their own achievements.
While the French and English use of civilization
was expansionary, outward-looking, and emphasized what was common to all human beings,
the German concept of Kultur accentuated national differences and group identity, and was
inward-looking. The conceptual antithesis between culture and civilization reflected the two
different worldviews and the marked social division between a relatively powerless middle-class
German intelligentsia, which emphasized genuineness, personality, sincerity, and intellectual development, on the one hand, and a Frenchspeaking, politically powerful, German court nobility, which championed outward appearance
and manners on the other. This conceptual and
social contraposition in turn reflected the political fragmentation of Germany as compared with
the unified “good society” found in France, in
which the rising middle classes, as already noted,
readily adopted aristocratic traditions and behavioral models, and only showed a moderate reformist opposition to aristocratic world-views. For
Elias, the implications of this were crucial in the
different paths of development of England,
France, and Germany and their subsequent use
of the term.
The contrast between civilization and culture
also formed a crucial conceptual opposition in a
number of books which influenced Elias’s work:
Thomas Mann’s Reflections on a Life (1924), which,
as part of his revolutionary conservative worldview, affirmed inward culture against moralistic
72
class conflict
civilization; Sigmund Freud’s Civilization and Its
Discontents (1930), which examined the conflict
between sexual desires and social mores as the
basis for aggression and violence in modern
civilization; and Oswald Spengler’s Decline of the
West (1918 [trans. 1926 and 1928]), which
employed biological metaphors to argue that cultures pass through cycles in which they rise,
mature, and decline. For Spengler, civilization
was the inevitable destiny of culture, and an expression of its decline: “Civilizations are the most
external and artificial states of which a species of
developed humanity is capable. They are the conclusion, the thing-become succeeding the thingbecoming, death following life, rigidity following
expansion” (31).
Equally, the British historian Arnold Toynbee,
in his comparative study of civilizations in The
Study of History (1934–61), attempted to analyze
the rise and decline of twenty-six civilizations,
while placing an emphasis on religion as a regenerative force. More recently, Samuel Huntington,
in The Clash of Civilizations (1998), has taken the
concept of religion further by understanding civilizations largely as synonyms for it in a conflictridden world.
However, because the concept refers to a
variety of contradictory facts, it has been notoriously difficult to define and use. Émile Durkheim
and Marcel Mauss in “Note on the Notion of
Civilization” (1913 [trans. 1971, Social Research
38]) defined civilizations as referring to phenomena which pass beyond political and national
frontiers: these are “interdependent systems,
which without being limited to a determinate
political organism are however, localizable in
time and space . . . systems of facts that have their
own unity . . . and form of existence a kind of
moral milieu encompassing a certain number of
nations.” More recent writers, by contrast, have
classified civilizations according to the relationship between humans and their environment
(Felipe Fernandez-Armesto, Civilizations, Culture,
Ambition, 2000). Moreover, the connotations of
collective self-approbation, especially by Europeans and Americans, which have become attached to the word have made many social
sciences reluctant to use the concept as an analytical category.
STEVEN LOYAL
civilizing process
– see Norbert Elias.
class conflict
– see social class.
class consciousness
coding
class consciousness
coding
– see social class.
The coding, categorizing, or classification of social
phenomena – an activity described by Robert
Edgerton in “Quality of Life from a Longitudinal
Research Perspective,” featured in Quality of Life:
Perspectives and Issues (1990), as “the American passion for reducing complex qualitative concepts to
simple scalar instruments” – is an essential part of
sociological research methodology under positivism. Coding, in theory, transforms otherwise unwieldy masses of disorderly phenomena, research
participant reports or participant observations,
into tractable data. The process of coding, essentially an exercise in the disaggregation of higherorder social phenomena and the assigning of
numerical codes to theoretically important, and
operationally defined, sub-phenomena (for example
identifying a specific suicide as anomic, egotistical, or altruistic), is a core component of the
experimental method, essential for the statistical
manipulation of data, and the employment of
inferential statistics to make population-based
claims about the generality of sociological issues
employing the logic of the hypothetico-deductive
method.
Coding operates on a number of levels, may
take place either before, during (“field-coding”),
or after data collection, and may index very different practices for different research methods. For
example, what is meant by coding for a study
influenced by grounded theory – with the important methodological and epistemological distinction in such work between the procedures of
latent and of manifest coding of textual material –
differs dramatically from the meaning of coding
to the designer of a study using scales to assess
the intensity of racial prejudice, or questionnaires
to measure quality of life. In the former case, as
with the very limited use of coding in discourse
analysis (where in practice the term often means
little more than the identification of like interpretative repertoires, in much the way one might
“code” one’s socks by their color), the coding of
emergent themes is a posteriori: categories/codes
arise from inspection of the data. In the latter
cases, coding refers to the assignment of a priori
(numerical/value) codes to broad categories of expressed attitudes, beliefs, values, etc., by researchers. An example of an extremely simple coding
scheme is illustrated in R. Schalock and K. Keith’s
Quality of Life Questionnaire (1993). Their semistructured measure of quality of life is presented
in Table 1. As is evident, coding the potentially
infinite possible interviewee responses to the
class interest
– see social class.
cluster analysis
A multivariate statistical technique, used in the
social sciences to divide a heterogeneous sample
into a number of smaller, more homogeneous
clusters, based on their similarity on a number
of variables, there are a number of different ways
of performing a cluster analysis. Small samples
(tens of cases) can be clustered by building the
clusters one link at a time, by joining cases with
their nearest “neighbor” in terms of their similarity on the variables. For larger numbers of cases,
algorithms exist to determine an appropriate
number of clusters, and iteratively allocate each
case to a cluster.
Cluster analysis was developed to deal with biological data (for instance, determining the family
structure of species of plants from the dimensions
of their various components). It rarely gives
such conclusive solutions in the social sciences
(where cluster membership is more complex, and
there can be many cases that do not easily fit into
any of the clusters). But it can be a very useful
exploratory technique, to determine the viability
and usefulness of treating a sample as one whole
or as several sub-samples.
For instance, Brendan Burchell and Jill Rubery
in “An Empirical Investigation into the Segmentation of the Labour Supply” (1990, Work, Employment
and Society) used cluster analyses on a sample
of 600 employees to divide them up into their
different positions and trajectories in the labor
market and to examine the ways in which advantaged and disadvantaged groups of employees are
composed. They described five main clusters, for
which the labor market operated in very different
ways. They interpreted their results as supporting
segmented labor market theories, whereby the
labor market is better characterized as a number
of non-competing groups for whom the relationship between productivity and rewards are very
different. Each of the five clusters was assumed
to represent one segment in the labor market. The
results of this analysis partly supported previous
theoretical accounts of labor markets, but also
revealed new insights into the very different sorts
of labor market disadvantage suffered by males
and females in declining labor markets.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
73
cognitive dissonance
Coleman, James S. (1926–1995)
item “How much fun and enjoyment do you get
out of life?” as 1 (not much), 2 (some), or 3 (lots), is
not only massively to attenuate the substantive
content of all possible responses, but also, of necessity, to engage in an impossibly unreliable exercise (by the standards of the experimental
method) in on-the-spot interpretation.
Table 1. Field coding scheme for prescripted
response alternatives
Item:
How successful
do you think you
are, compared
with others?
Code
description of it to the next subject, but had a
justification for their behavior in the size of the
reward, so did not experience dissonance. The $1
subjects did not have this, and so, as a result of the
experienced conflict, were motivated to revise
their belief as to the inherent interest of the task.
In essence it was a theory of why attitudes and
beliefs change. Subsequent work has elaborated
on what a cognition is, whether or not the aversive motivational state is essential, and the role
played by an individual’s sense of self and identity
in motivating or constraining a change.
DAVID GOOD
cohorts
Response (a)
Probably more successful
than the average person
1
– see generation(s).
Response (b)
About as successful as
the average person
2
Coleman, James S. (1926–1995)
Response (c)
Less successful than
the average person
3
Item:
How much fun
and enjoyment do
you get out of life?
Code
Response (a)
Lots
1
Response (b)
Some
2
Response (c)
Not much
3
In this regard it is crucial that we recognize
the potential shortcomings inherent in any account of sociological phenomena we derive from
analyst-imposed classification.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
cognitive dissonance
A theory developed by Leon Festinger (1919–90)
in his Theory of Cognitive Dissonance (1957); he
proposed that anyone holding two contradictory
cognitions experiences an aversive motivational
state. This leads the individual to reduce the dissonance by changing one of the cognitions, or by
including some justification into their thinking
which would reconcile the difference.
An example of this is provided by one of the
original tests of the claim. Subjects completed an
exceptionally dull task, and were then asked to
misrepresent it as very interesting to the next subject in the study. In one condition, subjects received
$20 ($135 in 2004 prices) for their duplicity, but
only $1 in the other. Subsequently, subjects rated
how interesting the task was. The $20 subjects gave
it significantly lower ratings than the $1 ones.
The explanation in cognitive dissonance terms
was that the $20 subjects witnessed a conflict
between their experience of the task and their
74
Professor of Sociology at the University of Chicago,
Coleman’s career covered work in various areas of
social science, methodology and theory, but his
main contribution was to the theory of social
action and structure (see agency and structure).
His early work was concerned with conflict and
power which he explored in Community Conflict
(1957), Power and the Structure of Society (1974), and
The Asymmetric Society (1982). He was a prolific
writer of books and journal articles over his long
career, and he focused on areas such as mathematical sociology in his Introduction to Mathematical
Sociology (1964); the sociology of education in The
Adolescent Society: The Social Life of the Teenager and its
Impact on Education (1961), Equality and Achievement
in Education (1990), and (with David Court) in University Development in the Third World (1993); and the
analysis of social change. In the area of the sociology of education, his research on the positive
effects of integrated schooling for underprivileged
black children, the Coleman Report (Equality of
Educational Opportunity, 1966), was most influential. He won many awards for his work including
the Paul Lazarsfeld Award for Research in 1983,
the Educational Freedom Award in 1989, and the
American Distinguished Sociological Publication
Award in 1992 for his book Foundations of Social
Theory (1990), which contained some of his contributions to the theory of social capital. His later
research focused on rational choice theory, for
example in Individual Interests and Collective Action:
Selected Essays (1986) and (with Thomas J. Fararo),
Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique (1992).
He founded the journal Rationality and Society in
1989. His most influential contribution was to the
development of the theory of social capital.
BRYAN S. TURNER
collective action
collective action
This concept refers to the process by which interest groups produce a public good. Pure public
goods have two properties: non-excludability
(anyone can consume it, including noncontributors) and jointness of supply (an increase in consumption does not reduce the amount available to
others). Collective action can also take the form of
mutual restraint in depleting shared resources, a
problem known as the tragedy of the common
good.
Collective action differs from collective behavior such as rioting or “groupthink,” in which
people in groups suppress critical faculties. However, collective action is not necessarily motivated
by rational self-interest. In The Logic of Collective
Action (1965), Mancur Olson (1932–98) argued
that rational actors will not contribute to public
goods if: (1) they can enjoy the public good even if
they do not contribute (the free-rider problem),
and (2) they cannot substantially increase the
public good even if they do contribute (the efficacy problem). Thus, rational actors will participate in collective action in large groups only if
selective incentives reward contributors and
punish noncontributors.
Olson’s work was criticized by sociologists who
countered that the provision of incentives is itself
a public good that presumes collective action
rather than explaining it. However, Douglas
Heckathorn showed that it can be rational to contribute to sanctions even when it is not rational to
contribute to public goods in the absence of social
control.
Gerald Marwell and Pamela Oliver also challenged Olson’s argument. In The Critical Mass in
Collective Action (1993), they showed how, with
high jointness of supply, collective action without
selective incentives is more likely in large than
in small groups. Large groups are more likely to
contain a critical mass of highly interested and
resourceful members. These statistical outliers
may be willing to provide the public goods for
everyone, no matter how many others benefit
for free.
Formal models of collective action have also
examined the role of social networks. It is often
easier to mobilize a critical mass of contributors
locally, which can then spread from cluster to
cluster until the entire population is involved.
Local interaction also facilitates informal social
control, such as the spread of reputation.
While much research on collective action
uses formal theory, researchers have also used
collective behavior
experimental laboratory research to study social
dilemmas. An important branch of research attributes collective action to the cohesive effects of
social identity rather than shared interests in a
public good. Henri Tajfel, Social Identity and Intergroup Relations (1982), shows how individuals are
more likely to contribute to public goods when a
group identity is salient. However, in “The Group
as the Container of Generalized Reciprocity”
(Social Psychology Quarterly), Toshio Yamagishi and
Toko Kiyonari argue that these studies may have
confounded the effects of identity with a selfinterested expectation of generalized reciprocity.
These and other experimental studies are
reviewed by Peter Kollock in the 1998 Annual
Review of Sociology.
Another branch of collective-action research
focuses on the mobilization of participation in
social movements. Key approaches include resource mobilization, which considers the strategic
attitudes and actions of participants, the political
process model, which examines the intersection of
political opportunities, social movements sectors,
and cycles of protest, and the new social movements perspective, which explores structural determinants and outcomes of movements.
MICHAEL MACY AND STEPHEN BENARD
collective behavior
Treated generically, this term refers to behavior
that is carried out by some sort of collective
rather than by an individual. While there are
classic accounts of concerted action in the
writings of Karl Marx and of Max Weber, there
have been a variety of recent, more focused, approaches to the mobilization of such behavior.
The specific “collective behavior” approach developed in the United States is associated with
two otherwise quite different theorists, Herbert
Blumer and Neil Smelser. Blumer’s symbolic
interactionist emphasis on elementary forms of
collective behavior, in which there is a lowering
of the self-consciousness that barricades the individual against the influence of others, has much
in common with Émile Durkheim’s stress on collective sentiments, rituals, and symbols. Blumer
distinguishes between three elementary groupings in which individualism and privatism are
transcended. These are: (1) a crowd, in which
physical proximity and density are important,
and which may range from the casual and passive
to the expressively intense and active; (2) a mass,
such as the audience for mass media events, in
which similar action can be provoked in spatially
75
collective behavior
disparate individuals by a common point of reference; and (3) a public, in which there is an
interactional coming together of previously disparate individuals in order to debate issues of
common concern. Blumer analyzes how these
nascent and spontaneous forms of collective behavior can be transformed into more enduring
and durable forms when the response to conditions of unrest involves the active creation of
social movements with an esprit de corps, clear
ideological values, and an organizational
structure.
The so-called “value-added” approach of Smelser’s Theory of Collective Behavior (1962), drawing its
inspiration from functionalism, emphasizes the
structural over the agency side of collective behavior. He identifies the response of groups to what
they see as “structural strain” in their environment as central amongst several factors that affect
whether, and to what extent, collective behavior
will occur. The other factors include: the specific
configuration of opportunities and constraints
confronting the group; the growth and spread of
generalized beliefs about what is wrong and what
should be done; the “trigger” of concrete events
that act as a focus for mobilization; communication networks that aid the coordination and
organization of the mobilization; and the response of social control agencies such as the police
or the media.
Employing the prisoner’s dilemma from game
theory, Mancur Olson’s influential The Logic of
Collective Action (1965) highlighted a specific problem in mobilizing collective action, that of the
“free rider.” The problem is that self-interested
individuals will prefer to free-ride on the activities of others, gaining the benefits of collective
actions but avoiding the costs of personal commitment. According to Olson, it is rational to
defect from such actions unless individual incentives are provided. Such an individualistic and
rationalistic approach sits uneasily with Blumer’s and Smelser’s more sociological emphasis
on extra-individual values, beliefs, and collective
sentiments. More recent work has refined and
complemented earlier insights. The resource mobilization school has demonstrated the significance for collective actors of resources gained
from external organizations and networks, while
innovative works such as Doug McAdam, Sydney
Tarrow, and Charles Tilly’s Dynamics of Contention
(2001) have developed historically specific and
grounded analyses of “cycles” and “repertoires
of contention.”
ROB STONES
76
Collège de Sociologie
collective goods
– see social capital.
collective rights
– see rights.
Collège de Sociologie
The powerful intellectual presence in France of
Émile Durkheim, prior to his death in 1917, was
due to the intellectual and organizational coherence of his school and to its elective affinity
with a politically significant reformist socialist
republican movement. Their collective work produced some positive responses from prominent
members of other disciplines, but it equally provoked hostility, which helps explain its subsequent limited role in higher education. After
World War I, few chairs in sociology were created
and many Durkheimians gravitated to specialized
research institutes. True, the Durkheimians influenced secondary education, but at the cost of a
subsequent increasingly abstract, nationalistic
and technocratic development of its precepts.
In the 1930s, intellectual ferment was linked
with Surrealist subversions of conventional art
and literature, an interest in more “primitive
cultures,” and a renewed interest in the ideas
of German thinkers, such as Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Karl Marx, Friedrich Nietzsche
(1844–1900), Sigmund Freud, and also Martin Heidegger (1889–1976). The work of the Durkheimians became increasingly marginalized: Paul
Nizan even blamed them for the authoritarian
nationalistic cast of education. Surprisingly, in
1937, the dissident Surrealists and anti-fascist activists Georges Bataille (1897–1962), Michel Leiris
(1901–90), and Roger Caillois (1913–78) organized
a Collège de Sociologie which met in a Parisian
bookshop between November 1937 and July 1939.
First announced in Bataille’s journal Acéphale, the
Collège aimed to create a contagious “Sacred Sociology.” Unaffiliated with any academic institution, the reputations, connections, and networks
of the Collège’s organizers and the promise of the
“note” in Acéphale brought to its sessions many
European literary figures, Surrealist and otherwise, historians, social theorists, and philosophers, including Alexandre Kojève (1902–68),
Pierre Klossowksi (1905–2001), Denis de Rougemont (1906–85), Hans Mayer (1907–2001), Jacques
Lacan, Georges Dumézil (1898–1986), Jean-Paul
Sartre (1905–80), Claude Lévi-Strauss, and Walter
Benjamin. Its major focus was the study of the
problems of power, the sacred, and myths. This
Collège de Sociologie
required forms of inquiry which would embrace a
person’s total activity and would entail working
in common with others, seriously, selflessly, and
with critical severity. To understand manifestations of the sacred, or their absence, historical
and comparative anthropological materials and
theories were needed and these were to be found
in the work of Durkheim, Robert Hertz (1881–
1915), Henri Hubert (1872–1927), and Marcel
Mauss. The lectures at the Collège and many associated writings have been brought together in
Denis Hollier (ed.), The College of Sociology 1937–39
(1988).
In their joint presentation in 1937 on the
“Sacred Sociology and the Relationships Between
‘Society,’ ‘Organism,’ and ‘Being,’” Bataille and
Caillois endorse Durkheim’s view that society
was an emergent sui generis reality, society being
something other than the sum of its individual
members, and while these naively represent themselves to themselves as indivisible unities they are
transformed by their subjection to the “communifying movements” of society, which is a “compound being.” Such movements create a feeling of
being a society, but this may be precarious, since
one society can produce a number of different
collectivities at the same time. Both Caillois and
Bataille drew on Durkheim’s analysis of the sacred
and profane dichotomy.
For Caillois, as he made clear in his lecture
“Festival,” the sacred is a key element both in
ordinary life and in the festivals found in primitive
societies, and to a much attenuated degree in
contemporary societies. Ordinary life tends to be
regular, busy, and safe; insofar as it is part of a
cosmos ruled by a universal order, the sacred only
manifests itself against potential disturbances of
this order or as expiations for any such disturbances. The very passage of time may be wearing
and exhausting and individual human beings and
social institutions get used up and every socially
conscious act leads to the accumulation of potentially toxic wastes. Regeneration may depend
upon the person who is its agent becoming polluted, for what is unclean may contain within
itself a positive active principle. The popular
frenzy of the festival may also be regenerative in
that it can release an active sacred energy, which
reverses the normal course of time and the forms
of social order, encouraging sacrilegious words
and deeds including sexual excesses. The festival
helps rediscover the creative chaos associated with
cosmic time and space and it may not only purify
and renew the established social order but change
it in fundamental ways.
Collège de Sociologie
Modern carnivals, however, are but dying
echoes of earlier festivals – for example, the joyful
destruction of a cardboard representation of a
buffoon-like king has little sacral relevance because, when an effigy replaces an actual human
victim, expiation or fertility are not a likely
consequence.
Caillois was a rigorous Durkheimian and his
analysis is in accord with Durkheim’s belief that
all forms of social phenomena that keep recurring
within societies of a particular species — whether
the phenomena superficially seem conformist or
deviant — are either themselves functional for
society as a whole or a necessary concomitant of
something that is functional.
Bataille significantly modified Durkheim’s distinction between the profane and the sacred.
Durkheim distinguishes between phenomena or
categorizations, homogeneous internally but
heterogeneous each to the other, but Bataille reinterprets the distinction as one between
the “homogeneous” and the “heterogeneous.”
The profane involves homogenization: deferred
gratification, analysis and calculation, planning
and utility, production and the controlled consumption necessary for the reproduction and conservation of economically productive human life,
conformist individuals experiencing themselves
as separate self-sufficient subjects, the possession
and consumption of objects.
The sacred is associated with heterogeneity:
socially useless activity, unlimited expenditure,
orgiastic impulses, sexual activity, defecation,
urination, ritual cannibalism, with extreme emotions, tabooed objects and their transgression —
for example corpses and menstrual blood. The
sacred evokes feelings of both attraction and repulsion and is linked with violence and its violent
containment; with the cruelty of sacrificing
others and with the subsumption of individuals
within totalizing group processes when they fearlessly confront death and are willing to sacrifice
themselves. It is potentially dangerous and destabilizing. More generally, while in contemporary
societies sacral processes have become more obscure and suppressed, less obviously religious,
they are still present, as can be seen in the way
that men are attracted to sacrificial ceremonies
and festivals. This discussion is to be found in “The
Use-Value of D. A. F. de Sade: An Open Letter to My
Current Comrades” in “Attraction and Repulsion”
(Hollier, 1988: 106–22): “The Structure and Function of the Army” (1988: 139–44), “Joy in the
Face of Death” (1988: 325–28), and “The College
of Sociology” (1988: 333–41).
77
Collège de Sociologie
In fact, historically, the sacred has been generated by taboo-violating rituals, and sacrifices have
been key elements in festivals which both regenerate the sacred and corral it. The activities that
both Caillois and Bataille describe are renewing and transforming cosmological social meanings and interpersonal and social relations, but
Bataille provides a model which presumes a
much lower level of integration, and which assumes less “societally functional” outcomes, than
does the model found in the discourses of
Durkheim (and Caillois). It is more marked by
contradictions and tensions and, hence, possibly
also subject to imperative elements.
The meetings of the Collège de Sociologie consisted of lectures followed by a discussion. Something less traditional is hinted at in Bataille’s final
lecture at the Collège. Bataille argues that the
sacred is produced when human beings communicate in such a naked way that they form new
beings. When humans unite with each other, for
example through love, this always involves a
mutual tearing and wounding. But lovers fear
that sustaining their relationship for its own
sake may subvert their ability to love to the point
of losing themselves in love. Thus, to sustain the
intensity of their feelings they must give themselves to turbulent passions and be with each
other in a state of heightened drama, even to the
point of being willing to embrace death. This may
involve just the two, but they may seek to increase
the intensity of their experience by incorporating
another person into their erotic domain, leading
to an even more annihilating expenditure. It is
not hard to see why Bataille would conclude his
lecture by claiming that eroticism slips easily into
orgy, but it is not as self-evident why he links this,
as he does, with sacrifice becoming an end in itself
and a universal value.
At that time, Bataille hoped, by the ritual execution of a consenting victim, to release sacred
energies. This was to have been a ritual enacted
by the members of the second Acéphale, the antiChristian and Nietzschean secret society Bataille
formed in 1936 and for which the Collège represented an outside activity. Much has been revealed
in the recent volume edited by Marina Galletti,
L’Apprenti Sorcier du cercle communiste démocratique
à Acéphale: Textes, lettres et documents (1917–1962);
rassemblés, présentés et annotés par Marina Galletti
(1999). From this it is evident that Acéphale’s
goals — “to change the torture that exists in the
world into joy within us; the Crucified into happy
laughter; our old immense weakness into will to
power” – were meant to be “communifying.” They
78
Collège de Sociologie
found a willing victim, probably Leiris, and it is
believed that Caillois was offered the role of the
sacrificer, the actual executioner. Immediately
after the sacrifice, the sacrificer was also expected
to kill himself – for Bataille, the executioner’s
desire was to be a victim. Caillois did not accept
the offer. Further, according to French sacrificial
theory, each sacrifice involves not only a victim
and a sacrificer but also a sacrifier (the source of
the desire for the sacrifice), and in this case each
member of the group was a sacrifier, and presumably each of them – through “contagion” – could
have been both sacrificer and victim. The human
sacrifice never took place.
Now, in his sole lecture at the Collège, “The
Sacred in Everyday Life,” Leiris’s emphasis was
psychological and personal. He was concerned
with the variety of things – objects, places, or
occasions – that awaken the mixture of fear and
attachment taken as indicating the sacred. Much
of his lecture was devoted to the symbolic meanings and associations of the sacred things that he
was familiar with in his own early years, but this
style of engagement had few resonances with
other lectures at the Collège. In fact, Leiris soon
distanced himself from its activities. One might
speculate that this was associated with the failure of Acéphale’s sacrificial promise, but, overtly
at least, he did so, from another place, as a professional ethnologist. In a letter to Bataille he
suggested three major objections to the way the
activities of the Collège had developed. It tended
to work from ideas that were ill-defined, thus
comparisons were often carelessly made with societies which were very different from each
other; it was in danger of becoming a mere
clique; and, finally, it overemphasized the sacred,
thereby subverting Mauss’s idea of a total social
fact. Caillois had made clear that the quality of
the collective work should be such that its results
could be substantiated and that the research
would command respect. He had become increasingly uneasy about the extent to which this was
being achieved. Indeed, his lecture “The Sociology of the Executioner” could be seen as a critique of Bataille’s overly voluntaristic and
socially decontextualized understanding of sacrificial ritual, an understanding which also, it
might be added, underestimates the necessary
role that alea or chance plays in producing the
sacred. Eventually, Caillois also distanced himself
from the Collège. Bataille, alone of the three, in
July 1939, attended the last session. In September
of the same year, all of its members withdrew
from Acéphale.
FRANK PEARCE
Collins, Randall (1941– )
Collins, Randall (1941– )
Professor of Sociology at the University of Pennsylvania, Collins has made important contributions
to historical sociology, the study of networks, and
sociological theory. His work in macrosociology
has been influenced by Max Weber, and he has
developed a distinctive interpretation of Weber in
Conflict Sociology: Towards an Explanatory Science
(1975), The Credential Society. An Historical Sociology
of Education and Stratification (1979), Weberian Sociological Theory (1986), and Max Weber. A Skeleton Key
(1986). From a Weberian perspective, Collins has
analyzed the rise and fall of major civilizations
and empires, and studied the conditions for capitalist growth in Macro History. Essays in Sociology of
the Long Run (1999). His most ambitious and influential study was on the global consequences of
networks for the development of philosophy in
his The Sociology of Philosophies. A Global Theory of
Intellectual Change (1998). He has also used the
work of Erving Goffman to develop a theory of
“interaction chains” to study such phenomena as
violence and sexual interaction in Interaction Ritual
Chains (2004).
BRYAN S. TURNER
colonialism
Often treated as synonymous with imperialism, it
seems helpful to distinguish between them. Imperialism refers to rule by a superior power over
subordinate territories, but it is consistent, as
with the Roman Empire, with the extension of
citizenship to members of the conquered territories. The early forms of colonialism, as with the
ancient Greeks, could also give rise to more or
less equal, self-governing colonies; but modern
colonialism, which has given the term its dominant meaning, usually refers to a fundamental inequality between metropole and colony, often
codified in law, and resulting in a basic dependence of the colony on the metropolitan power.
There have been two main forms of modern
colonialism. In the first, inhabitants of one country establish colonies in another country, often in
the process displacing or even exterminating the
indigenous inhabitants of that country. This was
the case, for instance, with the British colonies in
North America, Australia, and New Zealand;
though originally unintended, this also turned
out to be essentially the condition of the Spanish
and Portuguese colonies in the New World. Even
though it is clear that the colony is an off-shoot of
the parent body and remains tied to it in many
ways, the similarity of sentiment, habits, and political attitudes between metropole and colony
colonialism
tends to mean that the colonies eventually aim
at independence and self-rule – even if, as in the
case of some of the American colonies, this has to
be accomplished by force. We can – cautiously –
call this the Greek model, as it follows the basic
pattern of Greek colonization in the ancient
world.
The other form of modern colonialism is closer
to the old Roman model. Here a superior power
incorporates, usually by conquest, peoples of different ethnicities and levels of development.
Examples of this form would include the European colonization of much of Asia, Africa, and
the Pacific in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. In this form, colonialism shades over into
imperialism. There is usually an official ideology
of “the civilizing mission,” whereby the colonizing
power aims to bring up the colonies to the levels
of culture and material standards of its own society. There is no expectation, in principle at least,
that the colonies will eventually achieve independence, though their people may well, as in
the case of certain French colonies, achieve
degrees of citizenship. Though the civilizing mission is offered as justification to the world at
large, to their own peoples colonial powers usually justify colonial possessions in terms of their
benefit to the mother country. They are expected
to be a source of wealth and power, and to provide
raw materials and markets for the goods of the
colonial powers, together with opportunities for
investment. The fact that in very few actual cases
have things turned out as the colonizers hoped
has not prevented many people from continuing
to believe in the benefits of colonies – the Nazis,
for instance, attempted a form of colonialism in
Eastern Europe, as did the Italian fascists in North
Africa.
In the best-known instances of colonialism, the
colonies are overseas, separated from the metropole by large distances. But there can also be “internal colonialism,” in which what are effectively
colonies exist on the doorstep of the metropole.
Such, argued Michael Hechter in an influential
book Internal Colonialism (1975), is the case of the
United Kingdom, with the English the dominant
“colonial” power in relation to the “colonized”
Welsh, Scottish, and Irish. A similar argument
has been made about Russia in relation to its
eastward expansion, especially as regards regions
such as Siberia. There is an obvious degree of truth
in this conception, but the limitations of the internal colonialism model become apparent in the
cases of Spain and Canada, where the regions of
79
color blind
Catalonia or Quebec do not at all fit the idea of
exploited “colonies,” whatever the protestations
of the inhabitants.
Colonialism gave rise in due course to decolonization, especially in the period following World
War II, when most European empires shed their
colonies, with varying degrees of violence and
usually under the pressure of nationalist movements. Decolonization was generally hailed as a
victory for the principles of democracy and national self-determination, and in some senses
therefore could be held to be the fulfillment of
the western mission, since the principles clearly
derived from western thought and practice. But to
many observers the triumph was hollow, since
what took the place of formal colonialism was
informal neo-colonialism. In this view, the colonies achieve formal independence and national
sovereignty, but remain in many essential respects as dependent on the former colonial
powers as when they were colonies. This is shown
in such matters as a narrow economic specialization, geared to the requirements of the economies
of the advanced nations, and a culture that is
equally dependent on foreign, mostly western,
sources. Neo-colonial theorists point, as a telling
parallel, to the situation in Latin America, whose
countries were never formally colonized but
whose pattern of development was in important
respects dictated by the needs and interests of
dominant foreign powers, notably Britain and the
United States.
One should mention, finally, post-colonialism.
Unlike the other terms, this refers mainly to a
school of cultural criticism and analysis concerned with the conditions of societies that have
achieved independence, following a period of
dependence and subordination as a part of colonial empires. Its most thriving branch to date has
been on the Indian sub-continent, especially in the
work of the Subaltern Studies group; but it is
normal also to refer, for the founding texts, to
such works as Franz Fanon’s The Wretched of the
Earth (1961) and Edward Said’s Orientalism (1978).
Post-colonial studies cover a wide variety of fields,
but are especially marked by their exploration
of the complex and often contradictory effects of
the interaction between the colonized and the
colonizers in imperial settings, and of the lasting
legacy of this experience in the post-colonial
period.
KRISHAN KUMAR
color blind
– see prejudice.
80
communism
commodity Fetishism
– see alienation.
communism
As a form of social organization and ideas about
it, the term indicates societies in which property
is commonly and fully owned and shared. In this
sense, the only societies to which this definition is
empirically applicable have been pre-agrarian
(hunter and gatherer societies) or early agrarian
stateless societies. This so-called primitive communism is said to have disappeared with sedentary living, economic surplus, and social status
differentiation related to material wealth. In Karl
Marx’s stage-theory, history began with primitive
communism. Within modern state societies, forms
of communal living with shared property have occurred, but for sociological purposes are not
treated as examples of communism. Likewise, contemporary hunter–gatherer societies have escaped
this label in sociological theorizing, partially as an
outcome of disciplinary struggles with anthropology. In contemporary usage in the social sciences,
communism is often used as a shorthand for the
political regimes of the twentieth century that
were based on a diverse range of interpretations
of Marxist theory and doctrine. China, Cuba, and
North Korea are contemporary examples of societies explicitly led by communist doctrine.
Where it is used as regime-type label, however,
the connotation deviates sharply from the original theorizing of communism by Marx and
Friedrich Engels, where it did not signify a future
and desirable ultimate type of society (as interpreted by the Young Hegelians), but a “real movement” to transcend contemporary society
grounded in the present – for example in the
German Ideology (1845 [trans. 1965]) of Marx and
Engels. Therefore in Marx’s system of thought,
communism was no utopia. Marx’s concept
of communism is deeply rooted in philosophical
debates, specifically the Hegelian concept of
time. Disagreeing with Hegel’s conception of
the Spirit and its role in history, Marx understood
the transcendence of time and history as resulting
from human action. Seeing humans as expressing
themselves and their purposes, rather than
merely reproducing themselves, when engaging
in economic activities, Marx came to define the
workers as the agents of such transcendence. This
proposition introduced a much-debated paradox
into Marx’s theorizing, because he had to argue
that, at the same time as the material conditions
of capitalist production brought drudgery and
communism
misery to the workers, work itself was also the
source of human creativity and self-fulfillment
for the laboring class. The crux of the matter for
Marx was that labor time, not labor as such, was
commodified in the capitalist mode of production, thus leaving a residual for the self-actualization of labor. As he argued, with what now
appears as great foresight, taking control of labor
time becomes a paramount concern in class
struggle, industrial relations, and management
in capitalism.
Within this paradox, Marx – decisively for
future generations of Marxian faith-based political systems – had carved out a charismatic role
for labor, in the form of collective proletarian
revolutionary action. This vision contradicted his
evolutionary understanding of history, according
to which gradual progress within existing bourgeois institutions (the fulfillment of particular
objective material factors) would eventually bring
about ultimate human freedom. Marx took the
concept of communism to mean the social movement uniting all revolutionary proletarians, but it
remains unresolved as to how proletarian autonomy and consciousness, necessary to transcend
the current conditions, can be achieved against
the historical-materialist axiom of the theory
that social existence determines consciousness
and not vice versa.
Marx’s writings show incoherence in terms of
his assessment of the possibilities lying in the
empirically existent working class during his
lifetime. On one hand, he argued, the totality of
the relations of production, constituting the economic structure, is the foundation of the legal–
political superstructure, corresponding to definite
forms of social consciousness. The working class
thus was locked into structures provided by the
laws of history (see social structures). On the
other, as he and Engels argued in The Communist
Manifesto (1848) and observed in reality, he saw
some societies at the eve of a revolution, and
hoped this would carry enough critical mass to
overthrow the ruling classes and deliver a wholesome transformation.
Marx himself, after many years as a commentator on labor’s collective action, became the leader
of the first International, which was founded in
1863 by labor leaders as a nation-spanning alliance of workers in pursuit of the replacement
of the current economic system with one of collective ownership of the means of production. The
International became an active political threat to
those in fear of the “specter of communism”
the Manifesto had promised, and although it
communitarianism
dissolved in 1876 it was followed by two more
Internationals. The political movement behind
the International featured both agreement and
disagreement about the overthrow of capitalism
from diverse progressive forces.
The history of social organization based on communist ideology cannot be understood without
reference to socialism. While all forms of socialism are critical of capitalist organization and the
resulting social inequality, not all variants agree
over a centralized role for the state and the elimination of private property as preconditions for
a better society. Eduard Bernstein (1850–1932), for
example, embraced Marx’s scientific theory but
found it at odds with the real development of
industrial capitalism that showed an improved
standard of living and class inequalities far less
polarized than anticipated by Marx. He found a
pacification of class protests and institutionalization of socialist and communist parties. Bernstein
emphasized the role of democracy and advocated
social reform. A departure from Marx in another
direction was made by V. I. Lenin, who forged the
idea of the necessity of a vanguard party that
would translate the interests of the workers into
revolutionary action. Lenin’s version of Marxian
theory stressed socialism as more than a transitional phase: the bourgeois state would be eliminated while the proletarian state would be built.
Marx had anticipated, on the contrary, that the
state would wither away. He did not use in his
writings the term “dictatorship of the proletariat,” but subsequent ideologies and regimes,
and commentators on them, used the term to
establish or express the supreme role of the communist party in state leadership.
ANN VOGEL
communitarianism
A social philosophy that favors social formulations
of the good, communitarianism is often contrasted with liberalism, which assumes that the
good should be determined by each individual.
To the extent that social institutions and policies
are required, these should be based on voluntary
agreements among the individuals involved, expressing their preferences. In contrast, communitarians view institutions and policies as reflecting
in part values passed from generation to generation. These values become part of the self
through internalization, and are modified by persuasion, religious or political indoctrination, leadership, and moral dialogues.
In the 1980s communitarianism was largely advanced by Charles Taylor, Michael Sandel, and
Michael Walzer. They criticized liberalism for its
81
communitarianism
failure to realize that people are socially “embedded,” overlooking that people can have a strong
attachment to their societies. They lamented liberalism’s focus on the individualistic concept of
self-interest.
Asian communitarians argue that, to maintain
social harmony, individual rights and political
liberties must be curtailed. Some seek to rely heavily on the state to maintain social order (for instance, leaders and champions of the regimes in
Singapore and Malaysia), and some on strong
social bonds and moral culture (as does Japan).
Asian communitarians also hold that the West’s
notion of liberty actually amounts to “anarchy”;
that strong economic growth requires limiting
freedoms; and that the West uses its idea of legal
and political rights to chastise other cultures that
have inherent values of their own.
In 1990, a new school of communitarianism was
founded. Among its leading scholars are William A.
Galston (political theory), Mary Ann Glendon (law),
Thomas Spragens, Jr. (political science), Alan
Ehrenhalt (writer), and sociologists Philip Selznick,
Robert Bellah and his associates, and Amitai
Etzioni who wrote books that, in 1990, laid the
foundations for responsive (democratic) communitarianism. Key communitarian texts include Habits
of the Heart (1985) by Robert Bellah and colleagues,
The Spirit of Community (1993) and The New Golden
Rule (1996) by Amitai Etzioni, Communitarianism
and Its Critics (1993) by Daniel Bell, and The
Communitarian Persuasion by Philip Selznick (2002).
Responsive communitarians, a group founded
by Amitai Etzioni, assume that societies have multiple and not wholly compatible needs, in contrast
to philosophies built on one core principle, such
as liberty for libertarianism. Responsive communitarianism assumes that a good society is based
on a balance between liberty and social order, and
between particularistic (communal) and societywide values and bonds. This school stresses responsibilities people have for their families, kin,
communities, and societies – above and beyond
the universal rights all individuals command,
the focus of liberalism.
While a carefully crafted balance between
liberty and social order defines a generic concept
of the good society, communitarians point out
that the historical–social conditions of specific
societies determine the rather different ways a
given society in a given era may need to change
to attain the same balance. Thus, contemporary
Japan requires much greater tolerance for individual rights, while in the American society excessive
individualism needs to be curbed.
82
communitarianism
Communitarians pay special attention to social
institutions. Several of these form the moral infrastructure of society: families, schools, communities, and the community of communities.
Infants are born into families whose societal role
is to introduce values and begin the development
of the moral self. The role of schools is to develop
the moral self and to remedy moral development
if it was neglected or distorted by the family.
Communitarians emphasize that children
reared in well-functioning families and schools
will still not be sufficiently equipped for membership in a good, communitarian society. This is a
point ignored by those social philosophers who
assume that, once people have acquired virtue
and are habituated, they will be adequately
guided by their inner moral compass. In contrast,
communitarians assume that commitments to
moral values tend to deteriorate, unless these are
continuously reinforced. A major societal role of
communities is to reinforce these commitments
in their members. This is achieved by the community’s “moral voice,” the informal sanctioning of
others, built into a web of informal affect-laden
relationships, that communities provide.
Within this context, responsive communitarians point out that, if a society has communities
whose social webs are intact, who share a moral
culture, and whose members are willing to raise
their moral voice, such a society can rest its social
order largely on moral commitments rather than
on the coercive state. That is, the moral voice can
reduce the inevitable tension between liberty and
social order and enhance both.
In the same vein, communitarians argue that,
while everyone’s right to free speech should be
respected, some speech – seen from the community’s viewpoint – is morally highly offensive and,
when children are exposed, damaging. For instance, the (legal) right to speak does not render
verbal expressions of hate (morally) right.
While sociologists made numerous contributions to altered communitarian thinking, this
philosophy challenged sociology to face issues
raised by cross-cultural moral judgments. Sociologists tend to treat all values as conceptually equal;
thus sociologists refer to racist Nazi beliefs and
those of free societies by the same “neutral” term,
calling both “values.” Communitarians use the
term “virtue” to indicate that some values have a
high moral standing because they are compatible
with the good society, while other values are not
and hence are “aberrant” rather than virtuous.
In the same vein, communitarians reject the
claim of cultural relativism that all cultures
community
community studies
command basically the same moral standing, and
do not shy away from passing cross-cultural moral
judgments. Thus, they view female circumcision,
sex slaves, and traditional hudud laws (such as
chopping off the right hand of thieves) as violations of liberty and individual rights, and abandoning children, violating implicit contracts building
into communal mutuality, or neglecting the environment as evidence of a lack of commitment to
social order and neglect of social responsibilities.
Communitarian terms became part of the
public vocabulary in the 1990s, especially references to assuming social responsibilities to
match individual rights, while the term communitarianism itself is used much less often. The
number of articles about communitarian thinking in the popular press increased during the
last decade of the twentieth century.
AMITAI ETZIONI
community
Critics argue that the concept of the community
is of questionable value because it is so ill defined. In Colin Bell and Howard Newby’s edited
The Myth of Community Studies (1974), Margaret
Stacey argued that the solution to this problem
is to avoid the term altogether. Bell and Newby
similarly pointed out, “There has never been a
theory of community, nor even a satisfactory
definition of what community is” (1974: xliii).
Amitai Etzioni (New Golden Rule, 1996) points
out that community can be defined with reasonable precision. Community has two characteristics: (1) a web of affect-laden relationships among
a group of individuals, relationships that often
crisscross and reinforce one another (as opposed
to one-on-one relationships); and (2) a measure
of commitment to a set of shared histories and
identities – in short, a particular culture. David E.
Pearson states:
To earn the appellation “community,” it seems to
me, groups must be able to exert moral suasion
and extract a measure of compliance from their
members. That is, communities are necessarily,
indeed by definition, coercive as well as moral,
threatening their members with the stick of
sanctions if they stray, offering them the carrot of
certainty and stability if they don’t. (“Community
and Sociology,” 1995, Society)
Critics generally suggest that those who long
for communities ignore the darker side of traditional communities. “In the new communitarian
appeal to tradition, communities of ‘mutual aid
and memory,’” writes Linda McClain in “Rights
and Irresponsibility” (1994: 1029) in the Duke Law
Journal, “there is a problematic inattention to the
less attractive, unjust features of tradition.” Amy
Gutmann (“Communitarian Critics of Liberalism,”
1985, Philosophy and Public Affairs) pointedly remarks that communitarians “want us to live in
Salem,” a community of strong shared values that
went so far as to accuse nonconformist members
of witchcraft during the seventeenth century.
Communitarians counter that behind many
of these criticisms lies an image of old, or total,
communities, which are neither typical of modern society nor necessary for, or even compatible
with, a communitarian society. Old communities
(traditional villages) were geographically bounded
and the only communities of which people were
members. In effect, other than escaping into noman’s-land, often bandit territories, individuals
had few opportunities for choosing their social
attachments. In short, old communities had
monopolistic power over their members.
New communities are often limited in scope
and reach. Members of one residential community
are often also members of other communities,
for example, work, ethnic, or religious ones (see
work and employment, ethnicity, and religion).
As a result, community members have multiple
sources of attachments; and if one threatens to
become overwhelming, individuals will tend to
pull back and turn to another community for
their attachments. Thus, for example, if a person
finds herself under high moral pressure at work
to contribute to the United Way, to give blood,
or to serve at a soup kitchen for the homeless,
and these are lines of action she is not keen to
follow, she may end up investing more of her
energy in other communities – her writers’ group,
for instance, or her church. This multicommunity
membership protects the individual from both
moral oppression and ostracism. A M I T A I E T Z I O N I
community enterprise
– see social economy.
community studies
These studies are concerned with interrelationships of social institutions in a locality. Some studies encompass all such relations, while others (for
example Michael Young and Peter Willmott’s
Family and Kinship in East London, 1957) focus on
particular relations. Community studies traditionally understand “community” as a space defined
by multiple contiguous social networks. Studies
often share a number of characteristics. They
often use participant observation with the researchers living in the locale, sharing some of
83
companionate marriage
the experiences of the inhabitants, for whom they
consequently display sympathy. They tend to offer
detailed and lively descriptions of community life
but may not be extensively theorized. Robert and
Helen Lynd’s classical Middletown: A Study in American Culture (1929) charted cultural change and
strain in a “typical” American town, organized
around six themes – “getting a living,” “making
a home,” “training the young,” “using leisure,”
“religious practices,” and “community activities.”
Many studies followed, one of the most famous
being W. F. Whyte’s Street Corner Society (1943), a
study of gang life in Boston’s East End. Community studies remained popular through the 1950s
and there were several classical British studies
including N. Dennis, F. M. Henriques, and C.
Slaughter, Coal is Our Life (1956), but the method
was increasingly criticized as a-historical, having
an implicit model of functional equilibrium and
difficulty analyzing change. Ray Pahl’s six-year
study of the Isle of Sheppey (1978–83), later published as Divisions of Labour (1984), addresses these
criticisms by exploring changes in household divisions of labor over time in relation to broader
social structural processes. But in a period of
high social mobility, internet communications,
and transnational networks, the notion of
spatially defined communities has become less
central to sociology.
LARRY RAY
companionate marriage
– see marriage and divorce.
comparative method
It is rather paradoxical to write about comparative
method. All sociological method is intrinsically
comparative in the sense that it either involves
explicit and direct comparison of time and/or
space differentials or involves concepts that
were developed through such comparisons. Émile
Durkheim was well aware of this paradox already
when he argued that “comparative sociology is
not a particular branch of sociology; it is sociology
itself, in so far as it ceases to be purely descriptive
and aspires to account for facts,” in The Rules of
Sociological Method (1895 [trans. 1982]). But what
exactly did comparison mean? Did it mean simply
to compare and contrast across time and space?
Did it mean to search for analogies and parallels
across cultures and societies? Max Weber certainly
opposed such simplistic comparisons. In a note on
method hastily added to his The Agrarian Sociology
of Ancient Civilizations (1909 [trans. 1976]), almost as
an afterthought, Weber suggested that
84
complexity theory
[a] genuinely analytic study comparing the stages of
development of the ancient polis with those of the
medieval city would be welcome and productive . . .
Of course . . . such a comparative study would not
aim at finding “analogies” and “parallels,” as is done
by those engrossed in the currently fashionable
enterprise of constructing general schemes of
development. The aim should, rather, be precisely
the opposite: to identify and define the individuality
of each development, the characteristics which
made the one conclude in a manner so different
from that of the other. This done, one can then
determine the causes which led to these differences.
(1976: 385)
For Weber, then, comparison did not consist in
drawing parallels and analogies but in exploring
the trajectories of social institutions in their irreducible differences and singularities (for example,
Stephen Kalberg, Max Weber’s Comparative-Historical
Sociology, 1994). Here, as elsewhere, Weber’s debt
to Nietzsche’s conception of genealogy is unmistakable and perhaps remains one of Weber’s
lasting legacies for empirically grounded theorizing (for example, David Owen, Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the Ambivalence
of Reason, 1994).
ENGIN ISIN
complexity theory
A recent development in social theory, gaining
currency through the last decade of the twentieth
century, this has been described as an amalgam or
“rhetorical hybrid” of a range of insights drawn
from a variety of different fields, mainly in the
natural sciences, and applied to social relations.
Complexity theory is closely associated with the
foundation of the Santa Fe Institute in 1984, an
interdisciplinary research institute comprising
physicists, mathematicians, computer programmers, and systems analysts. It was also championed
by world-systems sociologist Immanuel Wallerstein
and Nobel-prize-winning scientist Ilya Prigogine
(1917– ) in the Gulbenkian Commission’s influential 1996 report on the restructuring of the social
sciences, Open the Social Sciences. The theory is essentially concerned with issues of order, adaptation, and feedback emerging from interactions
between the different elements or parts of complex systems, from weather systems to business
organizations. While it has produced compelling
insights in economics it is probably too soon to
say how fruitful it will prove to be in sociology.
An essential point for complexity theory, as it is
for realism, is that the properties, powers, and
effects of the system or entity that emerges from
the combination of parts can be both greater than
complexity theory
and different from the parts themselves. In Global
Complexity (2003), John Urry explains this, using the
taste of sugar as an example. This taste is simply
not present in the prior carbon, hydrogen, and
oxygen atoms that need to combine to produce
sugar. The flavor of sugar is thus an “emergent”
property that results from the relational interaction between the parts. It is a “nonlinear” consequence (one that differs from a “linear,” billiard
ball, conception of cause and effect, in which neither the ball that is hit nor the ball that hits alters
its essential properties) that arises from a transfiguring combination of individual components.
Complexity theory embraces insights from
chaos theory, sharing the latter’s emphasis on
nonlinear laws, but its focus is ultimately on order
rather than anarchy. Chaos theory concentrates
on the disruption of order, on turbulent behavior
in complex systems in instances where nonlinear
laws amplify the smallest of changes in initial
conditions, as in the classic example of the flapping of a butterfly’s wings producing large
weather effects on the other side of the world.
Complexity theory is more interested in the combination of order and disorder that is produced by
such emergent interactions, stretching away, as
they do, across space and time in open and interdependent networks. Institutionalized social processes, from households to large international
organizations, are in fact conceptualized as
islands of order within a sea of disorder. However,
even these forms of order themselves, manifested
as they are in billions of repeated social actions,
are seen to be constantly changing and transmuting, as the tiniest of local changes in these
repeated, iterated, actions generate “unexpected,
unpredictable, and chaotic outcomes, sometimes
the opposite of what agents thought they were
trying to bring about.” Thus there are “pockets”
of relative order existing within an overall patterning of disorder, and the relations between
the two are complex. The effects of any particular
localized action within this context is said to be
highly contingent; they can be microscopic or
global. Relatively ordered systems that appeared
robust can turn out to be vulnerable, and the
reverse can equally be the case. Metaphors, from
attractors and fractals, through implicate orders
and self-organization, to autopoeisis and emergent orders, have been liberally imported from
many natural and social science paradigms
and combined in an attempt to theorize this sense
of “order on the edge of chaos” and guidance
without a guide.
ROB STONES
Comte, Auguste (1798–1857)
Comte, Auguste (1798–1857)
A grand philosophical synthesizer who coined the
term sociology, he was the first to attempt its
establishment as a science. For Comte, society
was a rule-governed order of reality, irreducible
to the individuals who comprised it, and sociology
was a fundamental branch of knowledge which,
together with mathematics, astronomy, physics/
chemistry, and biology, made up knowledge as a
whole. Comte’s approach to sociology was comparative and historical, aiming to understand
how each type of society was institutionally constituted, and by what logic of development human
society passed from one form to another. Comte
divided his sociology into a “statics” (laws of order)
and a “dynamics” (laws of progress). The first
stressed the fragile relations between individual
and society, and the importance of family and
religion in securing the social tie. The second was
organized around a “law of stages” according to
which collective mental development, like that of
an individual, passed from an infantile “theistic”
stage, marked by imaginary causes and anthropomorphic projection, to a hybrid and abstractly
idealizing – “metaphysical” – stage of adolescence,
to a maturely “positive” stage where knowledge,
understood to be limited, became soundly based
on the evidence of the senses.
The rebellious son of a Catholic-royalist family,
Comte studied mathematics at the École Polytechnique in Paris and later transferred to the École du
Médecine at Montpellier to study biology. After
moving back to Paris he became Claude Henri de
Rouvroy, comte de Saint-Simon’s private secretary
from 1817 until their acrimonious parting in
1824, and then supported himself through
writing, private teaching, and a part-time post as
a secondary school mathematics examiner.
Comte’s overall project was to provide the
science-based (positiviste) intellectual and religious
synthesis he saw as needed to complete the work
of the French Revolution by establishing a new
industrial form of society. He founded the Positivist Society as his main organizational vehicle
which, following his conversion in 1854 (associated with the death of his beloved Clothilde de
Vaux), assumed the explicit character of a church,
with l’Humanité as its god and Comte as its grandprêtre.
At the center of Comte’s attention was the post1789 crisis of industrial society, with its unresolved class and ideological warfare between, as
he saw it, one-sided partisans of order and progress. Comte diagnosed the ongoing turmoil of
85
concentric zone theory
French society as a crisis of transition, which he
tried to understand and resolve by seeking to
synthesize the secular-progressivist viewpoint of
Étienne Condillac (1715–80) with the integralist
social theorizing of Catholic counter-revolutionaries like Joseph de Maistre (1753–1821). In all this,
Comte followed Saint-Simon, but before advocating a specific program of social reform he insisted
on the need for preparatory intellectual work,
beginning with the establishment of sociology.
Sociology would not only provide politics with a
scientific basis, but was itself an essential element
of the new synthesis of scientific knowledge without which the moral order appropriate to industrial society could not be constructed. Comte’s
six-volume Système de philosophie positive (1830–42)
carried out both aims. His later work – including
Système de politique positive (1851–4) as well as his
unfinished Synthèse subjective – was taken up with
further developing his system, now centrally organized around positivism as a religious and not
just theoretical project, and expanded to include
feelings (with altruistic love as the highest), as
well as knowledge and action, as organizing categories. Sociology, in this revision, was the theology of Humanism, doctrinally anchoring an
elaborate and grandiose plan for the unification
of l’Humanité through planetary federalism and
the establishment of a new post-theistic world
religion.
Comte is a relatively unexamined founding
figure of modern sociology. Ignored because of
his eccentricities, passion for systems, and sectarianism, his thought, nevertheless, has strongly
influenced classical and post-classical French sociology, as well as many philosophers and social
theorists from John Stuart Mill and Friedrich
Nietzsche to Karl Mannheim, Gaston Bachelard,
ANDREW WERNICK
and Louis Althusser.
concentric zone theory
– see urban ecology.
conjugal roles
This term belongs to those sociological traditions
that assumed heterosexual marriage to be the
normal status of adult human beings. Despite
the fact that this pattern never accorded with all
known individuals in any society, it was nevertheless assumed that women and men would internalize sets of social norms about the behavior
appropriate to marriage. Each party was expected
to acquire an understanding of both the rights
and the responsibilities of their role (for example,
the husband to “provide” for his wife and the wife
86
conservatism
to agree to sexual relations with her husband) and
this understanding could be expected of all
married individuals. The theory did not allow for
differences in power in marriage (for example, the
control of husbands over money) nor conflicts
that might arise from distinct and conflicting
interpretations of a particular conjugal role.
The very concept of a conjugal role, with its
implicit fusion of husband and wife (and its
equally implicit expectation of the greater power
within marriage of the husband – a power reflected in much western law until the 1970s),
disappeared when feminism challenged the
masculinist assumptions of certain aspects of
sociology and – with gay and queer theory –
problematized previously held understandings
about sexuality and marriage. Empirical studies
of the household suggest that many traditional
expectations about male and female behavior in
marriage/cohabitation persist but that these no
longer have the social or legal legitimacy which
the idea of conjugal roles once enjoyed.
MARY EVANS
conservatism
This is a political movement – an ideology with a
set of principles that relate to human nature,
rationality, and the role of the state and nation.
It arises historically as a reaction to liberalism and
a fear that the logic of liberalism points to notions
of universal emancipation that conservatives
consider unrealistic and utopian.
Conservatism is not, then, a disposition or attitude to life. This makes the notion far too broad. It
is often said that being a conservative involves
a pragmatic view that if things are “not broken,
don’t fix them.” While a conservative disposition may involve an unwillingness to accept
change, conservatism as a social and political
movement is much more precise than this (see
social movements).
It is argued – particularly by conservatives who
follow the ideas of Edmund Burke (1729–97) – that
conservatism is too flexible to be an ideology or an
“-ism.” But if we use the term ideology to denote
merely a system of thought (and not an argument
that is inherently dogmatic and authoritarian),
then conservatism is an ideology since it has a
set of principles, and these principles become
clear when the doctrine is challenged.
Conservatism sees people as naturally unequal,
and therefore holds that people do not have rights
that are universal. Why are they unequal? People
have differing innate abilities; they are brought
up in differing circumstances; some are more
conservatism
rational than others; they are influenced by the
particular nation in which they live; and so forth.
It is revealing that, although Margaret Thatcher is
often seen as a “neoliberal” and a Whig, rather
than a true Tory, she argues that people are inherently unequal. In this, she is impeccably conservative. It is true that “libertarian” conservatives of
the New Right pushed further away from traditional conservatism by extolling the virtues of
the “pure” market. They are better described
as anarchists – anarcho-capitalists – rather than
conservatives as such.
The notion of difference for conservatives
expresses itself in the form of natural hierarchies.
Conservatives have interpreted the notion of
“nature” to indicate a differentiation in roles –
between men and women, “civilized” and “uncivilized” – and conservatives, for this reason, have at
times opposed democracy, sexual (that is, relations between gays and straights) and gender
equality, the rights of all nations to determine
their own destiny, and so on. Nature is an eternal
force that promotes hierarchy and differentiation
rather than equality and sameness.
Conservatism is not just a philosophy of “realism.” Conservatives may advocate radical change
in egalitarian societies that they deem “unnatural.” The status quo deserves to be conserved
only if it is conservative!
Although ancient conservatism (as among the
Greeks) opposed democracy and the rule of the
“free” poor, in its modern form conservatism
takes its identity from opposition to the French
Revolution. Conservatives were particularly scandalized by the French Revolution because of its
beliefs in natural rights and universalistic notions
of freedom and equality. These were seen as abstract – that is, propositions that ignored circumstance and context. Notions of emancipation and
“perfectibility” are anathema since these concepts
ride roughshod over hierarchy and hierarchical
differentiation.
Conservatives favor the concepts of family,
state, religion, and nation. It is revealing that in
the statement so often cited by Margaret Thatcher
– “there is no such thing as society” – she does
speak of individuals and their families. The family
as a patriarchal and hierarchical construct is
favored by conservatism since it deemphasizes individual choice and stresses differentiation and
inequality. This accounts for the fact that there is
invariably a tension between conservatism and
the market, since market forces are seen as
eroding hierarchical communities and traditional
relationships. Indeed, Marxism draws upon
conservatism
conservative critiques of the industrial revolution,
while demurring at the aristocratic “solutions” to
the problem. Charity is preferred to welfare rights
since the former relies upon the benevolence
of the few rather than the entitlements of the
many. Support for private property must fit into
a hierarchical view of society.
The state is favored as an institution (although
of course conservatives may disagree on the
extent of state intervention) on the grounds that
people cannot govern their own lives, but need
leaders and authorities to tell them what to do
and think. The need to use force as a weapon of
last resort accords well with the conservative argument that order cannot rest simply upon rationality or persuasion. Some conservatives do
not reject reason so much as a view of reason
that is deemed abstract and liberal. Humans are
imperfect, and will harm others or themselves
unless social pressures including force are
brought to bear upon them. Rulers are like
parents who have, from time to time, to chastise
wayward children.
Religion is important for conservatives, since
they are skeptical that people can act in an orderly
way without an element of prejudice and mysticism. God is conceived as a patriarchal creator, a
lord and master whom we should obey instinctively (as we do our parents). National and
local sentiments that differentiate insiders from
outsiders, are seen as natural and inevitable.
Historically, conservatism supported empire and,
in the case of Benjamin Disraeli (1804–81), conservatives regarded it as the key to “safely”
expanding the vote, and the creation of workingclass conservatives. Conservatives are nationalists
since they believe that certain nations are “naturally” more preeminent than others and regard any
attempt to replace the nation-state with international institutions as dangerous and misguided.
Altruism, whether collective or individual, is
something that extends only to family, neighbors,
and friends. Of course, the conservatives of one
nation will differ from those of another nation,
even though, ironically, the mutual antagonism
arises from broadly shared principles.
It is important to differentiate conservatism
from doctrines of the radical right, like fascism,
even though conservatives often supported fascist
regimes on the grounds that they were the only
force capable of crushing socialism and trade
unions. Fascism is counterrevolutionary – creating
a society that is quite new – whereas conservatism
seeks to restore traditional regimes and values.
JOHN HOFFMAN
87
consumer society
consumer society
This is an ill-defined, but nonetheless popular,
concept gesturing towards the enhanced societal
importance of the purchase of commodities and
their cultural meanings and significance, it implies a comparatively greater role for consumption –
in contrast with work and employment, religion,
family, investment, or politics – in determining
economic organization, cultural institutions, and
personal motivations and experience. In general it
is a term with negative connotations, appearing
mostly in the course of critiques of the misuse of
affluence in postwar western countries. It is less
frequently used than the term consumerism,
which is often considered one of its associated
properties. It has received much less systematic
scholarly attention than the concept of consumer
culture, a term with more ambivalent and polysemic moral connotations and which has produced its own distinctive tradition of research.
John Benson, in The Rise of Consumer Society in
Britain (1994), summarizes the historians’ depictions of consumer societies as those “in which
choice and credit are readily available, in which social value is defined in terms of purchasing power
and material possessions, and in which there is a
desire, above all, for that which is new, modern,
exciting and fashionable.” But there is no consensus on the defining empirical features of a consumer society. There is also much disagreement
about when such a society might have first come
into existence, its origins having been dated variously from the seventeenth century to the 1980s.
In social theory, the term was promulgated
partly in reaction to economistic explanations
of social structure and social change prominent
during the period of the revival of neo-Marxism
in Europe in the 1960s and 1970s. In 1970, Jean
Baudrillard published the French version of The
Consumer Society: Myths and Structures (1970 [trans.
1998]), a reflection on the contemporary role of
consumption. Arguing that the productivist
concepts of Marxism – use-value and exchangevalue – were inadequate to capture consumerist
tendencies, he directed attention to sign-values.
Commodities are given meaning through a logic
of signs. The system of consumption was like a
symbolic code or language, a basis for communication rather than for the satisfaction of needs.
Baudrillard’s writing soon after took a postmodernist turn: indeed, consumer society is now
considered by some as coterminous with postmodern society. His personal legacy is found
more in cultural studies of consumption.
88
consumption
Zygmunt Bauman, also a principal theorist of
postmodernity, is the most eminent recent theorist of consumer society. He maintains that
consumption has superseded production as the
dominant organizing principle of society. Whereas industrial society engaged with its members in
their capacity as workers, the consumer society
“engages its members – primarily – in their capacity as consumers. The way present day society
shapes up its members is dictated first and foremost by the need to play the role of the consumer”
(Work Consumerism and the New Poor, 1998). The
consumer attitude becomes pervasive; that is to
say, people expect that their problems will find a
solution, and their needs satisfaction, through
their capacity to purchase goods and services. Consumption then becomes the principal means of
achieving social integration as a majority of the
population are seduced by the promises of consumer freedom.
ALAN WARDE
consumption
A somewhat nebulous concept which has only
recently been used extensively by sociologists, it
remains primarily a topic of interdisciplinary attention, with the related concept “consumer”
more widely deployed, especially in economics,
psychology, and marketing. Its growing importance arose from observation that, in a context of
material abundance, in consumer societies, focal
interests in much of everyday life had been reoriented towards the possession and use of an increasingly wide range of goods and services,
most purchased through the market, but also
many provided by the state.
The concept has two separate historic meanings. The first, and earlier, one had a negative
connotation – to destroy, to waste, to use up. In
political economy in the eighteenth century, a
neutral sense emerged to describe market relationships, hence distinctions between consumer
and producer, consumption and production. This
second meaning signaled concern with the
changing values of items exchanged in market
economies, rather than the purposes to which
goods and services might be put. These two meanings persist in analytic and normative tension.
Negative attitudes to consumption long prevailed, Puritan and Protestant cultures in particular displaying suspicion of luxury and waste.
T. Veblen coined the term conspicuous consumption in his Theory of the Leisure Class (1899) to describe the competitive pursuit of social status
through display of possessions by a section of the
consumption
American middle class. The Frankfurt School were
critical of mass consumption for its uniformity,
cultural mediocrity, and tendency to induce passivity. Modern modes of consumption were said,
variously, to engender narcissistic and hedonistic personalities, to reduce public participation,
to be indifferent to the labor conditions under
which goods are produced, and to cause environmental damage. Such critiques were often
associated with a more general critique of capitalism, especially the fundamental process of
commodification.
Empirical research about consumption was rare
until recently, the main exception being the tradition of research on poverty and inequality whose
roots lie in the nineteenth century. Access to
food, drinking water, and adequate health care,
still critical issues from the perspective of global
inequality, were tackled through state welfare
provision in Europe and North America throughout the twentieth century. In recognition, studies
of the material circumstances of private households were complemented in the 1970s by analyses of collective consumption, examining the
extended role of the state in delivering income,
goods, and public services to citizens. If the modern
postwar welfare state resulted in some overall
de-commodification, as provision through the
market was replaced or supplemented, the policies of the New Right from the 1980s gradually
reversed this. One consequence was described as
the creation of consumption cleavages. Some
people depend on public provision – for transport,
health care, housing, and pensions – while others
purchase these services through the market. To
the extent that state provision is of poorer quality,
which it may be because raising taxation to pay
for expensive services for everyone is politically
contentious, a new social division (arguably,
superseding class) emerges. Those entirely or
mostly dependent upon public provision are comparatively disadvantaged, with some demonstrated effect on their voting behavior and
political attitudes.
Differential consumption of goods and services
became of increasing interest in studies of social
stratification and cultural sociology in the later
twentieth century. Pierre Bourdieu’s classic study
Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
(1979 [trans. 1984]) demonstrated a strong association between class position and cultural taste in
France. He showed differences in taste between
the commercial and professional bourgeoisie, the
intellectual fraction of the middle classes, and the
working class. They differed in their preferences,
consumption
for example for food, interior decoration, and
music. Taste was shown to be a weapon in social
conflicts, as groups and classes towards the top of
the social hierarchy used their economic and cultural capital (see social capital) to establish and
legitimate their privilege.
Another source of inequality is access to positional goods. A positional good is one which delivers value to its user for only so long as not too
many others also have it. Thus, the use-value of
an automobile decreases the more roads become
congested with other motorists. The distinguishing symbolic value of a prestigious, novel, or
fashionable product declines as others acquire
them.
Symbolically significant items attracting the attention of sociologists of consumption include
possessions, cultural knowledge, and cultural participation, as well as preferences. As part of the
“cultural turn” in the 1970s, attention was increasingly shifted from the instrumental aspects
of consumption, from use-values, to the symbolic
dimension of the process, to sign-values. Increasingly, consumption came to be seen as a means
by which individuals and groups expressed their
identities. When combined with diagnoses of
postmodern culture, which stressed the fluidity
and malleability of identity, consumption came
to be understood as a key element in a process of
continually renewed self-constitution or selfassembly. The slogan that “there is no choice but
to choose,” now frequently applied to consumer
behavior, captures the sense in which individuals
are attributed with an autonomy previously
denied both by lack of resources and by the weight
of group or community conventions.
In tandem came a reorientation in the ethical
evaluation of consumption. Beginning in the
1980s in European sociology and cultural studies,
the moral condemnation of consumer behavior
was increasingly contested. (The USA had earlier,
from the late nineteenth century but particularly from the 1930s, a much more optimistic
understanding of the cycle of economic growth
and increased consumption.) The view of the consumer as a passive victim of processes associated
with mass production, of which advertising was
the epitome, was countered by demonstrations of
how people actively and creatively engaged with
goods, appropriating them for their own purposes. The importance of consumer social movements and associations, mobilizing in the name of
“the consumer” was also increasingly appreciated.
And as they flourish, governments claim more
frequently to speak and act on behalf of
89
consumption cleavages
“consumers,” rather than of, say, classes, the
nation, or citizens, and political discussion
increasingly refers to consumer sovereignty, consumer choice, and consumer rights. The discourse
of neo-classical economics takes prominence in
contemporary practical and ideological understanding of consumption.
ALAN WARDE
consumption cleavages
– see consumption.
consumption function
Rarely used in sociology, this term was central to
the macro-economics of J. M. Keynes, who was
concerned with the relationship between expenditure for consumption and saving (and thus capital
investment) in fluctuations in capitalist economic
growth. The consumption function describes the
relationship between consumption and income,
proposing that, all things being equal, consumption increases in proportion to income, though
not necessarily instantaneously. Indeed, many
conditions must be met for this relationship to
hold; stability of prices, rate of replacement of
durables, availability of credit, and level of inflation all affect the decision about when and
whether to consume. The proportion of income
devoted to saving also increases with rise in
income; the poor being less able to afford to
save, and poor countries therefore having less resources for investment. Subsequent work modifies
the Keynesian account. One alternative argues
that the relationship holds only in relation to
permanent income: if income fluctuates from
year to year, expenditure levels will be set in anticipation of long-run and predictable levels
of income. This is the permanent income hypothesis associated with Milton Friedman (1912– ). Another alternative, the life-cycle hypothesis,
maintains that the age of consumers affects their
expenditure, with the young and the old spending
a larger part of their income on consumption,
less on saving, than those in middle age. Such
accounts aim to estimate aggregate levels of expenditure and the savings ratio, indicators important to national macro-level economic
management but of limited relevance to understanding the social and cultural dimensions of
ALAN WARDE
consumption.
control group
This term relates to classic experimental design,
such as the pretest–posttest control group design,
which may be diagrammed like this:
90
convergence
For a somewhat facetious example, let’s say
that a researcher suspects that cigarette smoking
causes health problems. She or he recruits 10,000
young children, and randomly divides them into 2
groups of 5,000 each. The experimental group is
required gradually to take up smoking in childhood, with the amount of cigarettes gradually
rising to between 15 and 35 per day. The other
5,000, the control group, are never allowed to
smoke. The researcher then monitors the health
of the two groups over the decades. If the experimental group tends to develop more medical conditions such as emphysema, lung and throat
cancer, and heart disease than the control group,
the researcher can conclude that smoking causes
disease and lowered life expectancy. The experimental and control groups are the same beforehand, during the course of the experiment the
only difference is that the experimental group is
exposed to the “experimental stimulus” (in this
case, smoking), so that any difference in the end
must be due to (caused by) the experimental
stimulus.
The control group is the group in an experimental design that does not receive the experimental
stimulus and hence provides the essential comparator for the experimental group.
The essence of the true experiment is control –
the researcher controls everything except the
experimental stimulus so that any difference
between the experimental and control groups
must arise from the experimental stimulus. The
main advantage of the randomized experiment is
that, if it is carried out correctly, the researcher
can infer causality.
BERNADETTE HAYES AND ROBERT MILLER
convergence
Identifying a tendency for societies to become
more alike, in principle on any institutional dimension, the term “convergence” has most usually been applied to macro-economic and political
trends, most notably in the work of Clark Kerr,
John T. Dunlop, Frederick Harbison, and Charles
Myers in Industrialism and Industrial Man (1960).
Their convergence thesis, an account of social
development much debated in the 1960s and
1970s, maintained that there was a tendency for
industrializing countries to develop similar
conversation analysis
institutional arrangements. They argued that “industrial systems, regardless of the cultural background out of which they emerge and the path
they originally follow, tend to become more alike
over an extended period of time” and that they
move towards a “pluralistic industrialism” where
power is shared between state, firms, and individuals. Consciously in opposition to Marxist and
conflict theoretical accounts of social structure,
the convergence thesis envisaged greater harmony and consensus as industrialization progressed (see industrial society). Driven by the
so-called “logic of Industrial Society industrialism,” causal priority was given to technology and
the requirements of the industrial system. It was
anticipated that industrialization would produce
similar patterns of division of labor and industrial
relations, the separation of households from
work, urbanization, with rationalization spreading
from the economic sphere into other realms of
social life. Hence, the social and cultural differences between pre-industrial societies would
reduce. In many ways, this amounted to a prediction that all countries would eventually converge
on a pattern established by the modern societies
of the western world. This quasi-evolutionary account has not stood the test of time. It has been
criticized for inadequacies of theoretical explanation; for its propensity to economic and technological determinism; for the implication that
there is only one possible direction for the path
to economic development, that taken in Europe
and North America; and for lack of clarity as to
whether it is industrialism rather than capitalism
that has the effects detected. Empirically,
while industrial societies do have features in
common, they still exhibit very considerable variation in their economic, social, and political arrangements. It is currently more common to
consider instead varieties of capitalism, seeing
the prior institutional arrangements of countries
as laying down different paths of development.
Nor does it appear that material inequalities between countries are diminishing, another condition which would have to be met in order to
achieve convergence. Though the convergence
thesis is no longer invoked, some accounts of the
effects of globalization make similar projections
regarding the homogenization of culture, based
on the worldwide diffusion of the production
activities of large corporations.
ALAN WARDE
conversation analysis
A field of study concerned with the norms, practices, and competences underlying the organiza-
conversation analysis
tion of social interaction, conversation analysis
(CA), notwithstanding the name, is concerned
with all forms of spoken interaction, including
not only everyday conversations between friends
and acquaintances, but also interactions in medical, educational, mass media, and sociolegal contexts, “monologic” interactions such as lecturing
or speech-making, and technologically complex
interactions such as web-based multiparty communication. Originating within sociology in the
1960s and then developing with the privately circulated lectures of Harvey Sacks in 1992, CA has
grown into a field of research that is practiced
worldwide.
CA emerged from two intellectual streams in
sociology. The first is based on Émile Durkheim
and derives most proximately from the work of
Erving Goffman, who argued that social interaction constitutes a distinct institutional order
comprising normative rights and obligations that
regulate interaction, and that function in broad
independence from the social, psychological,
and motivational characteristics of persons. The
second is Harold Garfinkel’s ethnomethodology.
This stresses the contingent and socially
constructed nature both of action and of the
understanding of action, and the role of shared
methods in the production, recognition, and
shared understanding of joint activities. The CA
perspective was formed from a fusion of these
two perspectives by H. Sacks and Emmanuel
Schegloff, who were in direct contact with their
originators. Within CA, the Goffmanian interaction order structures the production, recognition, and analysis of action as it unfolds in real
time, through the use of shared methods or practices. This process (and its analysis) are possible
because participants reflexively display their analyses of one another’s conduct in each successive
contribution to interaction. Correlative to this, CA
starts from the perspective that (contra both Noam
Chomsky and Talcott Parsons) the details of conduct in interaction are highly organized and orderly and, indeed, that the specificity of meaning
and understanding in interaction would be impossible without this orderliness.
CA research centers on the analysis of audio- or
video-recorded naturally occurring interaction.
Recording is essential because no other form of
data retrieval is sufficiently detailed and accurate.
Naturally occurring interaction is essential because other forms of interaction – for example,
scripted theatre, role playing, or interaction in
experimental contexts – are designed in terms of
the designer’s beliefs about interaction which
91
conversation analysis
bear an unknown relationship to the interaction
order itself. Accordingly, CA practitioners regard
naturally occurring interaction as the basic data
for the analysis of interactional structure and
process.
CA proceeds at several analytic levels. At the
most basic level, CA looks for patterns in social
interaction for evidence of practices of conduct
that evidence systematic design. To be identified
as a practice, particular elements of conduct must
be recurrent, specifically situated, and attract responses that discriminate them from related or
similar practices. A central feature of this procedure is that the analysis of the practices used to
perform a social action (for example, prefacing an
answer to a question with “oh,” or identifying a
co-interactant by name in the course of a turn) can
be validated through the examination of others’
responses.
Second, CA focuses on sequences of actions. In
performing some current action, participants normally project (empirically) and require (normatively) the production of a “next” action, or range
of possible “next” actions, to be done by another
participant. Moreover, in constructing a turn
at talk, they normally address themselves to
immediately preceding talk, and design their
contributions in ways that exploit this basic positioning. By the production of next actions, participants show an understanding of a prior action and
do so at a multiplicity of levels – for example, by an
“acceptance,” an actor can show an understanding
that the prior turn was possibly complete, that it
was addressed to them, that it was an action of a
particular type (e.g. an invitation), and so on.
Within this framework, the grasp of a “next”
action within a stream of interactional projects,
the production of that action, and its interpretation by the previous speaker are the products of
a common set of socially shared practices. CA analyses are thus simultaneously analyses of action,
context management, and intersubjectivity, because all three of these features are simultaneously, if tacitly, the objects of the actors’ actions.
At a third level, practices cohere at various
levels of systemic organization. For example, the
turn-taking system for conversation is composed
of sets of practices for turn construction and turn
allocation. The question–answer pair is organized
by a large number of practices that structure the
timing and internal organization of responses to
maximize social solidarity. Evaluations of states of
affairs are structured by a range of practices
through which people manage the relative priority of their rights to evaluate them, and so on.
92
Cooley, Charles Horton (1864–1929)
Based on this framework, CA has developed as
an empirical discipline focused on a range of
domains of interactional conduct, including
turn-taking (the allocation of opportunities to
speak among participants), the organization of
conversational sequences, the internal structuring of turns at talk and the formation of actions,
the organization of repair (dealing with difficulties in speaking, hearing, and understanding talk),
story-telling and narrative, prosody, and body
behavior.
Implicit in CA’s sequential perspective is the
idea that social action is both context-shaped and
context-renewing, and that social context is not a
simple “container” of social interaction, but
rather something that is dynamically created, sustained, and altered across an interaction’s course.
Similar conclusions hold for the relevant social
identities of the participants, which are also activated, sustained, or adjusted on a temporally contingent basis. This perspective has generated a
growing CA research presence in the analysis of
social institutions. Some of this research has investigated practices, sequences, and organizations
that are earmarks of particular institutions or
their tasks. Much of this work has been descriptive
and naturalistic, but it has also been used in
explanatory or predictive multivariate models. Because these analyses are internally valid in an
“emic” sense, they have proved to be robust predictors of conduct, attitudes, and social outcomes,
and this use of CA is likely to grow in the future.
JOHN HERITAGE
Cooley, Charles Horton (1864–1929)
Rooted near his birthplace by the University of
Michigan campus, Cooley led an uneventful life
as an eccentric, renowned professor. A student of
John Dewey, he helped introduce pragmatist ideas
into American sociology.
Cooley’s Human Nature and the Social Order (1902)
set forth his famous notion of the “looking-glass
self ” – that the individual’s sense of self is
“mirrored” through others. He propounded this
against prevailing utilitarian assumptions of the
self as a natural given. His view of the self as a
social product – that individual and society are
not separable, but different aspects of the same
thing – became a key stimulus, along with ideas of
George Herbert Mead, to symbolic interactionism.
Relatedly, Cooley called on sociologists to employ
an empirical method he called sympathetic
introspection – investigating the consciousness
of actors by putting oneself in their place. This
formulation anticipated by generations the
corporate crime
late psychoanalytic catchword of “empathic
introspection.”
In Social Organization: A Study of the Larger Mind
(1909), Cooley elaborated another key concept,
the primary group, a core process at the heart of
institutions where close, intimate, face-to-face
interactions establish common symbols and
meanings. His Social Process (1918) emphasized
how human plasticity leads to social change as a
never-ending but fragile process of reciprocal
change in self, primary group, and social definitions. His pragmatist conception of the creative
potential of social disorganization held that social
dissolution of traditions generates virtues as well
as vices.
Other works include Life and the Student: Roadside
Notes on Human Nature, Society, and Letters (1927) and
posthumous papers, Sociological Theory and Social
Research (1930). A volume of selected writings, On
Self and Social Organization (1998), was edited by
Hans-Joachim Schubert, who wrote an authoritative intellectual biography.
DONALD LEVINE
corporate crime
– see crime.
correlation
Used in a number of more or less precisely defined
senses in sociology, in its loosest sense, this means
that two variables are related. So, if we state that
longevity is positively correlated with social
status, then we are saying that higher-status
people in any society live longer than lower-status
individuals. A negative or inverse correlation
would mean that as one variable increases,
the other decreases. So, cigarette smoking and
longevity are negatively correlated.
In its stricter sense, correlation is defined as a
statistical test to determine whether two variables
are related. There are a number of different
classes of statistic, and the choice of the appropriate type of correlation to calculate is determined
by the nature of the data, and whether it is
parametric or non-parametric.
Knowing that two things are correlated is itself
interesting, but usually social scientists want to
go beyond simple correlation and investigate
cause before they can really state that they have
started to understand the relationship between
two variables. Just the fact that two variables are
correlated tells us little about the causal relationships between them. For instance, there is a correlation between the affluence of a country and
the proportion of lawyers in the population. Is this
because people like the services of lawyers, so as
Coser, Lewis A. (1913–2003)
they get richer they can afford more of the good
things in life like ice cream and lawyers? Or is it
because lawyers make an economy operate more
efficiently, so that countries with more lawyers
become richer? Or is the relationship spurious,
and both lawyers and affluence are by-products
of a certain type of capitalism? We would need
some more complex form of analysis than simply
calculating the correlation to be able to understand that one!
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
Coser, Lewis A. (1913–2003)
Born Ludwig Cohen in Berlin, Coser left for Paris
in 1913, where he studied comparative literature and sociology. He was arrested by the French
government in 1940, but eventually escaped,
emigrating to the United States in 1941, where
he changed his family name to Coser. Under the
guidance of Robert Merton and Paul Lazarsfeld,
he obtained his doctorate from Columbia University. In the postwar period, he became a member
of the circle of New York intellectuals and published critical articles in Partisan Review, Commentary, and the Nation, and with Irving Howe and
others he founded Dissent, for which he served as
co-editor. He founded the sociology department at
Brandeis University and taught there for fifteen
years, before moving to the University of New
York – Stony Brook, where he remained until his
retirement. He was the President of the Society for
the Study of Social Problems in 1967–8. He was
President of the American Sociological Association in 1975. Coser received an honorary degree
from the Humboldt University in Berlin in 1994.
Coser is well known for his contributions to
the history of sociological theory, including Men
of Ideas (1970) and Masters of Sociological Thought.
Ideas in Historical and Social Context (1971). He
edited, with Bernard Rosenberg, Sociological Theory
(1957). He contributed to the study of social conflict in The Functions of Social Conflict (1956). The
principal influences behind Coser’s sociology
were Max Weber and Georg Simmel who inspired
his approach to classical sociological theory, but it
was Simmel in particular who shaped his study of
social conflict. Coser was concerned by the process
of professionalization in American sociology,
which had to some extent undermined the importance of sociology as social criticism. He feared
that the dominance of empiricism and methods
would erode the substance and significance of
sociological investigation. Coser was an influential teacher of sociology, as illustrated in his
Sociology Through Literature (1963).
BRYAN S. TURNER
93
cosmopolitan sociology
cosmopolitanism
cosmopolitan sociology
idea of “world patriotism” against the narrow
With the development of globalization, critics of
traditional sociology have argued that it was implicitly concerned with studying societies that
were nation states, and hence, to become more
relevant to a global world, sociology would have to
change direction and become more cosmopolitan.
The conventional methodologies that employed,
for example, comparative and historical research
could not understand global flows of goods and
communication where national boundaries are of
declining relevance. Ulrich Beck (2000) in Want is
Globalization? has spoken of the emergence of a
cosmopolitan vision in the evolution of transnational society, calling for sociology to embrace
a global understanding of an open world horizon.
A similar stance has been taken by Anthony Giddens in The Consequences of Modernity (1990) where
he argued that classical sociology had been too
much focused on the social structures of the
nation-state, which was implicitly but inadequately equated to the universalistic study of
society.
There are at least three issues which the notion
of cosmopolitan society raises. The first is possibly
trivial, namely, did traditional sociology make
an unwarranted equation of society with nationstate? For example, while anthropological research had the consequence of promoting the
idea of human diversity, nineteenth-century sociology as a product of the Enlightenment embraced
the idea of a unified science of society. Claude
Saint-Simon and Auguste Comte (1798–1857)
shared a common evolutionary view of society in
which the new industrialism would bring about
the destruction of Christian religion, but Comte
saw sociology as a new science – a new “religion of
humanity.” Positivist sociology promoted the idea
of socialism to transcend both the social class
divisions of capitalism and the Darwinian struggle
of the races. Émile Durkheim, as the heir of SaintSimon and Comte, saw the moral dimension of
socialism as a solution to the individualism and
anomie of modern society. For Durkheim, the role
of the state was to provide some moral guidance
to society to compensate for the instability that
was engendered by the market in a capitalist environment. Because Durkheim belonged to the
Enlightenment tradition, his view of history was
universalistic, and, while he was influenced by
British anthropology in The Elementary Forms of the
Religious Life (1912 [trans. 1954]), his thought did
not incline towards cultural relativism. In Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1992) he defended the
nationalism of his day. It can also be argued
that the political economy of Karl Marx sought
94
to understand the global economic process of capitalism, and through communism developed a
socialist version of cosmopolitanism.
Second, the globalization thesis may often
underestimate the resilience of the sovereignty
of the nation-state, and hence sociologists may
be justified in concentrating on the United States
or United Kingdom or France rather than on
global networks. There is little evidence that the
growth of global networks of interaction and
communication have seriously undermined the
political sovereignty of states, or that there is
any prospect of global governance.
Finally, it raises methodological problems about
how exactly sociologists might study global society. While sociology has developed a methodology
that is relevant, for example, to the study of social
groups, cities, and societies, we have yet to develop adequate methodologies relevant to global
society. The study of the internet is, of course, one
promising area of research, and sociologists – for
example, in Chris Mann and Fiona Stewart’s
Internet Communication and Qualitative Research
(2000) – have started to develop the opportunities
made possible by electronic communication
systems.
Despite these criticisms, cosmopolitanism will
become an important research topic in sociology,
and the moral implications of cosmopolitan
duties will have important consequences for the
evolution of sociology, which to some extent
remains bound within its national frameworks,
despite the emergence, for example, of the International Sociological Association and the
International Institute of Sociology. While globalization is influencing the intellectual development of sociology, the American Sociological
Association remains the dominant national institution, and publishing houses still focus on the
publication of work that is relevant to the Englishspeaking, western world.
BRYAN S. TURNER
cosmopolitanism
Historically cosmopolitanism has two related
meanings. Firstly, a cosmopolitan is someone
who embraces plurality and difference. In this
respect, modern cities are often seen as providing
the backdrop for the development of cosmopolitan sensibilities in that they house a number of
distinctive cultures, ethnic groups, and lifestyles.
A cosmopolitan is a polyglot who is able to move
cosmopolitanism
comfortably within multiple and diverse communities, while resisting the temptation to search for
a purer and less complex identity. Cosmopolitan
selves and communities, in this understanding,
will thrive when the right to be different is respected. Second, a cosmopolitan is literally a citizen of the world. This refers to a set of perspectives
that have sought to jettison viewpoints that are
solely determined by the nation, or their geographical standing within the world.
The political philosophy of Immanuel Kant
(1724–1804) argued that a cosmopolitan democracy should be developed to replace the law of
nations with a genuinely morally binding international law. For Kant the spread of commerce
and principles of republicanism could help foster
cosmopolitan sentiments. Kant’s vision of a peaceful cosmopolitan order based upon the obligation
on states to settle their differences through the
court of law has gained a new legitimacy in the
twentieth century with the founding of the
United Nations and the European Union.
More recently a number of political philosophers have argued that Kant’s earlier vision can
be revised to provide a new critical politics for an
increasingly global age. A cosmopolitan political
response is required where national politics has
lost much of its power but little of its influence.
Globalization has undermined the operation of
national democracies as they are increasingly
unable to control the flow of money, refugees,
and asylum seekers, viruses, media images, and
ideas and perspectives. Many have argued that to
begin to address these problems requires the
construction of overlapping forms of political
community connecting citizens into local, national, regional, and global forms of government.
The development of cosmopolitan perspectives is
fostered by the growing acceptance that many
of the problems that face the world’s citizens
cannot be resolved by individual states and are
shared problems. The cosmopolitan project
seeks to revive democracy in an age where it is
increasingly under threat.
There are three main criticisms of these arguments. (1) Such proposals are part of the liberal
enterprise of state building and fail to appreciate
the power of strategic interests apparent on the
global stage. In this understanding, many have
been concerned that the United States (the world’s
last remaining super power) will refuse, and even
try to subvert, cosmopolitan institutions. (2)
Cosmopolitan politics is an elite top-down version
of politics that will inevitably come to represent
the interests of the powerful rather than more
credentialism
“ordinary” or excluded populations. In this respect, some have suggested that we focus upon
the emergence of cosmopolitanism from below
in respect of nongovernmental organizations
(NGOs). (3) Finally, some have been concerned
that the two meanings of cosmopolitanism are
not compatible with one another. Despite the acceptance of universal human rights, the rule of
law, and democracy, many communities remain
excluded from participatory forms of democracy.
Here there is a concern that universal rules fail to
appreciate the difference in people’s identities.
NICK STEVENSON
counterfactual
– see explanation.
credentialism
“Credentials” are the key factors at the interface
between systems of education and systems of employment. Randall Collins’s The Credential Society
(1979) was an extension of his doctoral thesis on
“Education and Employment” which coincided
closely with the publication in 1967 by Peter M.
Blau and O. D. Duncan of The American Occupational
Structure. Belief in the acquisition of credentials –
educationally tested and graded capacities to perform occupationally in commensurately graded
employment tasks – is a by-product of a technocratic model of the social function of education.
As Collins succinctly represented it, the model
assumes that “Education prepares students in
the skills necessary for work, and skills are the
main determinant of occupational success . . .
Hence education determines success.” Collins perceived that the de-schooling movement was an
attempt to liberate education from credentialism,
and that the early work of Pierre Bourdieu on
social reproduction (which he linked with that of
Louis Althusser on the reproduction of the class
relations of capitalism) was also an attempt to
discredit the claims of technocratic and meritocratic thinking. Nevertheless, neither critique sufficiently emphasized the importance of cultural
markets in distorting the transmission of occupational opportunities. Collins argued that even the
civil rights movement in the United States failed
to destroy the supposed legitimacy of an a-cultural
model of educational and occupational allocation.
Disadvantaged groups sought to work the system
of credentialism, generating an inflation of
grades dubiously related to levels of educational
achievement.
Collins argued that in the 1960s the credential
system went into a state of “explicit crisis.” He
95
crime
suggested that the credential system was caught
between opposing forces. On one side the system
had become central to sustaining an economy of
excess productive capacity. On the other side, it
had become very expensive and relatively unrewarding for many individual investors. A balance
remained possible but there was a potential crisis
on either side. In the first instance, too
much growth in the credential market generates
disillusion and withdrawal of material investment, while, in the second, too little investment
produces economic depression.
He suggested that different ideological positions had been adopted about credentialism.
The basic opposition was between what he called
“credential capitalism” and “credential socialism,” but pressure from ethnic groups stimulated
“ethnic-patrimonial” or “patronage” credentialism which, in turn, provoked “credential fascism”
in reaction. He characterized “de-schooling” as a
form of “credential radicalism” but his view was
that there were only two “honest and realistic”
positions: either “credential Keynesianism” which
would recognize that education “creates an artificial credential currency” which does not assume
any precise occupational purchasing power, or,
preferably, “credential abolitionism” which would
force education to re-emphasize its intrinsic,
rather than instrumental, value. D E R E K R O B B I N S
crime
Societies have been concerned about behavioral
expectations, disruptions to social order, and the
protection of the natural flow of life since ancient
times. Ancient Babylon’s Code of Hammurabi is
the earliest evidence of a society that clearly identified a set of rules governing social life. King
Hammurabi (1795–1750 BC) established a historical precedent for other societies to follow. By
drawing notice to his subjects of what he saw as
acceptable behavior, he laid the foundation for a
more organized, purposeful, and civilized social
order. With varying degrees of formalization and
success, rulers have endeavored to protect their
kingdoms, albeit the wealth and power of monarchs have frequently superseded the interests
and protection of their citizens. The key issue
here is that rules governing social life have been
part of the social order of human communities
since recorded time. Violations of these codes of
conduct have also been part of the social fabric
and social experience since humans began living
in social groups.
Hammurabi was no doubt a prescient ruler.
There was a lengthy period between his rule and
96
crime
the eventual codification of conduct into formal
criminal and procedural laws. Before the development of such formalized codes, wrongs were dealt
with on an individual level. The norm was for
aggrieved parties to settle disputes or to right
wrongs between themselves. However, as societies
became more densely populated, urbanized, and
organized, behaviors that violated the sensitivities
of the collective were handled more formally and
eventually judiciously. Codification of unacceptable behavior became necessary. This formalization of expectations established the boundaries
of acceptable behavior by which citizens were to
abide. These violations of the social order have
evolved into what is today referred to as “crime.”
Jay Albanese in Criminal Justice (2002: 13) asserts
that “[c]rime is a natural phenomenon, because
people have different levels of attachments, motivation, and virtue.” He was, no doubt, building
on the notion first put forward by Émile Durkheim. Crime, Durkheim observed, is present in
all societies and is seen as an integral part of
“healthy” communities. In the chapter on “The
Normal and the Pathological” in The Rules of Sociological Method (1895 [trans. 1958]), Durkheim
asserted that “what is normal, simply, is the existence of criminality, provided that it attains and
does not exceed, for each social type, a certain
level.” He further defined crime as being actions
that offend certain very strongly held “collective
sentiments” (1958: 67). What makes crime
“normal” for Durkheim and Albanese is society’s
inability to be exempt from it. In other words, all
societies experience transgressions, albeit in varying forms and varying levels of severity. The mere
presence of crime across time and place makes it a
normal and expected part of group living.
Interestingly, once a society can identify tangibly those actions that are disruptive, the presence of crime can play a unifying role. For
example, if particular behaviors are seen as offensive or threatening the greater social order, those
behaviors will be barred, thus strengthening what
a group believes to be important defining characteristics of its culture. Violations that offend core
values and beliefs of a collectivity become the
foundations for the formalization of codes of conduct at a given point in time and place. The critical issue here is that the behavior must offend
collective sentiments rather than the sentiments
of an individual, thus differentiating between
civil and criminal wrongs.
While violations of social norms are a constant
in all societies, the term “crime” is stubbornly
recalcitrant to precise definition. It is a complex
crime
concept that has been the focus of criminological
and juridical research for many centuries. Crime
is a concept whose definition varies across time
and place. The definition is dependent upon perspective, viewpoint, and perception. Within criminology, there exist several competing theoretical
foundations, all of which construct different and
distinctive definitions of crime.
As with any element of social science, context,
perspective, and ideology play a significant part
in the formulation of concepts, variables, and
their operational definition. Crime is a social construct that reflects normative values, customs,
mores, and tradition of a given society at a given
point in time. Definitions of crime are also reflected in the political values and historical foundations of a social system. For example, the
medieval church played an important and instrumental role in shaping and monitoring the
morality of society, which in turn shaped what
was defined as criminal. For example, in seventeenth-century Europe, the criminality of witchcraft was constructed by political leaders who
were profoundly influenced by the religious community. The practices of witchcraft and sorcery
were feared and regarded as a serious crime
against the community, and as a result punishments were ultimately severe. Most jurisdictions
have since abolished their statutes and laws
pertaining to witchcraft with the development of
secularization.
Another example of how community values
shape the definition of crime is the specific crime
of theft. In western societies, theft is commonly
included in criminal statutes. However, in some
indigenous communities, there is no recognizable
crime of theft owing to a longstanding tradition
of community ownership. Because there is no
legal tradition of private property, there is
no corresponding formulation of a crime of theft.
Finally, religious doctrine also influences criminological and juridical perspectives on what is
acceptable behavior and what constitutes a crime.
For example, the holy law of Islam, the Shari’a, is
deeply rooted in the religious practices and institutions of Muslim societies, and the basic assumptions of the various schools of religious law
are reflected in the criminal codes of many Middle
Eastern and Asian societies today. However, in the
United States and other western societies, there
exists a philosophical and juridical doctrine that
mandates the separation of church and state. The
result is that many beliefs and activities that are
offensive to religious groups are not necessarily
criminalized.
crime
Three perspectives have been prominent in the
definition of crime, namely the legalistic approach, conduct norm, and conflict perspectives.
While there are other perspectives – as described,
for example, in John Hagan, Modern Criminology:
Crime, Criminal Behavior and Its Control (1987) –
these three approaches have been at the intellectual core of the definitional debate for some
decades. Undoubtedly, criminologists and others
who study crime will never come to any firm
agreement or lasting consensus as to what exactly
constitutes a criminal act. Nevertheless, these
perspectives or approaches do yield some
important starting points.
Somewhat naively, crime has been taken for
granted as simply being acts that violate criminal
law, the basis for the legalistic perspective. William L. Marshall and William L. Clark in their
essay on “The Legal Definition of Crime and Criminals,” in Marvin E. Wolfgang, Leonard Savitz, and
Norman Johnston (eds.), The Sociology of Crime and
Delinquency (1962: 14), state very clearly that
“crime is an act or omission prohibited by public
law for the protection of the public, and made
punishable by the state in a judicial proceeding
in its own name.” Inherent in this perspective is
the fact that laws are based on consensus. There is
general agreement as to what behaviors are repugnant and unacceptable. These are then reflected in
substantive criminal law. Crime is, therefore, a
function of beliefs and morality. Those actions
which violate morality and general social mores
become crimes and are constrained by law. In
theory these laws are to be applicable to all
members of society, regardless of social class and
the personal attributes of individuals.
Marshall and Clark clarify the argument that
crimes are public wrongs in contrast to civil injuries, which involve individual victimization. These
authors’ views on the legal framework of crime
are not uncommon. In fact, from the Classical
School through to the 1970s the legalistic approach has existed somewhat in isolation, and
has gone without systematic challenge. More
simply put, crime, according to the legal approach, is any behavior prohibited by criminal
law. Elements that constitute criminal behavior
and that are codified in the law change over
time. This problem of social change emerges
from the fact that norms, values, and beliefs
evolve in a given social context. Interestingly, at
various points in time, the norms and values of a
given society may well conflict with legal statutes.
For example, in the United States during the
1920s, national and local laws prohibited the
97
crime
sale, distribution, and manufacture of alcoholic
beverages. However, the existing laws did not
quench the public demand for alcohol. Public
demand for alcoholic drinks is believed to have
contributed to the emergence and proliferation of
organized criminal gangs. In the 1930s, social
pressure forced the US government to reconsider
its stance, which led to the decriminalization of
laws pertaining to the sale, transportation, and
manufacture of alcohol.
Two principles of law are associated with the
legalistic approach. Under common law, the basis
for many western legal systems, crimes are classified as either mala in se (evil in and of itself) or
mala prohibita (proscribed by law). Additionally,
under the legalistic approach, for a crime to
occur, it must have three elements. The first feature of any crime is that of a guilty act (actus reus).
The second feature is that of a guilty mind (mens
rea). Finally, both of these must concur — the criminal act must converge with a culpable mental
state.
Crimes are generally categorized as felonies,
misdemeanors, and acts of treason. Felonies are
the more serious transgressions and are usually
punishable by imprisonment for over a year. Misdemeanors are considered less serious and punishments range from community-based sanctions
through to jail time for less than one year. Treason
is an act against the state, thus reflected in
Federal Law, although some state constitutions
and statutes do contain treason definitions and
provisions.
While seemingly accurate, the legalistic perspective does not address the complexities and
intricacies of the conceptual problems surrounding crime. Therefore the reliance on the legalistic
aspect only tells a partial story.
The conduct norm model for defining crime
is perhaps best described in Thorsten Sellin’s
Culture Conflict and Crime (1938). He postulated
that the norms and values of the dominant social
class are reflected in criminal law. There is, as a
result, a built-in opportunity for disagreement
and conflict between the dominant group and
subordinate sections of society. Frequently, splinter groups emerge that are based on racial or
ethnic criteria of membership, and as a result
they formulate their own subcultures. From this
situation, a set of conduct norms evolve based
on their own values, beliefs, and interests. Therefore, society can be regarded as a collection of
diverse groups that compete for scarce resources
because they possess conflicting interests and politics. The perspective is built around a division
98
crime
between the conflicting interests and resources
of dominant elites and those of marginalized
social groups, thus setting the stage for constant
conflict.
Closely aligned to the conflict school of criminology, definitions of crime within the conduct
norm perspective are constructed in the interests
of the dominant class. In other words, the group
exercises power in such a manner as to construct
criminal laws to reflect their economic and social
position and interests. Furthermore, laws are unevenly applied in society. The poor and the underclass are most susceptible to unequal and unfair
practices and treatment before the law. Examples
of this inequality are the harsh treatment and
punishments handed down for street crime, traditionally attributed to offenders from the poor
and the underclass segments of society. Whitecollar offences, such as embezzlement and insider
trading, have far-reaching fiduciary losses and
long-term implications for their victims, but they
carry with them relatively minor penalties in comparison to street crimes. However, the treatment
of professional and business leaders in the Enron
accounting scandals in the United States may
suggest a change in legal attitudes towards such
business crimes.
According to the conduct norm perspective, definitions of crime are controlled by the wealthy
and powerful people of position, not from the
broad consensus of society. Therefore, crime is a
political concept designed to protect the powerful
members of the ruling class. According to this
perspective, “real” crimes include economic and
political domination, poor and inadequate working conditions, violations of human rights as reflected by racism, sexism, and imperialism, and
inadequate opportunities for education, housing,
and health care, and unequal participation in
the political process.
Along with the conflict and conduct norm perspectives, the symbolic interactionist perspective
began to challenge the legalistic perspective from
the 1970s. The interactionist perspective in defining crime has its roots in the works of George
Herbert Mead, Charles Horton Cooley, and
William I. Thomas. The tenets of this intellectual
tradition hold that people act in accordance to
their subjective interpretation of social reality,
through which they assign meaning to things
and events. Individuals learn the meaning of reality based on the ways in which others react, either
negatively or positively, towards those social definitions. From this reaction, a person re-evaluates
and interprets his or her own behavior in
crime
accordance with the meaning and symbols they
have learned from others.
The definition of crime reflects the preferences
and opinions of people who hold social power
in a given area. These individuals use their influence to impose definitions of “right” and “wrong,”
“acceptable” or “unacceptable,” on the rest of the
population. As a result, criminals are those whom
society labels as undesirable or as outcasts. The
reason for this label is that they have behaved
in a manner counter to the norms and values of
the rest of the group. Crimes are outlawed because society or the group defines them as such,
not necessarily because they are evil in and of
themselves.
The interactionist perspective is similar to the
conflict tradition in that people of influence determine the boundaries of acceptable conduct.
However, unlike the conflict school, the interactionists in criminology do not assume that the
exploitative relations of capitalist society are the
chief determinant of the disparity. By contrast,
interactionists argue that the boundaries of behavior are determined by moral crusaders, and
when morality shifts, so too do the criminal
laws. Larry Siegel sums up the interactionists’ definition of crime in Criminology (2000: 20) by concluding that “[c]rime is a violation of society rules
of behavior as interpreted and expressed by a
criminal legal code created by people holding
social and political power.”
Hagan in Modern Criminology (1987) identifies
several additional ways in which the term crime
can be defined. These definitions include: the
formal legal; social harm; cross-cultural universal
norm; labeling; human rights; and human diversity. In line with the legalistic perspective, the
formal legal definition holds that whatever
the state defines as being criminal constitutes a
crime. Social harm, according to Hagan, includes
both civil wrongs (disputes between individuals)
and criminal actions (disputes between the state
and the individual). The universalistic interpretation of crime assumes that there is no variation
in different societies. For example, the crime of
murder is a universal violation in all societies. A
crime can only exist when a society reacts to the
repulsiveness of its consequences. The foundation
of the labeling perspective therefore regards social
reaction to the offensive action as the most critical issue. The most comprehensive way to define
crime is Hagan’s human rights perspective, in
which any action that violates an individual’s
human rights would constitute a crime. This
would include acts of oppression, sexism, and
crime
racism. Finally, Hagan defines crime via a human
diversity approach. Related to the human rights
perspective, an action is a crime as a consequence of the social deprivations that arise from
oppressive and discriminatory situations.
The determination of what exactly constitutes
a crime has far-reaching consequences. It is not
just the philosophical considerations that are
taken into account when trying to set the boundaries for acceptable and unacceptable social behavior. The process of defining a behavior as
criminal is left to the legal scholars and criminologists to determine. However, the practical ramifications are important for policymakers. How a
society decides to respond to and enforce the laws
is somewhat dependent on the perceived legitimacy of the existing law. For example, laws that
prohibit the personal use of marijuana have not
been enforced to the full extent that law permits.
Rather, the law enforcement community, in some
areas, has been implicitly tolerant of the infraction, thus giving it a degree of legitimacy.
The study of crime has captured the attention of
many different academic fields. Many schools of
criminology have emerged over the past decades,
and in the social sciences the study of crime is
multidisciplinary, including sociology, psychology, biology, economics, ecology, and law. In
historical terms, criminology is a new member of
the social sciences. Within these social sciences,
countless research programs have been conducted
over the decades in order to understand the process of criminality, and how and why crime occurs.
The search for causal answers to the existence of
crime has covered free-will arguments, biological
and genetic causes, psychological and sociological
variables, and more recently environmental
influences.
Eugene McLaughlin, John Muncie, and Gordon
Hughes in Criminological Perspectives (2005: 8–9)
claim that crime is a “social fact.” Crime is a
product of free will, meaning that offenders
make rational choices when deciding to engage
in specific criminal behaviors. This viewpoint is
compatible with the classical school of criminology’s founding fathers. Cesare Beccaria (1738–94),
a utilitarian philosopher, believed that people
exercise free will when they choose to engage in
any form of behavior, including criminal actions.
He also argued that people’s choices could be
influenced by the level of the corresponding punishment, which should be proportionate, swift,
severe, and certain. Another juridical philosopher, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) postulated
that humans considered several factors before
99
crime
engaging in a particular behavior. Specifically, the
hedonistic or “felicific calculus” measured various
aspects of pleasure and pain, thus providing a
framework for decisionmaking. Simply stated, if
the pleasure gained from engaging in the activity
outweighs the pain associated with it, the person
will engage in the crime. Derek Cornish and
Ronald V. Clarke in The Reasoning Criminal: Rational
Choice Perspectives on Offending (1986) further developed the idea of a rational criminal by exploring the decisionmaking process of contemporary
offenders. Deciding on whether or not to engage
in crime, the person considers personal circumstances and motivations, such as the need for
money, revenge, in relation to situational constraints or opportunities, for example the degree
to which a target is protected, secure, or monitored. The decision to commit the crime will
take into account the risks of apprehension and
the threat of punishment against the benefits
of partaking in the activity. It is a matter of personal choice, given the availability of attendant
information.
Since the earliest foundations of criminology,
biological causes of crime have also been assessed,
especially in the debate about “criminal types.”
Cesare Lombroso (1836–1909) studied physical attributes of offenders in Italian prisons and concluded that there were indeed “born criminals.”
Other biologically related studies included works
by Enrico Ferri (1856–1929) and William Sheldon
(1898–1977). In contemporary criminology, there
is a renewed interest in turning to genetics in the
explanation of crime. In particular, studies have
focused on chromosomal abnormalities, chemical
imbalances, and nutritional deficiencies among
offenders. The research results of this approach
are mixed and inconclusive in their findings, but
the resurgence in biological theories has been significant in modern criminology. The search for a
“criminal gene” is perhaps the most prominent
feature of this resurgence.
Psychological approaches to the study of crime
examine how and why the mind operates and
therefore influences individuals to commit crime.
Historically, the ideas of Sigmund Freud were influential in suggesting a variety of conditions,
such as the weakened ego or superego structures,
that fail to contain the urges of the id, in the
explanation of criminal behavior. In addition to
the psychoanalytical approach, cognitive theories
approach crime slightly differently. Cognitive
theorists believe that crime occurs as a result
of a particular pattern of thinking, which
often includes short-term, self-indulgent, and
100
crime
self-gratifying actions in the absence of thoughts
about how the behavior may affect others.
The sociological approach to crime is by far the
most common and popular among those available. These sociological approaches evolved out
of the weakness of biological and psychological
theories in their ability to describe and explain
fully the occurrence of crime. Jay Albanese in
Criminal Justice (2002) categorizes the sociological
approaches to crime into four types: learning theories; blocked opportunity theories; social bond
theories; and choice-based theories, which have
been discussed previously. Edwin H. Sutherland
in Principles of Criminology (1934) first posited that,
along with all other forms of behavior, crime is
learned. Individuals learn how to behave by watching others or through role modeling. In essence,
those who commit crime have interacted with
others who have committed crime, thus learning
the process of committing the particular offense,
including ways of eluding police, or improving
their criminal technique. Theories highlighting
blocked opportunities developed during the
1940s–1950s, resulting eventually in the classic
work of Richard A. Cloward and Lloyd E. Ohlin
in Delinquency and Opportunity (1960). Crime, according to these theories, occurs as a result of individuals encountering structural barriers that
prohibit them from achieving culturally acceptable goals through legitimate means. Travis
Hirschi in his seminal research on the social
bond in Causes of Delinquency (1969) found that
the degree to which a person is “tied” to society
directly reflects the probability of committing
crime. In other words, someone who has a great
deal of attachment to a community, including
feelings of commitment to others, to conventional
activities, and to a sense of moral values, is less
likely to commit a crime.
A final approach to the study of crime is the
environmental perspectives. According to Jacqueline Schneider in The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology (2006), environmental criminology is a
theoretical tradition that examines crime in relation to its physical setting. Anthony Bottoms and
Paul Wiles in “Environmental Criminology,” in
the Oxford Handbook of Criminology (2002), also
claim that environmental criminology, rooted
theoretically in human and social ecology, studies
crime, criminality, and victimization in relation
to place, space, and the interaction between the
two. Of particular concern to environmental criminologists is the manner in which criminal opportunities are generated by the characteristics
and attributes of the physical setting. The overall
criminal justice system
aim is to identify methods by which to alter these
spatial characteristics in order to reduce criminal
opportunities at various points in time. Although
environmental criminology has been historically
under-utilized within mainstream criminology,
the perspective has been gaining prominence
since the 1970s.
Pat Brantingham and Paul Brantingham in Environmental Criminology (1991) observe that crime
has four determinants: law; offenders; targets;
and places. Classical criminology has focused on
the legal aspects, while the positivists have concentrated their work on the offenders and their
motivations. Environmental criminology addresses the last two determinants, targets and
places.
JACQUELINE SCHNEIDER
criminal justice system
This refers to a set of legal and social institutions
established to enforce the criminal law in accordance with defined procedural rules and limitations in any one country, society, or subdivision
of a society.
There are generally four key elements in a criminal justice system: (1) law enforcement – involving
the police, prosecution, and defense, which deal
with offenders from the stage of reporting of a
crime and arrest to prosecution in court; (2) the
courts – which normally make decisions about pretrial detention, adjudicate on the guilt of offenders,
and decide on sentences for those convicted; (3) the
penal system (or department of corrections) – which
involves fine enforcement through the courts, and
the delivery of penalties through community-based
penalties and intermediate sanctions such as
supervision, probation, and prisons, jails, or reformatories. In addition, parole agencies or boards
determine whether or not offenders might be released from custody early and under what conditions; (4) the fourth element of criminal justice
concerns crime prevention – which, in addition to
the agencies already mentioned, often involves a
local or regional unit of government and a wider
group of agencies which address broad social and
structural conditions that may lead to crime
(for example, drug addiction help sources and
housing advisory services). In addition, there are
numerous other agencies whose work involves
criminal law enforcement: vehicle licensing agencies, tax authorities, and transport authorities, for
example.
The criminal justice system in each jurisdiction
undergoes periodic change, most often following
a change in government and ideological direction,
or following media attention to a miscarriage of
criminal justice system
justice or a moral panic regarding particular
crimes. The shape of the criminal justice system
may also be influenced by business and publicemployee organizations, which have a major stake
in criminal justice issues. Although legislators and
other elected officials are not involved in individual cases, they are involved in the formulation of
criminal laws and criminal justice policy, and this
necessarily has a major impact on the way in
which a system functions.
Other institutions may also affect the operations and policy of criminal justice. In Europe,
for example, the European Court of Human Rights
serves to protect the rights and liberties of individuals within Europe. In this sense, the European
Court serves as a final appeal court for those dealt
with within European criminal justice systems.
There have been longstanding debates about
how far agencies of the criminal justice system
cooperate, how far they have a shared vision, and
how far they might be said to serve as a smoothfunctioning system rather than as a series of
loosely connected agencies. In this sense, we may
distinguish between agency-specific functions and
the goals of the system as a whole. Existing
systems include some ancient components (for
example, jury trials) and some which are of recent
origin (for example, specialized drug courts).
There are many variations in criminal justice
systems around the world. Crime, guilt, and
punishment are conceived and dealt with very
differently according to the laws and cultures
of different countries. The operation of any one
criminal justice system inevitably raises issues of
fairness and equality, rights, and responsibilities.
Crime control (with a focus on repressing criminal
conduct) and due process (with a focus on the
inviolability of legal rules and procedures so as
to protect the offender and victim from the arbitrary exercise of power) have been presented as
alternative models of criminal justice by Herbert
Packer in The Limits of the Criminal Sanction (1968) as
if systems are one or the other, but often criminal
justice systems are a mixture of these values or
completely different.
In Australia and New Zealand, for example,
crimes are perceived as community conflicts and
resolved outside the formal criminal justice
system via local restorative justice mechanisms
which involve local families and communities
meeting to resolve the conflicts and find informal
ways of repairing the harm done. Such approaches
(sometimes known as family-group conferencing)
are commonly used by indigenous populations.
Increasingly, criminal justice systems across the
101
criminal statistics
criminology
world are expressing interest in the possibility of
adopting and adapting elements of this approach
as an adjunct to the formal system.
LORAINE GELSTHORPE
criminal statistics
– see crime.
criminology
The study of crime has a longstanding and rich
history. In its earliest days, criminology was
thought to encompass any study that pertained
to the problem of crime. This simple description
was born out of a fundamental desire to know
more about deviant behavior, those actions that
violated social norms and mores. Today, criminology is an advanced theoretical field of study
pertaining to crime, criminal events, the actors —
offenders, victims, and those who respond to
crime – the etiology of crime, legal foundations
and parameters, and societal reactions to crime.
However, the definition, while accurate, is somewhat misleading and seemingly uncomplicated.
Reality tells us another story. Criminology is not
simply a science left to criminologists. There are a
number of related disciplines, with varied interests and perspectives, associated with this particular social science. Criminology is firmly rooted in
sociology, but is also studied by anthropologists,
biologists, psychologists, economists, political scientists, and legal scholars, among others. Criminology has been described by Eugene McLaughlin,
John Muncie, and Gordon Hughes in their edited
volume Criminological Perspectives (2003) as “a ‘site’
of contested meaning where competing theoretical perspectives meet.” Owing to the diverse
nature of those involved in the study of crime,
the literature is often rich with discussion, debate,
and interpretation.
Modern criminology is faced with multiple
areas of focus, thus making it a truly multidisciplinary field of study. The particular focus of
criminology is dependent on the perspective
taken. Generally speaking, criminology: describes
and analyzes the extent, nature, and distribution
of the various forms of crime, offenders, and
victims; analyzes causes of crime with the aim of
forwarding theoretical constructs; studies formulation of criminal law; studies the processes of
justice, including police, adjudication, and punishment; evaluates policy responses and initiatives; and evaluates social reactions to crime.
Given the large undertaking, the great task of all
criminology, according to John Tierney in his book
102
Criminology: Theory and Context (1996), regardless of
which underlying perspective is utilized, is to “unravel, or deconstruct, the concept of crime.”
The study of crime could be said to have originated with theologians, who equated criminal behavior with sin, demonic influences, or witchcraft.
Transgressions were investigated and found to
have causes firmly rooted in the dark workings
of the netherworld. Clergy were the obvious
choice to turn to for intervention, becoming
responsible for purging society from evil doings
(that is crime) by way of very harsh methods, such
as exorcisms and trials by fire. After this period of
religious influence, came two defining periods
that shaped today’s criminology: the Classical
School and the Positivist School.
Foundations for modern criminological
thought were laid down during the eighteenth
century with the seminal works of Cesare Beccaria
(1738–94) and Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), thus
creating the Classical School of Criminology. Developed during a time where individual rights and
interests were competing against those of the
states, most of Beccaria’s and Bentham’s writing
revolved around the need for reformation of the
criminal justice system. In other words, they were
advocates for structural changes that ended the
arbitrary application of laws and severe punishments. Instead, Beccaria and Bentham called for
the universal application of laws to all society’s
citizens, thus providing equal protection before
the law. Following this, they called for proportionate punishment. The utilitarian ideal of proportionality meant that punishment was determined
by the severity of the crime committed, not on the
individual characteristics of the offender. This
idea provides the foundation for most criminal
justice systems worldwide, thus leaving the classical school’s ideological mark on modern society.
Prevention was another guiding principle of the
Classical School. Feeling that prevention is far
preferable to punishment, the philosophers put
forth the idea that social systems of control must
take into account the rationality of people. Beccaria and Bentham believed that free will guided
behavior and that decisions to violate laws were
calculated in accordance to hedonistic tendencies.
People wanted to experience pleasure and avoid
pain; therefore individual decisions were based
on the probability of detection, and of being punished, set against the pleasure gained by partaking in the offending activity.
The classical school ended a system of arbitrarily applied justice and punishment. It also
criminology
provided a new way of examining theories of criminality that acknowledge the free will of participants. However, this school falls short in its
undertakings by failing to acknowledge external
forces that may well influence criminal behavior,
for example, social stratification and inequality,
thus providing a foundation for a new paradigm
to evolve.
The origin of the positivist tradition in criminology in the late nineteenth century is often associated with the work of Cesare Lombroso (1835–
1909), whose main contribution to the field was
the measurement of physical characteristics of
Italian prisoners. It is important to note that,
while the Positivist School rejected the free will
philosophies of the Classical School in favor of
determinism, the most important contribution
of the new school was the step-change in ideology
that was characterized by the drive to measure
empirically those phenomena associated with
crime. While Lombroso’s work is largely acknowledged as the starting point, the quest to measure
social phenomena can be traced to the work of
French and Belgian statisticians in the 1820s. For
example, Adolphe Quetelet (1796–1874) found predictability in the distribution of crime and crime
rates within French society. Therefore, the key aim
of the Positivist School was to quantify observations. Measuring phenomena provided data upon
which investigators could make inferences about
causal relationships. Empirical evidence obtained
via methods used in the natural sciences not only
provided an avenue for theorists to advance their
work, but also gave to the field of inquiry scientific respectability.
The work of Lombroso, Enrico Ferri (1856–1929),
and William Sheldon (1898–1977) into physical
characteristics and body types highlighted the
Positivist School’s contributions to criminology.
Lombroso, referred to as the father of criminology,
was a physician employed by the Italian penal
system, who noted the physical characteristics of
those imprisoned, thus putting forth the idea of a
criminal type. Running parallel with the work of
Charles Darwin, Lombroso’s scientific observations of the physical characteristics of prisoners
made generalizations about criminality possible.
Going beyond the examination of body types
and their connection to criminality, the Positivist
School also focused on isolating the differences
between criminals and non-criminals in terms of
psychological, social, and economic factors. Positivists disregard the notion of free will, as forwarded by the classical criminologists, in favor of
critical race theory
the idea that an array of social factors impacted
behavior. In other words, a range of social
factors caused or determined the course of action
an individual took.
The legacy of the positivists is the use of scientific methodology to frame criminological enquiry. However, this school is not without its
shortcomings. While the utilization of scientific
method is preferable to conjecture, there exists
the possibility of the misapplication of technique
and misinterpretation, thus resulting in misleading conclusions.
Other criticisms of the Positivists relate to the
definition of the term “crime.” Conflict criminology emerged in response to positivists’ claim that
an underlying consensus existed regarding the
nature and meaning of the concept of “crime.”
Rather, conflict criminologists believe that state
interests and the interests of the powerful determine the definitional parameters of the concept.
This skewed viewpoint puts those already at the
margins of society at risk for further disadvantage.
Additionally, critics believe that, all too often,
positivists ignore the relevance of cultural differences, as well as varying value systems that
underpin the concept of crime. The power of criminology is in its ability to “travel.” In other words,
theories, strategies, and criminological and criminal justice policy generated in one country are
increasingly exported to other countries. The influence is not just in the empirical research, but
also in the language and conceptual framework.
These can have a profound impact on politicians,
policymakers, and government officials, not to
mention those who are afflicted by crime, as well
as the general citizenry. However, it is ultimately
important to gain a firm understanding about the
values, culture, and social expectations within a
given society before setting forth to seek causal
explanations for crime.
JACQUELINE SCHNEIDER
critical race theory
Critical of liberal theories of rights, especially in
the area of race and ethnicity, this theory evolved
initially in legal theory in the post-civil-rights era.
Critical race theory (CRT) attacked the color-blind
approaches to justice that were typical of the early
days of reform. In fact, lack of significant progress
in social reform for black Americans was the main
force behind critical race theory. Many leading
black American intellectuals, such as Cornel
West in Race Matters (1993), criticized the hollow
promises of liberal reform and argued that there
103
critical race theory
was a cynical if implicit acceptance of racial
hierarchy and inequality in the distribution of
economic wealth and power in the United States.
In an influential article, D. A. Bell in “Remembrance of Racism Past. The Civil Rights Decline,” in
J. Hill and J. E. Jones (eds.), Race in America. The
Struggle for Equality (1993: 73–82), outlined three
shortcomings of existing liberal philosophies of
race. First, the Constitution rewarded property
over claims for justice. Second, whites support
racial reform only when it is in their self interest;
and finally, whites will not support reform if it is a
challenge to their social status. CRT had its
origins in jurisprudential debates about justice,
but it has also had an impact on educational
theory and practice, where it is argued – for
example by W. F. Tate in “Critical Race Theory”
(1996: 201–47), and by J. A. Banks in “The Historical Reconstruction of Knowledge about Race”
(1995: 4–17) – that a restrictive interpretation of
anti-discrimination laws limits the progress and
educational attainment of African-Americans. CRT
has also begun to influence theories of multiculturalism, where the liberal agenda does not
appear to have been successful from the perspective of black America.
CRT has a number of distinguishing features. It
has been critical of the traditional binary division
between “black” and “white,” especially where
blacks have “race” as a biological category and
whites have “ethnicity” as a social category. It
has welcomed sociological studies of the law because conventional jurisprudence has often neglected the social conditions that determine
injustice. It has taken a more positive view of
victims in giving recognition to the personal narratives of the oppressed. For example, M. Matsuda,
R. Delgado, and K. Crenshaw, in Words That Wound
(1993), explored victims’ narratives to understand
the connections between hate speech, the law,
and racial violence. Like African-American Studies,
CRT has encouraged interdisciplinary and comparative studies of racial oppression, such as
Howard Winant’s The World Is a Ghetto (2001).
There are several valuable introductions to CRT,
such as Richard Delgado and Jean Stefancic’s Critical Race Theory. The Cutting Edge (2nd edn., 2000)
and K. Crenshaw, N. Gotanda, G. Peller, and K.
Thomas (eds.), Critical Race Theory. The Key Writings
that Formed the Moment (1995). Although CRT has
been influential in law and pedagogy, it has
been less prominent in the sociology of race and
ethnicity. It appears to have had relatively little
impact outside the United States, possibly because
104
critical theory
racism in European societies has had a somewhat
different history.
BRYAN S. TURNER
critical theory
This phrase operates implicitly as a code for the
quasi-Marxist theory of society of a group of interdisciplinary social theorists collectively known as
the Frankfurt School. The term Frankfurt School
refers to the work of members of the Institut für
Sozialforschung (Institute for Social Research)
that was established in Frankfurt, Germany, in
1923 as the first Marxist-oriented research center
affiliated with a major German university. Under
its director, Carl Grünberg (1861–1940), the Institute’s work in the 1920s tended to be empirical,
historical, and oriented towards problems of the
European working-class movement.
Max Horkheimer became director of the Institute in 1930, and gathered around him many talented theorists, including Erich Fromm, Franz
Neumann (1900–54), Herbert Marcuse, and Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno. Under Horkheimer,
the Institute sought to develop an interdisciplinary social theory that could serve as an instrument
of social transformation. The work of this era was
a synthesis of philosophy and social theory, combining sociology, psychology, Cultural studies,
and political economy.
The first major Institute project in the Horkheimer period was a systematic study of authority, an
investigation into individuals who submitted to
irrational authority in authoritarian regimes.
This culminated in a two-volume work, Studien
über Autorität und Familie (1936), and a series of
studies of fascism, including Adorno, Else Frenkel–
Brunswik, and Daniel J. Levinson, The Authoritarian
Personality (1950). Most members were both Jews
and Marxist radicals and were forced to flee
Germany after Hitler’s ascendancy to power. The
majority emigrated to the United States and the
Institute became affiliated with Columbia University from 1931 until 1949, when it returned to
Frankfurt.
From 1936 to the present, the Institute has referred to its work as the “critical theory of society.” For many years, “critical theory” was
distinguished by its attempt to found a radical
interdisciplinary social theory rooted in Hegelian–
Marxian dialectics, historical materialism, and
the critique of political economy. Members
argued that Marx’s concepts of the commodity,
money, value, exchange, and fetishism characterize not only the capitalist economy but also
social relations under capitalism, where human
critical theory
relations and all forms of life are governed by
commodity and exchange relations and values.
Critical theory produced theoretical analysis of
the transformation of competitive capitalism into
monopoly capitalism and fascism, and hoped to
be part of a historical process through which capitalism would be replaced by socialism. Horkheimer claimed that: “The categories which have
arisen under its [traditional theory’s] influence
criticize the present. The Marxist categories of
class, exploitation, surplus value, profit, impoverishment, and collapse are moments of a conceptual whole whose meaning is to be sought, not in
the reproduction of the present society, but in its
transformation to a correct society” (“Traditional
and Critical Theory,” 1972: 218). Critical theory is
thus motivated by an interest in emancipation
and is a philosophy of social practice engaged in
“the struggle for the future.” Critical theory must
remain loyal to the “idea of a future society as the
community of free human beings, in so far as such
a society is possible, given the present technical
means” (230).
In a series of studies carried out in the 1930s,
the Institute for Social Research developed theories of monopoly capitalism, the new industrial
state, the role of technology and giant corporations in monopoly capitalism, the key roles of
mass culture and communication in reproducing
contemporary societies, and the decline of democracy and of the individual. Critical theory drew
alike on Hegelian dialectics, Marxian theory,
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900), Sigmund Freud,
Max Weber, and other trends of contemporary
thought. It articulated theories that were to
occupy the center of social theory for the next
several decades. Rarely, if ever, has such a talented
group of interdisciplinary intellectuals come together under the auspices of one institute. They
managed to keep alive radical social theory during
a difficult historical era, and provided aspects of a
neo-Marxian theory of the changed social reality
and new historical situation in the transition
from competitive capitalism to monopoly
capitalism.
During World War II, the Institute split up
due to pressures of the war. Adorno and Horkheimer moved to California, while Leo Lowenthal
(1900–93), Marcuse, Neumann, and others worked
for the United States government as their contribution to the fight against fascism. Horkheimer
and Adorno worked on their joint book Dialectic of
Enlightenment (1947 [trans. 1972]), which discussed
how reason and enlightenment in the contemporary era turned into their opposites, transforming
critical theory
what promised to be instruments of truth and
liberation into tools of domination. In their scenario, science and technology had created horrific
tools of destruction and death, culture was commodified into products of a mass-produced culture industry, and democracy terminated in
fascism, in which masses chose despotic and
demagogic rulers. Moreover, in their extremely
pessimistic vision, individuals were oppressing their own bodies and renouncing their own
desires as they assimilated and made their
own repressive beliefs and allowed themselves to
be instruments of labor and war.
Sharply criticizing enlightenment scientism
and rationalism, as well as systems of social domination, Adorno and Horkheimer implicated, however implicitly, Marxism within the “dialectic of
enlightenment” since it too affirmed the primacy
of labor, instrumentalized reason in its scientism
and celebration of “socialist production,” and
shared in western modernity and the domination of nature. After World War II, Adorno,
Horkheimer, and Frederik Pollock returned to
Frankfurt to reestablish the Institute in Germany,
while Lowenthal, Marcuse, and others remained
in the United States.
In Germany, Adorno, Horkheimer, and their associates published a series of books and became a
dominant intellectual current. At this time, the
term Frankfurt School became widespread as a
characterization of their version of interdisciplinary social research and of the particular social
theory developed by Adorno, Horkheimer, and
their associates. They engaged in frequent methodological and substantive debates with other
social theories, most notably “the positivism dispute,” where they criticized more empirical and
quantitative approaches to social theory and
defended their own more speculative and critical
brand of social theory. The German group around
Adorno and Horkheimer was also increasingly
hostile towards orthodox Marxism and were in
turn criticized by a variety of types of “Marxists–
Leninists” and “scientific Marxists” for their alleged surrender of revolutionary and scientific
Marxian perspectives.
The Frankfurt School eventually became best
known for their theories of “the totally administered society,” or “one-dimensional society,”
which analyzed the increasing power of capitalism over all aspects of social life and the development of new forms of social control. During
the 1950s, however, there were divergences between the work of the Institute relocated in
Frankfurt and the developing theories of Fromm,
105
cross-sectional design data
Lowenthal, Marcuse, and others who did not
return to Germany, which were often at odds
with both the current and earlier work of Adorno
and Horkheimer. Thus it is misleading to consider the work of various critical theorists during
the postwar period as being produced by members of a monolithic Frankfurt School. Whereas
there were both a shared sense of purpose and
collective work on interdisciplinary social theory
from 1930 to the early 1940s, thereafter critical
theorists frequently diverge, and during the
1950s and 1960s the term the Frankfurt School
can really be applied only to the work of the
Institute in Germany.
DOUGLAS KELLNER
cross-sectional design data
One of the most common forms of data used in
sociological analysis, this is the sort of data
gathered by a simple survey. It can be collected
relatively quickly and (dependent on how the
questionnaire is administered) cheaply. For instance, if a researcher wanted to determine the
attitudes of employees to their jobs, then a simple
cross-sectional design research project could be
completed by sending questionnaires to a sample
of, say, several hundred or thousand employees. If
care was taken, and the employees were selected
to be representative of a larger population (say, all
employees in the United Kingdom) then the
results could be generalized to that larger population through the use of inferential statistics. Averages could be calculated to describe the typical
British employee, or correlations or regressions
could be calculated to investigate the relationships between the variables, and find answers to
questions such as “what sorts of employees are
most satisfied with their jobs?”
However, cross-sectional designs have a number
of limitations that restrict their usefulness for
serious sociological enquiry. They provide a “snapshot” of how things are at one particular point
in time, but do not provide information on the
dynamics of a system; for example how things
develop over time, how inequality is perpetuated,
or how institutions reproduce themselves. They
are also poor at determining the causal nature of
the relationships that are detected.
Because of these limitations, much effort has
been expended on gathering large datasets that
provide more insight into how things change over
time, for instance the British Household Panel
Survey (BHPS) that re-interviews the same individuals and households each year ( see panel studies),
or birth cohort studies such as the National Child
Development Study that follows an entire cohort
106
cultural deprivation
born in one week in March, 1958, across the
United Kingdom, to investigate the relationship
between childhood environments and experiences
and outcomes in adult life or old age.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
cult(s)
The word cult is often used interchangeably
with new religious movements and, in everyday
language, tends to have a strong negative connotation (for example James Beckford, Cult Controversies: The Societal Response to New Religious Movements,
1989). Cults are generally seen as evolving around
individuals and/or beliefs that are outside the
mainstream. Specifically, the term is used to
denote the group solidarity attendant on an excessive degree of attachment and ceding of influence
to a particular person or to a particular set of
ideas and beliefs. The imposing leadership qualities displayed by founders of new religious movements, such as Jim Jones (the People’s Temple) or
David Koresh (Branch Davidians), or specific ideas
about Unidentified Flying Objects (UFOs) or paganism can variously produce a tightly bound
cult following among their respective associates
and believers. Cult-like behavior, however, is not
confined to religious movements; paralleling
charisma, of which it is an accentuated expression, leadership or personality cults are found
across politics (for example the cult of the emperor) and pop culture (for example Princess
Diana), and in economic corporations, among
other spheres. Within the religious domain, moreover, there is a long history of cultic adoration –
the cult of the saints and of devotion to the Virgin
Mary represent strong traditional forms of popular religion. Such cults play a large role today in
religious tourism and the popularity of religious
festivals, devotional rituals, local apparition sites,
and pilgrimages (see W. Swatos and L. Tomasi
(eds.), From Medieval Pilgrimage to Religious Tourism,
2002). Cults promote religious engagement, but
also stimulate concerns among church officials
that the cultic status of a particular saint may
undercut the routinized and institutionalized authority of church (see church–sect typology) officials to demarcate sacred beliefs, practices, and
MICHELE DILLON
places.
cultural capital
– see social capital.
cultural deprivation
This phrase refers to the idea that some racial and/
or working-class cultures are deficient because
cultural deprivation
they hinder school and social success. Cultural
deprivation theory was influential during the
1960s and 1970s. It was linked to ideas about the
culture of poverty, the underclass (see social
class), and to the idea of a cycle of poverty in
which the values associated with being poor
(such as fatalism and an antipathy to individually
accumulated wealth) and the practices associated
with poor communities prevented marginalized
groups from social and economic advancement.
Within the purview of cultural deprivation
theory, the concept of subculture took on its
earlier derogatory (and now discredited) definition as a deviant or otherwise marginal milieu.
From within the sociology of culture, the idea of
cultural deprivation drew upon work by Basil
Bernstein and Pierre Bourdieu. While Bernstein’s
focus was on language – in particular, the notion
that working-class speakers employed a “restricted” (versus “elaborated”) communicative
code – Bourdieu’s emphasis was on the idea that
the dominated class were unable to appropriate
“legitimate” forms of culture and thus were deprived of opportunities for advancement. Work in
the sociology of education buttressed these ideas
by showing how children from backgrounds
lacking in cultural capital or “home advantages”
were destined to fail because of a mismatch between the cultures of home and school. This argument was explored in Annette Lareau’s Home
Advantage (2000). The idea of cultural deprivation
has inspired various policy initiatives, such as
Headstart, from the 1960s onward, with the aim
of providing working-class and minority children
with the cultural tools they otherwise lack. It has
also been subject to considerable critique on a
variety of fronts, most notably ethnographic and
sociolinguistic.
On the linguistic critical front, William Labov’s
many studies – such as Language in the Inner City
(1972) – of nonstandard English described how depictions of the inferiority of black communicative
styles were simply ignorant of the meanings associated with that speech community, therefore
also showing how the idea of cultural deprivation
illustrated the white middle-class bias of both
social institutions and social science. In her study
of a black and economically disadvantaged community in Chicago, Carole Stack in All Our Kin
(1978) demonstrated how community members
posed alternative values and meanings, ones that
were, given the structural disadvantages and routine contingencies they faced, highly logical and
deeply practical. In Britain, Paul Willis’s Learning
to Labour (1977) showed also how the “lads” (as
cultural imperialism
the schoolboys came to be known in his study)
were seen to be actively engaged in processes of
resisting the meanings and values of mainstream
life. While the versions of cultural deprivation
theory developed by Bourdieu and Bernstein
were extremely useful in illuminating some
of the cultural mechanisms through which stratification systems are reproduced, the idea of
cultural deprivation can be understood as, ultimately, conservative, insofar as it implied that marginalized groups needed to abandon their initial
logics and practices in favor of “legitimate” forms,
to gain access to economic and expressive opportunities. In this respect, cultural deprivation
perpetuates what Richard Sennett and Jonathan
Cobb once famously referred to as The Hidden
Injuries of Class (1972).
TIA DENORA
cultural imperialism
Though the impact or imposition of foreign cultural values on subject peoples can be routinely
regarded as part of the general phenomenon of
imperialism, the term cultural imperialism has
come to be used more widely in discussions of
the influence of the values and beliefs of the dominant global powers on the poorer and weaker
societies of the world, whether or not these are
or have been subject colonies. Specifically the
term refers to the use of superior economic and
political power to export or impose values and
attitudes at the expense of native cultures.
At the most general level, this imposition can be
considered as a cultural or ideological offshoot of
the more general spread of a whole economic
system, such as that of capitalism (communism
in its heyday was also accused of cultural imperialism). In that sense, cultural imperialism takes
the form of the promotion of capitalist values of
individualism, competition, and materialism, at
the expense of alternative or more traditional
values, such as communalism and cooperation.
More discretely, cultural imperialism can be seen
simply as the expression of the influence and
popularity of the culture industries of the great
powers – the reach and influence of their television, film, music, publishing, and advertising
products.
While certain non-western and non-capitalist
powers – such as China in Tibet or the Soviet
Union in eastern Europe – have been accused of
cultural imperialism, it is generally laid at the
door of the major western capitalist societies, the
European and, especially, the American. In many
ways, indeed, cultural imperialism has become
synonymous with Americanization, since even
107
cultural lag
some European societies, notably that of France,
have protested at the degree of American influence on their culture. What is normally meant
by this is the steady spread of such things as
American eating habits, as symbolized by the
McDonald’s chain, and the dominant position in
the world of the American film and television
industries, as symbolized by Hollywood. Another
common concern is the worldwide spread of
large leisure and entertainment complexes,
such as the Disney Corporation with its Disneylands and Disneyworlds, and the dominant position assumed by large news corporations such
as CNN.
But “Americanization” is something of a misnomer, as is clear from the power of the Australian media magnate Rupert Murdoch and his
company News International – even though this
has large American operations, and Murdoch himself became an American citizen in 1985. Moreover, it has been shown by many studies that the
idea of cultural imperialism exaggerates the oneway flow of values and ideas. The claim for the
McDonaldization or “Disneyfication” of the world
ignores the extent to which local cultures mediate
and reinterpret the influences from outside, large
as these may be. The ambience and use of, say, a
McDonald’s restaurant can be very different
depending on whether it is in Dallas, Delhi, or
Beijing. In general one might say that cultural
imperialism is bound up with globalization, and
while, as with all processes of globalization, there
is a general tendency towards standardization and
uniformity, this is by no means uncontested or
ever complete.
KRISHAN KUMAR
cultural lag
– see William F. Ogburn.
cultural logic of late capitalism
– see Fredric Jameson.
cultural materialism
Materialists have traditionally seen culture as a
representation of an external reality. Culture is
deemed truthful to the extent that it “reflects”
the material world in an accurate way.
Cultural materialism breaks from this notion in
two ways. The first is that it argues that culture
itself is part of the material world. Culture is
defined much more broadly as human activity –
the way we organize our lives – rather than an
aesthetic representation of the world through
music, literature, and art. For example, the houses
we build, the way we relate to others, the leisure
108
cultural relativism
activities we pursue, should be deemed cultural
since they are part of (rather than reflect) material
reality. Whereas a traditional materialist view of
society examines the difference between social
reality and our cultural perceptions of it, a cultural materialist view of society sees this social
reality as itself culturally constituted.
Culture, then, is a force that actually creates
(rather than reflects or expresses) the material
world. Even conventionally conceived culture –
literature, music, and art – is seen as practical
and not merely theoretical, since it constitutes
the world as “discourse.” To put the matter
philosophically, culture ceases to be simply
“epistemological” – that is, concerned with accuracy, truthfulness, etc. – and becomes “ontological”
– that is, it constitutes the real world.
Cultural materialism is vulnerable to the argument that it makes critique impossible, since to
criticize a culture it is necessary to refer it to a
world that is external to it.
JOHN HOFFMAN
cultural relativism
This doctrine has two prevailing variants. One of
these is a version of moral conventionalism
positing that the validity of norms and values is
culturally specific and transcends cultural boundaries only coincidentally. Less rigorously but more
familiarly, this is a version of moral liberalism
that acknowledges that values vary both crossculturally and interpersonally, and prescribes
the accommodation of as great a plurality of
them as is procedurally possible. It has partial
precedents in the celebration by Johann Gottfried
von Herder (1744–1803) of the special “genius” of
each “nation”; in Giambattista Vico’s liberation of
the history of the “gentiles” from the preordained
destiny of the elect; even in the legal contextualism of such Renaissance humanists as Desiderius
Erasmus. Narrowed to a principle of method, it
emerges in the German humanistic academy in
the later nineteenth century, hand in hand with
the development of hermeneutics and the principles of the Geisteswissenschaften (see human sciences). Thus narrowed, it is an intrinsic aspect of
Max Weber’s interpretive sociology – in principle
if not always in Weber’s own practice. It has a
more expansive – and, in Europe at least, even
more influential – analogue in Émile Durkheim’s
early insistence on the analytical precedence of the
intersocietal variety of normative prescriptions
and proscriptions over the normatively universal.
As Elvin Hatch points out in Culture and Morality
(1983), it has its first advocates in the United
States in the anti-racialists and anti-evolutionists
cultural reproduction
of the end of the nineteenth and early twentieth
centuries, none of them of greater academic importance than the founder of American cultural
anthropology, Franz Boas. It remains the signature of that anthropology from Boas at least until
the 1970s, when it begins to weaken with the
weakening of the conceits of cultural insularity
and of ethnographic neutrality themselves.
The other variant of the doctrine is one version
or another of epistemological conventionalism,
positing at its most radical that what constitutes
knowledge is culturally specific and culturally
bounded. It has its most immediate ancestor and
most enduring complement in the linguistically
inflected conventionalism that emerges among
such German Romantic philosophers as Friedrich
von Schlegel (1772–1829) in the late eighteenth
and early nineteenth century, and acquires increasing temper and refinement in the work of
linguist Benjamin Sapir, anthropologist Melville
Herskovits, philosophers Williard Quine and
Nelson Goodman, and historians Thomas Kuhn
and Michel Foucault in the twentieth. Lucien
Lévy-Bruhl argues more directly for the incommensurability of primitive and modern scientific
thought in How Natives Think (1922 [trans. 1926])
and several other works of the same period. The
issue of the cultural relativity of both reason and
conceptualization engages the contributors to
Bryan Wilson’s important collection, Rationality
(1970). If there is a single manifesto of the several
versions of epistemological conventionalism circulating in the contemporary disciplines of cultural analysis, however, it is most likely Peter
Berger and Thomas Luckmann’s The Social Construction of Reality (1966). The “cultural relativism” of
only a few decades past seems to have been largely
displaced by the “social constructionism” of the
JAMES D. FAUBION
present.
cultural reproduction
This refers to the transmission of cultural capital
through inheritance; the cultivation of order
through normative coercion. The concept is most
closely associated with the sociology of Pierre
Bourdieu, who developed it in relation to the analysis of habitus and “symbolic repression” in Outline of a Theory of Practice (1972 [trans. 1977]) and
Distinction (1979 [trans. 1984]). He proposed that
every individual interiorizes symbolic master-patterns of thought and values as a condition of the
socialization process. These constitute a distinctive social and cultural perspective that facilitates
orientation and acts as a marker of social
belonging. These symbolic master-patterns are
cultural studies
reinforced through interaction with others.
Each carries distinctive social status within the
social order and constitutes the basis for economic resource allocation and the distribution of
prestige.
Alternative uses can be found in the work of
Louis Althusser (Lenin, Philosophy and Other Essays,
1971) in relation to the functions of the Repressive
State Apparatus, the Ideological State Apparatus,
and the interpellation of subjects; in Antonio
Gramsci (Selections From Prison Notebooks, 1971) in
relation to hegemony, complex unity, and cultural resistance; and in Basil Bernstein’s Class,
Codes and Control, 1971–7), an analysis of schooling,
power, and elaborated and restricted codes.
The concept is often criticized for dissolving
agency, knowledge, and reflexivity into social
mechanics. On this account, cultural reproduction is a substitute for social determinism. However, in Bourdieu’s sociology, the concept is
generally attached to the notion of an intellectual
or symbolic field which allows for the reflexivity
of the agent. Moreover, it is difficult to envisage
how questions of social order and change can
be addressed without utilizing a version of the
concept.
CHRIS ROJEK
cultural rights
– see rights.
cultural studies
This is an interdisciplinary field that arose in
the late twentieth century, and that focuses on
the study of modern and postmodern culture, culture being broadly understood as meanings, representations, symbols, and identities, together
with related sites and practices. Cultural studies
draws on many disciplines and discourses, including semiotics, communications studies, literary
theory, psychoanalysis, feminism, Marxism of
various kinds, sociology, cultural anthropology,
continental philosophy, (post)structuralism, and
critical theory. Media and popular culture are
prominent topics, but it encompasses high as
well as popular arts, literature and speech as
well as newer media, and extends to the examination of advanced industrial culture as a whole.
The methods and perspectives of Cultural studies
have also been applied to early and pre-capitalist
phenomena. While there have been tendencies to
institutionalize Cultural studies as a new trans- or
quasi-discipline, it is not unitary, and the lines
between it and neighboring areas like sociology
and literary studies have remained blurred. In
109
cultural studies
larger compass, Cultural studies is the site of a
more general, and contested, renovation of the
humanities and social sciences, as shaped by the
explosive post-1960s growth of various forms of
critical theory.
The emergence of Cultural studies as a distinct
(and distinctly named) area of study has been
mainly a development of the English-speaking
world. In the United Kingdom, a formative role
was played by the Centre for Contemporary
Cultural studies (CCCS) at Birmingham University
established in 1964 under the directorship of
Richard Hoggart. His Uses of Literacy (1958) traced
the impact of commercialized media (especially
print) on the formation of working-class culture. Another early influence was Raymond
Williams, whose Culture and Society (1958) traced
the history of, and broadened, the category of
culture itself, and whose later writings on literature, politics, and mass media connected these
interests with the 1960s and 1970s revival of
European Marxism, especially with regard to the
non-mechanistic understanding of ideology and
consciousness.
Under Hoggart and his successor (in 1968)
Stuart Hall, the CCCS did groundbreaking work
on urban youth subcultures, consumerism, and
the cultural side of Thatcherism and post-Fordist
restructuring. As against the Frankfurt School critique of “mass culture,” the Birmingham School
tended to emphasize the active and creative side
of popular culture, its differential elements of
class, race, and gender, and the political ambiguity
of, for example, punk. Its theoretical inspiration
was Marxist and neo-Marxist (Antonio Gramsci,
Georg Lukács, Walter Benjamin, Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno, Lucien Goldmann), but this was
accompanied by the assimilation of semiology
via Roland Barthes and Mikhail Bakhtin; poststructuralism via Louis Althusser, Michel Foucault, and
Jacques Derrida; Sigmund Freud through Jacques
Lacan; as well as of feminist theory and much else.
The conceptual strains introduced by this mixture
led to controversies about agency, the status of
the human subject, and the social power of discourse, as well as to a noteworthy polemic, in E. P.
Thomson’s Poverty of Theory (1978), against the elevation of theory as such. Following the CCCS
lead, other centers for Cultural studies were established in the United Kingdom, Australia, Canada,
and elsewhere. From the 1980s onwards a prominent role was also played by (the journal and
center) Theory Culture & Society (TCS) led by Mike
Featherstone. The TCS current was more closely
linked to sociology, and has pursued themes
110
cultural studies
such as the body, technology, and virtuality, the
cultural economy of media, and globalization.
American Cultural studies has followed the
same general course. Here too a turn to culture
within literary studies and social theory combined, in the context of post-1960s intellectual
radicalism, with a turn to (European) theory. This
is exemplified in the work of Fredric Jameson,
who moved from a Lukacsian examination of modernist literature to a multi-dimensional (though
still Marxist) interest in language, painting, and
architecture. The work of Jameson and others
was also important in fashioning an analysis of
postmodernism (as an aesthetic and intellectual
style) in relation to “the cultural logic of capital.”
Cultural studies in the United States, however,
was less social-science oriented than in Britain,
and more an outgrowth of developments in literary studies, philosophy, and art history. Hence
an emphasis on reading cultural phenomena, as
in the title of the influential journal Social Text. It
was in the United States too that there first developed a characteristic emphasis on the social
construction of race and gender, and on the marginalization and silencing of various types of oppressed other. While some work in this vein has
been linked to identity politics and has tended
to be experiential and anti-theoretical, an interest
in otherness has also connected to high theory
through the ethical phenomenology of Levinas
and through the linguistically and philosophically
self-conscious spirit of Derridean deconstruction.
Judith Butler’s Gender Troubles (1989) drew antiessentialist implications for understanding gendered bodies and helped to initiate queer theory.
Donna J. Haraway’s “Manifesto for Cyborgs,” in
Simians, Cyborgs and Women (1991), developed and
celebrated a general notion of hybridity. Also related has been the development of postcolonial
studies, with Edward W. Said’s Orientalism (1978)
as a paradigm, to which are linked such further
developments as subaltern studies in India (spearheaded by Gayatri Spivak) and the growth of aboriginal studies in Australasia, Canada, and Latin
America.
A further ingredient in the formation of Cultural studies has been the rise of media theory,
especially as influenced by the Toronto School of
communications, with its sensory grammar of
media and its civilizationally attuned interest in
media, culture, and technology. This influence
has been felt mainly through Marshall McLuhan,
though the Cultural studies mainstream has been
largely dismissive of McLuhan’s work both because of its apparent technological reductionism
culture
and because of its crypto-theology (the “global
village” of “the electric age” has echoes of Teilhard
de Chardin’s “noosphere”). Chardin (1881–1955)
defined “noosphere” as the stage of evolutionary
development characterized by the emergence of
consciousness, the mind, and interpersonal relationships. In Canada, the work of McLuhan’s
mentor, Harold Innis, has also received renewed
attention, while a more Baudrillardian version of
the culture and technology approach is evident
in the work of Arthur Kroker and the journal
C-Theory.
ANDREW WERNICK
culture
Traditionally the province of either anthropology
or the humanities, culture has become increasingly central to sociology, both as a subject of
study, and as a theoretical challenge to sociology’s
self-conception. The sociological definition of and
approach to culture, which refers to the form,
content, and effects of the symbolic aspect of
social life, has emerged out of a critical encounter
with the two more traditional definitions.
In the definition of the humanities, culture
refers to intellectual and artistic activity and the
artifacts produced thereby, to what Matthew
Arnold (1822–88) called “the best that has been
thought and said.” Culture is taken as the highest
moral and aesthetic achievements of civilization.
The sociology of culture has always provided critical distance from the pretensions of culture so
understood and its ensuing enshrinement in the
literary, dramatic, and musical canon. By showing
the links between social status maintenance and
taste, but also by carefully examining the aesthetics of both popular cultural artifacts, and the
creative cultural activities of social classes, races,
and genders traditionally excluded from the
realm of high arts production, the sociology of
culture has been essential to the deconstruction
of the high/middle/lowbrow culture typology. In
approaching culture as a social object of study,
the sociology of culture forms a subfield alongside
the sociology of religion and the sociology of
science, and takes within its purview both high
literature and pulp fiction, Fellini films and
Hollywood schlock, art music and rock ’n’ roll.
With the advent of the production of culture perspective in the 1970s, centered around the work of
Richard Peterson, and the concepts of field and
cultural capital, drawn from the work of Pierre
Bourdieu, this subfield has gained both empirical
purchase and theoretical sophistication.
In the anthropological definition, culture is expected to do the comparative work of differentiating
culture
the peoples of the world, and thus also to unify
their study; it forms the counterpoint to physical
anthropology’s theories of human nature. Historical sociology, however, has shown the connections between the anthropological imagination
and various nationalist and colonialist projects
of nineteenth-century Europe, whereby the totalizing concept of culture was complicit in the exoticization and simultaneous subordination and
colonization (and sometimes extermination) of
native populations. Extensive debates about the
political valences and historical guilt of the concept of culture have ensued. But perhaps more
importantly for ongoing empirical research, sociologists have found the anthropological concept
of culture to be underspecified; for sociology, differentiating culture from nature is not enough.
Rather, culture must be defined in relation to
society, history, and individual psychology, and,
furthermore, the differentiation between culture
and nature must itself be examined historically
with an eye towards its varying social effects
(many anthropologists have also come to this conclusion). Thus, while sociology has drawn extensively on symbolic, structuralist, and linguistic
anthropology for its own studies of culture, it
has resisted the temptation to conflate culture
directly with the social as such, and the culture/
society distinction has been a productively unstable one. And it would be fair to say that social
constructionist forms of cultural research have
distanced themselves significantly from the
“essentializing” concepts of an earlier era.
However, both the sociology of culture and the
critique of culture inside and outside of anthropology beg fundamental questions. Why are social
actors so interested in cultural artifacts in the
first place, as opposed to other, functionally
equivalent, status markers? If cultural difference
cannot be grasped inside scientific anthropological theory, does that mean that it cannot
be grasped at all? What is the role of meaning
and symbolic structures in modern and late capitalist societies? To answer these questions outside
of the confines of the humanist tradition and
postcolonial anthropology has been the central
task for cultural sociologists, who since the 1960s
have developed a set of increasingly subtle and
nuanced approaches to this contested term of
culture.
For sociology, then, culture refers to the symbolic element of social life, which has been
variously conceptualized, identified, and studied:
signifiers and their signifieds, gestures and their
interpretation,
intended
and
unintended
111
culture
meanings, written discourse and effective speech,
situational framing and scientific paradigms, and
moral and political ideals. Concretely, culture
refers to those social objects and activities which
are primarily or exclusively symbolic in their
intent or social function, such as art, music, and
sports. Analytically, culture refers to the symbolic
and ideational element of any social action, social
relationship, or historical pattern. In modern and
postmodern societies, these two senses of culture
are increasingly intertwined in ways that must
be studied empirically: people may learn how to
conduct intimate relationships from poetry or
romantic movies, and rock stars may endorse
politicians.
The methodologies for studying culture so
conceived range widely, and include surveys of
attitudes and beliefs, participant observation,
ethnography, structured and unstructured interviews, textual analysis of written and visual
media, and conversational analysis. Ultimately,
however, all of these methods involve the interpretation of meaning, and thus cannot be mapped
directly from the methods of the natural sciences,
though the extent to which scientific methods can
be adapted to the study of culture is a matter of
significant dispute. Furthermore, culture not only
requires interpretation, but the meanings of symbols have to be understood in a holistic manner,
which is to say that any given sign or symbol takes
its meaning in relation to those with which it is
contrasted and figuratively related. The meaning
of the term culture is not an exception to this,
and as culture has become central to sociology, its
meaning has emerged in relation to three central
concepts, namely social structure, action theory,
and critical theory. After discussing these, we will
briefly discuss the ways in which the consideration of culture has affected other aspects of the
sociological field.
The distinction between culture and society is,
like culture itself, contested and controversial,
and, since it often conflates the analytic and concrete dimensions of culture, it is perhaps better to
discuss the relationship of culture to social structure. Talcott Parsons distinguished the cultural
from the social system in a strictly analytic fashion (his student Niklas Luhmann would later
claim that this should in fact be a concrete distinction). And Parsons suggested that the study of
culture in all its symbolic elaborations could be
left to anthropology, and that sociology could
focus on the place where culture and social structure met, namely, on the institutionalization
of values and norms. Structural-functionalism
112
culture
suggested that culture, through the normative interpenetration of society, could perform an
integrative function in the service of social equilibrium, and thus that social change came with a
breakdown in value consensus (as in Chalmers
Johnson’s (1931– ) theory of social revolution).
These assertions were then subjected to relentless ideological attack for suppressing the role of
strife and domination in society (and in the use of
culture). However, it is perhaps more instructive,
now, to notice a deeper problem with structuralfunctionalism, namely its interpretive deafness.
By approaching culture as “norms and values,”
structural-functionalism not only projected certain liberal ideals onto its model of society, but
more significantly, evacuated meaning from culture, robbing its analysis of nuance and empirical
specificity. For an engagement with the multiple
layers of the symbolic immediately reveals that
culture in modern societies is neither homogenous nor consensual. Rather, the size and makeup
of collectivities that share certain symbolic articulations vary significantly (from small religious
cults to large voting populations), and these symbolic articulations are contested both within and
without collectivities.
Mid-century Marxism and post-1960s conflict
theory insisted that culture was more of a guarantor of hierarchy, exploitation, and inequality, and
thus saw culture as ideology. And though the political commitments and theoretical presuppositions of conflict theory were fundamentally at
odds with those of Parsonian functionalism, one
can discern in the studies of the objective basis
of systematically distorted communication, and
in references to the political and economic functions of ideology, very similar problems to those
that plagued the structural-functional approach.
Here too, culture is assumed to be relatively uniform, at least in its social effects, and its study is
guided by theoretical intuitions about the workings of the social system, in particular the exploitation of labor, and for a contemporary example
see David Harvey’s The Condition of Postmodernity
(1989). Thus Marxist repudiations of culture as
ideology also suffered from a lack of musicality,
and inattention to the empirical details of
culture’s varied production, performance, and
reception.
In both cases, these problems were exacerbated
by imagining social structures as hard, real, and
external to the actor, in opposition to culture as a
more pliable and less efficacious possession of
individual minds. Furthermore, both structuralfunctionalism and Marxism were embedded in
culture
teleological philosophies of history and social
evolution that enabled them to locate the appropriate relations between social structure and culture in an a priori theoretical manner. As these
teleologies came to be seen as more the meaningful, ideational constructions of sociologists’ own
cultures than ontological certainties about actual
societies, the strict scientific distinction between
social structure and culture began to break down,
as did the various conceptions of their relationship. This breakdown created an opening for sociology to develop the tools necessary for a more
sensitive and empirically sophisticated approach
to culture in its collective forms. This has been
accomplished by studying culture as a structure
in its own right, a theoretical development that
has taken three main forms.
First, the study of symbolic boundaries, associated with the work of Michele Lamont (Money,
Morals and Manners, 1994) and her students, has
shown how actors construct and maintain meanings as a mode of ordering, including, and excluding their fellow humans, over and against the
exigencies of social structure. Thus, the economic
basis for class is overwritten by an attribution of
certain moral qualities to certain humans, based
on criteria (including religion, race, and so forth)
that may crosscut the expectations of more reductively minded sociologists that would map class
consciousness directly onto economic position,
and so on.
Second, the study of discourse and its relationship to power, based on the pioneering work of
Michel Foucault, has enabled sociologists to examine not only articulated boundaries, but also
unstated exclusions, and more generally the cultural construction of certain taken-for-granted
“positivities” of modern life. Thus one can examine from a reflexive historical perspective how
certain kinds of human subjects (for example,
insane people and medical patients) and social
problems (for example, homosexuality) came to
be of such great concern, and how their meaningful construction effected the way they were dealt
with, inside and outside mainstream society.
Though Foucault’s work has been largely appropriated in the humanities as a set of theorems
concerning power and knowledge more appropriate to critical theory than to empirical sociology,
his early studies of madness, medicine, and the
episteme of the classical and modern ages are in
fact rich historical reconstructions of landscapes
of meaning, and their essential role in the social
processes of treatment, exclusion, and philosophical understanding. These issues are developed
culture
in Foucault, Madness and Civilization (1961 [trans.
1971]) and Chandra Mukerji, A Fragile Power: Scientists and the State (1990).
Finally, the conception of culture as a structure in its own right has enabled the sociological
transformation of a set of tools from literary
theory and semiotics. Culture can be studied as
a social text, replete with codes, narratives,
genres, and metaphors. Then, culture can be
examined in both its concrete and its analytic
autonomy from social structure, which enables
us to isolate and make clear its effects (and its
varying political valences) from a sociological
point of view. So, for example, the long struggle
for women’s rights in the United States can be
seen as a discursive battle for civil inclusion,
according to which a new set of actors came to
be coded in a democratic and morally positive
way (Jeffrey Alexander, “The Long and Winding
Road: Civil Repair of Intimate Injustice,” 2001).
This conception of culture suggests, moreover,
that social structures themselves are interpreted
variably by social actors, and thus must be
attended to hermeneutically by cultural sociologists, with an eye to their meaningful aspects,
their locality, and their historical specificity
(see Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures,
1973, and Jeffrey Alexander, The Meanings of Social
Life, 2003).
If culture was often contrasted to social structure, and furthermore associated with subjectivity, then it should not be surprising that it has
often been erroneously conflated with action and
its related terms: agency, reflexivity, and consciousness. However, as culture has become recognized as a structure in its own right, the
relationship of culture to action has become a
key component both of sociological action theory
and of sociological research more generally. The
ongoing debate about culture and action has its
roots in two different sociological traditions, both
of which contribute to the contemporary understanding of culture within sociology.
On the one hand, the analytic tradition, descending from Parsons’s formalization of Max
Weber’s means–ends approach to action, approached culture in terms of the ways culture
sets the ends of action. Action is thus structured
not only by interests, but by norms as well. Originally opposed to economistic accounts of social
action, the strictly analytic approach to purposive
action has been revived in contemporary sociological debates about agency and rationality. But
a deeper understanding of the role of culture
for action has been developed from within this
113
culture
tradition by recognizing culture as an internal
environment for action, arguing thus that culture
orients action by structuring subjectivity. Social
actors respond to sets of internal typifications of
the social world and thus are dependent upon
meaningful symbolization in setting their goals,
and in imagining how they can go about meeting
them. By reintroducing the symbolic as an environment of action full of rich narratives and morally and emotionally loaded oppositions, this
approach integrates the expanded approach to
culture-as-structure elaborated above.
On the other hand, the pragmatic tradition,
descending from George Herbert Mead and
Herbert Blumer, rejects the means–ends characterization of action outright, and suggests instead
that actors constantly negotiate situations in an
improvisatory way, attempting to make sense of
and solve both social and physical problems as
they arise. Originally, because of its distance
from the analytic abstractions of the Parsonian
tradition, and its tendency towards methodological individualism, this tradition was not really
oriented towards culture per se, though it had a
conception of the use of symbols and framing on
the micro level. Increasingly, however, the descendants of this tradition have developed a conception of culture-as-use that conceives of the
knowledgeable agent as the link between culture
and society. It is actors, in social situations, who
draw on culture when institutional consistency
breaks down.
Thus the contemporary debate is structured by
two positions, that of culture-in-action which is
illustrated by Ann Swidler in “Culture in Action:
Symbols and Strategies” (1986), and that of culture
as thick environment for action by Jeffrey Alexander in Action and Its Environments: Toward a New
Synthesis (1988). Both approaches have significant
insights to offer. The first emphasizes that actors
continually work to render coherent and solvable
discursive and institutional problems that arise in
the flow of social life. The second emphasizes the
way in which the social world is constructed for
the actor by previous interpretations and collective languages. In either case, these approaches
suggest the importance of culture for the study
of social life. For example, we should perhaps
discuss the discursive repertoires of politicians,
and the resonance of these repertoires with the
shared codes of their audience–electorates, as opposed to the “revealed preferences” of either. The
contrasts between the two approaches have, however, produced significantly different forms of
theory and research.
114
culture
One important manifestation of the symbolic
interactionist tradition has been Gary Fine’s development of the concept of idiocultures, whereby
small groups develop an idiosyncratic set of meanings (beliefs, knowledge, and customs) that
forms the basis for mutual understanding and
further interaction and action. Thus, cooks in various classes of restaurants develop an aesthetic
language that enables them to communicate
with each other concerning the manifestly practical problems of smell and taste.
Alternately, Robin Wagner-Pacifici, in The Moro
Morality Play (1986) and Theorizing the Standoff
(2000), has developed the concept of social drama
within the more analytic tradition of action and
its environments, so as to enable the study of
social situations where symbolic and physical violence interact. In studying terrorist kidnappings,
standoffs between government and its discontents, and surrenders, she develops a deep understanding of morally loaded environments for
action. When the social fabric is breached, actors
must work within certain dramatic frameworks,
and with certain obtainable identities. Thus, in a
standoff between the Freemen of Montana and
the United States Government, it was a mediator
who had fought in Vietnam and, like some of the
leaders of the Freemen, had formed his core identity in the crucible of that experience and its
subsequent narration who was able to bridge the
symbolic gap between the antagonists. Action was
deeply structured by the symbolic environments
of traumatic memory and the enactment of
masculinity.
The specificity of the kinds of meanings that
are enacted, however, points both to the possible
misinterpretations of the relationship between
action and culture, and to the way forward in
the theoretical debate. For the exclusive emphasis
on culture as it is used by actors can support the
naturalistic approach to social structure and thus
an understanding of culture as unstructured and
primarily the possession of individuals. In this
conception, it is meaningless institutions that set
the parameters of the action problem, and culture
is merely the way actors make sense of things as
they are solving it – perhaps important for filling
out an explanation, but not essential to it. The
environments to action approach is faced with a
similar danger, for, insofar as it retains vestiges of
Parsons’s action frame of reference, it can be
taken to indicate that sociology can produce, in
theory alone, a mechanistic explanation of the
interaction of norms and interests that will apply
everywhere, regardless of cultural differences.
culture
Perhaps most significantly, it is important that
action theory be prevented from becoming a sort
of existential meditation on the capacities (or incapacities) of human freedom, rather than a way
to examine the social contingencies of actually
existing meaning. If the knowledgeable agent becomes a sort of philosophical and methodological
hero, whose reflexivity about her location in structure ultimately makes her the master of the cultural formations in her head, then the sociological
purpose of examining cultural structures is vitiated, as collective meaning formations melt away
in the face of agency and knowledge as developed
by Anthony Giddens in The Constitution of Society
(1984).
Thus, the way forward in the action–culture
debates lies in the development of a meaningful
account of action through a theorization of social
performance, by linking action theory to Erving
Goffman’s dramaturgical sociology and Kenneth
Burke’s literary theory, but also to Judith Butler’s
reconception of the poststructuralist tradition of
social thought. By thinking of social situations of
varying scope (from small-group interactions to
media events watched by millions) as dramas
being played out on a public stage, with certain
actors and audiences, props and social powers,
emergent scripts and cultural backgrounds, we
can conceive of the exigencies of social action in
a thoroughly cultural way that does not reduce
meaning to social structure. Action, then, involves
putting certain intended and unintended meanings into the social scene. This is to say that the
theorization of action not only has to take into
account cultural structures, but must further
focus on how actions are themselves interpretations of these structures, and thus respond to
logics of meaning and identity underneath the
interests and norms that were once supposed to
do the analytical work of explaining these actions;
this argument is developed in Jeffrey Alexander,
Bernhard Giesen, and Jason Mast (eds.), The Cultural
Pragmatics of Social Performance (2006).
The sociological critique of culture used to be
based almost entirely on references to the social
as existing outside of culture itself. It was thus
diametrically opposed to the sense of criticism
associated with the detailed reading of the literary
canon, and with humanistic studies more generally. The obvious exception was Marxist literary
criticism, in particular that of Georg Lukács and
Raymond Williams, which entered into literary
texts themselves to find the logics of ideology in
the content and form. While their work foreshadowed the development of Cultural studies, it
culture
remained nonetheless within the discourse of suspicion about culture, usually understood as bourgeois culture (and its discontents). Increasingly,
however, sociology has brought its normative concerns with democracy, social inclusion, and the
critique of power to the interpretation
of culture, as well as to the debunking of ideology.
This is to say that the project of hermeneutics,
once associated with the conservative aesthetic
hierarchies of the German philosophical tradition,
can now be seen as a rich source of critique in
a post-positivist and post-orthodox-Marxist age,
as exemplified by the work of Michael Walzer,
Luc Boltanksi, and Laurent Thevenot. The epistemological implication of their work is that
sociological critique must abandon its pseudoscientific assumption of an exterior stance or
view from nowhere, and develop critical distance
through extensive engagement, dialogue, and interpretation. They develop critical perspectives
on contemporary societies that share some of
the empirical purchase of cultural sociology, but
have as their ultimate goal the articulation of
new normative understandings of justice and
equality. More generally, in so far as sociological
critique is no longer beholden to scientific certainty, revolutionary upheaval, and the genre of
debunking, its normative repertoire of critical
tropes, subtle ironies, and imagined ideals can be
expanded.
That culture has become a central theoretical
term in sociology means that it has had significant effects on the sociological imagination as a
whole, extending beyond the study of culture as a
set of socially produced artifacts. “Culture,” in
sociology, indicates a perspective as well as an
object of study, and as such has addressed itself
to nearly all of the classic and varied problems of
sociological research. We cannot do the wide variety of cultural research in sociology full justice
here, rather we will point to a few particularly
telling examples.
Sociology’s ongoing occupation with modernity,
and the history of state formation, has led to a
focus on the constitution of nations as collective
identities. In explaining economic takeoff in western Europe, the consolidation of the power of
states, and the emergence and importance of
democratic publics and the free press, sociologists
have increasingly focused on the construction of
nations as “imagined communities,” or “discursive fields,” and nationalism as “a unique form
of social consciousness,” for example in Benedict
Anderson’s Imagined Communities (1991), Lyn Spillman and Russell Faeges, “Nations,” in Julia
115
culture
Adams, Elisabeth S. Clemens, and Ann Shola Orloff (eds.), Remaking Modernity (2005), and Liah
Greenfeld’s Nationalism (1992).
The sociology of sex and gender has likewise
experienced a cultural overhaul. While feminist
and queer theory have questioned the naturalness
of the sex/gender distinction, sociological research
has examined the effects of actually existing cultural schemas of gender and sex for social outcomes, including family structure, women’s
tendency to join or opt out of the workforce, and
the ongoing existence of sexism in wage levels and
status attainment. These studies examine both
gender as a highly rigid structure of meaning,
and its varying enactment by women and men
who attempt to negotiate the political and economic contradictions of modern society, for instance in Judith Stacey, Brave New Families (1990);
Sharon Hays, The Cultural Contradictions of Motherhood (1996); and Mary Blair-Loy, Competing Devotions
(2003).
Finally, sociology’s longstanding normative concern with democracy and its incipient populism
has also taken a cultural turn. For example, analyses of American political participation and activism have investigated how certain meanings
either enable or discourage civic participation.
The results have often been counterintuitive:
doctrines of individual empowerment encourage
activity and public responsibility, while norms of
civility and politeness discourage political conversation and involvement, a theme which is developed in Nina Eliasoph, Avoiding Politics (1998),
and Paul Lichterman, The Search for Political Community (1996).
Culture has thus moved towards the center of
sociological discourse, as both a topic of study and
a perspective from which to view the social. As reinterpretation is a primary form of theoretical
advance, the perhaps predictable result of this is
that, simultaneously, the classics of social theory
have come to be seen in a new light. New readings
of Karl Marx, Weber, and Émile Durkheim have
emerged.
While all twentieth-century Marxisms have
given more importance to culture and ideology
than did the crude economic Marxist orthodoxy
that followed Marx’s death, the turn to culture in
the 1960s and 1970s is evident in the increasing
attention given to Marx’s analysis of commodity
fetishism in Capital, as well as to the importance of
the early, humanist, and perhaps even idealistHegelian Marx. Either way, Marx is read as attentive to the capacity of meaning as a social force.
One important result of this has been the way
116
culture
structuralist and poststructuralist theories of language have merged with Marxist historiography
to produce a central thesis concerning postmodernism, namely that the postmodern age is one
in which the workings of capitalism are increasingly dependent on signifiers as well as signifieds,
that is, on the relational field of social symbolism. These approaches are illustrated by Frederic
Jameson, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (1992),
and Jean Baudrillard, For a Critique of the Political
Economy of the Sign (1972) [trans. 1981]).
Likewise, since the mid-1960s, we have seen a
recovery of Weber’s sociology of art, as well as
continuing debate on the Protestant Ethic thesis.
However, most significantly, the concern with
culture has also entered into Weberian debates
about the consolidation of state power and the
institutionalization of rational bureaucracy. Here,
sociologists have increasingly read Weber as a
hermeneutic student of rationality as a cultural
form specific to western history. In doing so,
Weber’s concerns are read as not so different
from Foucault’s, and bureaucracy as less a mechanism to be uncovered than a form of symbolic
action to be interpreted. This interpretation is
developed in Philip Gorski, The Disciplinary Revolution (2003).
Finally, the cultural turn in sociology has seen
a renaissance and reconsideration of Durkheim’s
later works, and, in particular, of The Elementary
Forms of Religious Life (1912 [trans. 2001]). This work
has come to be seen as a key prolegomena to the
symbolic study of society as a general project, as
well as to the study of the role of culture in
modern, industrial societies. Durkheim is thus
read as uncomfortable with the materialist interpretations given to The Division of Labor in Society
and as having made a key epistemic break in the
years between the publication of Suicide (1897
[trans. 1951]) and that of Elementary Forms, an
argument developed by Jeffrey Alexander in “Rethinking Durkheim’s Intellectual Development II”
(1986). As a result, Durkheim can be seen as a
precursor to cultural structuralism in his emphasis on the autonomy of symbolic forms, and
the importance of belief and ritual for the organization of society.
If culture has become central to sociology
(though some may not hold this opinion, or at
least be unhappy with this development), it has
also remained a controversial subject. And as empirical research on culture has exploded, the theoretical presuppositions of this work, which often
does not fit the model of positivist or scientificrealist sociology, have been left relatively
culture
unexplored. This is to say that, in the future, social
theory must address not only culture, but its accompanying methodological and epistemological
term: interpretation. This can be done by
returning to the fundamental questions of the
philosophy of social science, as well as by articulating the immanent epistemological selfconsciousness of cultural research in sociology.
There are two fundamental concerns central to
the question of sociological interpretation,
broadly understood.
The first regards the role of the investigator in
social analysis. Though most cultural sociologists
accept neither scientific norms nor postmodern
normlessness as the parameters for their truth
claims, what norms they do accept is an important issue to discuss in the abstract. In particular, it
seems clear that sociologists want the meanings
they reconstruct to be translatable, so that cultural comparison is possible, not so much so as
to determine active and latent mechanisms, but
so as to perceive more clearly the varied relationships of meaning in action. Thus, even single case
studies or ethnographies implicitly contain a
comparison, at least to the investigator’s own
meaningful social contexts, and this comparative
consciousness forms an important basis for the
development of theory and research in cultural
sociology.
The second question concerns how much the
methods and modes of explanation common to
cultural sociology may apply outside the domain
of what is analytically or concretely called culture.
A lot of work within poststructuralist theory has
examined the symbolic and discursive basis for
what sociologists are more likely to call social
structure, namely, institutional formations, social
sanction and exclusion, and even violence, as
argued in Judith Butler’s Gender Trouble (1989).
But the extent to which these aspects of social
life can actually be explored empirically remains
to be verified by an epistemology more comfortable with the possibility of truth claims that are
relatively autonomous from power. Thus, for
example, we need to ask how even the reconstruction of political strategies and economic exigencies involves the interpretation of highly reified
and strictly executed meaning.
Ultimately, then, the advent of culture in sociology and the study of its subtleties and social
contestations leads to fundamental questions
about sociology itself. If culture is a perspective
from which to examine society, it is also a perspective from which to examine the meaningformation called sociology. As such, its most
cybernetics
important effect will be to push the central concepts of sociology (structure, action, critique),
empirical research topics, and the readings of
sociological classics towards the interpretation
of meaning. I S A A C R E E D A N D J E F F R E Y A L E X A N D E R
culture industry
– see Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno.
culture of poverty
– see poverty.
custom
– see norm(s).
cybernetics
A field of scientific inquiry devoted to self-regulating information systems, cybernetics, derived
from the Greek word meaning helmsman or governor. Developed alongside computing in the later
years of World War II, the reference to governors
attaches the term to the regulatory mechanisms
first used on nineteenth-century steam engines.
The first phase of cybernetic science was mathematical, an attempt to quantify the amount of
information in a given system. A critical breakthrough came with the information theory proposed in The Mathematical Theory of Information
(1949) by C. E. Shannon and W. Weaver, employees
of Bell Labs, the leading commercial research laboratory of the time. Bell needed to find engineering solutions for massive increases in telephone
use in the later 1940s. Shannon and Weaver proposed a probabilistic model in which the information content of a message could be calculated as
the ratio of signal – meaningful communication –
to noise. “Noise” they defined as anything insignificant, from static hiss to repetitions and redundancies. Mathematically, the highest probability
was for randomness in communication. In the
Cold War period, early cyberneticians identified
randomness with entropy, the tendency of
systems to cool down, to move to less ordered
states. In complex systems such as living beings
or social organizations, increasing entropy dissipates the information content or patterned relationships. The task of cybernetic technologies was
to maintain homeostasis: the state of a system
with a high degree of predictable structure, or
order.
As the term suggests, however, homeostasis is
negative entropy in the sense that it resists
change. This was the tenet of two Chilean researchers, H. R. Maturana and F. J. Varela, in
Autopoesis and Cognition (1980); they proposed the
117
cyberspace
term that ushered in cybernetics’ second phase:
autopoesis. Consonant with the ambitions of the
Macy conferences which, through the 1950s,
extended the scope of cybernetics to embrace
fields as diverse as economics and meteorology,
the concept of autopoetic machines is a general
model of any self-sustaining system: a unity composed of processes which produce components
which in turn realize the processes and constitute,
continually reconstituting, the machine or organization as a unity. This internal circuit depends,
more explicitly than earlier models, on the interaction of the autopoetic machine – technological,
organic, or human – with its environment. This
variant of cybernetics provided Niklas Luhmann
with the foundations for his influential conception of society as a network of discrete functional systems (law, education, science, and so
on), each of which replicates itself according to
its own processes, but does so by treating neighboring systems as environmental inputs. For
Luhmann, society’s internal differentiation debars
it from acting as a single unified entity, a capacity
restricted to its internal systems. It can and
indeed must, however, embody the mutual
feedback mechanisms between its distinct
components.
The third phase of cybernetics abandoned the
centrality of homeostasis in favor of theories
capable of explaining change. Variously known
as chaos or complexity theory, contemporary cybernetics uses dynamic models like hydrodynamics to model complex boundary states between
order and chaos, with a special interest in the
emergence of new ordered states from apparently
chaotic forebears. Importantly, the term chaos
does not signify randomness but rather a system
whose subsequent states are not entirely predictable from its original state. The model is closely
allied with the development of network communications, and may be related to Ulrich Beck’s concept of risk society, but is also widely used to
SEAN CUBITT
justify free-market economics.
cyberspace
This term is used to refer to electronic communications networks and was first used by sciencefiction author William Gibson in his 1986 novel
Neuromancer to describe a fictional parallel universe created by computers and inhabited by information (including the “avatars” or data
representations of human characters). With the
arrival of the worldwide web in 1993, the term
took on a practical application, describing the
online world, the interactions and networks of
118
cyberspace
persons, groups, and information connected
electronically through the worldwide web. In
some usages, for example that of the Electronic
Frontier Foundation, the term describes an open
terrain which may be occupied or homesteaded on
the model of the westward expansion of the
United States during the 1870s, and is in this
conception a liberated and liberating geography,
parallel to reality – physically copresent social
transactions – but potentially far larger. The ambiguity of the term cyberspace and the juxtaposition to real, social life – does it describe an actual
or a metaphorical geography? – derives from the
unprecedented social relations which the worldwide web enabled.
For some, cyberspace denotes a field of open
opportunities distinguished from the real world
by its freedom from constraint. For others, it denotes a new market in information and services –
one not substantially different from other
markets, but different in the degree to which it
has only begun to be tapped. For many social
theorists, cyberspace is interesting both for its
internal relationships – new forms of socialization
such as bulletin boards (BBSs) and massively multiplayer game environments (MMPs) – and for its
articulation with real, geographical material
spaces.
The interconnection with reality takes several
forms. Cyberspace is a source of news and opinions, many of them unsanctioned by traditional
gatekeeping institutions, which may provide infrastructure for the development of new forms of
public life. Cyberspace is also feared as a barely
comprehensible jungle where pedophiles and con
artists thrive. The greatest fear is that, through
the powers of the internet, cyberspace may intervene in real, social space, for example in allowing
a child molester to make a rendezvous with a
potential victim, or con men to access real bank
accounts. Since Amsterdam’s, France’s, and India’s
initial forays in the early 1990s, many city and
some national governments have extended the
provision of services to online environments, including in some cases voting and other forms of
citizen participation in government. At the same
time, the subversion of electronic systems
(“hacking”) has become a weapon of war, notably
in the Middle East during the Second Intifada in
the Israeli–Palestinian conflict. Identifying even
such basic data as the number of participants in
cyberspace has proved difficult. Describing its
sociological characteristics is equally difficult,
and a nascent scholarly field. Among significant
contributions are A. R. Galloway’s Protocol (2004),
cyberspace
S. Lash’s Critique of Information (2002), C. May’s Information Society (2002), and T. Terranova’s Network
Culture (2004).
The material infrastructure of cyberspace is
composed of a large number of computers linked
by electronic networks. A proportion of these
computers act as servers, storage devices
allowing open access from other computers. A
smaller proportion are routers, responsible for
conveying data across the network. A small
number of globally agreed software packages
(protocols) permit the traffic to be used on almost
every personal or institutional computer. Some
subnetworks (intranets) are closed to all but
named users. The major languages employed
cyberspace
are English, Mandarin, Spanish, and Korean.
Many networks, routers, and servers are integrated with national and global telecommunication and entertainment corporations. But many
are not, and the technology is cheaply available
to individuals, groups, and companies who wish
to communicate with the public. The most successful applications to date are e-mail, which
allows person-to-person communication, and
file-sharing, through which users can swap data,
commonly music, images, and software. Cyberspace raises serious challenges for law (intellectual property), justice (online and international
crime), the military (information warfare), and
representational democracy.
SEAN CUBITT
119
D
Dahrendorf, Ralph (1929– )
The author of close to thirty books including Class
and Class Conflict in Industrial Society (1959) and Society and Democracy in Germany (1967), Dahrendorf’s
most influential contributions to sociology
include the conceptual elaboration of factors
affecting the likelihood of group conflict (see
social conflict), which are empirically variable
across time and place; an attendant critique of
Karl Marx’s universalizing of his historically
narrow analysis of class conflict in nineteenthcentury Europe; an insistence on the analytical
differentiation of industrialism from capitalism;
and a concern with formal variations in types of
organization and association, in types of authority
relations, in patterns of conflict regulation, and
in relations of stratification along a number of axes.
Dahrendorf is popularly known as a “conflict
theorist” but in fact has always refused to oversimplify reality through exaggerating tendencies
of integration (as, for example, in functionalism)
or of conflict (as, for example, in Marx). He is an
anti-utopian who urges people to have the maturity to live with complexity. To emphasize this
complexity, he has drawn attention throughout
his work to the relatively independent nature of
many aspects of social life, from those specific to
international relations, industrial society, politics,
and nuclear weapons, through divergent forms of
ownership and control to, latterly, those related to
the environment and to biological issues associated with genetic engineering, to name just
some. His sociology is marked deeply by a political
commitment to liberal values and to the welfare
state, to both liberty and citizenship entitlements.
Dahrendorf has combined his intellectual work
with a hugely impressive presence in the practical
worlds of both politics and academic administration. At the end of the 1960s he was a Free Democrat (FDP) member of the German Bundestag and a
parliamentary secretary of state at the Foreign
Office, then a European Commissioner in Brussels
in 1970–4, before becoming the Director of the
London School of Economics in 1974–84. From
1987 to 1997 he was Warden of St. Anthony’s
120
College, Oxford. He was created a United Kingdom
life peer in 1993.
ROB STONES
Darwin, Charles (1809–1882)
The theory of natural selection was developed
independently by Charles Darwin and Alfred
Wallace (1823–1913). It was first introduced by
Darwin in 1859 in Origin of the Species. Both men
developed the theory on the basis of intensive and
substantial empirical work.
From 1831 to 1836 Darwin served as naturalist
aboard the HMS Beagle, a mapping and scientific
expedition sponsored by the British government.
During this voyage he worked in the Galapagos
Islands and elsewhere, studying new species and
collecting them for later study. Wallace worked in
the Amazon area and the East Indies in the 1840s.
He also collected examples of species unknown to
the western world.
Their studies led to the assertion that evolutionary change is gradual, stretching over thousands
of millions of years. The main mechanism for
evolution was a process called natural selection.
And they argued that the millions of species alive
in the modern era probably arose from a single
original life form through a branching process
called “specialization.”
Biological laws, Darwin and Wallace argued,
affect all living beings, including humans. Population growth within limited resources leads to a
struggle for survival. Certain characteristics confer advantages and disadvantages upon individuals during this struggle. The selection of these
traits, and their inheritance over time, leads to
the emergence of new species and the elimination
of others.
For many social scientists, the theory of natural
selection should be seen as a product and reflection of its time. This was a point made in our contemporary era by, among others, Michel Foucault.
Darwin is seen as a high Victorian, his ideas being
little more than the struggle for existence in
society being transferred to the natural world.
Furthermore, even the distinction between scientific and nonscientific knowledge is seen by many
Darwin, Charles (1809–1882)
contemporary sociologists as spurious. “Science”
is obfuscation, a way of legitimating the power of
institutions and dominant social classes.
The parallels between the theory of Darwin and
Wallace and the society in which they worked
were also pointed out by Karl Marx. The class
struggle in Victorian England, he argued, was
being transplanted by Darwin back onto the natural world. Similarly, the “specialization” of species
was the division of labor in human society, again
extended to the realm of nature. Marx, and to
an even greater extent Friedrich Engels, nevertheless recognized that Darwin’s theory was an exceptionally important piece of science. Darwin
and Wallace had uncovered real causal mechanisms which were generating species. These issues
regarding the social construction of Darwin and
Wallace’s scientific theory remain important and
are developed and discussed in a number of texts
concerned with the social construction of science.
These include D. Amigoni and J. Wallace, Charles
Darwin’s “The Origin of Species” (1995).
Darwin’s and Wallace’s theories and ideas were
certainly colored by the experience and predominant values of their day and they have since been
developed by scientists such as S. Gould, Ever Since
Darwin (1980). But the fact that Darwin’s and Wallace’s theory has survived largely intact for over
150 years suggests that it is much more than a
social construction. It described, as Marx and
Engels implied, real relationships and processes.
All knowledge is inevitably “socially constructed,”
but this need not mean that knowledge is only
socially constructed. It can refer to relationships,
processes, and mechanisms which are real, if not
necessarily observable. But, as discussed in evolutionary psychology, social Darwinism, and Herbert
Spencer, the direct application of Darwin’s and
Wallace’s ideas to human society remains full of
difficulties and dangers. Human behavior cannot
be simply attributed to our evolutionary history,
evolutionary processes being always mediated in
complex ways by social relations and social processes. Similarly, and despite the attempt by
Spencer and others to transfer Darwin’s work to
human society, there are few useful parallels to be
made between the structure of organisms and
those of society.
Darwin himself was very cautious about making
parallels between biological and social evolutionary theory. On the other hand, his 1901 book
The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex
did make some preliminary forays into these
difficult connections. And his 1872 text, The Expression of Emotions in Man and Animals, suggested
data
that human emotions and expressions could be
traced back to “man’s” evolutionary origins. It
can be seen as an early version of evolutionary
psychology.
PETER DICKENS
data
The term data (which is plural) comes from the
Latin “things given.” This notion is a misleading
one because usually the gathering of evidence
involves much painstaking endeavor on the part
of the social scientist. Data come in all shapes and
forms and include responses to questionnaires or
interviews, observational materials, documentary
records, statistical information, visual materials,
oral histories, and so on. The key question for
researchers is how the sources of knowledge
(data) and the sources of understanding (theory)
relate.
The data-design phase of research involves considering how best to collect data that will allow
the investigator to answer the questions that he or
she has posed. One of the frequent divisions drawn
in data type is the distinction between quantitative and qualitative. These two approaches to data
collection have often been pitted against each
other as if quantitative and qualitative researchers had completely different understandings of
how to gather knowledge of the social world.
While there may be some difference in emphasis
between those who work mainly with numeric or
statistical data and those who work with more
interpretative and phenomenological data, there
is much overlap between the two. The importance
of data design is in getting a “good fit” between
research question and type of data. If you want
to know the differences between men’s and
women’s pay in the United Kingdom it is unlikely
that you will get far without delving into statistics; but qualitative information on how men
and women view their pay may also provide
important insights into differences. If you want
to know why women are under-represented in
top managerial jobs, then you will require not
only statistical knowledge about the relative success rate of job applicants but also highly contextualized information on men’s and women’s
different life circumstances. Ideally, quantitative
and qualitative data should complement each
other.
Another distinction is between primary and secondary data. It is wrong to think of social research solely in terms of the first-hand collection
of data by means of, say, observation or asking
questions. A great deal of information is already
available having been collected by others, and
121
data
often for other reasons. A wide range of data
sources is available to the social researchers.
Here I will just deal with two: statistical data
sources and documentary sources. Recent developments in information technology, such as the
worldwide web, make data sources increasingly
accessible and amenable.
There is a huge array of statistical data, commonly referred to as official statistics. These are
collected by government agencies. But the degree
to which the data are official varies enormously.
Some data, such as vital statistics, are the by product of administrative processes like the statutory registration of births, marriages, and deaths.
Others, like many of the surveys assembled by the
Office of National Statistics, are based on collections of data by voluntary social surveys. The Census is the most extensive (in the sense of sample
coverage) data that is available and, in Britain, the
Office of National Statistics Longitudinal Study,
based on just 1 percent of the total population,
allows for the tracking of population change on a
year by year basis.
The whole process of archiving and dissemination of large-scale survey data has been revolutionized because of the increasing availability of
computing power. It is now possible for the
researcher to select survey data for secondary analysis and to download the whole survey or particular sub-samples for further analysis. Secondary
data analysis involves extracting new findings
from existing data by reanalyzing the original
data resource.
The important thing in using secondary data is
to be mindful of the original purpose for which
they were collected and the particular agendas
that the collection of the data may have served.
Many quantitative researchers are acutely aware
that statistics are, to some extent, social constructions. In other words, the concepts and measures
often reflect those that dominate official, political, and economic life (Government Statisticians’ Collective, 1979). For example, employment surveys
may use a definition of work that is at odds with
the sociological interest in non-paid caring and
leads to an under-valuing of women’s contribution to the economy. This does not mean that
data from employment surveys are not useful for
sociological analysis, but it does mean that the
researcher has to be fully aware of its limitations
and strengths.
Written documentary sources also pose great
opportunities and challenges for social scientists.
Few researchers need reminding that documents
can rarely be taken at face value. To assess the
122
de-professionalization
value of documentary sources as evidence, it is
necessary to know why they were gathered in the
first place. Documents differ in terms of their
authorships – whether they are personal or official documents. They also differ in terms of access,
which varies from closed through to openly published. John Scott, in his book A Matter of Record
(1990), proposed that knowledge of authorship
and access is important for answering questions
about a document’s authenticity (whether it is
original and genuine), its credibility (whether it
is accurate), its representativeness (whether it is
representative of the totality of documents in its
class), and its meaning (what it is intended to say).
Social-research data cannot be separated from
ethical and political concerns. Most professional
bodies have ethical guidelines that govern the
collection of data and stipulate desirable practices, such as the obtaining of informed consent.
However, arguably, some of the most serious
instances of data abuse come at the analytical
and writing-up stages. Research claims sometimes
far exceed what the evidence or data warrant. This
is a practice that W. G. Runciman in his book The
Social Animal (1998) describes as an “abuse of social
science.” He cites several examples of where sociologists are espousing ideology or opinion which
goes far beyond what the data can support. The
importance of being wary of over-stretching data
claims should apply, whether or not the conclusions drawn are deemed politically correct.
Data archives (both quantitative and qualitative) serve many important roles in modern social
science. It is worth mentioning three. First, they
allow for data to be widely accessed for secondary
research. Second, they encourage the cumulative
nature of social science by allowing researchers to
build on and replicate (often in different contexts
and times) what has gone before. Third, they help
safeguard the highest professional standards by
ensuring that social science evidence is available
for further scrutiny and reanalysis. J A C K I E S C O T T
data analysis
– see data.
data resources
– see data.
Davis and Moore debate
– see functional theory of stratification.
de-professionalization
– see profession(s).
de-schooling
de-schooling
Ian Lister, in Deschooling. A Reader (1974), has
claimed that the “de-schooling movement” was
“a general drift of thinking” which flourished in
the 1970s in advanced capitalist societies. A precursor of the movement was the American social
critic, Paul Goodman, who published Compulsory
Miseducation (1962). In the United Kingdom, John
Holt, who had written How Children Fail (1964), How
Children Learn (1967), and The Underachieving School
(1971), considered himself a “de-schooler” from
the early 1970s. This coincided with the publication of the work and author most identified with
the movement, Ivan Illich’s De-Schooling Society
(1971), and also with Everett Reimer’s School is
Dead (1971). Reimer defined schools as “institutions which require full-time attendance of specific age groups in teacher-supervised classrooms
for the study of graded curricula.” The defining
characteristics of de-schooling thinking are implicit in this definition. De-schoolers opposed the
institutionalization of learning, arguing that
state-controlled socialization inhibited the expression of individual freedom and creativity. Logically,
they could have no time for credentialism. There
was a nonconformist zeal about their views:
schools should be disestablished and secularized.
“To identify schools with education,” wrote Illich,
is “to confuse salvation with the church.” While
the movement might have seemed to be in alliance with the radical pedagogy of educationists in
the Third World, such as Paulo Freire (1921–97),
there was an ambivalence in that the resistance to
state intervention might be interpreted as a conservative inclination to retain the social status quo
and to resist the potential of state schooling to
counteract inequality.
DEREK ROBBINS
death and dying
At its simplest, the cessation of life, death appears
to be a biological rather than a sociological phenomenon. However, diagnosing death is not a
simple process as conflicts around the status of
patients in persistent vegetative states demonstrate. Within medicine, death can be defined in
different ways: as the cessation of pulse and
breathing; as the loss of the body’s coordinating
system, that is, lower brain stem, death; and cerebral cortex, that is higher brain stem, death. The
current definition of death as the cessation of
cerebral functioning is intimately tied to the harvesting of organs from people now dead, but
whose vital physical functions – circulation and
breathing – are intact and keeping their organs
viable for transplantation.
death and dying
While all individuals will die, how and when
they die will reflect broader patterns of inequality
in society, especially around socioeconomic status,
gender, and ethnicity. Unskilled manual workers
die earlier and sooner of known preventable diseases than their skilled and professional counterparts. While women experience more diagnoses
of ill-health – based around the medicalization of
their reproductive functions – they will outlive
men by five years; and members of significantly
disadvantaged ethnic minorities, particularly aboriginal people, will die from preventable conditions twenty-five years earlier than the affluent
and educated members of higher social classes,
who have much longer life expectancy. The greater
the inequality in a society, the poorer the
quality of life and the earlier the death for those
at the bottom of the social system. Death is far
from a straightforward biological event occurring
to individuals as a consequence of fate.
The occurrence of death, particularly in hospitals, is a socially accomplished event. In Time for
Dying (1961), Barney Glaser and Anselm L. Strauss
demonstrated how dying was accounted for and
made explicable and conformed to scripts that
enabled patients, staff, and relatives to handle it.
They identified “trajectories of dying”; the lingering death, which placed greatest strain on those
around it; the expected quick death, which the
staff could handle, but which took the relatives
by surprise; and the unexpected quick death
which challenged everyone’s account of the situation. David Sudnow, in Passing On: The Social
Organisation of Dying (1967), demonstrated the
medicalization of dying in the hospital, where
the doctor decides when death has taken place,
certifies its occurrence and announces it, and coordinates the process so that those affected perform according to the rules. He also showed how
the diagnosis of death would be delayed and
heroic measures taken to save the life of an individual based on their perceived social standing:
the young, the white, and the apparently well-off
were all subjected to more medical interventions
before they were finally “dead.” Sociologists have
also argued that social death can occur long
before biological death. In this, individuals (for
men as a consequence of retirement from work
and for women as a consequence of widowhood)
lose their social networks, become socially isolated, and lose the social roles that had provided
their identity.
As a consequence of the demographic transition
as a result of which more individuals now survive
infancy and more women survive childbirth,
123
Debord, Guy (1931–1994)
social reactions to death have also changed. In the
past, as Philip Ariés (1914–84) has shown (Western
Attitudes Towards Death From the Middle Ages to the
Present, 1974), the presence of death in everyday
life was commonplace. As such it involved the
whole community, with the dying person at the
center of the event, presided over by a priest, with
extensive public mourning. Modern death, under
the control of the medical profession, is hidden
away in the hospital, individualized and medicalized with little or no scope for public mourning.
Death has become dirty and disgusting and an
affront to modern medicine. The cultural highpoint of this attitude to death was reflected in
the development of funeral parlors in the United
States where morticians recreated the dead person as life-like, making them up and setting their
hair.
Ariés’s picture has in part been challenged by
the rise of the hospice movement, established in
England in 1967 by Dame Cicely Saunders (1918–
2005). In a reaction to the prolongation of death as
a consequence of medical interventions, Saunders
sought to free death from medical control and its
bureaucratization in the hospital, and to reassert
its meaning in the context of a secular society.
With the growth of hospices and the occupation
of bereavement counselors we are now urged to
talk about our death, to anticipate it as a serene
and comfortable process, even to experience it as
an opportunity for growth. Legislative changes
around the rights of the terminally ill reflect
this change: living wills allow us to stipulate donot-resuscitate orders if we suffer neurological
damage from accidents or medical misadventure;
and lobbying for euthanasia – the right to a good
death – is on the agenda of many European political parties. The assertion of the right to experience bereavement, too, has been legitimated by
the popularity of the works of Elizabeth KublerRoss (On Death and Dying, 1969) and her argument
that denial and anger were appropriate responses
to death. As the population ages in the West,
issues of rationing at end of life, definitions of
death, euthanasia, and various forms of physician-assisted suicide will all become major social
KEVIN WHITE
policy issues.
Debord, Guy (1931–1994)
Born in Paris, Debord committed suicide in 1994.
He was a founding member of the revolutionary
group Situationist International, whose journal
of the same name he established and edited from
1958 to 1969. He was influenced by, and critical of,
Dadaism and Surrealism, and more importantly a
124
decarceration
critical reading of Karl Marx’s work, Korl Korsch’s
Marxism and Philosophy (1923 [trans. 1973]) and
Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness (1923
[trans. 1971]), as well as at crucial junctures works
by Georges Bataille and especially Henri Lefebvre.
Debord is best known for his writings for Situationist International but, above all, for his Society of
the Spectacle (1967 [trans. 1970]). He is much less
well known for his films, including La Société du
spectacle (1973).
Set out in the form of theses, and lacking a
specific definition of the spectacle, Debord outlines a critique of capitalist society as a whole as
a society of the spectacle of the commodity. For
him the spectacle should not be understood as a
collection of images (and therefore is not confined
to mass media technologies) but as a social relation between people that is mediated by images.
The social relations in question are those of the
dominant capitalist economic order, a world of
appearances, of independent representations.
The spectacle unites individuals as spectators
only in their separation. Such reflections constitute Debord’s attempt to think through Karl
Marx’s theory of commodity fetishism (see alienation) and Lukács’s conception of reification in
the context of contemporary capitalist societies,
with an apparent abundance of commodities,
such that the latter have totally colonized social
life. The suggestive nature of the theory of the
spectacle impacted upon later social theories of
consumption and consumer society, and in the
critique of modern urbanism and the notion of
the city and its spaces as spectacle. The historical
analyses of techniques for the creation of the
spectacle have also been informed by Debord’s
work. As an intended revolutionary theory, it
informed the student revolt of 1968 and beyond.
DAVID FRISBY
decarceration
This concerns a deliberate process of shifting
attention away from prison towards the use of
alternative measures in the community. While
the search for alternatives to imprisonment has
roots in the nineteenth century, the decarceration
movement developed in the 1960s as part of a
general critique of institutional responses to
crime and deviancy and as part of what Stan
Cohen in Visions of Social Control (1985) has termed
the “destructuring impulse.” Prisons and other
total institutions (see Erving Goffman) attracted
criticism for their degrading treatment of offenders, and their ineffectiveness in deterring and
rehabilitating them.
decolonization
The decarceration movement is closely associated with the radical penal lobby and abolitionist movement in Scandinavia, western Europe,
and North America. Strong as these movements
have been, there is seemingly little evidence to
suggest effectiveness; on the contrary, prison rates
soar on a worldwide basis. Thus “prison-centricity”
continues to dominate political thinking about
punishment. Critics have also indicated unintended consequences of decarceration. Andrew
Scull, for example, in Decarceration: Community
Treatment and the Deviant – A Radical View (1984),
has pointed to the benign neglect of offenders
within the community. Cohen has suggested that
the extension of community treatment and punishment in place of prisons serves to reflect Michel
Foucault’s notion of “dispersed discipline” in Discipline and Punish (1977). Thus, ever wider and
stronger nets of social control are created rather
than community measures displacing imprisonment. In recent years, the boundaries between
liberty in the community and confinement in
prison have been blurred through the development of home curfews and electronic monitoring,
in particular.
LORAINE GELSTHORPE
decolonization
By the end of World War II, European conquest
left some 750 million people, roughly one-third of
the world’s population, living under colonialism.
Propelled by national liberation movements, decolonization proceeded relatively rapidly, albeit unevenly in time, space, and form, with experiences
ranging from violent revolution via guerrilla warfare in Algeria – theorized by revolutionary Franz
Fanon in The Wretched of the Earth (1961 [trans.
1965]) – to India’s non-violent resistance led by
Mahatma Gandhi (1869–1948). Uprisings were
often brutally repressed, as Caroline Elkins, Imperial Reckoning: The Untold Story of Britain’s Gulag in
Kenya (2005), makes clear. Tragically, independence often ushered in new ruling elites, an
“administrative bourgeoisie” as Gerard Chaliand
argues in Revolution in the Third World (1989). In
other instances, peoples elected to remain part
of the metropolitan country as citizens, as in the
Caribbean island of Martinique, in a move supported by leading figure of the African diaspora
Aimé Césaire.
While Haiti and Latin America underwent decolonization during the revolutions establishing
independent republics in the 1800s, in 1945 parts
of the Middle East and much of Africa and Asia
were still colonies. In the context of Cold War
rivalry, postwar American sociology and western
deconstruction
social science became engaged in the study of
decolonization and newly independent Third
World states, initially as part of the field of modernization studies. Yet the transformation of academic life during the turbulent 1960s opened up a
variety of new approaches towards these questions, emphasizing social conflict over consensus.
Among the new approaches seeking to understand the decolonization process were variants of
what became know as development theory, including dependency and world-systems analysis.
More recently, a host of other approaches to the
question of decolonization have appeared, from
postcolonial theory to the work of the subaltern
school.
Recent work by sociologists emphasizes that
colonization and decolonization come in waves,
with the latter intimately related to hegemonic
transitions and great power wars. So, for example,
the global wars that characterized the period
before the final emergence of British hegemony
in the 1800s set off the Hispanic American revolutions. Likewise, World War II helped set off the
period of formal decolonization of much of the
rest of the world during the period of American
hegemony. Peruvian sociologist Anibal Quijano
coined the term “coloniality of power,” to deal
with the continuation of colonial-type relationships between core states and racial-ethnic, class,
and gender groups even after formal decolonization. Mahmood Mamdani in Citizen and Subject
(1996), and Crawford Young in “In Search of
Civil Society,” in J. Harbeson, D. Rothchild, and
N. Chazan (eds.), Civil Society and State in Africa
(1994: 33–50), have brilliantly analyzed colonialism
and decolonization in Africa. There is now a dialogue taking place on these questions, with calls
for a new, more radical, round of decolonization.
Imperialism, colonialism, and decolonization
are key processes that have shaped the world,
with reverberations right up to the present. The
varieties of the colonial and postcolonial experiences, and perspectives on the aftermath of
European, Japanese, or Soviet conquest, whether
they be from the frameworks of neocolonialism,
postcolonialism, or the coloniality of power,
will continue to play an important part in debates regarding the past, present, and future of
humanity.
THOMAS REIFER
deconstruction
This refers to a poststructuralist philosophy, associated with structuralism, much of whose impetus
was provided by the writings of the French philosopher Jacques Derrida (1930–2004). Its early key
125
deduction
democracy
texts were his Of Grammatology (1967 [trans. 1977])
and Writing and Difference (1967 [trans. 1978]). The
contested nature of this philosophy, which has
had a significant impact in literature, Cultural
studies, architecture, gender theory, and some
postmodern social theory, lies in its rejection of
traditional philosophical groundings of knowledge and language. The latter assumes that the
meaning of something is directly accessible to
consciousness by its presence. Derrida, in contrast,
argued that our understanding of an object necessitates grasping how it relates to other things and
contexts, that is, to its difference. In particular,
claims to universality would be challenged by this
position. So too would be the binary oppositions
found in structuralist analyses, in sociology
(sacred/profane; community/society) and in wider
discourse (man/woman).
The deconstruction of such oppositions or
dualisms, which hierarchically privilege the first
of the two oppositions in the dualism, also has
a subversive intention. This is directed at what
Derrida termed the “logocentrism” of western
thought, which has been devoted to the search
for an order of truth and a universal language.
Derrida argued that there were no fixed orders
of meaning. Deconstruction therefore challenges
the legitimacy of such preestablished hierarchical dualisms, in order to remove their authoritative status. It therefore also aims to empower
those marginalized by such discourse, and to
encourage the proliferation of difference.
DAVID FRISBY
transformed. Where the moral framework of the
dominant value system promotes the endorsement of existing inequality in ways that the subordinated accept as legitimate, and this legitimacy
is expressed through their deference both to those
in positions of localized and immediate authority
and to the social status order in general, which
they exemplify through the types of civil society
that they choose to construct through their networks, then deferential workers are reproduced.
These deferential workers presume that the social
order comprises an organic entity, with the rich
man in his castle and the poor man at his gate.
Thus, inequality is seen to be inevitable as well as
just; the social order is seen as fixed and the
individual’s place within it is relatively unchangeable. The idea of the deferential worker has been
widely used and generalized to address the overlay of both gender and ethnic relations on the
basic social class model of society that Lockwood
employed.
STEWART CLEGG
definition of the situation
– see William I. Thomas.
delinquency
– see deviance.
delinquent subculture
– see deviance.
demedicalization
– see medicalization.
deduction
democracy
– see explanation.
Derived from the Greek terms demos (the people)
and kratos (power), democracy usually describes a
form of political rule that is justified and exercised by the people for the benefit of the people.
Democracy is a model of government that can
apply to different types of political communities
and levels of political organization. In the contemporary context it is most commonly associated
with the institutional framework of the nationstate. However, modern democratic states are
representative democracies and therefore quite
different from the democratic order that was initially proposed in the classical Greek model of
direct democracy. This distinctiveness is probably
best expressed in terms of different notions of
freedom, as described by Benjamin Constant in
The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of
the Moderns (1819 [trans. 1988]). In the classical
direct democracy system, each citizen had a fair
chance of holding political office and, therefore,
deferential workers
These workers were identified by David Lockwood
in The Blackcoated Worker (1958) while he was
researching car workers in the British General
Motors plant at Vauxhall. Many workers entered
the automobile industry from other occupations,
attracted by high postwar wages. Lockwood analyzed their images of society. Some had deferential attitudes to authority, which, as Howard
Newby in The Deferential Worker (1977) explored,
were ingrained in rural life and which translated
into their attitudes to authority in the plant. Not
everyone shared the same image of society and
the differentiation was patterned. For Lockwood,
the patterning was attributable to social origins
and their social reproduction through extended
networks of social interaction; it was through
the latter that the former were reproduced or
126
democracy
of influencing the political choices of the state. In
a modern representative democracy, in contrast,
individual citizens can only influence the political
decisionmaking process at the margins, and their
involvement in democratic governance is generally limited to electing the political representatives who will speak in their name. It must be
stressed, however, that early forms of democracy
could only provide such political opportunities by
restricting the political franchise to certain categories of citizens. In later democratic systems, the
franchise slowly expanded to include the poor,
women, slaves, and other ethnic/racial groups,
but this greater inclusiveness unavoidably
reduced the number of opportunities for direct
political involvement available to any one citizen.
Early critics of representative forms of democratic government, like Jean-Jacques Rousseau
(1712–78), argued that this model of democracy
was so far removed from the original conception
of this political process that it did not deserve its
name. This criticism is also at the heart of many
contemporary critiques of democratic politics (for
example neo-Marxism, radical democracy, grassroots democracy), which argue that people experience a very limited form of democracy in the
institutions of the modern nation-state. There
are, however, powerful arguments that support
the notion of representative democracy as the
most appropriate form of modern governance.
Max Weber presented the emergence of this representative model as a consequence of the rise of the
bureaucratic state and the bureaucratization (see
bureaucracy) of politics. In “Politics as a Vocation”
(1919 [trans. 1994]), Weber argued that, because of
the complexity of government and society, political parties staffed by professional politicians were
needed to organize mass politics in a manageable
and effective way. This process was conducive to a
plebiscitarian type of democracy, in which people’s ability to govern themselves was to be understood principally in terms of their being able to
choose their leaders from amongst those professional politicians running for office. This empirical approach to understanding the functioning of
modern democracy was reinterpreted by Joseph
Alois Schumpeter, and it became popularly known
as a “minimalist” model of democracy. In Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (1942), Schumpeter
likened this approach to democratic politics to
an analysis of the economic behavior of agents in
free-market capitalism. To liken voters’ behavior
to consumers’ choice is to say that the agents’
freedom essentially consists in buying or not
buying the products that are being offered by
democracy
competing parties/companies. Such an approach
provided the impulse for the statistical study of
electoral politics in terms of voters’ behavior that
dominates political life today.
The other important difference between modern and ancient democracy is the role of the
liberal Constitution. Building on the tradition of
liberalism, modern democratic states are constitutional orders that stress the importance of a
rule of law (see law and society) that protects
the rights of the individual. This constitutional
model, which, in the tradition of Baron Charles
de Montesquieu’s The Spirit of the Laws (1748 [1989]),
usually involves a degree of formal separation
between executive and legislative power, protects
citizens not only from the despotism of unelected
leaders, but also from the abuses of democratically elected governments. This latter concern is
probably best presented in terms of the opposition
between constitutional democracy and majoritarian democracy. Liberal constitution orders are
designed to avoid the main drawback of majoritarian systems that Alexis de Tocqueville described
in Democracy in America (1835–40 [trans. 2000]) as
“the tyranny of the majority.” While in a majoritarian democracy it is possible for the majority to
vote in favor of the elimination of a minority, in a
liberal democracy such a possibility can be countered by constitutional provisos. Although the
people can change the Constitution, this process
is a lengthy and complex one, which ensures that
in the short term at least certain political options
are not available to the elected political leaders –
but as the example of the Weimar Republic
(1919–33) illustrates, this system is never entirely
foolproof.
At the end of the twentieth century the notion
that democracy is most meaningfully embodied by
a liberal democratic form of government has
become widespread, particularly after waves of
democratization swept across Latin America and
southern and eastern Europe as far as Russia. However, the idea that democracy and liberalism necessarily go hand in hand has been challenged in east
Asia and in the Muslim world by proponents of
“Asian values” and “Islamic democracy.” These
actors argue that the “Western” liberal assumptions contained in this dominant discourse about
democratic governance reflect a cultural bias.
Today, despite the efforts of advocates of deliberative democracy, like Jürgen Habermas, who
emphasize the possibility of a consensus reached
through public deliberation, it seems that the
only definition of democracy that can avoid these
cultural dilemmas is one that is couched in
127
democratization
negative terms. In other words, democracy is a
form of government in which those wielding political power do so only by virtue of the popular
mandate that they received from the citizens,
and no other claim to legitimacy can trump this
principle of democratic rule. As a political principle, the utilization of the notion of democracy
has, therefore, important epistemological implications. It indicates that in this political order, as a
matter of principle, no citizen can claim to know
better than his or her neighbor what is politically
desirable and achievable. Democracy as a form of
government simply reflects this equality of judgment in political life and its institutionalization
in a political system. And, as we enter the information age, changes in the way in which political
opinion can be estimated and fed back into the
decisionmaking process have the potential to
redefine democratic politics at the level of both
party politics and state politics.
FREDERIC VOLPI
democratization
– see democracy.
demographic transition
– see demography.
demography
The term demography comes from the Greek
words for population (demos) and for description
or writing (graphia). The term de´mographie is
believed to have been first used in 1855 by the
Belgian statistician Achille Guillard in his book
Elements of Human Statistics or Comparative Demography (1855 [trans. 1985]).
Demography is concerned with how large (or
small) populations are – that is, their size; how the
populations are composed according to age, sex,
race, marital status, and other characteristics –
that is, their composition; and how populations
are distributed in physical space, for example
how urban and rural they are – that is, their
spatial distribution. Of equal or greater importance, demography is interested in the changes
over time in the size, composition, and distribution of populations, as these result from the
processes of fertility, mortality, and migration.
Demography is also concerned with answering
the question of why these variables operate and
change in the way they do. That is, why do populations increase (or decrease) in numbers? Why
do they become older or younger? Why do they
become more urban or rural?
One paradigm in demography uses mainly demographic variables to answer the above questions,
128
demography
and this is known as formal demography. Another
paradigm uses mainly non-demographic variables
drawn from sociology, economics, psychology,
geography, biology, and so forth, to answer the
questions, and this is known as social demography
or population studies.
For instance, formal demographers might address population differences in birth rates or in
death rates by examining their differences in age
composition or in sex composition. Other things
being equal, younger populations will have higher
birth rates than older populations; and populations with an abundance of females over males
will have lower death rates than populations with
an abundance of males.
Alternately, social demographers might address
the above differences in populations by examining differences in, say, their socioeconomic status.
Other things being equal, populations with high
socioeconomic status will have lower birth rates
and death rates than populations with low socioeconomic status.
Demographic data will help illustrate the differences between these two approaches. Take the
demographic question of why human populations
have different levels of fertility. Countries differ
with respect to their total fertility rates (roughly
defined as the average number of children born to
a woman during her childbearing years). In Spain
and Italy in 2004, for instance, women were producing an average of 1.3 children each, whereas in
Somalia the average number was 7.1 and in Niger,
8.0 (Population Reference Bureau, 2004). Why do
these fertility differences exist? The social demographer would go beyond purely demographic
concerns and might focus on the processes of
industrialization and modernization, while the
formal demographer would rely more on purely
demographic kinds of explanations.
Another example focuses on rates of population
growth. In 2004 the rates of population change due
only to births and deaths in Hungary and Bulgaria
were –0.4 percent and –0.6 percent respectively. In
contrast, the rates in Malawi, and Saudi Arabia
were 3.1 percent and 3.0 percent, respectively.
Why are these four countries growing at such
drastically different rates? Why do two of the
countries have negative growth rates and the
other two positive rates? The formal demographer
might develop an answer by considering the birth
rates of these countries. The numbers of babies
born per 1,000 population in 2004 in Hungary,
Bulgaria, Malawi, and Saudi Arabia were 9, 9, 51
and 32, respectively. The latter two countries have
higher rates of growth than the former two
demography
countries partly because their birth rates are
higher. The social demographer would first consider the birth rate differentials, but would then
go beyond this demographic consideration to an
answer involving non-demographic factors which
may be influencing the birth rates. Perhaps the
economy has something to do with these differences, where countries with low per capita
incomes and low literacy rates for women tend
to have higher birth rates. Perhaps the level of
industrialization of the country has an impact
(the more industrialized countries generally have
lower birth rates).
Social demography is broader in scope and
orientation than formal demography. As S. H.
Preston writes in “The Contours of Demography:
Estimates and Projections,” in Demography (1993:
593), it includes “research of any disciplinary
stripe on the causes and consequences of population change.” Demographers, however, do not
always agree about the boundaries and restrictions of their field. J. Caldwell states the problem
succinctly in “Demography and Social Science”
(1996): “What demography is and what demographers should be confined to doing remains a difficult area in terms not only of the scope of
professional interests, but also of the coverage
aimed at in the syllabuses for students and in
what is acceptable for journals in the field.”
In the United States, most graduate training
programs in demography are located in departments of sociology (although this is not the case
in many other countries). Some American demographers thus argue that demography is best
treated as a subdiscipline or specialization of
sociology, owing to this organizational relationship. The late Kingsley Davis (1908–97), who served
at different times as President of both the Population Association of America and the American
Sociological Association, wrote in 1948 in his classic sociology textbook, Human Society (1948), that
“the science of population, sometimes called
demography, represents a fundamental approach
to the understanding of human society.” The
relationship between sociology and demography
is hence a fundamental one: “Society is both
a necessary and sufficient cause of population
trends.”
Change in the size of a population over a certain
period of time is due to changes in the same time
period in the three demographic processes of fertility, mortality, and migration. A population may
change its size over a given time interval by adding the number of persons born during the period,
subtracting those dying during the interval, and
demography
adding the number of persons moving into the
area and subtracting those moving out of the area.
The dynamics of population change may be
represented in a form known as the population
equation, also known as the balancing equation
P2 ¼ P1 þ B D þ = M
where P2 is the size of the population at the end of
the time interval; P1 is the size of the population
at the beginning of the time interval; B is the
number of births occurring in the population during the interval; D is the number of deaths occurring in the population during the interval; and M
is the net number of migrants moving to, or away
from, the population during the interval.
To illustrate, the following are data for the United States for the time interval of July 1, 2001 to
June 30, 2002:
US population size, July 1, 2002: 288,368,698;
US population size, July 1, 2001: 285,317,559;
Births from July 1, 2001 through June 30, 2002:
4,047,642;
Deaths from July 1, 2001 through June 30, 2002:
2,445,837;
Immigrations from July 1, 2001 through June 30,
2002: 1,664,334;
Emigrations from July 1, 2001 through June 30,
2002: 215,000.
These data may be incorporated into the population equation as follows:
P2ð288; 368; 698Þ ¼ P1ð285; 317; 559Þ þ Bð4; 047; 642Þ
Dð2; 445; 837Þ þ Mð1; 664; 334 215; 000Þ
The population equation describes a closed and
determinate model, provided its geographical
area remains the same. This is so because population change can occur only through the operation of the three demographic processes. Stated
in another way, a population changes in terms
of two forms of entry (births and in-migration) and
two forms of exit (deaths and out-migration); no
other variables need be entertained. Of course,
if one wishes to determine why fertility and mortality are at certain levels, or why in-migration
and out-migration are different, other nondemographic variables need to be entertained. As
discussed above, these are the concerns of social
demography.
The word “population” derives from the Latin
populare (to populate) and the Latin noun populatio. Geoffrey McNicoll, in the Encyclopedia of Population (2003), notes that, in ancient times, the verb
populare meant to lay waste, plunder, or ravage
and the noun populatio meant a plundering or
despoliation. These usages became obsolete by
the eighteenth century. The modern use of the
129
demography
word population first appeared in 1597 in an essay
by Francis Bacon (1561–1626).
Strictly speaking, a population is a group or
collection of items. But to a demographer a population is a group or collection of people. We may
distinguish between a specific population or
group of actual people alive at a given period of
time – for example the population of the United
States as of April 1, 2000 – and the population that
persists over time even though its actual members
may change, for example the population of China
over the past 4,000 years, and even into its future.
The more common use of the term population by
demographers and in modern English usage is
with reference to a delimited set, with unambiguous membership criteria, such as the population of the People’s Republic of China as
identified and enumerated in its 2000 census.
In a similar vein, N. B. Ryder, in “Notes on the
Concept of a Population” (1964 American Journal of
Sociology 69 (5): 447–63), defines a population as an
aggregate of individuals defined in spatial and
temporal terms. It is not necessarily a group,
which in sociological terms requires some forms
of interpersonal interaction and the development
of a sense of community. The analysis of human
populations is inherently dynamic because attention is focused on changes in the population over
time. The population equation is a demonstration.
Ryder also states that the population model is
both microdynamic and macrodynamic in nature.
This means that processes of change in fertility,
mortality, and migration can be identified at both
the individual and aggregate levels. This distinction lies at the very heart of the population model
because it introduces Alfred J. Lotka’s distinction
between the persistence of the individual and
the persistence of the aggregate, to be found in
Analytical Theory of Biological Populations (1934
[trans. 1998]). All human beings are born, live
for some period of time, and then die. But a
population aggregate is not temporally limited,
provided that enough individuals continue to
enter the population to replace those exiting; the
population in this sense is immortal.
Population aggregates, in terms both of the
changes in numbers and of the characteristics of
those entering and exiting, can experience
changes not reducible to individuals who constitute the population. For instance, when individuals enter a population through birth or inmigration, they will “age” by becoming older.
But the population aggregate cannot only become
older, it can also become younger, provided that
births exceed deaths and the in-migrants are
130
denomination
younger than the out-migrants. The racial and
sex composition of a population aggregate may
also change if more members of one race (see
race and ethnicity) or sex enter it than another.
Typically, persons do not change their race or sex.
Indeed, all human institutions and organizations
may be conceived in these terms. One way that
social change may be studied is by the monitoring
of compositional change caused by entrances and
exits.
Age is the key variable in the study of populations because it reflects the passage of time. It is
subject to metric measurement and provides a
precise statement of the time spent by individuals
in a population. Demographers use two key concepts in studying age-related changes, namely, the
life-cycle and the cohort. The former permits the
charting of the life-course experiences of individuals, for example, age of entry into and exit
from formal education, entry into full-time
employment and subsequent retirement, first
marriage, births of first and last children, and so
forth.
The cohort is an aggregate of individuals who
experience important events in their life-cycles at
the same time. The defining event is often year of
birth, but cohorts are also based on year of entry
into or graduation from college, year of birth of
first child, year of retirement, and so forth. In
this context, age as the passage of time is the
linkage between the history of the individual
and population.
Cohorts (see generations) are valuable analytically because they are subpopulations intermediate between the behaviors of individuals and the
population. In terms of birth cohorts, we can conceptualize the population at any given moment in
time as a cross-section of cohorts which are
arranged uniformly in a staggered manner, each
one on top of its immediate predecessor in time.
In recent decades some of the most impressive
and enduring accomplishments in demography
have been made in formal demography. Features
of the population model, some of which have just
been discussed, have been developed, and the
fruitfulness of the approach and its core concerns
have been demonstrated.
DUDLEY L. POSTON
denomination
This term is used to differentiate among diverse
religious traditions and to categorize diverse
affiliations within a shared tradition (most usually
within Protestantism and Judaism). Denominationalism emerged as a useful construct in
describing and understanding American religious
denomination
history because of the pluralism of its religious
traditions and the notable diversity of the range
of Protestant sects (see church–sect typology)
that have characterized America since colonial
times. Symbolically, denominationalism offers
tacit acknowledgment that there is no “one true
universal Church,” but that diverse religious
denominations, while founded in a belief in a
common divine source, develop in particular
ways and assume particular organizational characteristics because of the accretions of history and
culture. Denominationalism is a dynamic process
contingent on multiple contextual factors and in
American society is seen as a critical component
of cultural identity and belonging. Will Herberg
argued that the tripartite options of ProtestantCatholic-Jew (1955) offered a socially acceptable
way for Americans of diverse ethnic and religious
backgrounds to maintain a distinct identity while
affirming their shared commitment to religion
and, by extension, to American values (its civil
religion). Denominationalism is intertwined with
other significant aspects of American religion,
including the centrality of personal freedom and
choice in regard to churches and doctrines.
The heuristic use of denomination rather than
church or religion offers a nuanced way of thinking about the place of religion in a particular
society; in the contemporary United States, for
example, although Protestantism is the largest
religious tradition (or church), Catholicism is the
largest single denomination, and is followed by
(Protestant) Southern Baptists. The comparative
social status of different denominations (in
terms of membership, institutional activities, political influence) over time is also a useful way of
tracking, and theorizing about, changes in denominational membership and activities. Historically, denominational splitting occurred within
Protestantism because of disputes over various
theological and doctrinal questions (for example,
requirements for salvation or the meanings of
baptism and the eucharist) or forms of authority
(hierarchical or congregational), differences in
geographical region, ethnic/national origins (for
example, Scotch Presbyterians), or social class,
and in regard to political issues (such as slavery).
Each denomination, therefore, has a discrete
historical, cultural, and organizational identity
whose worldview and practices distinguish it
from other denominations.
In recent decades, there is increased evidence
that denominational identity is weakening in
the United States. Although it was never an allencompassing identity – as indicated by the
deskilling
significant rates of intermarriage among Protestants of different denominations, and of
church and denominational switching or mobility
more generally – it has lost some of its salience
both as an anchor of individual identity and in
terms of demarcating sociocultural and political
boundaries. There is some evidence that the
conservative/liberal ideological division within
denominations is more important in differentiating individuals and producing coalitions among
individuals and groups independently of denomination (for example, Robert Wuthnow, The Restructuring of American Religion, 1988). Denominational
affiliation still matters, however, and constrains
or moderates individual attitudes and behavior
(such as health and life-style practices). Strong
denominational loyalties and commitments on
the part of individuals can also constrain interorganizational relationships between denominations, and have an impact on specific issues (such
as welfare reforms and gay marriages) in the
formation of public policy.
One of the tensions confronting denominations
today is to achieve a balance between articulating
their own particular denominational identity and
simultaneously engaging in interdenominational
and interchurch discourse and cooperation across
various theologically charged (for example, abortion or stem-cell research) and economic and political issues (such as globalization).
MICHELE DILLON
denominationalization
– see denomination.
dependency theory
– see development theory.
deprivation
– see relative deprivation.
descent
– see kinship.
descent groups
– see kinship.
desegregation
– see segregation.
deskilling
Philosophical anthropology sometimes conceives
of the essence of humankind in terms of homo
faber rather than homo oeconomicus. The former
highlights people’s capacity to acquire skills,
131
determinism
engage in creative labor, and derive pleasure from
exercising these skills. In contrast, rational economic calculation could lead to deskilling to cut
material and monetary costs. In general, deskilling reduces the skills needed for a given product
or service and/or involves loss of skills due to
failure to exercise them (for example, through
long-term unemployment).
Classical political economy discussed deskilling.
Adam Smith (1723–90) illustrated it through the
division of labor in pin manufacture, and Marx
showed how this was reinforced by the transition
to machinofacture. Postindustrialism in turn deskills intellectual labor through smart machines
and expert systems that integrate tacit knowledge
and intellectual skills. Examples include automation of scientific tests, software for legal work, and
work in call centers.
Labor economists and economic sociology continue to discuss whether modern economies
require more or less skilled labor. This reflects
two countervailing trends: while new labor processes and products may be more knowledge- and
skill-intensive, the pressure to rationalize such
processes and products may lead to deskilling.
These contradictory tendencies were both emphasized in the work of Harry Braverman, the foremost proponent of the deskilling thesis in
monopoly capitalism, in Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the Twentieth Century
(1974). Some commentators also suggest that deskilling leads to worker alienation, disempowerment, and dehumanization, and may prompt
resistance from manual and mental labor. Others
emphasize that it can lead to cleaner and less
physically demanding work.
BOB JESSOP
determinism
This is the view that, given certain prior conditions, there is an inevitability about the social
processes, events, and happenings that will subsequently be brought about. These subsequent happenings are said to be entirely determined by the
given prior conditions. Determinism can take
many forms but perhaps the Marxist variant is
the most well-known sociological example. Determinism here is associated with those interpretations of Karl Marx’s work in which the economic
base is said to determine what happens at the
level of law, politics, and ideology. The determining conditions here are the economic and class
relations structured around the mode of production, whether this be feudal, capitalist, or some
other. Politics, law, and ideology, the so-called
superstructures, would be seen as merely the
132
determinism
surface manifestations, the epiphenomena, of
the deeper economic and class structures that
provide the real force and energy driving all of
social reality. Determinism can also take a range
of other forms in which, instead of the economic
taking the role of the determining force, this role
is given to the genetic, cultural, discursive, demographic, or militaristic dimensions of social life, to
name but some. Thus, many racist and sexist arguments are based on forms of genetic determinism
in which allegedly inferior genetic inheritances
determine lower levels of capability. Or, in a military version, it may be assumed that the nation
with the greatest firepower will inevitably come to
dominate the world economy. It is the economy
this time that plays the role of epiphenomenon.
While there can sometimes be some truth in
deterministic arguments – such that the economic
level does clearly have effects on other aspects of
life, and that genetic inheritance will make some
things broadly possible and other things impossible – the truths are often partial and overly simplified, and at other times they are simply wrong.
Two salient weaknesses can typically be found in
deterministic arguments. The first entails a crude
view of the nature of the object or set of relations
that are said to be doing the determining. Thus, to
take the Marxist example, the economic level
itself does in fact require certain legal, political,
and ideological preconditions for it to exist in the
first place, something stressed by many twentiethcentury neo-Marxists. The economic level is itself
a more complex and plural entity than a crude
account suggests.
The second weakness is closely related, and
entails an overly simple, or reductionist, view of
the causal process by which the determining
object is said to bring about the things it determines. In contrast to a laboratory experiment in
which strict controls ensure that object X produces certain effects on object Y without any
unwanted factors intervening, causality in social
life is freighted with a plurality of complicating
factors. Any effect that an object such as the economy has on another entity such as politics – even
if it were possible to draw a ring around the two so
neatly – would typically be mediated, tempered,
and complicated by many other factors. These
factors could include anything from constitutional statutes and party doctrines to media representations and nationalistic ideologies, not to
mention the uncertainties and creativities of
human agency within each of these spheres.
The typical stance of determinism has been a
view that social events are pre-determined, and
detraditionalization
that they are pre-determined by a particular kind
of entity to the exclusion of other entities. A more
adequate view is that social happenings do have
causal determinants which bring them about, but
that these determinants tend to be both internally
complex and plural, and that they combine to
produce social events but without having been
bound to do so.
ROB STONES
detraditionalization
– see tradition.
development theory
Coming to prominence in the context of United
States hegemony and attendant Cold War superpower rivalry, development or modernization theory assumed the existence of national societies
developing in parallel with each other in a natural
and universal evolutionary process. There were
strains, to be sure. The Russian Revolution, as
Theodor Shanin argued in Russia 1905–07. Revolution as a moment of Truth (1986), can be seen as the
outcome of some of the contradictions of “developing societies,” and rapid industrialization (see
industrial society) thereafter – though brutal –
was held up as a model for Third World states
seeking to overcome economic backwardness.
Both the United States and the Soviet Union
aimed to convince other states to ally with them
in the Cold War in exchange for military and
economic aid, each arguing for the superiority of
their model of economic development.
Structural-functionalist
theorists,
notably
Talcott Parsons, held up those industrialized capitalist societies that had achieved high levels of
wealth and democratic political forms, notably
western Europe, its settler offshoots – the United
States, Australia, Canada, and New Zealand – and
states such as Japan, as models of successful development. Poverty and underdevelopment were
conceived of as reflecting the prevalence of
traditional cultural values thwarting moves
towards greater economic development and
differentiation.
In the context of the wave of decolonization
after World War II, and new international bodies
like the United Nations (UN), new voices challenged this consensus. One early important critique was that developed by the UN Economic
Commission on Latin America (ECLA), based in
Santiago, Chile, and formed in 1948 despite the
strong objections of the United States, and led by
the Argentine Raúl Prebisch (1901–86). While
Latin America had been independent since the
Hispanic American revolutions of the 1800s, the
development theory
ECLA’s economists emphasized the continued
structural dependence of the region on advanced
countries such as the United States. The ECLA
analyzed how the formation of peripheral export
economies served the needs of the powerful states
at the center of the global capitalist economy
throughout the colonial period and thereafter.
The ECLA’s studies had a major impact on the
emergence of a distinct Latin American perspective on development and underdevelopment, thus
playing an important role in the emergence of
dependency theory. The career of Celso Furtado
(1920–2004), widely regarded as the most influential Brazilian economist of the twentieth century
and a leader of the structural economists of the
region, exemplifies this connection. Prebisch saw
Furtado’s ability early on and chose him as the
first head of the newly created economic development division. In a 1956 book, Furtado became
one of the earliest social scientists to use the
term dependency, and went on to serve as Brazil’s
Minister of Planning in the populist government
of João Goulart (1918–76), until the United States
overthrew the democratically elected government
in 1964.
The structural economists of ECLA advocated
the importation and development of infant industries through import substitution industrialization (ISI) and Keynesian (see John Maynard
Keynes) techniques of economic demand stimulus. Yet, aside from the relatively unique experience of East Asia, for all the gains made in
economic growth and development, ISI failed to
overcome economic dependency on foreign actors
and thus gave way to the emergence of a radicalized dependency theory. In the context of the
Cuban Revolution and the United States response
to this in the region, including through support
for the emergence of military regimes, many of
the dependency theorists advocated anti-imperialist revolutions, often as part of a broader socialist
or Marxist-inspired strategy for Third World
development.
Marxist economist Paul Baran (1910–64) was an
early precursor of the dependentistas, who included
left-wing social scientists such as Samir Amin,
Frederick Clairmonte, Alain de Janvry, Anibal Quijano, Cheryl Payer, Dudley Seers, Walter Rodney,
and Theotonio dos Santos. Among the most prominent were Fernando Henrique Cardoso (later
President of Brazil) and Andre´ Gunder Frank,
both of them associated to varying degrees with
ECLA. Frank coined the term “the development of
underdevelopment,” arguing the two dimensions
were dialectically related. In contrast to the
133
development theory
modernization school, dependency theorists
argued that the poverty of the periphery and
wealth of the core were a structural outcome of
unequal power relations between different states
and peoples, not cultural differences or tradition.
Such so-called feudal remnants – the domination
of landed classes and so forth – were seen instead
as products of capitalist development in the Third
World dictated by the center. While inspired by
the arguments of Karl Marx, dependency theorists
differed in that they argued capitalism brought
not modernization but instead subordination
and polarization through surplus extraction.
The institutional structure of domination here
included what Peter Evans, in Dependent Development (1979), called the “triple alliance” of multinational, state, and local capital. Associated
critical actors, which Robin Broad, David PionBerlin, Michael McClintock, and others have analyzed, included the core states, US-dominated
Bretton Woods institutions – the International
Monetary Fund (IMF) and the World Bank (WB) –
and associated core military intervention and
support for repressive regimes.
Despite all the frustrations of postwar development, it is now seen by many as the golden age of
postwar capitalism. Governance of market forces
and related social programs led to high growth
rates and a growing advantage in the 1960s and
1970s for Third World states in the area of trade
and development. The 1980s, in contrast, saw such
dramatic reversals in social gains that it was
called “the lost decade of the South.” The generalized economic crisis hit both the Second and
Third Worlds, eventually leading to the collapse
of the Soviet Empire in eastern Europe and the
breakup of the Soviet Union, and the return of
much of the region to its original Third World
role. These epochal shifts of the 1980s were part
of the “counterrevolution in development policy”
associated with the hegemony of neoliberalism,
globalization, and finance capital, propelled by
the United States’ move towards high interest
rates and massive borrowing on the global capital
markets. Yet among radical critics, such as those
of world-systems analysis, what was signaled here
was actually not the victory but instead the crisis
of developmentalism, the shared belief among
self-declared capitalist or communist states that
the gains and benefits of the world economy were
open to all those who put in the requisite effort.
Here, the rise of liberation theology, Islamic fundamentalism, and other social movements were
seen as part of the resistance to developmentalism
and its failures.
134
development theory
The US economic boom of the 1990s, coming in
the wake of the communist collapse, added to the
revival of modernization ideologies and the neoliberal Washington Consensus, seen as the endpoint of history by scholars such as Francis
Fukuyama in his The End of History and the Last
Man (1989). For a time, the Asian economic crisis
of 1997 and concomitant dramatic plummeting of
incomes in the region led to renewed discussion
about the superiority of the United States model
of capitalism. Yet soon afterwards mainstream
intellectuals such as Jagdish Bhagwati, along
with radical critics such as Walden Bello, and
Peter Gowan in his The Global Gamble (1999),
pointed towards the unleashing of speculative
capital – from hedge funds to derivatives – called
for by neo-liberal policymakers, as causing the
crisis. In the wake of the collapse of the US speculative boom, the bursting of the bubble, the ensuing corporate scandals and economic meltdown of
Argentina – the former darling of the IMF – more
sober assessments, questioning both the modernization and neo-liberal approaches, thus gained
ground.
Authors such as Alice Amsden, Bruce Cumings,
Chalmers Johnson, Robert Wade, and former chief
World Bank economist Joseph Stiglitz, highlighted
the structural conditions allowing for East Asia’s
economic advance and the role of neoliberalism in
the crisis. Particular attention was paid to the
developmental state, as Meredith Woo-Cumings
explores in her edited volume (The Developmental
State, 1999), and Alexander Gershenkron’s advantages of backwardness or late development, along
with a host of unique conditions – land reform,
US military aid for export-oriented industrialization in a productivist mold, limitations on foreign
direct investment, and capital controls – that
allowed for East Asia’s ascent, now joined by
China. In essence, contrary to ideologies of neoliberalism, in East Asia’s export-oriented industrialization the state played a pronounced role in
guiding market forces. More recently, Ha-Joon
Chang in Kicking Away the Ladder (2002) has shown
that virtually all the developed countries used
infant industry promotion and protectionism
before opening their markets to free competition,
as Frederich List predicted, by telling the rest of
the world – through organizations ranging from
the IMF to the World Trade Organization – that
they were not allowed to use such mechanisms.
Indeed, advanced countries still interfere with
market forces in numerous ways, from agricultural subsidies to military spending serving to
prop up high-technology industry.
development theory
Development theory is today being radically
reformulated by a host of iconoclastic scholars,
from Mike Davis in Late Victorian Holocausts: El
Nino Famines and the Making of the Third World
(2001) to the efforts of the Nobel-prize-winning
economist Amartya Sen. Though Sen generally
stays away from the question of power in the
global economy as a whole, his works nevertheless
complement these perspectives. In books such as
India: Development and Participation (2002), Jean
Dreze and Amartya Sen redefined development
as the process of enhancing human freedom,
focusing on the quality of life and related social
opportunities, seen as both the means and ends of
development. By shifting focus from the question
of income to human capabilities – with poverty
redefined as capability deprivation – Sen and his
colleagues redirected attention towards inequalities within states and regions. Though not denying the potentially positive relationship between
economic growth, rising incomes, and livelihood,
Sen demonstrates that various countries with a
high Gross National Product have abysmal indicators in terms of the quality of life, while, through
political action and public policy other societies
have made tremendous achievements in terms of
quality of life, even in the absence of significant
economic performance. Moreover, in books such
as Development and Freedom (1999), drawing on a
wealth of empirical studies, Sen demonstrated
the positive relationship between the improvement of people’s freedom and capabilities – notably basic education, health, rights to information,
and democratic participation, especially for
women – for economic growth, development,
and fertility reduction. Sen has furthermore highlighted success stories, from the Kerala region in
India to East Asia, the latter of which, for all its
problems, can be seen in relative terms as what
Fernado Fajyzylber, in his important Unavoidable
Industrial Restructuring in Latin America (1990),
called the “Growth-with-equity-industrializing
countries.”
World-systems analysts have drawn on the work
of Roy F. Harrod (1900–78) who, in a series of
famous articles, created the modern theory of
growth. In particular, Giovanni Arrighi in The
Long Twentieth Century (1994) and Fred Hirsch in
The Social Limits of Growth (1976) have shown that,
while options for upward mobility are open to
some, ultimately they rest on relational processes
of exploitation and exclusion that reproduce
the oligarchic structures of the world economy,
within which income and resources are used
disproportionately by the few at the expense of
deviance
the many. Though many states of the South
internalized aspects of the social structures of
the core through industrialization, this failed to
close the widening development gap. Recent United Nations Human Development Reports (1998, 1999)
note that (1) the wealthiest 20 percent of the
world’s population accounts for some 86 percent
of private consumption expenditures; and (2)
income inequality between the world’s poor and
rich states has increased from roughly 3:1 in 1820,
to 11:1 in 1913, before rising from 35:1 to 70:1
from 1950 to 1992. The Forbes (2004) most recent
annual report on the nearly 600 billionaires in the
world reveals their wealth to be close to US$1.9
trillion; this at a time when over a billion persons
across the globe live on under a dollar a day,
according to World Bank statistics, while the gap
between high-, middle-, and low-income states
continues to widen. In recent years these increasing inequalities have given rise to a global social
justice and peace movement, replete with its own
annual World Social Forum, bringing together
concerned citizens and activists in non-governmental organizations, to build a better world.
Thus, at the dawn of the twenty-first century, the
questions of economic development and what
model(s) might allow for truly universal values of
greater global democracy, prosperity, and sustainable development remain one of the great unresolved questions of the present.
THOMAS REIFER
deviance
In simple terms, this can be defined as (real or
purported) non-normative behavior that, if detected, can be subject to informal or formal sanctions. Deviant behavior is norm-violating conduct
that is subject to social control. In their textbook
Social Deviance and Crime: An Organizational and
Theoretical Approach (2000), Charles Tittle and Raymond Paternoster summarize the predominant
ways in which sociologists have defined deviance
and offer their own definition: any type of behavior that the majority of a given group regards as
unacceptable or that evokes a collective response
of a negative type (13). Deviants are those who
engage in behavior that deviates from norms in a
disapproved direction in sufficient degree to
exceed the tolerance limits of a discernible social
group, such that the behavior is likely to elicit a
negative sanction if detected.
Howard S. Becker, an influential scholar of
deviance, pointed out in Outsiders: Studies in the
Sociology of Deviance (1963) that deviance is not a
quality of the act one commits, but rather a consequence of the application by others of rules and
135
deviance
sanctions to an “offender.” Whether an act is deviant depends on how others who have social power
and influence define the act. One could commit
any act, but it is not deviant in its social consequence if no elements of society react to it. Becker
called social acts “rule-breaking behavior,” and
actors violating norms of society “rule-breakers.”
As John I. Kitsuse (1923–2003), a well-known scholar of deviance best-known for furthering a “labeling approach” to understanding rule violation,
made clear in his body of work spanning over
three decades, forms of behavior per se do not
differentiate deviants from nondeviants; conventional and conforming members of the society
identify and interpret behavior as deviant, and
then transform rule-breaking behavior into deviance and persons who break rules or norms into
deviants.
Many theoretical frameworks, including strain,
subculture, learning, and labeling, have been
developed by sociologists to explain the occurrences, forms, consequences, and labeling of
deviance. One way to make sense of these various
frameworks is to organize them according to the
degree to which they are designed to address one
of two central questions in the study of deviance.
First, normative theories ask “who violates norms
and why?” Second, reactivist theories ask “why are
certain types of norm violations by certain types
of individuals (and not others) reacted to as deviant and result in the stigmatization of the rulebreaker?” Relatedly, theories of deviance can be
classified as macro and micro. Macro-theories
focus on societal and group structures, while
micro-theorists focus on individuals and the interactional patterns in which they engage and to
which they are subject. Classified along these
dimensions, many – but not all – theories of deviance have been categorized by James Orcutt as
“macro-normative,” “micro-normative,” “macroreactionist,” and “micro-reactionist” (Analyzing
Deviance, 1983). In recent decades, however, sociologists have integrated theories of deviance so
that elements of these four types of theories can
be found in a single theory organized around a
central causal mechanism.
The macro-normative approach to the study of
deviance examines how societies and communities are organized, to determine why varying
rates of deviant behavior appear across subgroups
in the population, locations in a community or
society, and at different points in history. For
example, the French sociologist Émile Durkheim,
perhaps the most frequently cited classical theorist of deviance, studied how social structure
136
deviance
facilitates or impedes the production of deviance,
by emphasizing that structural strain produces
what he called “pathology” in the population.
Based on empirical data on suicide rates across
Europe in the latter part of the nineteenth century, Durkheim argued in Suicide (1897 [trans.
1964]) that changes in the rate of suicide are not
adequately explained by individualistic approaches to deviance. Rather, fluctuations in the rates
of suicide within and between societies were best
explained by the way societies were structured,
especially in light of three types of social conditions that produce strain: (1) anomie, a societal
condition characterized by a state of normlessness
in which individuals become disassociated from
a collective moral authority; (2) egoism, a societal
condition in which the normative order is too
weak and individuals are not sufficiently integrated into society, and thus they are not bound
by the norms of the society; and (3) altruism, a
societal condition in which the normative order
is too strong and individuals are overly integrated into society in ways that compel them to
willfully take their own life.
From a Durkheimian point of view, an appropriate level of “pathology” is “normal” for society
because it serves positive functions, including: a
boundary-setting function that delineates the distinction between right and wrong; a group solidarity function for those united in collective
opposition to the normative threats of nonconformity; an innovation function insofar as breaking
norms often leads to healthy social change; and a
tension-reduction function for those who “blow
off a little steam” by engaging in low-level forms
of deviance (Durkheim, 1895 [trans. 1938]).
Consistent with Durkheim’s path-breaking
approach to deviance, many contemporary deviance theorists explain varying rates of deviant
behavior in terms of an array of structural features of society. Robert K. Merton, for example,
extended Durkheim’s work in Social Theory and
Social Structure (1957). He sought to explain why
people in the same environment behave differently, sometimes conforming and sometimes exhibiting deviant behavior. He borrowed Durkheim’s
key term – anomie – to conceptualize structural
strain as an acute disjuncture between cultural
norms and goals and the socially structured capacities of the members of the group to act in accord
with them. In simple terms, Merton argued, when
people are faced with blocked access to legitimate
means to reach culturally acceptable goals, they
will “adapt” to the situation by pursuing illegitimate means – deviant behavior – to achieve
deviance
conventional goals. Because economic opportunity is not evenly distributed across society, rates
of deviance, especially crime and delinquency, are
also unevenly distributed. More recently, Steven
Messner and Richard Rosenfeld in Crime and the
American Dream (1994) reformulated Merton’s theory by proposing that anomie fostered by economic inequality is most likely to produce crime
and delinquency when economic and noneconomic institutions fail to offset the material
success available to those engaging in deviance.
Versions of social ecological theories of deviance
constitute another type of structural explanation
of deviance. Social disorganization theory, which
developed at the University of Chicago in the 1930s
and continues to inspire volumes of research
today, emphasizes the correlation between spatial
location and rates of criminal and deviant behavior. The concept of social disorganization refers to
both social and cultural conditions, such as value
and norm conflicts, mobility, cultural change, and
weak relationships. Social disorganization undermines internal and external social control,
thereby promoting unconventional and deviant
behavior.
Some spatial locations have so much social disorganization that a delinquent subculture arises.
Albert Cohen argued in his book Delinquent Boys:
The Culture of the Gang (1955) that youth become
frustrated (a form of anomie) when they find
themselves unable to perform in school on a par
with their more privileged peers. Seeking solace
with other lower-class peers, together they engage
in deviant acts as a way to flaunt traditional
norms. Richard Cloward and Lloyd Ohlin furthered subculture theory with their book Delinquency
and Opportunity: A Theory of Delinquent Gangs (1960).
They specified three types of delinquent gang
subcultures: criminal, conflict, and retreatist.
Criminal subcultures focus more on making
money than being violent; conflict subcultures
are violent towards law-abiding and criminal
groups alike; and retreatist subcultures comprise
individuals who cannot make it in either the legitimate or the criminal world – therefore, they
resort to deviant (and illegal) activities such as
the excessive or inappropriate use of drugs,
alcohol, and so forth.
Other ecological theories of deviance include:
routine activities theory, which posits that the convergence of a motivated offender, a suitable target,
and the absence of a capable guardian produces
crime and deviance (Lawrence Cohen and Marcus
Felson in “Social Change and Crime Rate Trends: A
Routine Activity Approach,” American Sociological
deviance
Review, 1979); gender and power-control theory
(John Hagan, Structural Criminology, 1989), which
points to the family as the primary source of varying socialization experiences for boys and girls, to
explain gender differences in nonconforming
behavior; classic control theory, such as Travis
Hirschi, Causes of Delinquency (1969), which emphasizes sources of social bonding and attachments as
key to understanding who deviates and why; and
contemporary control theory, which emphasizes
lack of self-control and directs attention to the
social organization of the family as producing
(and inhibiting) deviance (for example, Michael
Gottfredson and Travis Hirschi, A General Theory of
Crime, 1990).
Others have theorized about why some people
in an environment (and not others) fail to conform to group norms and, instead, engage in deviant behavior. These theorists focus on the
experiences and interpersonal interactions of
those who learn to engage in deviant behavior.
Orienting to deviance as a form of learned behavior, these theorists treat the underlying mechanisms that produce deviance as essentially no
different from those that produce conformity.
However, theorists disagree on what the precise
mechanisms of learning entail.
The early roots of a learning perspective on
deviance can be found in a French magistrate’s
work on imitation and suggestion as the “cause”
of juvenile delinquency and crime. Gabriel Tarde
argued in The Laws of Imitation (1890 [trans. 1912])
that the explanation of crime lay not in biology
but in the social world and that crime is transmitted through intimate personal groups. In simple terms, he argued good boys associate with and
imitate bad boys and, in the process, become bad
boys themselves. Regardless of what characteristics one has at birth, Tarde argued, one must learn
to become criminal by association with and imitation of others, just as one learns a trade or learns
about and imitates the latest fads and fashions.
A far more systematic and consequential learning theory was presented in 1939 by the American
criminologist Edwin H. Sutherland in Principles of
Criminology, which is now in its eleventh edition
and continues to be one of the best-selling criminology textbooks (see Sutherland, Cressey, and
Luckenbill, [eds.] 2002). Sutherland argued that
crime and other forms of deviance do not result
from social disorganization; rather, some groups
are organized for criminal activities and some are
organized against these activities. Sutherland
hypothesized that any person can be trained to
adopt and follow any pattern of criminal behavior
137
deviance
and any pattern of conforming behavior. Such
patterns were developed through differential
social organization and differential association.
Sutherland, and later his co-authors Donald Cressey and David Luckenbill, argued that differential
social organization could explain the crime rate
(just as the macro-normative theorists would suggest), while differential association could explain
the criminal behavior of a particular person. The
differential association element of this approach
posits that deviant behavior is a product of learning via communicative interaction. This type of
learning involves defining certain situations as
the appropriate occasions for deviant behavior;
mastering the techniques of successful deviant
activity; and acquiring the motives, drives, attitudes, and rationalizations that justify violations
of norms and/or laws (see law and society).
One key to learning deviance is what Gresham
Sykes and David Matza refer to as “techniques of
neutralizations,” which are justifications and
excuses for committing deviant acts (“Techniques
of Neutralization: A Theory of Delinquency,” American Sociological Review, 1957). By denying responsibility, denying injury or harm, denying the victim,
and appealing to higher loyalties, deviants are
able to free themselves from the pressure to conform to social norms for a specific act. Techniques
of neutralization play a key role in deviance disavowal – the deviant’s rejection of the application
of deviant labels – by enabling the deviant to
distinguish himself from his deviance in an
effort to maintain a conventional identity as a
conventional member of society.
Techniques of neutralization also play a key role
in deviancy drift theory as developed by Matza in
Delinquency and Drift (1964). Matza’s drift theory
assumes that people live their lives on a continuum somewhere between total freedom and
total constraint, and often people move between
conforming and deviant behavior. This movement
occurs because delinquents can maintain a commitment to the dominant norms while neutralizing their controlling effect on their deviant
behavior. Indeed, the frequent deployment of
techniques of neutralization shows that deviants
generally hold values and beliefs very similar to
those who conform.
More contemporary theoretical treatments of
the role learning plays in producing deviance
have examined other dynamics crucial to learning
both deviant and conforming behavior. For example, Ronald Akers (Social Learning and Social Structure, 1998) looks beyond differential association to
differential reinforcement. Reinforcement refers
138
deviance
to the process by which other people reward or
punish a particular deviant act. Akers stresses that
this process is complex and is built upon reciprocal feedback loops that precede the moment of
engaging in deviance.
Moving away from the normative question of
who engages in deviance and why, sociologists
working within the “constructionist” or “reactionist” tradition analyze the origins and content of
rules, norms, traditions, and laws in order to
understand why certain types of behavior and
people are constructed and categorized as deviant
in the first place. Here the focus is on the social
construction of deviance, a process whereby
conduct, events, and people are constructed as
abnormal, atypical, pathological, and ultimately
stigmatizable. Rather than focusing on the causes
and correlates of deviant behavior, this perspective devotes analytic attention to the processes
whereby the boundaries between “normal” and
“deviant” are demarcated at the societal level.
At the macroscopic level, sociologists have studied the formation of criminal law and other
forms of social policy and rule-making as one
empirical measure of a group, community, or
society marking behavior as unacceptable and
subject to social control. Over a half a century
ago, Edwin Sutherland published one of the earliest and best-known sociological investigations of
the origins of a specific type of criminal law. In
“The Sexual Psychopath Laws” (Journal of Criminal
Law and Criminology, 1950), Sutherland argued that
the origins and the diffusion of sexual psychopath
laws are largely the result of two things: the
manipulation of public opinion by the press and
the influence of experts on the legislative process.
These factors invented what is now identifiable as
the sexual psychopath, declaring certain people
deviant and in need of social control.
Since the publication of Sutherland’s classic
study on the criminalization of sexual psychopathy, sociologists have pointed to a plethora of
demographic, organizational, political, structural,
and institutional conditions that shape when and
how social behaviors and statuses become defined
as deviant over time and across geopolitical
boundaries. For example, taking a decidedly materialist approach to criminalization, William
Chambliss detailed in his now-famous and often
reprinted article “A Sociological Analysis of the
Law of Vagrancy” (Social Problems, 1964) how changing demographic and economic conditions
enabled vagrancy laws, which define people without a permanent residence as deviant, to emerge
in the fourteenth century. A more recent work on
deviance
the topic of homelessness by Gregg Barak (Gimme
Shelter: A Social History of Homelessness in Contemporary America, 1991) demonstrates that gentrification and redevelopment in central cities, coupled
with changing views of “the homeless,” led to a
plethora of laws that criminalize homelessness
and, in the process, deviantize the homeless as
misfits and vagabonds living outside the conventional moral order and threatening those who do
not.
Similarly, Joseph R. Gusfield in Symbolic Crusade
(1986) explains how the distribution and sale of
alcoholic beverages was constitutionally defined
as criminal in the United States in the early twentieth century. In the process, native groups effectively deviantized immigrants, Catholics, and
urban dwellers, who consumed alcohol in more
visible ways than natives, Protestants, and rural
dwellers. In more recent work on status politics
and law, Valerie Jenness and Ryken Grattet analyzed in their book Making Hate a Crime (2001) the
crucial role grassroots activists and organized
social movements have played in instigating and
formulating hate-crime law in the United States
that criminalizes bias-motivated violence across
the nation; as a result, in the latter part of the
twentieth century, age-old violent behavior deriving from bigotry became recognizable as hate
crime. Similarly, Elizabeth Boyle’s work Female
Genital Cutting: Cultural Conflict in the Global Community (2003) shows how processes of globalization
have redefined centuries-old normative behavior –
female genital cutting – as unacceptable, deviant,
and, in some cases, criminal behavior.
At the microscopic level of analysis, sociologists
of deviance examine the interactions between
deviants and “normals” and the consequences of
such interactions for the production and management of stigma, the engine around which deviantization motors. The term stigma (or stigmata)
dates back to the Greek word for “tattoo-mark”
and references the mark made with a hot iron
and impressed on people to show they were
devoted to the service of the temple, or on the
opposite spectrum of behavior, that they were
criminals or runaway slaves. In its most literal
usage, the term stigma refers to a mark or stain
that ruins an individual’s reputation. To understand the concept of stigma and its relevance to
the social construction of deviance, Erving Goffman’s classic work Stigma: Notes on the Management
of a Spoiled Identity (1963) emphasized a distinction
between virtual social identities and actual social
identities. Virtual social identities are normative
expectations about how people should behave and
deviance
characteristics people should possess; and actual
social identities are the actual behavior of individuals and the characteristics individuals actually possess. Goffman argued that discrepancies
between virtual and actual social identities often
cause us to reclassify an individual from one
socially anticipated category to another less desirable one. For example, coming to understand
someone is homosexual, an ex con, or the carrier
of a fatal disease, after presuming the individual
was heterosexual, a law-abiding citizen, or generally healthy, can result in the reclassification of
someone as a particular type of person. However,
attributes do not, in and of themselves, cause
stigmata; whether or not an attribute is stigmatizing depends upon the circumstance and the
social audience. An attribute that stigmatizes
one type of person can confirm the usualness of
another and therefore is neither creditable nor
discreditable as a thing in itself. Context matters
because it is only within specific contexts that
attributes get negatively labeled and reacted to
as such. In short, deviance is necessarily relative.
The process of labeling, as anticipated by Frank
Tannenbaum, conceived by Goffman, and elaborated by Howard S. Becker, Edwin Schur, Edwin
Lemert, and Stephen Pfohl, has loomed large in
empirical studies of deviance. Relying upon the
basic tenets of symbolic interactionism, sociologists have documented many sources and consequences of stigma by empirically examining
diverse types of people, situations, and judgments that spoil actual social identities in an array
of institutional settings. For example, stigma attached to the presence of a criminal record reduces the perceived value of potential employees
for potential employers. Moreover, specific sexual
practices, health conditions, family histories, bodily forms, and religious practices can, if and when
they become known, demote individuals in the
eyes of what Goffman called “normals.”
Finally, identities and subcultures can be organized around shared stigma, and deviance can be
amplified as a result. In Lemert’s classic formulation (Human Deviance, Social Problems, and Social Control, 1967), primary deviance is norm-violating
behavior that does not result in consequential
public labeling because it does not surpass a
group, community, or society’s tolerance threshold; therefore it is ignored or normalized. In
contrast, secondary deviance occurs when normviolating behavior passes the group, community,
or society tolerance threshold, is subject to a “dramatization of evil” (Tannenbaum’s terminology)
and stigmatized, and results in a changed
139
deviance
self-concept for the deviant(s). Unlike primary
deviance, which derives from multiple causes
and is sporadic, secondary deviance is role-based
behavior and is more predictable. In other words,
secondary deviation is a function of societal reaction and stigmatizing labels. Related, deviance
amplification is the unintended consequence of
formal and informal social control efforts, which
often stimulate a spiral of deviance. The way people (for example teachers and parents) and organizations (for example the criminal justice system)
react to relatively minor deviance can result in the
formation of deviant subcultures and deviant
careers. This is because stigmatization changes
self-concepts, and changed self-concepts provide
the principal link between the stigmatized labels
and future deviant behavior. In simple terms,
labeling theory posits that people take on deviant
identities and play deviant roles because they are
strongly influenced into doing so by the application of stigmatizing labels to them. This line of
thinking has been applied most commonly to juvenile delinquents, as well as the mentally ill, rapists,
nudists, homosexuals, ex-convicts, shoplifters,
and people struggling to manage their weight.
Sociologists have also examined the ways stigmatized identities and groups organized around
them have become the source of political consciousness and attendant social movement activity. For example, in the latter part of the
twentieth century, those sustaining the gay and
lesbian movement, the prostitutes’ rights movement, the disabilities movement, the movement
to advance fat acceptance, and the movement to
normalize mental illness have sought to destigmatize the very attributes, identities, and behaviors
that bind them together as a discernible socialpolitical group. Kitsuse commented on this uniquely modern trend in a presidential address to
the Society for the Study of Social Problems aptly
titled “Deviance Coming Out All Over: Deviants
and the Politics of Social Problems” (1980). A little
over a decade later, United States senator Daniel
Patrick Moynihan, a sociologist, reiterated the
constructionist theme of the elasticity of social
boundaries between conventional and deviant
behavior and expressed concern about the degree
to which what was once seen as deviant behavior
is now seen as conventional behavior in an article
entiled “Defining Deviancy Down” (1993).
More recently, Joel Best has pointed out in his
history of deviance, Deviance: Career of a Concept
(2004), that labeling theory came under fire from
feminist critics who found labeling theorists
too sympathetic towards those who victimized
140
deviance
women, identity politics that sought to remove
the stigma from certain activities and attributes,
and mainstream sociologists who claimed that
labeling theory was empirically wrong, which
was probably the most damaging of the critiques.
According to Best, as labeling theory became
unpopular, scholars turned to more specialized
studies – such as the study of social problems
and social movements and deviant transactions –
because they allowed the scholars the freedom to
condemn some deviants while celebrating others.
Since the mid-1970s, a number of explanations
for deviance have emerged that do not fit into
the categories of theories described above, precisely because they are integrated theories. Integrated theories, by design, draw elements from
normative and reactionist theories at both the
macroscopic and microscopic levels, add new
causal mechanisms to elements drawn from these
theories, and present the synthesis as a new explanatory framework.
Developing integrated theories requires the
scholar to recognize that the elements of one theory are compatible with another, even though the
theories operate on different levels of abstraction.
Ernest Burgess and Ronald Akers in their article
“A Differential Association–Reinforcement Theory
of Criminal Behavior” (Social Problems, 1966) successfully combined social learning theory and
Sutherland’s differential association theory. As
Messner and Liska point out in their textbook
Perspectives on Crime and Deviance (1999), Burgess
and Akers did this by recognizing that youths
“hanging out” with delinquent peers and learning
from them (differential association) is merely one
particular type of operant conditioning (learning
theory). A second integrated theory is found in
John Braithwaite’s Crime, Shame and Reintegration
(1989). Braithwaite draws upon elements of structural strain theory, learning theory, and societal
reactionist theory to argue that the type of shaming to which rule-breakers are subject is crucial
to producing deviance. Specifically, one type of
shaming – disintegrative shaming – reproduces
deviance; another type of shaming – reintegrative
shaming – reduces the occurrence of subsequent
deviance by providing the opportunity for individuals to recommit to conventional society. More
recently, in Control Balance: Toward A General Theory
of Deviance (1995), Charles Tittle relies upon elements from many different theories and the
notion of “control-balance” to develop a new theoretical framework. In Tittle’s theory, “controlbalance,” or the ratio of how much a person is
able to control compared to how much the
deviance
deviant case analysis
individual is controlled (itself a product of social
structures, interaction patterns, and other ecological variables), explains both conforming and
deviant behavior.
As integrated theories continue to be developed,
so too do general assessments of the status of the
sociological study of deviance. On the one hand,
the sociology of deviance’s book-length obituary
has been written by Colin Sumner (The Sociology of
Deviance: An Obituary, 1994), who accuses the field
of no longer advancing a viable, coherent, and
legitimate body of knowledge. This skepticism
about the future of the field has been affirmed
by others, including Anne Hendershott, who
argues in her book The Politics of Deviance (2002)
that scholars have romanticized deviant behavior;
and by J. Mitchell Miller, Richard Wright, and
David Dannels in their article “Is Deviance
‘Dead?’” (2001). On the other hand, Erich Goode
has pointed out in several articles and in his popular textbook Deviant Behavior (1994) that practitioners of the sociology of deviance continue to
teach graduate and undergraduate courses on the
topic across the United States and abroad.
Arguably, Alexander Liazos’s strident critique in
1972 of the sociology of deviance as the impoverished study of “nuts, sluts, and perverts” has been
overcome by what continues to be a vibrant and
exciting field that remains intimately connected
to larger sociological concerns. Influential scholars continue to write articles and books that offer
new and improved approaches to the study of
deviance. For example, Charles Tittle and Raymond Paternoster’s book Social Deviance and Crime:
An Organizational and Theoretical Approach (2000)
calls for an organizational approach to deviance.
In addition, others call for approaches to the
sociology of deviance that integrate normative
and reactionist frameworks and build more flexible and inclusive definitions of the term deviance
(see Alex Heckert and Druann Maria Heckert’s
article “A New Typology of Deviance: Integrating
Normative and Reactivist Definitions of Deviance,” Deviant Behavior, 2002). Finally, leading scholars specializing in deviance, including Jack Katz
and Christopher Williams, have encouraged colleagues to recognize that engaging in deviance
and crime can be fun and exciting, perhaps even
creative and artistic. As these calls for reform circulate, the sociological study of deviance continues to be integrated with other areas of
sociology, most notably criminology, the study of
social stratification, community, queer theory,
moral panics, and social movements.
VALERIE JENNESS AND PHILIP GOODMAN
deviance disavowal
– see deviance.
deviancy
– see deviance.
deviancy amplification
– see deviance.
deviancy drift
– see deviance.
deviant behavior
– see deviance.
deviant case analysis
Perhaps one of the clearest instances of the differentiation of quantitative and qualitative
approaches in sociology is the treatment of deviant cases in a dataset. Anomalous cases in the
quantitative tradition are regarded as sources of
error, bias, or “noise,” tend to be termed “outliers” and are, if not deleted, “transformed” until
they approach “normality” prior to statistical analysis. In contrast, in qualitative work, particularly
in the sub-disciplines of ethnomethodology and
conversational analysis (CA), deviant cases are
actively cherished for their potentially crucial
analytic import.
These qualitative approaches, which were originally inspired by Harold Garfinkel’s Studies in
Ethnomethodology (1967), analyse “breaches” in the
mundane social order in which the exception
may illuminate an otherwise-taken-for-granted,
and hence “invisible,” rule. The analysis of cases/
instances that seem to run counter to established
patterns or theoretical claims has become a canonical methodological procedure in ethnomethodology and CA, and in variants of discursive
psychology which draw upon this heritage. The
analysis of deviant cases is designed, then, in
order to get at, in Garfinkel’s terms, the “seenbut-unnoticed background features” of everyday
life.
Thus, given contemporary ethical constraints
on real-life “breaching experiments,” investigators
will actively search for naturally occurring
breaches of conventionally normative social conduct. An example can be taken from Alec McHoul
and Mark Rapley’s “Should we make a start then?:
A Strange Case of a (Delayed) Client-Initiated Psychological Assessment” (2002, Research on Language
and Social Interaction, 35). This case involved the
study of the initiation of a psychological test by
the testee rather than, as would normatively be
141
dialectical materialism
expected, by the tester. Deviant case analysis may,
alternatively, involve – for example – combing a
dataset of telephone-call openings. Emmanuel
A. Schegloff, in “Sequencing in Conversational
Openings” (1968, American Anthropologist 70),
looked for the single instance (that is deviant
case) out of a collection of 500 in which a social
actor (“member”) broke the putative rule that
“answerer speaks first,” to develop a more sophisticated theoretical account. Thus, in Schegloff’s
research, the analysis of the deviant case showed
that it did, in fact, lend support to a higher-order
theoretical conception of “summons–answer”
sequences. Similarly, the McHoul and Rapley
study supported the work of Harvey Sacks in his
two-volume Lectures on Conversation (1995). Through
an analysis of the breach of the normative conventions of membership in asymmetric social categories, Sacks’s account of the conditions under
which an omni-relevant device for conversation
may be theoretically inferred were, in fact, empirically demonstrable.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
dialectical materialism
– see Marxism.
diaspora
A term originally applied to the experience of a
people dispersed from their original homeland for
long periods, yet who retain cultural memories
and ties, diaspora has gained increasing currency
to describe a host of such peoples in a world in
which movement and flight are common. While
the term was traditionally applied to the stateless
Jewish people, among the most important diaspora communities today are, ironically, the Palestinians displaced from their homeland with the
formation of the Jewish state of Israel, thus pitting
two diasporic communities against each other.
The modern world has seen numerous largescale migrations, forcible and voluntary, from
the African slave trade, to the movement of the
Irish during the potato famine and thereafter.
Today, the experience of the African and Irish
diasporas form important components of the blossoming field of diaspora studies. Sociologist Paul
Gilroy coined the influential term The Black Atlantic
(1995) to capture the African diaspora experience,
while Irish scholars now use the term “The Green
Atlantic.” Increasingly, with globalization, there
are transnational diaspora communities – including those fleeing war and poverty – of overseas
migrants and citizens whose resources are
critical to those left in their home countries.
142
differentiation
Thus, diaspora communities, from the experience
of Puerto Ricans, Salvadorans, or Latinos as a
whole, are today proliferating. And with the
ascent of East Asia and China in the contemporary
global economy, there has also been increased
attention paid to the (often wealthy) Chinese
diaspora community in East Asian and Chinese
development.
THOMAS REIFER
diasporic studies
– see diaspora.
differential association
– see deviance.
differentiation
The differentiation of tasks in society – or the
division of labor – is a central focus of sociology.
Sociologists have studied the effects of increasing
specialization and complexity and have classified
societies in terms of the nature and level of
differentiation.
During the Scottish Enlightenment, writers like
Adam Ferguson (1723–1816) and John Millar
(1735–1801) distinguished four sociologically distinct stages of society: hunters and gatherers;
shepherd or pastoral society; husbandmen or agricultural society; and commercial society. Karl
Marx’s materialist theory of history represents
social development in terms of successive modes
of production. Marx introduces the idea that
social differentiation is associated with inequality
and that conflict among social classes is one of
the principal motors of social change.
Functionalism provides an alternative account
of differentiation, concerned with the problem of
interdependence among the parts of a differentiated system. Émile Durkheim set out a model
of types of societies from elementary to more
complex types. The two poles of this continuum
were respectively characterized by mechanical
and organic forms of solidarity. Talcott Parsons
expanded this scheme with a full theory of structural differentiation, where the four functional
imperatives that all societies must meet allows a
classification of societies in terms of the degree of
institutional specialization around each of the
functions these four functions were called the
pattern variables, relating to the economy, polity,
value system, and motivation that all societies
must satisfy.
Many sociologists became suspicious of the
emphasis on linear development and the teleological implications of both Marxian and functionalist approaches. Feminist theory criticized each
digital divide
disability and impairment
approach for the neglect of the sexual division
of labor and the role of gender inequalities in
capitalist modernity. Postmodern sociologists
have emphasized the possibility of dedifferentiation as well as forms of hyperdifferentiation.
JOHN HOLMWOOD
digital divide
As the internet has grown in scope and usefulness,
so too has concern about equitable access to its
services and benefits, especially to information.
The term digital divide is a catch-all phrase to
cover many perspectives addressing equity issues
in terms of the way mediated electronic communication and information resources are available
to, or used by, various groups. The emphasis is on
disparities among groups.
An early digital-divide concern, which came to
particular prominence in the late 1980s, was over
computer access. Computer access was seen as
being mal-distributed along gender lines. Some
felt that, since males were by far the heaviest
users, aggressive intervention programs were
needed to boost female participation. Although
varied programs were launched to interest girls
in careers in computer science, little appear to
have been accomplished. A similar concern
regarding gender was expressed in the early era
of the internet, when males were heavy adopters.
However, over time, advancing ease of use and
engaging content alone appear to have solved
this “divide” as women have become as heavily
involved in online activities as men. While there
is some variation, such as women appearing to be
more interested in online social interaction than
are men, this dimension of concern over a possible
digital divide has largely disappeared.
Yet gender is but one of a series of other possible
digital divides reflecting various inequities. These
would include mal-distributions along lines of
geographic, racial/ethnic, economic, institutional,
age, educational, religious, and handicapped status. In many ways, there appears to be little about
these “divides” that is uniquely digital. The very
factors that might create a digital divide have
already acted to create other opportunity divides.
For instance, digital-divide concerns along international dimensions is actually a subset of the
already existing inequality between “rich nations”
and “poor nations.” Also, from a practical viewpoint, conceptual distinctions in access to digital
resources are multiple and overlapping. At the
same time, there are some interesting ways that
the politics of the issue play out. While there is
broad public concern over inequitable access to
internet resources, similar inequalities in access
to mobile communication resources command little attention. This is true despite the fact that it
may be that mobile communication resources are
more important economically to those on the
margins of the global system than to those at the
core.
In terms of geographic digital divides, there are
stubborn problems of unequal distribution of
information and other resources, with rural and
less densely populated areas not keeping up with
their urban counterparts. In addition, poorer
areas tend to be less well-served with information
and other resources. Much has been made of perceived racial/ethnic inequalities, and these concerns are frequently accompanied by far-reaching
program proposals. While it is true that certain
racial/ethnic minorities are underrepresented in
the online world, it is equally true that others are
“overrepresented.” Interestingly, when educational achievement is considered, it is generally
the case that the racial/ethnic divide disappears.
Put differently, people with low education are the
ones who have low participation rates, rather than
there being something unique or disinclining
about their cultural characteristics that prevent
members of that culture from using the internet.
There are enormous differences internationally
among usage levels of the internet. These also
seem to be a result of international inequalities
of income and productivity, as well as local telecommunication pricing policies. Although the
internet was seen originally as a solution to the
gap between the rich and poor countries, it now
appears that many international aid bodies feel
that efforts are no longer necessary to try to wire
the less-developed countries. As J. Katz and R. Rice
show in Social Consequences of Internet Use (2002),
mobile communication, especially via cell phones,
is seen as an avenue for economic progress in
developing countries.
JAMES E. KATZ
diploma disease
– see credentialism.
disability and impairment
Both terms, which are culturally specific and contested, are used to designate a particular relationship of the individual to bodily norms and to
society in general. Disability has different meanings in different cultures, and in many western
countries legislative definitions of disability have
become increasingly complex, because they result
in the provision of rehabilitation services or
welfare payments to disabled people. Indeed, the
143
disability and impairment
definitions adopted by western governments have
changed so often that one can argue that disability
is basically defined by public policy, and therefore
disability is socially produced by policy decisions.
In the traditional medical literature, impairment is defined as the inability of a physiological
or body system to perform the function for which
it was designed. A functional loss occurs when an
impairment limits a person’s ability to perform
basic functional activities like climbing stairs,
running, or jumping. Disability is present when
the functional loss limits a person’s ability to
ambulate, do daily self-care activities, perform
the duties of a parent, work and function in
society.
Scholars in the United States and United Kingdom objected to this “medicalized” view of disability because it focused on individual limitations
and deficiencies, not on the larger environment.
In the British version of the social model of disability, impairment is the term used to refer to
medical conditions, or differences from normal
bodily or cognitive functioning, and disability
refers to the social reactions to impairment, particularly experiences of discrimination, oppression,
social exclusion, and marginalization.
Today, it is evident that disability cannot be
simply reduced to a medical or biological definition nor located entirely in the environment.
From an ecological perspective, disability is
defined not only by the biology of the injury or
disease, but more significantly by the interaction
between biology and an individual’s physical,
social, economic, and political environment, as
well as by the demands of the person’s physical,
social, and occupational activities. Disability is a
physical condition and social experience that is
not necessarily permanent and can be modified,
if its determinants can be altered.
Dealing with impairment can be a very difficult
experience, because it often involves admitting
vulnerabilities, revealing intimate or private bodily details, and dealing with unexpected biographical disruptions. Every impairment has its own
unique features, but there are four important factors affecting the way an individual responds to
their impairments: the age at which a person
acquires impairment, the visibility of the impairment, the degree to which others comprehend the
impairment, and the influence of illness. The
social acceptability of the impairment is also
important – some types of impairment are far
more stigmatized than others.
This distinction between impairment and disability, which is at the heart of the social model
144
disability and impairment
of disability, is valuable because it emphasizes the
need to remove the barriers, discrimination, negative images, and lack of opportunities which many
disabled people experience. Access is fundamental
to the construction (and contestation) of disability. There is a sense in which every discrimination
can be seen as a problem about access: access to an
equal, unhindered social role. Social restrictions
and discrimination are a central part of the
experience of disability for people with any sort
of impairment. Regardless of whether these barriers stem from inaccessible built environments,
proscriptive notions of intelligence, the inability
of the public to communicate using sign language, a failure to provide resources in accessible
formats, or the discrimination experienced by
people with invisible impairments, these experiences have a negative social dimension which can
be addressed in the creation of a more just and
equitable society.
A medical model of disability might suggest
that such problems with access are caused by
an individual pathology, but the social model
of disability which is favored by disability rights
activists and by disability studies suggests that
the unaccommodating nature of the environment is to blame. The politicization of access
issues could therefore be seen as one of the great
benefits of distinguishing between impairment
and disability in this way. Understood through
a social model, disability is not an individual
trait, it is a social construction constantly made
and remade through beliefs, practices, institutions, environments, and behavior. In this vein,
disability is produced by the perception of
physical, mental, and emotional variation. The
implication is that non-disabling environments
and patterns of behavior can be developed – if
disabled people have rights, support, recognition,
and self-determination.
A British group, the Union of Physically
Impaired Against Segregation (UPIAS), was particularly influential in promoting the distinction
between impairment and disability and in defining disability as a form of oppression. UPIAS has
argued that it is society which disables physically
impaired people. Disability is something which
is imposed on top of existing impairments by the
ways in which people with impairment are unnecessarily isolated and excluded from full social
participation. Disabled people are consequently
an oppressed social group. In order to understand
this situation, it is necessary to recognize the distinction between physical impairment and the
social situation called the “disability” of people
disability and impairment
with such impairments. Impairment is defined as
lacking part of or all of a limb, or having a defective limb, organ, or mechanism of the body, while
disability is the disadvantage or restriction of
activity caused by contemporary social arrangements. Disability occurs when social institutions
take little or no account of people who have physical impairments, thereby excluding them from
participation in the mainstream social activities.
Physical disability is a particular type of social
oppression.
Although the initial definition of disability provided by UPIAS focused on people with physical
impairments, it was subsequently broadened to
include other impairments. The UPIAS definition
of impairment and disability has become well
known, partly due to the fact that a leading disabled academic, Mike Oliver, has consistently
relied on them in his work, but also because other
academics have accepted these definitions.
An important element of the UPIAS approach to
disability was the promotion of self-determination. UPIAS has rejected the idea of experts and
professionals holding forth on how people
should accept disabilities, or providing academic
lectures about the psychology of impairment. In
contrast, UPIAS argues that they are interested in
finding ways to change their own conditions
of life, thereby overcoming the disabilities which
are imposed over and above existing physical
impairments.
This approach identifies disabled people as the
experts on their own lives, and has given many
disabled people the confidence to challenge the
barriers and negative attitudes which they experience in their daily lives. Instead of the sense of
powerlessness, dependency, and shame which
may result from the medical model of disability,
such an approach gives disabled people a sense of
confidence, empowerment, and removes feelings
of shame, stigma, and guilt from discussions of
access requirements.
The central element of this approach to disability is its emphasis on the need to remove the
barriers that prevent people with impairments
from taking their rightful roles in society. The
essential message is that, although disabled people may have significant bodily, cognitive, or psychological differences which distinguish them
from non-disabled people, those differences do
not justify inequality and should not result in
the denial of citizenship rights. Society creates
many of the problems that disabled people experience and society has a responsibility to address
them. Thus it is suggested that it is impossible to
discourse analysis
identify the number of disabled people in a
society. From the perspective of the social model
of disability, people are only disabled by an environment which does not meet their needs. There
is no fixed number of disabled people, because
people with impairments may not be disabled
in every context.
MARK SHERRY AND GARY L. ALBRECHT
discourse
– see discourse analysis.
discourse analysis
An omnibus term to describe a wide range of
socio-cultural analytic perspectives developed in
the aftermath of the linguistic turn in the social
sciences during the 1960s, at the broadest level,
the domain of discourse analysis encompasses the
study of language use beyond the level of the
sentence or utterance, in relation to social or societal context. In this broad conception, discourse
analysis embraces both speech and interaction
and written texts as objects of study.
Much of Anglophone discourse analysis stems
from the widespread influence of the “ordinary
language philosophy” practiced by John L. Austin
(1911–60) and John Searle (1932– ). This perspective was elaborated in opposition to the notion
that the primary function of language is representational. Austin in How to Do Things with Words
(1962) at first argued that language use involves
both “constative utterances” (that represent states
of affairs) and “performatives” (for example, “I
now pronounce you man and wife”) which function to perform social actions and which only do
so if certain normative conventions are satisfied.
Subsequently Austin concluded that speech mingles the performance of actions with the predication of states of affairs, and this theme was given
more formal expression in Searle’s development
of “speech act analysis” in Speech Acts (1979).
At the same time Anglophone discourse analysis
has embraced the notion that language use embodies indexical properties which ensure that the
meaning-making process will inevitably involve
the use of the relationship between utterance
and context to elaborate the meanings of social
actions. These basic ideas have been developed in
several distinctive intellectual and disciplinary
contexts. In linguistics, H. Paul Grice (1913–88)
created the theory of “conversational implicature”
(implicit meaning derived from construing what
is said explicitly in relation to social context).
Based on the notion that cooperative conversation
is organized in terms of a number of basic
145
discourse analysis
principles that license inferences about the communication of meaning, this theory has been
highly important in the development of linguistic
pragmatics which incorporates the analysis of
speech acts, presupposition, “deixis,” and related
topics. In anthropology, Dell Hymes (1927– ) built
on the theory of speech acts to develop a broader
model of the ethnography of speaking, based on
sixteen dimensions of a speech event. This marks a
departure from the traditional anthropological
emphasis on documenting and preserving threatened indigenous languages, and towards a focus
on the relationship between language, culture,
and the use of speech acts within given communities and activities. Moreover, it does so with the
provision of an anthropologically informed sense
of the variety of language games that may be
sustained within a given culture. In sociology,
Erving Goffman’s conception of social interaction
as driven by normatively mediated face wants was
a proximate source both for the development of
conversational analysis, and for the development
of a theory of positive and negative face in Penelope Brown and Stephen Levinson’s highly influential cross-linguistic analysis of face-threatening
behavior and politeness.
In all the forms of discourse analysis described
so far, the fundamental research effort is to isolate the endogenous norms, practices, and reasoning which inform the participants’ construction
and interpretation of social interaction. Other
forms of discourse analysis, in particular critical
discourse analysis, approach the analysis of text
and interaction by examining them in relation to
power and ideology and to the perpetuation of
race-based, gender-based, and other forms of disadvantage and social exclusion. While this
method has been applied to social interaction,
some of its most successful manifestations have
emerged in the analysis of written texts such as
newspaper articles, political directives, and so on.
This work has links to the broader poststructuralist discourse analysis associated with Michel
Foucault, Fredric Jameson (1934– ), Stuart Hall,
and others. Moreover, in its focus on text and
other forms of cultural production (including
art, film, and television), this form of discourse
analysis has clear affinities with broader trends
in cultural and semiotic analysis.
The emergence of discourse analysis has coincided with a new emphasis on narrative as a vehicle for the communication of basic human
understandings, as a basic form in which human
knowledge is stored and represented, and as a
means of socialization, memory, empathy, and
146
disorganized capitalism
catharsis. Vladimir Propp’s analysis of Russian
fairy tales in his Morphology of the Folk Tale (1969)
was among the first efforts to subject narrative to
systematic description and it has been followed by
many others which analyze narrative as a sociolinguistic, conversational, cultural, and artistic
process. In this way narrative analysis has become
a major site at which many forms of discourse
analysis converge, ranging from the microanalytic study of story-telling as situated action,
to macrocultural analyses of the narratives of political decisionmaking and warfare, and the historical narratives of imagined communities.
JOHN HERITAGE
discrimination
This is a social practice that organizes prejudicial
attitudes into the formal or informal segregation
of social groups or classes stigmatized by the collective prejudice. The earliest use of the word in
the English language was in the sense of “to discriminate” as to cultural taste, for example in
Pierre Bourdieu’s Distinction (1979 [trans. 1984]).
Discrimination can therefore be defined, sociologically, as a practice whereby the cultural tastes of a
dominant group or social class are projected negatively on groups or classes they consider inferior.
Discrimination presents as a cultural attitude but
is organized and sustained as a structural effect
with legal, social, and economic consequences.
The term is commonly associated with racial
discrimination, but discrimination has also come
to be used as a general term to denote any discriminatory practice of sufficient structural durability to exclude classes of people from economic
opportunities, political rights, or social freedoms;
for example, the 1964 US Civil Rights Act, while
directed primarily at racial discrimination, was
broadly conceived to end discrimination with
respect to race, color, religion, sex (gender), or
national origin. Discriminatory beliefs and actions
are rooted in everyday-life attitudes and social
practices, usually ones backed by a long tradition.
They are, therefore, so embedded in the local or
regional culture that they are difficult to define
legally and sociologically: for example, the distinction between racial and ethnic discrimination, the
reluctance to take gender discrimination seriously, and the outright hostility to legislation
aimed at eliminating discrimination on the basis
of sexualities.
CHARLES LEMERT
disorganized capitalism
– see capitalism.
distribution
distribution
This refers to the nature of any variable that is
collected as part of a quantitative research
method. For instance, it could be measures of the
income of individuals, the levels of crimes of cities
or the health differences between nations. But a
statistician’s approach to examining a distribution of a variable is the same regardless of
whether we are measuring health or wealth, or
whether our units (or cases) are individuals or
countries. When we examine any distribution,
there are four key aspects that should be examined. If any of them are missed, the sociologist
risks missing some important features of the data.
These features are the central tendency, the
spread, the shape, and outliers.
The expression “central tendency” is a summary
of the average value in the data. Most commonly
this is calculated with the mean, although in
many cases the median gives a better typical
value. The mean is calculated by summing all of
the cases, and dividing by the number of cases.
The median is obtained by rank-ordering the
cases, and taking the value of the middle case.
For categorical variables, the mode (the most commonly occurring category) is the most common
measure of central tendency.
Although less obvious, sociologists are often
more interested in how spread out, or heterogeneous, the cases are. For instance, amongst the
richest few dozen countries in the world, the nature of the societies and the quality of life of the
citizens seems to vary surprisingly little with the
mean level of income. But the spread of incomes –
that is the size of the gap between the richest and
poorest, seems to have a greater effect on outcomes such as health and average life expectancy.
Often sociologists and statisticians pay too much
attention to averages, and neglect the spread of
data. There are a number of measures of spread,
the common ones being the standard deviation
and the midspread (aka the interquartile range).
Many statistical tests assume that, when the
data are plotted in a histogram, they will form a
bell-shaped curve, also called the normal or the
Gaussian distribution. In practice, few sociological
variables actually form such a neat distribution –
so to call it a normal curve is somewhat of a
misnomer. For instance, the distribution of hourly
income in most countries is very skewed, with a
long upwards straggle towards the small number
of employees with very high incomes, while most
people’s wages are slightly below the mean. And if
one plots weekly hours of work, one obtains a
double consciousness
“bimodal” graph, with one peak around full-time
(36-40 hours) and the other peak around half-time
(20 hours). In such cases the shape of the distribution tells one far more than the average value.
In many sociological measures, a small number
of cases on “outliers” seem to be very different
from all the others. For instance, if one counted
the number of sexual partners that individuals
had over the past twelve months, many people
would score 0 or 1, but a small proportion would
have had dozens or hundreds of sexual partners in
that time – for instance, prostitutes. Pooling all of
the cases to calculate an average would be misleading. For some analyses, it would be appropriate to exclude those extreme cases, called outliers.
In other cases, the research might learn more
from those cases that deviate from the norm, the
exceptions that prove the rule. But beware, those
extreme cases often arise because of some error in
the research!
To summarize, it is good practice in sociological
research to investigate all four of these aspects of
any distribution.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
division of labor
– see labor.
divorce
– see marriage and divorce.
domestic labor
– see labor.
domestic violence
– see family.
double consciousness
A theory of black consciousness in the United
States that is associated with the sociology of
W. E. B. Du Bois, who was influenced in his analysis of white–black relationships in America by
G. W. E. Hegel’s description of the master–slave
relationship. For Hegel, the master and the slave
cannot enter into a relationship of mutual recognition and respect because they are separated by a
relationship of absolute power. Du Bois argued in
The Souls of Black Folk (1961: 16) that the black man
always has consciousness of himself through the
consciousness of the white man, and thus “[i]t is a
peculiar sensation, this double-consciousness, this
sense of always looking at one’s self through the
eyes of the others, of measuring one’s soul by the
tape of a world that looks on in amused contempt
and pity.” The black man’s consciousness had
147
double shift
been destroyed by the experience of slavery, and
Du Bois proposed an educational reform that
would begin to restore self-respect and hence
self-consciousness.
BRYAN S. TURNER
double shift
– see family.
Douglas, Mary (1921– )
A former student at Oxford and biographer of E. E.
Evans-Pritchard (1902–73), Douglas is the most
widely influential British anthropologist of the
second half of the twentieth century. She conducted her original fieldwork among the Lele of
present-day Zaire, but from the 1960s onward her
expertise in the ethnography of Africa has been
put to broader comparative purposes. Two thematics dominate her mature work. The first is
the social-organizational determination of perception, classification, and cosmology. The second is
the dynamic tension between social order and selfinterest. Both thematics come to her from Émile
Durkheim through Evans-Pritchard’s mediation.
Analytically, she remains virtually the only Durkheimian purist writing in anthropology today.
Critically, she tends to favor hierarchy more vigorously and to take greedy individualist self-interest
to task more readily than even Durkheim was ever
inclined to do. She is comparable in this respect to
her British-trained contemporary, Louis Dumont.
Her own biographer, Richard Fardon (Mary Douglas:
An Intellectual Biography, 1999), attributes such
“sociological conservatism” less, however, to her
postsecondary training than to her continuing
devotion to the Catholicism into which she was
born.
Purity and Danger (1966) and Natural Symbols:
Explorations in Cosmology are the double centerpiece of her theoretical program. In the earlier
work, she argues that any given society’s collective preoccupations with purity and pollution are
the more salient the more its moral system is
ambiguous or paradoxical. In the later work,
noticeably but not fundamentally revised from
its first (1970) to its second (1973) edition, she
postulates that the intersection of the variable
intensities of the two general dimensions of social
control that she names “grid” and “group” operate
on the ever-ready semiotic vehicle of the human
body to generate distinctive pairings of the expression of the self and the imagination of the cosmos.
In tandem, these works join Pierre Bourdieu’s Outline of a Theory of Practice (1970 [trans. 1977]) as
contemporary foundations of the anthropology
148
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1868–1963)
of the body and as productive challenges to the
sociological insensitivity of many of the applications of phenomenological hermeneutics in cultural and in religious studies. They are also the
point of departure for her own further research
into such diverse topics as dietary prescriptions
and proscriptions; the patterns and the teleologies
of consumption (in The World of Goods, with Baron
Isherwood, 1978) and the correlative definition of
lifestyles; and the study of dietetics and dietary
theology that are the focus of her last work to
date, Leviticus as Literature (1999). Douglas has largely lived in and worked on the society of the
United States since moving there in 1977. She
subsequently collaborated with Aaron Wildavsky
in writing Risk and Culture (1982), a somewhat
unflattering portrait of the ecological anxieties
and opportunistic activism of the American middle classes that, unsurprisingly, was not well
received in the United States itself. After the
1970s and in the midst of several forays into the
epistemology of the social sciences and the sociology of epistemology, her most systematic refinement of her theoretical commitments remains
JAMES D. FAUBION
How Institutions Think (1986).
dramaturgical analysis
– see Erving Goffman.
drug abuse
– see addiction.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1868–1963)
A historian, sociologist, race man, social theorist,
poet, journalist, political and civil rights leader, in
his time, William Edward Burghardt Du Bois was
ignored by white-dominated official sociology in
the United States. Yet, as the segregation of blacks
subsided, Du Bois emerged as one of the most
original academic sociologists of the twentieth
century.
Du Bois was born in Great Barrington, Massachusetts, in 1868, in the years following the
American Civil War. In this small New England
town, he was accepted in the local schools and
excelled as a pupil. His higher education began
in 1885 at Fisk University in Nashville, where for
the first time he encountered the vicious racism of
the American South; he then studied at Harvard
and in Germany (1892–4) before earning his PhD
at Harvard. His doctoral thesis, The Suppression of
the African Slave-Trade to the United States of America,
1638–1870, became the first of his published scholarly books in 1896. Du Bois began his academic
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1868–1963)
career at Wilberforce University (1894–6) before
accepting a research position at the University of
Pennsylvania. There he did the exhaustive fieldwork
on Philadelphia’s Negro community which led to
The Philadelphia Negro (1899), the first important
urban ethnography in America by an American.
Shortly after, Du Bois published the book that
established his reputation as a major social thinker and writer, and a fresh voice in American
racial politics, Souls of Black Folk (1903). Souls is
best known for its poetic description of the double
consciousness (or “twoness”) concept that
appeared in its lead essay: “One ever feels his
twoness, – an American, a Negro; two souls, two
thoughts, two unreconciled strivings; two warring
ideals in one dark body, whose dogged strength
alone keeps it from being torn asunder.” The double-consciousness idea exerted its influence late in
the twentieth century as a model for postfeminist
social theories of the self as comprising a number
of conflicting identities shaped from a matrix of
domination (for example Patricia Hill Collins,
Black Feminist Thought, 1990). Souls of Black Folk also
introduced the cultural and political theory of
racial uplift as led by a talented tenth of highly
educated black leaders. Du Bois’s emphasis on
cultural training set him at odds with the thenreigning race-leader in the United States, Booker
T. Washington (1856–1910), founder of the Tuskegee Institute in Alabama. Washington’s program
for racial uplift was based on the agricultural and
industrial education of poor blacks. From 1895,
when Washington declared his Atlanta Compromise (that blacks would work with whites economically, but keep themselves socially separate),
until his death in 1915, Booker T. Washington
was anointed by whites as the spokesman for
blacks in America. In “On Mr. Booker T. Washington and Others” (also in Souls), Du Bois directly
challenged Washington’s philosophy. Thus began
a political feud that would last until Washington’s
influence began to wane after 1910, the year
Du Bois joined in the founding of the NAACP
(National Association for the Advancement of
Colored People).
In 1910, Du Bois left his academic position at
Atlanta University, which he had held since 1897,
to work in New York City with the NAACP. He
immediately founded Crisis magazine, which
soon became, under his editorial leadership, the
most widely read news and literary paper in black
America. He continued in this work until 1934
when his authority as Washington’s successor as
the foremost Negro leader in the United States fell
under attack.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1868–1963)
Du Bois’s 25-year association with the NAACP
was always uneasy. He was temperamentally a
man of firm ideas and methods. He did not suffer
fools gladly, especially those who kowtowed (as
Washington had) to powerful whites. Throughout
these years in New York, Du Bois continued to
write prolifically, to engage in political commentary and direct action, and to assert his lifelong
commitment to the importance of culture (notably
as a leader in the Harlem Renaissance of the
1920s).
Du Bois’s career as an academic sociologist was
split into two parts, both at Atlanta University. In
the early years (1897–1910), he taught economics
and history while engaged in empirical sociological research. In addition to The Philadelphia Negro,
Du Bois conducted a series of field studies of rural
Negro communities in the South. Max Weber
attended one of the conferences on these studies
during his 1904 visit to the United States. Du
Bois’s second academic career was as Chair of the
Department of Sociology at Atlanta (1934–44).
Though he was in his eighth decade of life, Du
Bois returned to sociological scholarship with the
vigor of a young man. It was in this period that he
completed his most important work of historical
sociology.
Black Reconstruction (1935) is increasingly recognized today as a brilliant structural sociology of
social change in the United States after the Civil
War. The book attacked the history profession’s
then current attitude that the failure of Reconstruction (1863–77) was a failure of the freed
Negroes to make economic and social progress.
Du Bois responded in sharply sociological terms
that demonstrated that the freed people had
made remarkable progress given the structural
constraints. The three and a half million freed
Negroes, as a class, were trapped in a structural
conflict between the poor white workers and the
planter class. Planters ultimately restored their
economic dominance after 1877 by using the
poor whites as political pawns to pressure the
federal government to give up Reconstruction.
The poor whites were, in effect, granted the
higher racial status in compensation for their economic misery. This has been called the racial wage
by David Roediger in Wages of Whiteness (1991). The
genius of Du Bois’s concept was that it was empirical, structural, and historical sociology that
explained a local practice (segregation) as an element in the social structures of the post-Civil-War
South.
Du Bois died in 1963, in Accra, Ghana, in exile
from the United States he had sought to redeem in
149
dual economy
Duncan, Otis Dudley (1921–2004)
his youth. The civil rights movements of the 1960s
brought Du Bois’s ideas into currency. He earned a
place in history as much for his political work as
for his scholarship and writing. C H A R L E S L E M E R T
dual economy
Dual economy models were developed to challenge unilinear accounts of capitalist development, by emphasizing the persistent importance
of areas of economic activity that do not involve
large-scale corporations, mass production, or even
formal market relations. One example, from development studies, concerned the coexistence of an
informal subsistence economy with a formal plantation economy. Another addressed the persistence of small-scale enterprises and low-paid
work alongside the business alliances and internal
welfare regimes of corporate capitalism, as in R. T.
Averitt’s analysis of The Dual Economy (1968) in the
United States, and N. Chalmers’s analysis of Industrial Relations in Japan (1989). Here, dualism
between types of firm was matched by labor market dualism, as large firms utilized primary, and
small firms, secondary, labor markets.
The critical power of these analyses depends
on explaining the survival of the subordinate
economy in terms of its role for the dominant
economy, by absorbing surplus labor or providing
low-cost production capacity. However, such
dependencies have been specified in quite varied
ways, with different implications for the dynamics and persistence of dualism. For example,
M. J. Piore and C. F. Sabel, in The Second Industrial
Divide (1984), portray the erstwhile subordinate
small-firm sector as a potential challenger to
large-scale mass production. Dual economy models also rest on clear contrasts in the organization
and dynamics of the two economies, but specifications of the interlinkages and dependencies
between them often lead to more differentiated
accounts of production chains and hierarchies of
employment conditions. This moves away from a
clear dualism, but still addresses the processes
that may sustain differentiation and uneven development in capitalist economies over time.
TONY ELGER
Louis Dumont (1911–1998)
A student of Marcel Mauss, his early work was on
French festivals, about which he published an ethnographic study of La Tarasque (1951). He made a
major contribution to the analysis of Indian social
structure in Homo Hierarchicus. The Caste System and
its Implications (1972) and Religion, Politics and History in India. Collected Papers in Indian Sociology
150
(1970). He also wrote on ideologies of equality
and individualism in western societies in From
Mandeville to Marx. The Genesis and Triumph of Economic Ideology (1977) and Essays on Individualism.
Modern Ideology in Anthropological Perspective (1986).
He contrasted the hierarchical caste society of
India, with its emphasis on the social whole over
the individual, and western society where the
social whole is subordinated to the individual.
Following the tradition of French structuralism,
Dumont wanted to uncover the underlying principle of caste, which he argued was the contrast
between pure and impure. Caste hierarchy was
founded on this dichotomous principle. By “hierarchy,” Dumont did not mean social stratification.
Rather, hierarchy explains a relation of opposites
that can nevertheless cohere within a cultural
unity. Dumont’s contrast between holism and
individualism has become an important aspect of
BRYAN S. TURNER
the debate with Orientalism.
Duncan, Otis Dudley (1921–2004)
Completing his PhD at the University of Chicago
in 1949, Duncan was a member of the Faculty
at Penn State University, and the universities of
Wisconsin, Chicago, Michigan, Arizona, and California, Santa Barbara. His most influential publication was with Peter M. Blau on The American
Occupational Structure (1967) which received the
American Sociological Association Sorokin Award
for the most distinguished scholarly publication
in 1968. Using the first large national survey
of social mobility in the United States, Blau and
Duncan showed how parents transmit their social
standing to their children mainly by influencing
their children’s education. Their approach to
social mobility showed that mobility takes the
form of small rather than dramatic steps up
the social ladder. In addition to its substantive
findings, The American Occupational Structure
showed how an important sociological topic could
be analyzed rigorously with appropriate quantitative methods. Through his exploration of path
analysis, Duncan contributed to the development
and use of structural equation models in the
social sciences. He invented a measure of social
standing of occupations – the Duncan Socioeconomic Index. He also developed an index of residential segregation between blacks and whites in
Chicago. He was President of the Population
Association of America in 1968–9. He published
Notes on Social Measurement (1984), Statistical Geography: Problems in Analysing Areal Data (1961), and
with H. Pfautz he translated M. Halbwach’s Population and Society: Introduction to Social Morphology. His
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
general argument was that quantitative sociology
summarized empirical patterns in between-group
differences, while temporarily ignoring the pattern of within-group individual differences.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
Generally considered as one of the founding
fathers of sociology, and by some as the sociologist par excellence, Durkheim labored to establish
the intellectual distinctiveness and significance of
the discipline and to charter it as a fully legitimate component of academia. The following
account of his thought is focused on four books
that are conventionally considered the most
significant.
Born in 1858 to a Jewish family, in the French
town Epinay (Lorraine), Durkheim witnessed as an
adolescent the defeat of the Second Empire in the
Franco-Prussian War and the subsequent tragedy
of the Paris Commune. In 1879–82, at the École
Normale Supérieure, in Paris, he studied chiefly
philosophy and history. Subsequently he taught
philosophy in a lycée, but five years later joined
the faculty at the University of Bordeaux. His
teaching subject was the philosophy of education,
but early on he coupled it with “social science”
and later with “sociology.”
At the time, in France and in other parts of
Europe, sociology was cultivated by intellectuals
and scholars, but was not accepted as an academic
discipline. Durkheim gave the first major demonstration of his own understanding of it, and of its
entitlement to recognition and institutionalization, in his massive doctoral dissertation The
Division of Labour in Society (1893 [trans. 1933]).
Targeting a phenomenon which had been and
was being thematized chiefly by economists, Division agreed with them that the division of labor
was a most significant phenomenon, particularly
so in modern society. He also agreed with the
social Darwinist view of the division of labor
(put forward principally by Herbert Spencer) as
the human variant of a universal biological
process, the progression from simple forms of
life to differentiated, complex ones.
Durkheim, however, rejected what later came to
be called the utilitarian interpretation of the
causes and consequences of the division of labor.
He believed that the causes could not lie, as Spencer had claimed, in the individual’s pursuit of
his own egoistic advantage through increasingly
specialized, and thus increasingly efficient and
competitive, activity. The division of labor had
taken off originally in societies so simple and so
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
cohesive that their members did not conceive of
themselves as possessing interests of their own, to
be pursued at their own behest and initiative.
That all early human societies were so constituted was indicated, according to Durkheim, by
the way they typically responded to violations of
their norms. That response took the form of punitive sanctions, of inflictions of pain on the violators by, or in the name of, the whole society, in
order to reassert universally shared and strongly
entertained understandings.
These early societies all embodied the following
“morphological” pattern. A small population, with
low demographic density, subsists in a relatively
large territory, exploiting its resources extensively,
through very simple practices, assisted only by the
most primitive technology. Such societies are segmented into even smaller, very similar subunits,
which subsist in the manner indicated, each
embodying the same culture but interacting
with the others chiefly on ritual occasions, which
renew in everyone the awareness of and dedication to shared, sacred beliefs and practices. Under
these conditions, the society hangs together
mechanically, because it is highly homogenous,
and presents no fissures to be mended.
Many times in the course of pre-history, the
equilibrium of such a society, according to Durkheim, has been disturbed by a critical development of a distinctively social nature, not
expressing the intentions and strategies of individual actors (who at this point exist only as separate biological entities). An increase in population
occurs, and the increased demographic density
puts the resources under growing competitive
pressure. Either the society in question falls prey
to strife and disorder, thus leaving no further
trace on the pre-historic record, or it spontaneously embarks on a course of sustained change,
chiefly by dividing labor.
This latter solution leads, over many generations, to a society with dramatically different
traits from the previous one. Its population is
large, and, although it operates over a large territory, is much denser. It now makes intensive use
of the territory’s resources, because distinct parts
of that territory are as different as the countryside
on one hand, towns on the other. Furthermore, a
differentiation process has also penetrated those
parts, for that intensive use requires the components of the population of even the same
locality to develop different skills and different
technologies.
Only a very small part of the society’s cultural
patrimony is shared by all parts and by all the
151
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
components of each part. Increasingly diverse
beliefs and norms now activate and guide individuals in their differentiated activities. They are
less sharply formulated than those obtaining in
the former kind of society. They authorize and
broadly orient the individual’s diverse activities
rather than commandeering them and narrowly
directing them. They allow for more variation in
the ways they are understood and implemented.
They also acknowledge, regulate, and protect
the pursuit by individuals of interests which are
private to themselves.
The violation of the greater part of the norms,
in particular, does not evoke the wrath of the
whole society. Rather, sanctions are typically not
punitive but “restitutive,” that is they seek to
remedy the damage the violation has done to the
interests of given individuals, and only if these
request such remedy.
Thus the normative bonds underwritten by and
addressed to the whole society are fewer, relative
to the totality of sanctioned expectations, and
somewhat looser. But this does not abandon the
society to disorder and strife. It now hangs
together primarily because its different parts
interact with, and deliver goods and services to,
one another. The mechanical solidarity of simple
society with a minimal division of labor has been
replaced by an organic one. This reminds one of the
evolution of advanced biological species, which
present organs which are diverse in structure
and operation, but all subserve the needs of each
other and of the whole.
This result was the main consequence of the
division of labor, not the increased happiness of
society as Spencer claimed. Spencer, furthermore,
while correctly emphasizing the role that contracts play in establishing and managing the relations between individuals in modern societies,
had not realized that “not everything in the contract is contractual.” These individuals only avail
themselves of the contracts as juridical instruments of their private pursuits because public
authorities had created and sanctioned the institution of the contract. In fact, advanced societies
required such authorities to work towards
their integration, not to shrink into mere “night
watchmen” as Spencer wanted them to.
The Rules of Sociological Method (1895 [trans. 1958]),
which appeared two years after Division, was a
manifesto for a positivistic conception of sociology’s mission, for it considered the natural
sciences as an appropriate methodological model
for the development of sociology itself. Durkheim,
however, did not like the expression “positivistic”
152
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
to be applied to him, for it was associated with a
specific philosophical posture, and in spite of his
philosophical training he was keen to lay a boundary between philosophy and sociology. His strategy was to commit sociology, by means of two
chief arguments, to a self-conscious strategy of
empirical reference. First, sociology had a distinctive realm of facts – social facts – to attend to.
Second, it had to treat those facts as things, that
is as phenomena which are external to those perceiving them (including those studying them) and
which lay constraints on their activity.
A further boundary had to be established
between sociology and psychology. The most significant social facts are collective ways of acting
and thinking, that is représentations, or mental constructs, unavoidably lodged in the psyches of
human individuals. Collective representations,
however, are distinguished from those that are
not collective – and which can be left for psychology to study – by one significant characteristic.
They are sanctioned, that is society makes
arrangements for the eventuality that they are
not, in a given case, respected and complied with.
It is in the very nature of such representations
that they can and indeed are occasionally violated.
On this account, Durkheim shockingly declared,
even crime itself is normal. Its occurrence and its
modalities should be registered by sociologists,
and its causes investigated, without indulging in
philosophical moralizing.
The same empirical posture is implicit in various strategies of investigation Durkheim recommended to sociologists. For instance, they should,
as early as possible, define clearly the phenomenon they study (and their definitions may well
vary from the conventional ones). They should be
aware of variations in that phenomenon, study
them comparatively, and seek to establish their
causes, and distinguish these from their consequences or functions. The more significant variations will probably be associated with different
types of society. These types are to be constructed
in the first instance by the morphological criteria
already developed in Division, which emphasize
the complexity (or lack thereof) of a given society
or group.
Durkheim continued teaching at Bordeaux
until 1902, when he was appointed to a chair of
science of education at the Sorbonne, in Paris.
However, he had already become identified as
the most authoritative practitioner and promoter
of sociology. He was committed to the discipline
also on moral grounds, expecting it to attain
valid scientific results regarding the conditions
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
obtaining in his beloved France. Such results
could in turn find practical and political use in
the construction of new and more appropriate
public institutions by the Second Republic. Durkheim sought to accomplish this, among other
things, by acting as a consultant to ministerial
authorities. He also worked hard at selecting and
training young people who shared his own view of
sociology’s scope and method, and subsequently
sought to have them appointed to the positions
which were being created in that discipline and in
neighboring ones.
Most of Durkheim’s tireless energy, however,
was expended in strictly scholarly tasks. In 1896
he began editing, in Paris, L’Année Sociologique, a
journal devoted to reviewing, year by year, the
most significant publications which had appeared
in sociology and in neighboring disciplines, in
several European languages, over the previous
year or two. It also published original contributions, including essays by Durkheim himself and
by his students.
In 1897 Durkheim published his third major
sociological book – Suicide: A Study in Sociology
(trans. 1951). The phenomenon the book addressed was, and remains, of considerable public significance. It was relatively well documented, and
had already been discussed by many scholars from
various European countries. Durkheim’s treatment of it focused on a particular aspect. Suicide
is, on the face of it, a most private act, a peculiarly
individual undertaking. Yet the data concerning
its occurrence, which Durkheim painstakingly
assembled and analyzed over years of research,
showed remarkable regularities in the suicide
rate, that is the frequency of the occurrence of
suicide relative to the size of the population.
The suicide rate varies, sometimes widely, from
country to country, or from one to another subunit of a country’s population, and does so consistently, year in, year out. Furthermore, the
differences between subunits (for example, city
dwellers versus country dwellers, women versus
men) are remarkably similar from one country to
another, and are stable over time. Finally, over
longer periods of time, one may detect consistent
trends in the suicide rate, the most significant
trend being its increase in modern times.
These data, Durkheim argued, suggest unequivocally that a certain propensity to suicide is a
significant collective property of a given population or population subunit. That property manifests itself through a number of suicidal
occurrences, each the product – we may well
assume – of the particular circumstances of the
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
individual in question, the final episode in a
unique biography. The attempts other students
have made to account for the regularities in the
suicide rates by referring, for instance, to the geographical environment of a national population,
or its ethnic composition, are demonstrably inadequate. The reasons for such regularities must then
be found in the “moral constitution” of a given
population or subunit, in the varying nature and
intensity of the “suicidal currents” associated
with that constitution.
The prohibition or the strong disapproval of
suicide is common to all such constitutions. In
this perspective, the universality of the suicide
phenomenon (for all its variation) suggests that
it should be interpreted by reference to two
aspects of all societies. These are, on the one
hand, the extent to which in a given society individuals are induced to interact, to take each other
into account, and to form more or less cohesive
bonds with one another, and, on the other, the
extent to which societies address individuals with
rules, and with normative guidance about how
they should conduct themselves and think. Each
aspect, however, may impinge on the suicide rate
(or on the occurrence of other forms of deviance)
both when the moral constitution of a society
emphasizes it excessively and when that emphasis
is too weak.
According to Durkheim’s analysis, many of
these data point to high suicide rates that correspond with a low significance of one (or both) of
those aspects, namely bonding or regulating. For
instance, Protestants show much higher suicide
rates than Catholics. He attributes this difference
to the lower social cohesion the Protestant
denominations generate by stressing the autonomy of the individual believer, by their less pronounced and authoritative hierarchical structure,
and by the lower frequency and intensity of their
ritual occasions. Alternatively, the suicide rate
is lower among married than among unmarried
adults, lower among those married and with
children than among those without children.
This last instance shows the untenability of
what could be called a utilitarian understanding
of differential suicide rates, which would associate higher rates with situations more likely to put
people under pressure, or to confront them with
greater hardships. Memberships which impose
demanding responsibilities upon those holding
them, by the same token, put in place support
structures which may support them if they find
themselves in those desperate circumstances
which tempt them to suicide.
153
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
Looser, less demanding, but by the same token,
less cohesive memberships are less likely to offer
such support. This, paradoxically, may take the
form of reminding individuals of their responsibilities and obligations towards other members,
for to fulfill such obligations requires them in the
first instance to remain alive. Without such
reminders, individuals who face a particularly
harsh crisis may well succumb to that “suicidogenic current” Durkheim calls “egoistic,” for it
results from the supremacy in their own minds
of considerations relating exclusively to their own
well-being, which is now seriously threatened.
Lack of regulation, of morally authoritative criteria by which to judge one’s circumstances and to
orient one’s conduct, exposes individuals instead
to the threat of “anomic” suicide. Anomie may
derive from the accelerated pace at which social
and cultural change occurs, from the individuals’
exposure to a multitude of diverse stimuli, inciting them to seek ever-new experiences, new horizons, or new occasions of pleasure. Insofar as they
yield to such entreaties, individuals place themselves outside the reach of established, sanctioned
expectations. By the same token, their continuous
effort to respond to those stimuli, to challenge the
current boundaries of their existence, becomes an
end in itself. Supposing again that a serious crisis
befalls them, they cannot overcome it by appealing to norms and values which confer significance on what they have and who they are. The
conventional sources of meaning may no longer
suffice, and have not been replaced by new ones.
The suicido-genic effect of anomie is proven
according to Durkheim by the high suicide rates
of such people as divorcees, especially male divorcees. The bounding of desire, the framing and
shaping of conduct previously afforded them by
marriage, is no longer available, leaving them at a
loss. Also, variations of the suicide rate over time
suggest this circumstance, for it rises during periods of accelerated economic change – and that not
only, Durkheim claims, at times of bust, but also
at times of boom. Economic booms engender a
general feeling that one must improve one’s position, devalue old possessions and associations,
strive for continuous improvement. People who
act upon that feeling are out on a limb; should
any misfortune befall them, it may find them
unable to attach to their identities and possessions, to whatever they had accomplished in the
past, a value which may sustain them, justifying
the effort to remain alive and the related burdens.
Egoism and anomie together, according to
Durkheim, increasingly characterize the moral
154
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
atmosphere of modern society, the one amounting to a deficit of cohesion, the other to a deficit
of meaning. But Suicide also points to the suicidogenic effects of an excess of cohesion. Under certain conditions, people may have such a sense of
their own dependence on society, of society’s
entitlement to their devotion and sacrifice, that
they become prone to a third, “altruistic” type of
suicide. In some cases, society positively expects
them, in certain circumstances, to dispose of
themselves. In others, it gives them such a diminished sense of their own significance, of the
value of their own survival, that if (again) a
deep crisis occurs in their existence they easily
surrender to it.
This phenomenon is much more in evidence in
Oriental societies than in western ones, but is
echoed here, Durkheim claims, by the relatively
high suicide rate characteristic of a specific constituency – the members of the military profession. The army teaches the individuals that
compose it to attach much less significance to
themselves, qua individuals, than they attach to
the group of which they are part, be it the fatherland or a specific military unit. It thus predisposes
them to a suicide flowing not (as with egoistic
suicide) from their acute sense of their own importance, but from a heightened sense of their
dispensability.
All three suicide types (egoistic, anomic, and
altruistic) are connected with universal social
norms – respectively, that enjoining the individual to take some responsibility for her/himself;
that encouraging her/him, under certain circumstances, to seek experiences “unprogrammed” by
conventional culture; finally, that urging the individual to consider and to place her/himself at
society’s disposal. It is the priority among these
different, though equally significant, commandments that varies from society or group to society
or group – and unavoidably so, because of their
mutual incompatibilities.
There is, however, a certain affinity between
egoism and anomie (Durkheim acknowledges the
difficulty of clearly distinguishing them), which
together, as we have seen, characterize modern
society. This is largely because egoistic attitudes
and anomic dispositions are intrinsically connected with that society’s economic arrangements, currently dominated by industry and
centered on the market and on technological
innovation.
The growing hold of such phenomena on society
at large increasingly worries Durkheim, who in
Suicide (as in other writings) suggests how to
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
moderate the damage it can do to the society’s
moral temper. Again, public action is called for –
but not directly that of the state. This (as Durkheim conceives of it) is an organ for the formation of general norms and of broad, durable
policies, incapable as such of attending competently to the highly diverse and dynamic processes
of economic life. Rather, public action on economic phenomena should be entrusted to corporate bodies organizing all those who are
professionally involved (as employers or employees) in the various branches of industry. Such
bodies can identify the potentialities and needs
of each branch, regulate its activities, moderate
the conflict between employers and employees,
and generate among their constituents both a
feeling of fellowship towards one another and a
sense of responsibility towards the broader public.
The concern over the current tendencies of
modern society that motivates such proposals is
to an extent sublimated away in Durkheim’s last
great book, The Elementary Forms of Religious Life
(1912 [trans. 2001]). The theme of religion had
attracted him before, possibly because of its close
connection with morality. For Durkheim, it had
long been axiomatic that society was at bottom a
moral reality. Its continuing existence and welfare
depended on the willingness of individuals to consider each other not as instruments, but as fellow
beings equally entitled to respect and solidarity,
and society itself as demanding not only obedience but devotion. Society, furthermore, was not
just the addressee, as it were, of moral conduct,
but the source itself of morality. Durkheim argued
that morality, in all its forms, is only encountered
in society, and only varies in relation to social
conditions. Society imparts to its expectations a
quality of moral obligation that its own sanctions
are meant mainly to symbolize, rather than
to engender, and that is the essence itself of
morality.
Morality refracts itself, as it were, in a plurality
of social institutions. For all the variety of the
social interests they guard and they discipline,
all institutions, at bottom, impart to their own
commandments, more or less openly, that same
quality of intrinsic dutifulness. (Although it has
its own institutions, the sphere of economic life is
least likely to orient to such considerations the
conduct of those taking part in its activities –
and that is what worries Durkheim about it). The
relationship of the whole institutional realm to
religion is revealed in the close affinity between
the quality in question – the particular prestige
moral facts enjoy in the mind of a society’s
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
members – and the distinctive sacredness of religious beliefs, norms, and practices.
According to Durkheim, all institutions, mundane as their themes may be, have arisen as articulations and differentiations of a single, great
institutional matrix – religion itself. For, as Durkheim sees it, religion, in all its varieties, rests on
and affirms the very distinction between its own
realm – that of the sacred – and the contrasting
realm of the profane, which encompasses all
that must be kept at a distance from the sacred,
acknowledging its unique powerfulness, awesomeness, dangerousness. The noli me tangere of
all social institutions – their projecting themselves as public realities which individuals must
not tinker with in their private pursuits, but
accept and continuously validate as legitimate
constraints upon them – is a derivation, however
remote, of the sacred so understood.
But the question becomes – what engenders the
division itself between the sacred and the profane? Durkheim holds that such a primordial
and universal distinction must be rooted on an
equally primordial and universal experience, best
conveyed by the most primitive form of religious
life one can find, which he claims to find in the
totemism of Australian aboriginal populations.
Here multiple, diverse bodies of beliefs and ritual
practices, different as they are, agree on two
points. Each celebrates the unchallengeable sacredness and the unique significance of an object
(generally a biological species). Each asserts the
identity between that object – the totem – and
the tribe itself, among other things by attaching
to both the same name.
This assertion provides Durkheim with a critical
cue. As it worships the totem, the tribe worships
itself. Quite generally, in fact, it is the confrontation with the superiority, the powerfulness, the
generosity of a group, that generates in its members the experience of the sacred itself – an experience which myth and ritual continuously revisit
and reproduce. When religions attain an idea of
God, that idea symbolically represents society
itself. Other religions may convey a less distinctive
notion of a sacred force. All of them, however,
partition reality into a sacred and a profane
realm, assert an asymmetry of significance
between them, and design collective activities
which celebrate that asymmetry and align the
participants with the higher realm. As they do
so, the participants draw new strength and assurance from that part, rededicate themselves to the
myths and the rituals of the group, many of which
affirm the intrinsic obligatoriness of its manières
155
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
d’agir et de penser. At the same time (dialectically,
one might say), the participation of the faithful in
the worship of that superior force posits and
reconstitutes its existence (and thus the unique
validity of those manières).
All religions do this, though perhaps none as
clearly as the totemic ones. Even these, of course,
do so in varied and contrasting ways. Each tribe
attributes sacredness to a different totemic being,
and thus implicitly to itself. Each celebrates it
through a different ensemble of myths and rituals.
This very diversity may suggest to the observer that
religion itself is at bottom an arbitrary exercise in
self-delusion, a delirium.
Yes, Durkheim agrees – “but it is a wellgrounded delirium.” In all its forms, religion
asserts symbolically a basic truth. The individual
owes everything to the society. Reciprocally, only
the individual’s respect for and devotion to society
itself, asserted more directly through religious
practice, less directly by dutiful submission to varied institutional commands, confirms the very
existence of society and the continuing validity of
its institutions.
If this is the core argument of Elementary Forms,
one may well see one problem it poses for Durkheim himself. If religion is the ultimate source of
all morality, and if it is necessary to the very
survival of society, what of modern society itself?
Has modernization not displaced religion?
By the time he wrote Elementary Forms, Durkheim himself had recognized some validity to
the secularization thesis, and had become less
and less confident in the validity and sustainability of the modernization project. Yet in Elementary
Forms and in other writings he tries hard, one
senses, to be optimistic. Modern society, like all
others, needs religion, for without religion society
would face dissolution. And it has in fact, for all
appearances to the contrary, a religion of its own,
156
Durkheim, Émile (1858–1917)
compatible of course with other aspects of its
nature, but not yet sufficiently conscious of itself
and of its own distinctiveness.
Modern religion – the cult of the individual –
sacralizes the human person, the human being as
such. It surrounds with a halo of dignity each
member of society, forbidding others to treat the
individual as a morally neutral, merely factual
component of society, as a means or as an obstacle. Its content is revealed, in particular, by political constitutions which attribute some rights to
all citizens, irrespective of their social condition.
This recognition of a juridically significant
capacity which belongs equally to everyone is a
significant moral advance of modernity. That capacity is periodically celebrated by political rituals,
and its scope is destined to grow in the future. Its
moral significance is under threat from contemporary developments which encourage egoism
instead of affirming the sacredness of the individual. But such developments can be countered by
institutional innovations, in particular those that
regulate and constrain competitive conduct on
the market. Furthermore, it can be expected that
more and more societies – beginning with European ones, which represented for Durkheim the
front edge of modernity – will assert in their constitutions the equal moral significance of all their
members. They will thus contribute to establishing a form of religion appropriate to modernity.
Durkheim’s expectations of further moral
advances from European societies were harshly
negated by the advent of World War I. This conflict at first gave new impulse to his French patriotism; but at length its carnage brutally thinned
out the ranks of his own students. When his own
son perished during a military expedition in the
Balkans, this personal tragedy broke Durkheim’s
heart and paralyzed his mind. He died in 1917.
GIANFRANCO POGGI
E
economism
This is a term for theories that regard economic
activity as the primary focus of social life, in which
political or cultural arrangements are, at best, secondary to, or derivative of, more fundamental economic forces. Examples of economism include
theories (such as the economics of the market,
and certain types of Marxism) and social activities
(such as free trade or trade unionism) that are
perceived as neglectful of interactions between
economic and noneconomic aspects of social life.
The term is usually applied by critics rather than
supporters of economism. To describe something
or someone as economistic is usually to diagnose a
one-dimensional approach to social analysis that is
inadequate to the complex or multidimensional
character of social phenomena. Few sociologists
would identify with economism in an extreme
form, even though many would regard the economy as a central (perhaps the central) aspect of
social structure, power, and social inequality.
The idea of economism rests on the modern
assumption of a social differentiation. This
perspective sees society as becoming differentiated into distinct spheres – the economy, government, law, and culture – that are autonomous
from one another and centered on specialized
institutions – such as markets and factories, parliaments and law courts, and so forth. The idea of
differentiation, however, raises questions as to the
relationship between different spheres, in this
case between the economy and the rest of society.
While economistic thinking sees this in terms of
the causal primacy of the economy over polity and
culture, this assumption remains controversial.
Sociologists generally prefer alternative accounts
which emphasize the role of government and
culture in the constitution and regulation of
economic life.
ROBERT HOLTON
economy
In the most simple and general sense, the concept
of the economy is used to refer to the social
organizations and institutions that are involved
in the production and distribution of goods and
services in society – firms, labor, money-capital,
and the markets and networks by which they are
connected and articulated. The term is derived
from the ancient Greek oeconomicus which referred
to the practical activity of household (oikos)
management. From the late Middle Ages onward,
particularly in western Europe, the social organization of production and exchange became
increasingly detached from the feudal and communal social relations of households, manors, and
patrimonial estates. Home and work gradually
became structurally separated. An early sociological analysis of this process is contained in
Max Weber’s General Economic History (1927 [trans.
1981]).
Early nineteenth-century classical economics saw
the resulting “economy,” comprising the factors
of production of land, capital, and labor, as a relatively autonomous subsystem of society that was
governed by the economic laws of the market, conceptualized by Adam Smith (1723–90) as the “invisible hand.” This approach identifies the “economy”
with the “market.” Talcott Parson’s social theory
endorsed this distinction between “economy” and
“society”; but there have also been two critical
responses within sociology to this conceptualization. First, Karl Polanyi, following Karl Marx and
Weber, contended that the modern market economy should be understood as a historically specific type of economy in which production and
exchange had become separated, or “disembedded”
from wider social relations and norms. Second, as
Mark Granovetter has argued, economic relations
in modern economies are also social relations.
In a critique of the postulate of natural scarcity
in classical economics, Marx argued that it was a
socially produced consequence of the unequal
and exploitative relations in the economy. He classified different types of economy as historically
located modes of production, distinguished by different technological “means” and “social relations”
of production between owners and nonowners.
Marx identified a sequence of development from
primitive communism – through ancient, Asiatic,
feudal, and capitalist – to communism or socialism.
157
economy
The general Marxian approach to the analysis of
economies is developed by the modern Parisian
Regulation School, exemplified in Michel Aglietta’s
The Theory of Capitalist Regulation (1979). Regulation
theory identifies three successive modes of regulation of capitalist economies from the middle of the
nineteenth to the late twentieth century: (1) the
nineteenth-century competitive mode of regulation; (2) twentieth-century “monopoly capitalism”
and mass production or Fordism (see Post-Fordism); and (3) the 1970s crisis of Fordism and the
subsequent partial disintegration of flexible specialization, and development of regional industrial
districts, or disorganized capitalism.
In The Long Twentieth Century (1994), Giovanni
Arrighi synthesized the Marxian and Weberian
classical sociology with the economics of Adam
Smith (1723–90) and with the history of Fernand
Braudel (1902–85), to produce an analysis of the
successive hegemonies of structurally different
capitalist economies from the Renaissance Italian
city-states, to the Netherlands, Britain, and the
United States.
Modern sociology, for example in P. Hall and
D. Soskice (eds.), Varieties of Capitalism: The Institutional Foundations of Comparative Advantage (2001),
has been concerned with the question of the diversity of modern capitalist economies. In the first
place, the success of East Asian capitalism and the
rapid advance of the German and French economies after World War II led to a debate on
whether there existed equally efficient and effective forms of capitalism to the Anglo-American
liberal market system. In Stock Market Capitalism:
Welfare Capitalism, Japan and Germany Versus the
Anglo-Saxons (2000), Ronald Dore argued that
Japan and Germany had been able to combine
economic success with social welfare. The debate
continues in the context of the relatively poor
performance of these economies from the late
twentieth century. Second, the transition from
the central planning of communism in the former
Soviet Union and the continued liberalization and
growth of the Chinese economy have stimulated a
debate on the type of capitalist economy that is
likely to develop in the former state socialist
economies.
A further important consideration, also discussed in Bruno Amable’s The Diversity of Modern
Capitalism (2003), is whether economic globalization will reduce the existing diversity of different
types of capitalism in a process of convergence
towards the Anglo-Saxon liberal market type of
economy.
GEOFFREY INGHAM
158
education
education
A concern with education has been inseparably linked with the development of sociology,
especially in the French tradition. In defining sociology, Auguste Comte argued that there had been
a historical progression in the advancement of
all science from deploying religious and metaphysical conceptual frameworks to adopting
procedures of positivist analysis, based on observation. This intellectual progression was mirrored
institutionally by corresponding forms of social
organization – from feudal and aristocratic
systems to that culminating form which would
be the consequence of secular, social engineering.
The emergence of positivist analysis of human
and social relations would necessarily entail the
construction of forms of social organization
which, for the first time, would be founded on
science rather than prejudice or privilege. Positivist scientists would become the legislators of mankind. Comte was aware that the prevalence of
positivist principles in social practice in mass society would require some emotional underpinning, and he proposed the institutionalization of
a positive religion which would generate a sense
of ideological and social inclusion, operating as a
secular, surrogate Catholic Church.
The third French Republic – of “intellectuals” –
tried, from 1871, to introduce a system of state
education which would perform the function that
Comte had projected for an organized positivist
religion. The function of the education system
would be to generate social solidarity by initiating
the whole population of the country into the secular values which informed its organization and
operation. It was Émile Durkheim who tried to
implement Comte’s program in the 1890s by
carrying out sociological research and by articulating rules which should govern the method of
sociological enquiry, but it is important to remember that he taught pedagogy at the same time
as sociology for the whole of his life. In his first
post at the University of Bordeaux, from 1887
until 1902, he gave weekly lectures on pedagogy
to teachers and, when he moved to Paris, it was
to the Chair in the Science of Education at the
Sorbonne. Durkheim’s writings on education
were assembled posthumously, notably Education
and Sociology (1922 [trans. 1956]), Moral Education: A
Study in the Theory and Application of the Sociology of
Education (1925 [trans. 1961]), and Pedagogical Evolution in France (1938 [trans. 1977]). In his introduction to the first of these texts, Paul Fauconnet
insisted that Durkheim’s parallel attachment to
education
sociological and educational analyses was not at
all accidental, but, rather, that “it is in as much as
it is a social fact that he approaches education: his
doctrine of education is an essential element of
his sociology.” The two dimensions of Durkheim’s
thinking explain the traditional affinity between
sociology and the study of education: on the one
hand pedagogical practices within the educational system were necessary instruments for fulfilling the social mission which was the legacy of
Comtist thinking. On the other hand, it was important that the study of education should exemplify sociological rigor. Typically, Durkheim began
his discussion in Education and Sociology with a
critical examination of the existing definitions of
education. He argued that the word had been used
too broadly to include the influence of nature on
human will and intelligence and that, instead, it
should be restricted to mean solely the action
which adults exercise over the young. To define
this education more closely would entail an analysis of educational practice in different times and
places. In faithful positivist fashion, Durkheim
concluded:
We do not know a priori what is the function of the
respiratory or circulatory systems for living beings.
By what privilege should we be better informed
concerning the educative function? ... Hence, must it
not be the case that to constitute a preliminary
notion of education, to determine the thing which is
denominated in this way, historical observation
appears to be indispensable.
His social history of pedagogy in France fulfilled
just this function. For Durkheim, the sociology of
education was to be pedagogically prescriptive by
being methodologically exemplary.
The inaugurating concern of sociology with
education was the product of a particular set of
social and intellectual circumstances in France at
the end of the nineteenth century. Consideration
of the legacy of this concern raises broad questions about the transcultural and transtemporal
applicability of the social sciences. In considering
the “predisciplinary history of social science” in
general, in his The Rise of Social Theory (1995), Johan
Heilbron has argued that this rise was part of a
progressive secularization of human societies. At
first this involved a return to the works of classical
antiquity, and to Aristotelian “practical philosophy” in particular, but this was the starting-point
for the articulation of modern notions which characterized the predisciplinary history of social science. There followed stages of development which,
in Heilbron’s view, moved from primary interest
in conceptions of state and law to concern with
education
economic theory until, in the eighteenth century,
there emerged a secular approach to the concept
of society which meant breaking with both
theology and political theory.
There is a reciprocal relationship between developing social conditions which generate new
social sciences and the contributions which social
scientific analyses of these emergent developments make towards their realization. Durkheimian sociology of education was in a reciprocal
relationship with those social and political forces
which suggested that the introduction of a statecontrolled national education system would actualize the concept of a conscience collective which
would ensure social cohesion and foster a national
identity. There was an affinity with the distrust
of individualism manifested at the same time in
Germany in the formulation of the notions of
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft (see Ferdinand
Tönnies).
In the United Kingdom in the same period,
the response to similar forces arising from similar
phenomena of industrialization (see industrial
society) and democratization (see democracy)
developed within a different conceptual framework – that of liberalism. In his contribution to
The Rise of the Modern Educational System: Structural
Change and Social Reproduction, 1870–1920 (1987), the
English Marxist social historian, Brian Simon,
demonstrated that the consequence of the United
Kingdom Elementary Education Act of 1870 was
that three levels of schooling came into being
in the period from 1860 to 1900: “public” schools
for the upper middle class, elementary schooling
for the working class, and a new set of schools
aimed at accommodating the middle classes. The
outcome, he contended, was “the establishment of
a highly differentiated system in which each level
served, in theory at least, a specific social class (or
subsection of a class), with each having a specific
function.” In the early years of British sociology,
the problem of education was much less central
than in France precisely because education was
not required to perform the same social function.
There was little expectation that the educational
system should contribute towards the development
of a self-conscious social democracy and, rather,
the enlargement of educational provision was a
carefully regulated mechanism for legitimating
the allocation of individuals to pre-established,
stratified, social and professional positions.
In general terms, the liberal tradition led to
research which focused on the performance of
individuals and on the relationship between educational and occupational hierarchies. In part, the
159
education
emphasis was on educational psychology and
the measurement of intelligence. In so far as this
tradition generated a sociology of education, it
was a sociology which, particularly in the United
States, responded to the given structure of relations between education and the economy. It
was the impulse towards egalitarianism provided
by World War II which, in the United Kingdom,
stimulated an adoption of a Durkheimian orientation towards the sociological analysis of education. It is significant that it was in this period that
Durkheim’s texts on education were first translated into English, and sociological analysis began
to operate reciprocally in tandem with the movement towards the comprehensivization of the
schooling system.
The stimulus given to British sociology of education by the publication in 1971 of the collection
of articles edited by M. F. D. Young, entitled Knowledge and Control. New Directions for the Sociology of
Education – which first popularized early articles
by Basil Bernstein and Pierre Bourdieu – came
largely from a re-discovery of Durkheim’s societal
perspective. In France, however, Bourdieu’s work
was provoked by his sense that the official ideology of the French educational system masked
social differentiation and that it was no longer
possible, in any case, to assume that the achievement of equality within an educational system
could guarantee social equality. Bourdieu problematized the systemic legacy of Third Republic
educational ideology and also refused to limit the
sociology of education to the analysis of pedagogical relations within schooling institutions.
The shift in his thinking was accurately reflected
in the English rendering of the title of his book on
reproduction which, in France in 1970, was subtitled “Elements for a Theory of the Educational
System”, but, in English in 1977, was called Reproduction in Education, Society and Culture. Writing
within the Durkheimian tradition, Bourdieu
offered a framework for analyzing the function
of schooling within a society which was conceived
as being in a state of conflict or competition,
where educational attainment, cultural taste, occupational position are mobilized in interacting
ways to acquire and legitimize the acquisition
of power. Without renouncing the ideal of the
socialist tradition – of achieving social equality,
solidarity, and inclusion – Bourdieu provided a
conceptual apparatus which could accommodate
the interests of the liberal tradition. It is significant that Bourdieu’s work of the 1960s became
available in translation in the United States at
the end of the 1970s. The technocratic model of
160
Eisenstadt, Shmuel Noah (1923– )
education had become dominant in the United
States. It operated on the assumption that the
graded performance of students in education
was a reliable indicator of eligibility for posts
in a correlative hierarchy of occupations. Several
challenges to this assumption emanated from the
United States: the de-schooling movement;
the articulation of the influence of a hidden
curriculum in formal learning contexts; and
the critiques of credentialism. In different ways,
these were all attempts to rescue the sociology of
education from subservience to the status quo
of assumed relations between school and work
and, therefore, between educational and economic opportunities. The refusal to accept the acultural assumptions of the technocratic model
was strengthened by the association with the
civil rights movement (see social movements)
and the concomitant interest in affirmative action
as a way of enabling educational opportunity to
overcome cultural disadvantage.
If we accept, first, that the sociology of education at any time is in reciprocal relationship with
educational policies; second, that it has emerged
in the West in two, ideal-typical, philosophical
traditions of socialism and liberalism; and, third,
that its history in the West demonstrates the
effects both of the internal reciprocity between
theory and practice and of cross-cultural conceptual transfer between these competing traditions –
then, two provocative questions arise, one local
and the other global. If the hegemony of the conservative party in British politics from the 1970s
to 1997 suppressed the resurgence of a socialist
sociology of education, has the effect of the
New Labour accommodation with Thatcherism,
associated with the sociological work of Anthony
Giddens, neutralized sociological critique and
encouraged the development of a postmodern
version of the technocratic model? Does the appropriation of cultural difference through the overriding force of economic performativity now
mean that a sociology of international education is doomed to stand impotently by as the
technocratic model begins to prevail globally?
DEREK ROBBINS
Eisenstadt, Shmuel Noah (1923– )
Emeritus Professor in the Department of Sociology
and Anthropology at the Hebrew University of
Jerusalem and a recipient of the Balzan Prize in
1988, Eisenstadt has made important contributions to comparative, historical and political sociology. In The Political System of Empires (1967), he
examined pre-industrial societies to establish the
elective affinity
conditions that contributed to their instability
and ultimate transformations. He made a major
contribution to the study of generations and
social change in From Generation to Generation: Age
Groups and Social Structure (1971). Eisenstadt was in
general concerned to understand development in
non-western societies in terms of the legacy of
Max Weber in The Protestant Ethic and Modernization
(1968). He has been fascinated by Japanese society
in Japanese Civilization (1996), because Japan raises
many acute questions about whether the western
model of development is unique. Eistenstadt has
therefore been influential in arguing that there
are many forms of modernity rather than a single,
uniform process of modernization. His idea
of “multiple modernities” has been explored in
Patterns of Modernity (1987) (with D. Sachsenmaier),
and he edited Reflections on Multiple Modernities:
European, Chinese and other Interpretations (2002)
and Comparative Civilizations and Multiple Modernities
(2003). He has also contributed to the sociological
understanding of fundamentalism in Fundamentalism, Sectarianism and Revolution (1999), arguing that
Islamic fundamentalism is not anti-modern or
even traditional, but another type of modernity.
BRYAN S. TURNER
elective affinity
– see Max Weber.
Elias, Norbert (1897–1990)
Born in Breslau, German sociologist Elias studied
medicine and philosophy before graduating with
a doctorate in philosophy in 1922. He worked with
Alfred Weber, before becoming academic assistant
to Karl Mannheim in Frankfurt in 1929. After fleeing to Paris in 1933, following the rise of the
Nazis, Elias settled in England in 1935, taking a
research fellowship at the London School of Economics. In 1954, he was appointed to the subsequently influential Sociology Department at the
University of Leicester. He also held university
positions in Frankfurt, Ghana, Bielefeld, and
Amsterdam.
Elias’s approach has often been characterized as
figurational sociology, though he came to prefer
the term process sociology. This approach was
designed to avoid reified accounts of social institutions and to emphasize the historical character
of social life. His work is therefore often contrasted with the functionalism of Talcott Parsons.
The defining features of this approach hold
that: (1) human beings are born into relations of
interdependency so that the social structures that
they form with each other engender emergent
Elias, Norbert (1897–1990)
dynamics, which cannot be reduced to individual actions or motivations. Such emergent dynamics fundamentally shape processes of individual
growth and development, and the trajectory of
people’s lives; (2) these figurations are in a constant state of flux and transformation; (3) longterm transformations of human social figurations
are largely unplanned and unforeseen; and (4) the
development of knowledge takes place within
such figurations and forms one aspect of their
overall development.
Elias’s first work, though not published until
1969, was The Court Society, in which he examined
the social pressures facing the “court nobility”
under the reign of Louis XIV. According to Elias
the court rationality of the nobility, in which
rank and prestige determined expenditure, can
be contrasted with the economic rationality of
the bourgeoisie, where consumption is subordinated to income. Like economic rationality, court
rationality involved forms of self-restraint which
were expressed in literature, architecture, and philosophy. Elias’s magnum opus, however, remains
The Civilizing Process (1939 [trans. 2000]). Drawing
on a variety of thinkers, including Karl Marx,
Mannheim, Max Weber, and Sigmund Freud, Elias
offers a bifocal investigation of psychological and
behavioral transformations among the secular
upper classes in the West, which, he shows, are
integrally tied above all to processes of internal
pacification and state formation. Because of the
late and separate publication of volumes I and II
in English, in 1978 and 1981, the study of long-term
psychological changes, the history of manners, and
the capacity for greater self-control in volume I
has often, misleadingly, been read independently
from the study of changes in social structure and
state formation outlined in volume II.
Elias’s other writings often develop ideas originally elaborated in The Civilizing Process. Together
with Involvement and Detachment (1987), which outlines the social conditions for the possibility of a
scientific sociology, Elias’s other crucial work is
What is Sociology? (1978), in which he outlines
among other things a series of “game models.”
These demonstrate the regularity of social processes which generate emergent dynamics that
cannot be reduced to individual actions. These
constrain and mold the habitus and behavior of
individuals.
Other important works by Elias include (with
J. Scotson) The Established and the Outsiders (1965);
and (with Eric Dunning) Quest for Excitement (1986);
The Society of Individuals (1991); and Time: An Essay
STEVEN LOYAL
(1992).
161
elite(s)
elite(s)
While in classic analyses the term elite carries
a connotation of superiority (“the cream”), in
contemporary social analysis it is used in a nonevaluative manner: it means a powerful minority
affecting public and political outcomes in a
systematic and significant way. Elite influence
reflects control over “power resources” concentrated in large organizations, for example capital,
authority, means of coercion, mass communication, knowledge, and charisma, as well as the
capacity of elite groups to act in concert. Elites
emerge in all organized societies, especially
those with strong bureaucratic states. Therefore,
the most visible parts of national elites are political elites (leaders). In democratic regimes, such
elites operate electoral systems in which they
compete for popular support. They also interact –
collaborate, compete, and sometimes contend –
with state-administrative, business, media, trade
union, military, and religious elite groups. If this
interaction is peaceful, and if elite groups achieve
a high degree of consensus, stable democratic
regimes may emerge. Elite warfare, by contrast,
is a trademark of unstable and non-democratic
polities.
While the empirical delineations of elites are
arbitrary – power and influence are matters of
degree – most elite researchers restrict their size
to about 300–1,000 persons. Such elite persons are
identified “positionally,” as holders of the top
power positions in the largest and most resourcerich organizations, or by involvement in making
key decisions, or by reputation among their peers,
or, finally, by a combination of the three methods.
National elites are also seen as internally stratified, with political leaders typically placed at
the apex of national power structures. At the
other end of the power spectrum are the masses
(“non-elites”). Between these two extremes, social
scientists also distinguish “political classes” – the
power strata from which elites are drawn, and
on which elites rely in wielding power – and
“influentials,” those who can affect elite decisions.
Elites are sometimes conflated and sometimes
contrasted with “ruling classes” (see social class).
The latter are seen as much broader collectivities
distinguished by ownership of capital. Class theorists typically see elites as “executive arms” of the
ruling class(es). Elite theorists, by contrast, criticize class reductionism and point to the autonomy of political elites, as reflected in their
capacity to expropriate ownership classes (for
example in revolutions).
162
elite(s)
Classical elite theory was developed at the turn
of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries by
Vilfredo Pareto, Gaetano Mosca, and Robert
Michels, under the strong influence of both positivism and the theories of Max Weber. It constituted a critique of democratic theory that
predicted a radical dispersion of political power,
and of Marxism that foresaw class conflicts and
a triumph of egalitarian socialism. In contrast
with both, the classic elite thinkers suggested persistent and inescapable power concentration in
elites’ hands. Revolutions (see revolution, theory
of ), including “socialist revolutions,” claimed
elite theorists, merely reconstituted elites, and
they did not narrow down the elite–mass power
gaps.
Both classic and contemporary elite theorists
see the bases of elite power in certain psychological predispositions, organizational abilities
(rare in general populations), small size, and internal cohesion. Elite cohesion does not preclude
the possibility of temporary intra-elite conflicts
and divisions on specific policy questions. However, when their power is threatened, elite
members defend it in a solidary way. Their firm
grip on power is strengthened by alliances with
non-elite social forces – dominant strata, movements, classes, and organized groups – and by
control over their succession exercised through
exclusive schools, corporate hierarchies, and party
machines. Contemporary elite theorists, such as
C. Wright Mills, see the United States elite as
firmly anchored in the core organizations: the
national government, the military directorate,
and the largest business corporations.
A comprehensive overview of modern elites is
provided by Tom Bottomore in Elites and Society
(1993) and by Robert Putnam in Comparative Study
of Political Elites (1976). Bottomore highlights elite –
ruling class connection. Putnam stresses elites’
anchoring in social and institutional structures,
and he sees elite conduct as heavily constrained
by ideologies (revolutionary elites) and national
legal frameworks (liberal elites). Other contemporary elite theorists, such as John Higley and
Eva Etzioni-Halevi, elaborate the conceptions
of elite unity and democracy. They focus on
elite effectiveness, consensus, and competition.
According to Higley and his collaborators, elites
that “craft” and maintain stable democratic
regimes are united in their support of peaceful
electoral competition, broadly integrated, and
well connected with the major mass constituencies, typically through party organizations and
elite(s)
civic associations. Etzioni-Halevi sees effective
“coupling” of elites with lower/working classes as
a key condition of democracy, the latter seen as a
regime of competing elites.
More recently, there has been a shift in elite
researchers’ attention, reflecting a change in the
structure and composition of contemporary elites.
It can be summarized in five points:
(1) The emergence of transnational power networks and elites. While nation-states remain
the most important institutional loci of power,
other power concentrations emerge in the
process of globalization and the formation
of such transnational bodies as the United
Nations, the World Bank, the International
Monetary Fund, Greenpeace, and Islamic movements. The increasingly transnational/global
nature of the problems national elites face
(for example terrorism, environmental degradation, the drugs trade, uncontrolled migrations and the spread of AIDS) forces them
into supra-state and transnational domains.
(2) Widening elite autonomy. One of the key
trends of the last decades seems to be a
widening of non-elective elites capable of
initiating, and sometimes directing, social
change. Thus what are arguably the most
momentous events of the twentieth century,
such as the dissolution of the Soviet Union,
the collapse of Soviet communism in eastern
Europe, and the liberalization of the Chinese
economy, have been engineered by elites.
(3) Emergence of pro-democratic elites. The recent
wave of democratization (1989–95) has been
championed mainly by elites “crafting” and
consolidating democratic regimes, often with
only weak support from mass populations.
Pro-democratic elites have emerged in southern Europe, Russia, central and eastern Europe,
and East Asia.
(4) Intense elite differentiation and circulation.
Contemporary studies show that new elite
groups emerge with the expansion of new
industries, civic groups, social movements,
and nongovernmental organizations.
(5) The declining impact of ideologies in advanced western societies. Western elites cultivate mass support in a pragmatic and ad hoc
manner, often through media “spin” and campaigns focusing on personalities of leaders.
This reflects the fact that the support constituencies of western elites are less anchored in
specific classes, ethno-segments, or religious
categories.
JAN PAKULSKI
emotions
embeddedness
This concept suggests that economic conduct is embedded within and influenced by wider social structures, institutions, and cultures, and represents a
sociological critique of standard economic models
that equate economic processes with atomistic
market transactions between self-interested individuals. Mark Granovetter codified this critique in
“Economic Action and Social Structure: The Problem of Embeddedness” (1985), in the American Journal of Sociology. He argued that trust, suspicion, and
manipulation in market transactions cannot be
explained by the calculations of autonomous
(undersocialized) economic actors or by (oversocialized) cultural determinism. Rather, they are explicable in terms of the specific networks of social
relations inhabited by such actors: a shared network may underpin trust rather than suspicion,
but may also create more scope for abuse of trust.
This is not an argument for uniform embeddedness. First, in some societies economic processes are
largely structured in terms of nonmarket relations,
in which case formal market models are entirely
inappropriate. Second, market processes in capitalist societies are not autonomous and self-sustaining, as much economic theory implies, but rather
generate tensions and challenges that prompt
efforts at institutional regulation. Third, market
transactions are differently conditioned by specific
institutional features: thus different liberal market
and “alliance” capitalisms involve various levels
and types of embeddedness. Finally, the greater
embeddedness of economic processes in “alliance”
capitalisms, through ties among enterprises and
with the state (and sometimes organized labor),
may generate trust and cooperation more readily
than liberal market capitalisms.
However, the invocation of embeddedness only
provides a starting point for such arguments. The
consequences of different sorts of embeddedness,
and their advantages and disadvantages for different economic actors, have to be addressed
through more detailed specification and research.
TONY ELGER
embodiment
– see body.
emotional labor
– see emotions.
emotions
Although typically understood in terms of feelings
and bodily sensations, which are components of
163
emotions
any emotion, emotions are best regarded as
experiences of involvement. Social circumstance,
expressive communication, and actor intentions
are crucial to the genesis of emotional experience
and its quality. Thus, emotions can be seen to
underscore values, interests, and meanings in
social life. Emotions, then, are implicated in rational as well as irrational action and outlook.
Max Weber’s distinction, for instance, between
rational action and affective action, therefore
loses its coherence when emotion is not confined
to a particular type of action but seen to underlie
all action. Similarly, while some emotions may
rise and fall within a short time-frame, it is not a
necessary characteristic of emotions that they
are of short duration, though this applies to those
emphasized by experimental work in psychology:
here laboratory research studies chiefly reactive
and highly visceral emotions, readily elicited
from experimental subjects usually drawn from
undergraduate student populations. Many important emotions, however, are not brief and
episodic but enduring or ongoing. Another misunderstanding holds that those experiencing emotions are necessarily conscious of them. They
need not be. Many emotions, including the most
important for social processes, are experienced
below the threshold of awareness. Thomas J.
Scheff, for instance, has shown that much social
conformity can be explained in terms of shame of
which the subject is not consciously aware.
The relevance of emotions to sociological explanation is original to the discipline, central to
the eighteenth-century precursors of sociology, including Adam Smith (1723–90) in The Theory of
Moral Sentiments (1759) and Adam Ferguson
(1723–1816) in An Essay on the History of Civil Society
(1767), and to nineteenth- and early twentiethcentury sociological pioneers, including Alexis
de Tocqueville, Émile Durkheim, Vilfredo Pareto,
Ferdinand Tönnies, and Georg Simmel. Since the
1970s, after at least half a century of neglect by
sociologists, a sociology of emotions has emerged.
An approach associated with these developments
concerns emotion management and emotional
labor as in Arlie Russell Hochschild’s The Managed
Heart (1983). Emotion management is the broad
process that matches face or emotional expression
to circumstance, a process achieved by emotional
labor. Emotional labor, like labor in general,
refers to activities performed in an employment
setting for a wage, in which the labor is to induce
or suppress feelings in order to sustain an outward countenance or emotional expression intended to produce a particular state of mind in
164
emotions
others. The affective parameters within which
emotional labor is performed are the culturally
defined feeling rules that prescribe the content
of emotional expression and the circumstances
in which particular expressions are appropriate.
Hochschild estimated that, in the early 1980s
when she wrote her book, approximately onethird of American workers had jobs substantially
involving emotional labor and that approximately
half of all female workers had jobs involving such
forms of emotional work. She argues that the
costs of emotional labor to those engaged in it
are high: it affects the capacity to feel and may
lead to loss of the function of emotional display or
expression. The deleterious consequence of performance of emotional labor postulated by Hochschild is supported in many of the documented
cases of emotional labor. And yet case studies
seldom control for other aspects of the work that
may be responsible for negative emotional outcomes. In a comparative examination of occupations, Amy Wharton in Work and Occupations (1993)
found that emotional laborers are no more likely
than other workers to suffer emotional exhaustion and somewhat more likely to be satisfied
with their job. What determines whether work
leads to emotional exhaustion or a sense of emotional inauthenticity is the level of job autonomy
and involvement. When these are low then the
jobs involved tend to produce emotional exhaustion and low job satisfaction, whether emotional
labor is a primary aspect of the job or not.
The sociology of emotion management and
emotional labor predominantly understands emotions in terms of social and cultural manipulation, transformation, and restraint. While this
aspect of emotions is important it does not exhaust the ways in which emotions may be sociologically considered. The way in which emotions
spontaneously emerge in social processes and also
the extent to which they constrain and orient
social processes. A general theory of emotions developed by Theodore Kemper in A Social Interactional Theory of Emotions (1978) postulates three
basic propositions. First, all social interactions can
be characterized in terms of two formal dimensions of social relations, namely power and status,
or involuntary and voluntary compliance, scaled
in terms of whether they are in excess of what is
required in the relationship, adequate for it, or
insufficient. Agency – who might be responsible
for too much or not enough power, say – can
similarly be differentiated, as “self ” or “other.”
Second, specific physiological processes are stimulated by specific experiences of power and status.
empiricism
Finally, particular emotions are physiologically
specific. Physiological processes are thus the
mechanisms that translate the structure of interactions into the emotions of the actors and are
therefore an intermediary variable. In summary,
the particular emotions that people experience
arise out of the structure of the relations of power
and status in which they are implicated. Thus,
insufficient power in a relationship is likely to
lead to experience of fear, excess of power to guilt;
excess status is likely to lead to shame, insufficient status to depression, and so on. According
to this account, emotion is in the social relationship: the subject of relations of power and status
experiences emotional change, and, in being so
changed, is disposed to change the relationship
itself. Thus emotion is a necessary link between
social structure and social actor. The connection is
never mechanical, though, because emotions normally do not compel but bias activity. Emotion is
provoked by circumstance and is experienced as
transformation of dispositions to act. It is through
the subject’s active exchange with others that
emotional experience is both stimulated in the
actor and orientating of their conduct. Emotion
is directly implicated in the actors’ transformation of their circumstances, as well as the circumstances’ transformation of the actors’ disposition
to act.
JACK BARBALET
empiricism
This is a position in epistemology which states that
only that which is observable, that is, empirical,
can be used in the generation of scientific knowledge. There can be no recourse to unseen forces,
underlying causes, or claims that behind the appearance of reality there lies a more fundamental
reality.
In contrast to theological accounts of how we
gain knowledge of the world – through divine
revelation, faith, and the teachings of the church
fathers – empiricism was an epistemological position, evolved through the Enlightenment, arguing
that knowledge of the world was a product of
careful observation by the individual, the sorting
of these observations, and the generation of laws
governing them. As developed in Newtonian
mechanics, the world was conceptualized as orderly and lawful. As developed by John Locke
(1632–1704) in political philosophy, we are born
into the world as a blank sheet and, through sensory experience and by induction (that is, by
moving from the knowledge of the particular to
the knowledge of the general), gradually build our
endogamy
knowledge of the world. However, Immanuel Kant
(1724–1804) argued that reality is too infinitely
complex for us to know what to abstract out
of it; that in our own lifetime we could never
make sense of it; and hence the mind must come
prepared to make sense of the empirical world.
Thus he proposes that the categories of reason –
of causality, mass, weight, time, and so on – are
a-priori characteristics of the human mind. Alternatively, Émile Durkheim proposed that the
categories of the mind are not individual achievements since we are born into already existing
explanations of the world, and that knowledge,
natural and social, is a social achievement,
specific to each culture in its own time.
Applied in the social sciences by Auguste Comte
and Durkheim, empiricism led to the claims that
society could be studied in the same way as nature,
and that, with the methods of the natural sciences
(observation, classification, comparison, and experiment) and the use of statistics, the laws of
social life could be demonstrated.
The critique of the empiricist position has continued in the history and philosophy of science in
the twentieth century. On the one hand, historian
of science Thomas Samuel Kuhn argued, in The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1970), that scientific knowledge was not the product of nature, but
of the scientific communities who constructed it.
We come to have knowledge of the world through
socialization into specific world-views, which give
a definition of what reality is, how to investigate
it, what questions to ask about it, and how to
answer them – in short, paradigms. Kuhn demonstrated that paradigms rose and fell and that
knowledge was not cumulative: for example, Newtonian mechanics and Albert Einstein’s relativism
are not cumulative and they cannot be reconciled.
Put another way, our knowledge of the world is
not built on any correspondence theory of truth.
This point was made most importantly by W. V.
Quine, in Words and Objects (1960), where he
argued that there was nothing in reality or our
sensory experience of it that led to the logical
distinctions that we make about it. K E V I N W H I T E
encoding/decoding
– see Stuart Hall.
end-of-ideology thesis
– see ideology.
endogamy
– see kinship.
165
Engels, Friedrich (1820–1895)
entrepreneurship
Engels, Friedrich (1820–1895)
An interpreter, collaborator, and popularizer of
Karl Marx. Born in Barmen, Germany, he went to
Britain to manage the family factory in Manchester. He first met Marx in 1842 and his Outlines for a
Critique of Political Economy was well received by the
latter. The two agreed to work together in attacks
on the Young Hegelians and in 1845 Engels published his Condition of the Working Classes in England,
a study based on detailed empirical work on the
plight of workers, particularly in Manchester.
Engels’s strength was his clarity of argument.
Critics have felt that he oversimplified Marx
and extended Marx’s theory into areas such as
the natural sciences where it is not appropriate.
His loyalty (and financial assistance) to Marx is
not questionable, however. He wrote fascinating
historical work on Germany after the crushing
of the 1848 revolutions (see revolution, theory of),
and his Anti-Dühring was a fierce critique of a
German socialist. His Socialism: Utopian and Scientific appeared in English in 1892, a popularizing
work that was widely read. In 1894 he wrote
the Origin of the Family, Private Property and the
State, a work that built sympathetically on
the anthropology of Lewis Henry Morgan (1818–
81). In 1888 his Ludwig Feuerbach and the End
of German Classical Philosophy was published, and
did much to expound Marxist theory as a dialectical and historical materialism. His Dialectics of
Nature appeared posthumously in 1927. After
Marx’s death, Engels devoted the rest of his life
to editing and translating Marx’s writings.
JOHN HOFFMAN
Enlightenment
In the western tradition, Enlightenment (éclaircissement, aufklärung) refers to the process of becoming
rational in thought and action. It can be individual or society-wide. Either way, reason is figured
as a light that illuminates the understanding and
dispels the darkness of ignorance and superstition. Enlightenment thus conceived has two sides.
Positively, it entails the empowering discovery
of well-founded knowledge; critically, it is a movement of demystification, skeptical towards anything that cannot give an adequate account of
itself before the bar of reason or experience.
Historically, the term is associated with the
eighteenth-century European intellectual movement that championed reason and progress
against the enchainment of thought by, especially religious, tradition and belief. Hence “the
Enlightenment” (capitalized) to designate that
166
movement, and the broader shift towards secularism, republicanism, humanism, and science to
which it was connected. Important centers of
Enlightenment thought were Scotland (Hutchinson, Hume, Ferguson, Smith), France (Montesquieu, Diderot, Voltaire, D’Alembert), England
(Shaftesbury, Paine, Bentham, Wollstonecraft),
and the United States (Franklin, Jefferson), though
its crowning philosopher was Immanuel Kant
(1724–1804). For many Enlightenment thinkers, a
model for reason (and intellectual progress) was
provided by the natural sciences, with Francis
Bacon taken as their prophet and Isaac Newton’s
“terrestrial” and “celestial” mechanics as their
paradigm – whence a further ambition to extend
the scientific model to the human realm. Just as
the sciences of nature could lead to material progress, so knowledge of man as part of nature could
lead to social and moral progress. Such thinking
led to ambitious totalizations like that of the
French Encyclopédistes, as well as to the more specialized development of what became the disciplines of psychology, economics, sociology, and
anthropology. While Enlightenment thinking
had a technocratic strain, it also linked reason
with freedom and autonomy, as in Kant’s 1794
definition of enlightenment as “man’s leaving
his self-caused immaturity” by “daring to think.”
Optimism about the emancipatory and civilizing
potential of knowledge-based progress peaked
in the nineteenth century, but waned in the disasters of the succeeding century. Max Horkheimer
and Theodor Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment
(1948 [trans. 1972]) criticized the actual course of
enlightenment in their own time as a totalitarian
disaster in which enlightenment itself had regressed to myth. Against this, and also against postmodernists like Jean-François Lyotard and Jacques
Derrida who deconstructed logocentric narratives
of progress, Jürgen Habermas has defended
enlightened modernity as “an unfinished project.”
ANDREW WERNICK
entrepreneurship
This topic is discussed in several social-science
disciplines, and therefore a sociological view of
entrepreneurship has to include references to
non-sociological works. This, for example, is decidedly the case with the work of the founder of
the study of entrepreneurship, economist Joseph
Alois Schumpeter.
Schumpeter presented the essentials of his
theory of entrepreneurship in The Theory of Economic Development (1911 [trans. 1934]). The essence
entrepreneurship
of entrepreneurship, it is here suggested, is a new
combination of already existing elements in the
economy. Schumpeter also emphasizes that one of
the great difficulties for the entrepreneur is that
he or she has to break with the past. There is
typically a strong resistance to change that has
to be overcome, if there is to be an innovation.
In a famous passage in The Theory of Economic
Development, Schumpeter enumerates the main
types of innovation: (1) the opening of a new
market; (2) the introduction of a new merchandise; (3) the introduction of a new method of
production; (4) a change in the organization
of an industry; and (5) getting a new and cheaper
source of raw materials or half-manufactured
goods. Innovations, in other words, can happen
anywhere in the economic process, from the
assembly of material for production to the end
product being marketed and presented to the prospective customer. What drives the entrepreneur
is not so much money, Schumpeter also argues, as
the joy of creating, the possibility of creating one’s
own kingdom, and to succeed for the sake of success. A successful innovation, Schumpeter adds,
creates entrepreneurial profit – which tempts
others to imitate the initial entrepreneur till a
situation is reached when no more entrepreneurial profit is to be had. In Capitalism, Socialism and
Democracy (1942) Schumpeter, finally, feared that
huge corporations would kill the initiative of the
individual to be an entrepreneur.
As Richard Swedberg shows in Entrepreneurship
(2001), post-Schumpeterian research on entrepreneurship has, to repeat, been interdisciplinary
in nature. There exists, for example, whole literatures on entrepreneurship by psychologists,
economic historians, and economists.
Sociologists lack a sustained tradition of studying entrepreneurship but have nonetheless produced a number of interesting studies during
the last few decades. One genre of such studies
deals with so-called ethnic entrepreneurship or
the role that entrepreneurship plays in various
ethnic groups. One insight, for example in Roger
Waldinger’s Ethnic Entrepreneurs (1990), from this
type of literature is that successful ethnic entrepreneurs have to find other customers than their
co-ethnics (“the ethnic market”) if they are to
become truly successful. Sociologists also tend to
emphasize the role of the group in entrepreneurship, as opposed to the single individual.
Entrepreneurship in modern corporations, for
example, often means the putting together of a
group, in combination with an effort to stimulate
its members to work on some task, as Rosabeth
environment
Moss Kanter shows in The Change Masters (1983).
Finally, much contemporary sociological research
looks at the earliest stages of entrepreneurship,
so-called start-ups, but also what goes on before
these exist – an issue which is discussed in
Howard E. Aldrich’s entry on “Entrepreneurship,”
in R. Swedberg and N. Smelser (eds.), Handbook of
Economic Sociology (2004).
RICHARD SWEDBERG
environment
Since its emergence as a political and social issue
during the 1960s, the environment has been a
topic of sociological interest. Owing to its intrinsic
complexity and its intimate connection to a nonsocial and nonhuman “natural” realm, the environment has shown itself to be difficult to subject
to sociological scrutiny, however. The traditional
demarcation between nature and society that is
assumed by many, if not all, sociologists to be a
defining characteristic of modernity has caused
difficulties, which have been reinforced by institutional barriers which tend to separate sociologists from other environmental scientists, as well
as from the users of their knowledge.
Nonetheless, in recent years sociologists interested in the environment have produced a variety
of theoretical insights and empirical research findings, even though there is little agreement among
them about how environmental issues are most
appropriately to be comprehended and investigated. The sociology of the environment, or environmental sociology, as it is sometimes called, has
suffered from many of the same processes of specialization and compartmentalization that have
affected other sociological subfields.
In comparison to other areas of social life, and
in relation to the discipline as a whole, the environment has remained a relatively marginal topic
of explicit sociological interest. It can be suggested that other social scientific disciplines have
been more successful in “appropriating” the environment as a topic for investigation. Particularly
in regard to external research funding and programs in environmental science, sociologists have
tended to be less active and less visible than political scientists, psychologists, economists, geographers, and policy scientists. This is not merely
because of a lack of entrepreneurial skill or energy
on the part of sociologists. There is also a structural or disciplinary basis for the relative lack of
interest in the environment among sociologists.
For one thing, most of the classic sociological
texts give short shrift to environmental problems,
and have thus provided little intellectual guidance
in helping latter-day interpreters to deal with
167
environment
them, either theoretically or empirically. Generally viewed as “side effects” or subplots in the
main story-lines of modernity and modernization,
environmental issues were, for the most part,
bracketed out of the foundational narratives
of the discipline. Karl Marx, Max Weber, Émile
Durkheim, and George Herbert Mead, as well as
Herbert Spencer and Ferdinand Tönnies, all expressed in varying degrees a positive attitude to
the human exploitation of the natural environment, if they referred to it at all. They all shared
a respect for, and indeed sought to emulate, the
natural and engineering sciences, whose development is generally considered to be one of the root
causes of environmental problems.
It can be suggested that this identification with
science, and the attempt to make sociology itself
into a science, has served to limit the seriousness
with which sociologists have concerned themselves with the environment. Even though there
were significant differences among them, the
founding fathers of the discipline placed whatever
criticisms they might have had about science and
technology and the exploitation of nature in the
margins, or footnotes, of their works. While Marx,
for instance, praised the “civilizational role” of
modern industry and of its science and technology
in no uncertain terms, he only noted in passing
that this civilization had negative implications
for nonhuman nature. He never placed environmental issues in the foreground of his analyses of
capitalist society, which was exclusively focused
on the underlying dynamics, or laws of society.
Similarly, Max Weber analyzed and, on occasion,
bemoaned the rationalization processes of contemporary life, but the environmental implications of those processes were never examined
explicitly. As such, the environment was marginal
to the formation of a sociological identity, or
imagination.
As sociology became institutionalized in the
course of the twentieth century, the environment
continued to be neglected as a topic of investigation. The kinds of environmental problems that
became socially significant in the 1960s – industrial pollution, energy and resource limitations,
consumer risk and safety – were issues that fell
far outside the disciplinary mainstream. They
had either been delegated to other social science
disciplines (economics, geography, and political
science, in particular) or they were seen as aspects,
or secondary dimensions, of other sociological
concerns, such as urbanization, social conflict, regional development, or science and technology.
It might be suggested that the paradigms or
168
environment
disciplinary matrices of sociology as a field had
come to “frame” the sociological objects of study
in such a way as to make environmental issues
marginal at best and invisible at worst. The environment was seldom viewed as an independent
variable or a social issue in its own right.
The environmental debate of the 1960s, associated with such popular writings as Rachel
Carson’s Silent Spring (1962) and Paul Ehrlich’s
The Population Bomb (1968), had only a minor impact on sociology. The key texts of the environmental “movement” were written by natural
scientists or science writers, and received little
interest from sociologists. For reasons of language
and education, as well as inclination and interest,
the new issues were considered of secondary importance for sociologists. It was not until the
emergence of major environmental conflicts in
the 1970s, particularly over energy policy, and
nuclear energy in particular, that an environmental subfield began to develop with any intensity.
Subsequent sociological concern with the environment has been strongly divided into what
C. Wright Mills, in The Sociological Imagination
(1959), once called “grand theory” and “abstracted
empiricism.” While the theorists have sought
to integrate environmental issues into broader
conceptualizations and frameworks of interpretation, the more empirically minded have gradually added environmental issues to the growing
number of social problems and social movements
that they investigate. In this respect, a sociological
interest in the environment has often been mixed
with an interest in other social domains: the
media, public administration, urban conflicts,
and development. Little attempt has been made
to “test” the rather abstract notions that the
theorists have proposed with empirical research,
and there has been little coordination of the various projects carried out by the empiricists in order
to develop generalizations or systematic comparisons. As a result, the sociology of the environment
has come to be fragmented into a number of
approaches that are seldom combined in any
meaningful way.
In theoretical terms, sociologists have generally tried to incorporate the environment into
the received frameworks of interpretation that
they have derived from the so-called classics.
Many have been the attempts to apply the terminology of Marx, Weber, or Durkheim to the sociology of the environment. An early effort by
Alan Schnaiberg (The Environment: From Surplus to
Scarcity, 1980) proposed the concept of the “treadmill of production” to characterize the social basis
environment
of environmental problems, which was derived
from the Marxian concept of capital accumulation.
Schnaiberg and the many other Marxian theorists
who have followed have generally sought to frame
environmental problems in materialist or historical materialist language, and thereby to connect
the environment to relations of production. As
with environmental economists, these theorists
have tended to see environmental problems as dependent on, or determined by, other more fundamental social processes.
The influential theory of Ulrich Beck has, on the
other hand, drawn on the classical conceptions of
Tönnies and Weber to develop a social theory in
which environmental problems are given a more
central or determinant place. In the 1980s, Beck
proposed the concept of risk society as an allencompassing term to reflect the underlying social
changes that had brought environmental issues
into social and political life. Like other theorists
of postindustrial society, Beck’s theory posits a
fundamental shift in the overall logic, or rationality, of society, in his case from the production of
goods to the manufacture of uncertainty, endemic
risks, and dangers. Environmental problems are
thus a structural characteristic of the contemporary age, a determinant factor in society. For Beck
and many of the “risk” theorists who have been
inspired by him, social processes and activities are
no longer dominated by the conditions of modern
industry – instead, we have entered the age of
what Beck terms “reflexive modernization.”
At a somewhat lower level of abstraction, and
with a more explicitly political ambition, the risksociety thesis has been modified into a theory of
“ecological modernization,” which has exerted a
wide influence over many European social scientists and policymakers. Ecological modernization
has been developed both by sociologists and by
political scientists for analyzing institutional arrangements and administrative procedures that
have been devised, primarily in relation to the
political and social programs of so-called sustainable development. As such, ecological modernization has served perhaps more as a political
ideology or policy doctrine than as a theoretical
framework for academic sociologists.
A distinction can be made between those theories that seek to link environmental issues explicitly to sociology and social theory and those that
draw on concepts from the natural and environmental sciences, and are thus less directly disciplinary. This “ecological turn” has been facilitated
by interdisciplinary research programs in global
environmental change and human ecology, as
environment
well as by institutional linkages, or networks
that have been established between sociologists
and environmentally interested scientists in other
fields. Some have distinguished between environmental sociology and ecological sociology. In the
more ecological theories, social processes are
depicted in terms of resource and energy flows,
as theorists make use of concepts derived from
systems theory, and, more recently, complexity
theory.
The sociological interest in the environment
has from the 1970s been fragmented into a number of empirically delineated specialty areas. Sociologists have investigated a wide range of
environmental conflicts, movements, and forms
of activism, as well as the myriad processes of
institutionalization, professionalization, (see profession(s)) and organization of environmental concern. There has also been a continuous research
activity, using quantitative and survey methods to
explore public attitudes to environmental problems, shifts in media coverage of environmental
issues, membership patterns in environmental organizations and campaigns, and aspects of environmental lifestyles and consumer preferences. In
these more empirical areas, links have been established between environmental sociologists and
sociologists of science and technology, as well as
with organizational sociologists and scholars of
social and political movements. In many cases,
particularly in relation to local environmental
conflicts, sociologists have combined an academic
and an activist role in new forms of action, or
action-oriented research.
In both theoretical and empirical terms, the
sociology of the environment has provided fundamental contributions to what might be called
the reinvention of the sociology of knowledge.
Since the use of knowledge and expertise plays a
central role in almost every significant environmental conflict, sociological analysis has helped
elucidate some of the main processes involved.
Depending on the terminology, these processes
have been characterized as organizational learning, reflexive knowledge, citizen science, or cognitive praxis, to mention only some of the concepts
that have been developed. In this respect, the
sociology of the environment has contributed to
the broader social understanding of knowledge
production, and has, in many specific cases, combined environmental sociology with the sociology
of science, or scientific knowledge. The way
in which science has come to be used in environmental policy has been a major focal point of
sociological investigation.
169
environmental movements
The sociology of the environment has also been
central to the opening of sociology as a whole
to interdisciplinary and cross-cultural interactions. An environmental focus or point of departure has proved valuable for initiating
collaboration across disciplinary boundaries and
for opening spaces for communication between
the human and the nonhuman sciences. As a
result, there has been a fertilization and “translation” of theoretical terms and concepts in both
directions, and there has also been a variety of
hybridizations of social scientists and natural
scientists into transdisciplinary environmental
scientists.
In the future it can be expected that the tension
between environmental sociology as a distinct
subfield within the discipline and as a part of a
broader and less academically defined intellectual
activity will continue. The value of sociological
understanding for the resolution of environmental conflicts and the solution of environmental
problems is significant, and it is to be hoped that
sociologists will continue to contribute to the
broader pursuit of a sustainable development or
an ecological society.
ANDREW JAMISON
environmental movements
– see social movements.
environmental rights
– see rights.
epidemiology
Defined as the study of the patterning and determinants of the incidence and distribution of disease, the discipline of epidemiology is concerned
with environmental factors – whether physical,
biological, chemical, psychological, or social –
that affect health, and also considers the course
and outcomes of disease in individuals and in
groups. Where social variables are emphasized –
the distribution of disease by social circumstances
and social class, for instance, rather than more
strictly biological aspects of sex, race, or geographical environment – the term social epidemiology is
often used.
The formal beginning of the discipline was in
the nineteenth century with the work of the pioneers of public health. John Snow (1813–55), in his
Report on the Cholera Outbreak in the Parish of St.
James, Westminster (1854), famously demonstrated
the transmission of cholera through contamination of the London water supply, “cured” by the
removal of the handle of the Broad St. pump. The
epidemiological approach, comparing rates of
170
epidemiology
disease in subgroups of populations, became increasingly used in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth century, applied at first mainly to the
investigation and control of communicable
disease.
Well-known examples of its nature and successes include assisting in the eradication of
smallpox in the world by the l970s. A classical
triumph of epidemiology was the conclusive demonstration by Sir Richard Doll (1912–2005) in 1954
of the association between smoking and lung
cancer. This classical follow-up study of the mortality of almost 35,000 male British doctors continued to offer results for over fifty years. In 2004 a
new report in the Lancet celebrated this milestone
in public health by showing that the risks of persistent cigarette smoking were actually greater
than previously thought, and about one-half to
two-thirds of all persistent smokers would eventually be killed by the habit. It was also shown,
however, that quitting at any age, even up to the
60s, gains years of life expectancy.
Epidemiology is essentially a statistical discipline, dealing in rates of disease and mortality,
but has always acknowledged multiple and interactive causes of ill-health. Behavior and lifestyle
are increasingly held to be important in the causal
analysis of population, and epidemiology studies
their effects, and also how the control and prevention of problems in both can be more effective.
One of the most recent examples of the contribution of epidemiology has been to the study of
the HIV/AIDS epidemic, where it has been vital to
trace out the worldwide patterns of spread and
control, rates of transmission, and changing outcomes. This health crisis has also been responsible
for some coming-together of ethnographic and
qualitative sociological methods of enquiry with
the more statistical science represented by epidemiology, since unconventional methods were
necessary to gain knowledge (of, for instance,
drug use, prostitution, and intimate sexual behavior) essential for the modeling of epidemiological
statistics and predictions.
Medical sociology in some respects grew out of
social epidemiology, and still has close links with
it. Some divergence between the disciplines, however, relates to the fact that epidemiological statistics are population statistics and so can say
nothing about any individual. How doctors present this to patients, and how lay people interpret
at a personal level the statistical facts of epidemiology in the form of rates and probabilities, is a
topic of interest in medical sociology, particularly
in the currently active fields of genetics and risk.
epistemology
Environmental epidemiology, an important
branch of the discipline, faces contemporary challenges of global change. The study of causal pathways at societal levels is sometimes called
eco-epidemiology. Globalization is also relevant
in relation to the necessity for global control of
pandemic diseases.
MILDRED BLAXTER
epistemology
The theory of knowledge, epistemology is one
of the core subjects within philosophy. It tries to
answer questions about the nature, sources, scope,
and justification of knowledge. In some languages,
epistemology is often equated with the philosophy
of science. However, in sociology, epistemology has
also often been used in a broader sense. Epistemology of the social sciences, for instance, deals with
issues of method. What, if any, methodological
guidelines ought to be adopted? What, if any,
are the differences between the social and the
natural sciences? In this respect, two debates are
worth mentioning. First, in the Methodenstreit in
nineteenth-century Germany, positivism and hermeneutics were opposed to each other. Positivist
authors postulated methodological unity between
the social and the natural sciences; it assumed the
existence of laws or law-like generalizations in the
social realm; and it postulated the possibility of
value-free social science. Hermeneutic authors
argued that the study of historical and social phenomena aims to understand (not explain) specific
instances (not general laws). They also argued that
sociology and history could never obtain valueneutrality. Max Weber adopted an intermediate
position in this debate. Second, in the 1950s the
Positivismusstreit opposed the positivist school and
critical theory. Positivist-inclined authors, like
Hans Albert and Karl Popper, tried to establish
the scientific foundations for sociology. For critical theorists, like Theodor Adorno and Jürgen
Habermas, sociology should be preoccupied with
self-emancipation and critique of society. For
them, value-neutrality is impossible.
In philosophy the traditional notion of epistemology searches for the universal foundations which
underpin an individual’s knowledge and secure
its validity and neutrality. This notion of epistemology has come under recent attack. First, influenced by American pragmatism, Richard Rorty
(1931– ) argues that we should substitute hermeneutics for epistemology. Whereas epistemology
tries to establish a-temporal foundations for
cognitive claims, hermeneutics is sensitive to the
situated nature of knowledge. For Rorty, recent
equality
developments within analytical philosophy (for instance, the work of Donald Davidson [1917–2003]
and Willard Quine [1908–2000]) have made epistemology (as the search for foundations of knowledge) untenable. Philosophy should aim at
Bildung and self-edification. Second, social epistemology pays particular attention to the social
aspects of the sources, justification, and diffusion
of knowledge. Social epistemology draws on Science and Technology Studies. It can be an explanatory and descriptive endeavor (for instance, how
did a particular theory become widely held?) or a
normative enterprise (for instance, how can we
organize academic institutions more effectively?).
Third, feminist epistemologists emphasize the gendered nature of knowledge, the extent to which
men and women develop different types of knowledge. Some forms of feminism challenge the assumption of neutrality and advocate standpoint
theory. According to standpoint theory, women
are in some respects better placed to obtain knowledge. This is by virtue of their specific position in
society. Some theorists extend standpoint theory to
refer to superior forms of knowledge linked to any
marginal, subordinated, or oppressed category.
PATRICK BAERT
equality
The problem of equality has been a persistent
topic of western philosophy and political theory.
There is considerable debate about equal treatment of individuals in society as a normative
principle (“people ought to be equal”) and the
claim “all human beings are equal” as a statement
of fact. Before the modernization of society,
human beings were thought to be equal (“in the
eyes of God”) in religious terms, or they were
equal (in nature) under Natural Law. The contradiction between the normative view and the empirical condition of inequality produces conditions
for radical social change. Secular theories of
equality are associated with Karl Marx who argued
that human beings were equal before the advent
of private property and the development of class
relations in capitalism. For Marx, socialism would
restore the equality between men through a revolutionary change of society. In his study of Equality
(1931), R. H. Tawney combined socialism and
Christian theology to develop a normative theory
of society. Tawney was critical of capitalist society
that intensified inequality by stimulating human
greed for commodities. His study of Religion and
the Rise of Capitalism (1926) developed a critique
of individualism as an alternative to Max Weber
171
equality
and The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
(1905 [trans. 2002]). In the post-war period, social
reconstruction was often pursued through the
Keynesian (see Keynes, John Maynard) welfare
state, and by developing social citizenship many
western governments committed themselves to
social policies that were designed to reduce inequalities. However, in the 1970s and 1980s many
western governments embraced neo-liberal social
policies, associated with British Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher (1925– ) and the American President
Ronald Reagan (1911–2004), that emphasized entrepreneurship, individualism, profit, and self-reliance. The consequences of these policies, which
involved, for example, cutting personal income
tax, were to increase the efficiency of industry
and the profitability of investment, but they also
increased social inequality, as measured, for instance, by post-tax income. Some economists such
as Partha Dasgupta in An Inquiry into Well-Being and
Destitution (1993) argue that infant mortality rates,
life expectancy at birth, and literacy rates provide
better measures of resource allocation in society
than measures of income inequality, such as the
gini coefficient. These can be regarded as traditional measures of inequality, but with globalization and the revolution in information there are
new aspects to inequality such as the digital divide.
Access to electronic information via the internet is
increasingly important as a measure of equality.
The principal theme in philosophical debate
has been to determine to what extent differences
between human beings can be derived from natural differences and from social evaluation. For
example, as a matter of fact, men in the United
States are on average taller than men in Japan,
but should this natural difference lead to any
difference in evaluation? Ralph Dahrendorf, in a
famous essay “On the Origins of Social Inequality”
(in P. Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds.), Philosophy,
Politics and Society 2nd series, 1962), distinguished
four types of inequality. The first concerns natural
differences of kind (such as the color of eyes).
Second, there are natural differences of rank (between talents or intelligence). Third, there is the
social differentiation of positions (such as the division of labor); and finally there is social stratification, involving a rank ordering of individuals
(by prestige and wealth). Sociologists have typically concerned themselves with this fourth type of
inequality, have sought to avoid normative judgements about the ontological equality of people as
human beings, and have focused their empirical
research on the various dimensions of inequality
in studies of poverty, income distribution, and
172
equality
wealth. As a result, equality has not been studied
directly, because it is implicitly treated as the
residue of inequality. The level of equality in society is implicitly measured by the extent of
inequality.
There are broadly four types of equality. First,
there are religious arguments in favor of an ontological equality of human beings, regardless of
their de facto differences. This type of equality
was supported by Natural Law philosophers, but
it is now associated with human rights, because
Article 1 of the United Nations Universal Declaration
of Human Rights announced in 1945 that “All
human beings are born free and equal in dignity
and rights.” Second, there is the liberal notion of
equality of opportunity, which means that access
to important social institutions such as higher
education should be available to all on universalistic criteria. This principle emphasizes talent over
inheritance and promotes the idea of meritocracy
(see credentialism). The argument is that social
roles should be open to achievement and competition, not ascription. Sociological research shows,
however, that this form of equality is often
limited as a result of racial discrimination or
gender bias against women.
Equality of opportunity can never fully guarantee a “level playing field.” For example, successful
parents will tend to pass on their wealth and
cultural capital (see social capital) to their children. Third, equality of condition involves various
strategies to address limitations in equality of
opportunity. For example, taxation (of personal
income and the inheritance of property) can be
used to reduce inter-generational inequalities.
Affirmative action programs also attempt to
ensure that equality of condition is not compromised by negative attitudes, for example towards
the employment of mothers, the elderly, or minority groups. Affirmative action programs are also
relevant to the fourth type of equality, namely
equality of outcome. A university that decided to
offer every student a degree regardless of their
actual performance would have a policy of equality of outcome. However, to create an egalitarian
society requires considerable state intervention
into society, especially in the market, through
taxation, affirmative action, and legislation. Liberals and anarchists believe that the state should
not interfere with the right of individuals to
dispose of their own assets. Liberals argue that
the fundamental principle of freedom is the right
to individual property. From the perspective
of functionalism, individuals have to be motivated
to fill positions in society that are dangerous, or
essentialism
estates
demanding, or require extensive training. In the
Davis and Moore debate (see functional theory
of stratification), social inequality in terms of
prestige and wealth is necessary to ensure that
functionally necessary tasks are undertaken.
Although liberal democratic societies typically
embrace the idea, expressed in the Declaration
of Human Rights, that all human beings are equal,
very few governments are willing or able to implement policies that would radically promote equality among their citizens. In a parliamentary
democracy, the economic interests of the wealthy
will always prevail over the interests of the
poor. Since the early 1980s, governments adopting
post-Keynesian strategies have cut personal taxation, reduced expenditure on welfare, and privatized social services. The consequence has been to
increase inequality.
BRYAN S. TURNER
essentialism
This term has been, since the mid-1980s, at the heart
of debates about the extent to which the human
condition is formed by the natural characteristics
of gender and race. The politics of essentialism
have revolved around the double-sided possibilities
of essentialism: asserting the importance of a
category such as “woman” allows a politics organized around that term and yet at the same time
contains female people within a concept which
may be interpreted as naturalistic and potentially
coercive. Similar arguments apply to the use of
racially and ethnically specific terms; in all cases,
the powerful arguments for political organization
and mobilization around certain definable characteristics – which often underpin considerable similarities of circumstance and experience – are
contested by those who argue that any form of
“essential” identity is in itself an identity imposed,
and maintained, by those who are more powerful.
For women, essentialism has been contested because it positions women within a binary opposition in which they can never be men and in which
all forms of social negotiation have to be conducted through a “natural” condition. From the
end of the twentieth century, considerable theoretical energy has been devoted to separating both
masculinity and femininity from male and female;
resistance to this idea remains considerable, particularly from psychoanalytically informed sociology which maintains that distinct biologies of
male and female do exist and that the recognition
of this fact (and consideration of its consequences)
does not in itself constitute essentialism.
MARY EVANS
estates
A system of social stratification in which rights and
duties were legally defined, estates were based on a
common principle of the hierarchical organization
of social strata in pre-industrial societies, such as
feudalism. The analysis of the survival of estate
systems has been an important aspect of the theory
of revolutions. In Economy and Society, Max Weber
(1922 [trans. 1978]) classified estates as a form of
traditional authority, specifically patrimonial authority or “estate-type domination.” Estates, which
were typically divided into nobility, clergy, and
commoners, flourished in France, Germany, and
Russia before the rise of capitalism, when new
forms of economic power confronted the traditional distribution of aristocratic titles and privileges. Estate domination in Weber’s terms involved
an authoritarian, militarized nobility surrounding
a monarch or emperor. The heyday of the French
system of estates corresponded with the rule of
Louis XIV (1643–1715) and the consolidation of absolutism in the seventeenth century. Whereas in
France the estate system remained an inflexible
system of privilege, the English social structure
permitted the entry of bourgeois capitalists into
the nobility. Although the traditional authority of
the English nobility was undermined by the English Civil War and the execution of Charles 1 in
1649, the division between the House of Lords and
the House of Commons in the British parliamentary system represents the last vestiges of the
“estates of the realm.” The French system of estates
was destroyed by the French Revolution (1789–98),
but a militarized and conservative nobility (known
as the Junkers) survived in Germany and was an
important aspect of Weber’s analysis of the political and cultural rigidity of Germany at the beginning of the twentieth century. The German nobility
was shattered by the crisis of World War I, but the
political system based on authoritarian “statism”
survived much longer, according to G. Kvistad in
The Rise and Demise of German Statism (1999). An
estate system also existed in Russia until the
Bolsheviks came to power after the October Revolution of 1917, when military defeats, food shortages,
and revolutionary conflict brought an end
to autocratic Tsardom. Given the strength of the
Russian estate system, Weber remained pessimistic
about the possibilities of social change in Russia in
his The Russian Revolutions (1917 [trans. 1995]). In
conclusion, the rigidity of the system of estates –
the survival of the nobility and the peasantry into
modern times – has often been seen as an obstacle
to the development of democracy, for example in
173
ethnic group
ethnicity and ethnic groups
Barrington Moore’s Social Origins of Dictatorship and
Democracy (1966).
BRYAN S. TURNER
ethnic group
– see ethnicity.
ethnic mosaic
This expression is a euphemism used by dominant
ethnic groups to represent their political and
economic intentions towards ethnic minorities
as benign or, even, well-intentioned. Similar expressions include “melting pot,” “salad bowl,”
and “multiculturalism.” From the late twentieth
century, terms like “melting pot,” which convey
the cultural ideal that ethnic differences will in
time melt away, have been replaced by terms that
serve to respect the differences as reconcilable if
unbridgeable. Thus, after the 1960s in the European diaspora, popular groups tended to speak of
the national society as a salad bowl, in which the
differing vegetables contribute to the cultural
taste of the whole without relinquishing their
differences. Evidently multiculturalism is a somewhat more abstract version of the same well-intentioned theory that different ethnic groups can
achieve a state of peaceful coexistence – as in
fact they occasionally do, for example between
the French and the English in Canada and the
Walloons and Flemish in Belgium. Ethnic mosaic
is a somewhat more scientific term used in the
social sciences to lend an analytic legitimacy to
what is otherwise a historical incongruity. The
ethnic mosaic, like the metaphorical salad bowl,
connotes the ideal that ethnic conflicts are aberrations limiting the social good which can be
achieved when groups set aside differences to
work together for the common good. In real history, the ethnic mosaic ideal strains against
ethnocentrism, which seems to be a deeper structural feature of ethnic groups. The disposition to
consider one’s own group as superior aggravates,
even in the most stable of ethnic mosaics, the
potential for affirmation of differences that the
dominant culture may be unable to suppress.
CHARLES LEMERT
ethnic nationalism
– see nationalism.
ethnicity and ethnic groups
These concepts are intended to define social differences associated with, but theoretically distinct
from, racial ones. It is common, thereby, for social
analysts to link race and ethnicity to suggest that
174
ethnic differences go beyond, while including,
racial ones. The distinction is not entirely arbitrary owing to the predominance of biological
theories of race in late modern European diasporic cultures. Among the most notable modern
examples of the confusion wrought by race and
ethnicity is the United States, where racism has
long been a structural feature of its status in the
capitalist world-system. It is necessary to distinguish race from ethnicity when there is reason to
justify a national or regional economy’s reliance
on slavery or other pre-modern forms of feudal
or despotic production. West African people captured and transshipped to the Americas from
the long sixteenth century until the nineteenth
century, were defined as a race as opposed to
an ethnic group for two reasons: one, they had
lost their ties to their original ethnic cultures in
Africa; two, the shame of economic reliance
on slave labor called for a pseudo-scientific justification in the form of the racial attribution being
offered as a sign of an inherent biological difference that stipulated the mental, even categorical,
inferiority of blacks. Today, it is very well known
that racial differences are biologically insignificant and that ethnicity must be considered quite
apart from its assumed associations with race.
The word ethnic descends from the Greek
noun ethnos, which has entered into modern languages, including English, variously as “people”
and “nation.” Yet, the somewhat awkward derivative “ethnicity” did not come into play until relatively late in the nineteenth century when
sociology and other academic social sciences, still
immature institutionally, were forced to account
for the social conflicts arising from the presence
of immigrant groups in European and North
American cities. It was then that “heathen” or
“barbarian,” a third but already archaic sense of
ethnic differences, may be detected in analytic
usages. Ethnic differences are thus most severe
in host societies when groups considered foreign
come to live in close proximity. Their languages,
customs, religions, cuisines, and other cultural
practices appear strange to established citizens
of the host nations — even when their own ancestries can be traced to groups whose social habits
were once alien.
Simply put, ethnicities are of analytic importance when differing peoples are forced to live
close by each other in an established region or
political territory such as the modern nation-state.
Ethnic differences are most acute when the prevailing nation-state is unable to manage the
ethnicity and ethnic groups
conflicts that inevitably ensue when established
groups of the region depend on the aliens to satisfy their need for cheap and plentiful labor. In
the United States, for example, in the nineteenth
century, European groups were recruited to the
eastern and middle states, as Asian groups had
come to the western states, to relieve the acute
shortage of workers for hard labor in industry,
farming, and mining. In times of rapid economic
expansion, industrializing areas necessarily suffer
labor shortages. Whatever scruples the dominant
group may have as to the cultural habits of foreigners, they must embrace them if the economic
growth is to continue. The embrace is almost
always false and short-lived. Very often, the foreign labor is recruited from among the most stigmatized groups in the host nation, as when, in the
United States after 1914, World War I cut off
access to European immigrant labor, forcing the
northern industrial centers to recruit blacks from
the rural South.
Usually, ethnic groups are invited as (in the
European expression) “guest workers” to work in
low-end service, manufacturing, or agriculture
sectors. Yet, ethnic differences can also rise to
perplexing visibility when immigrant workers
are needed for highly skilled labor, as when,
from the last quarter of the twentieth century,
South Asian peoples came to play a major role in
technological and financial sectors throughout
the European diaspora.
Ethnicities, thus, are most salient when the host
nations are unable to manage the conflicts that
inevitably arise between the new ethnic groups
and the assimilated dominant groups or among
the ethnic groups themselves. Ethnic conflicts can
break into open warfare and civil discord when
the political sovereignty of the national or regional authorities weakens, as, after 1989, when
the collapse of the Soviet Union led to ethnic
violence in regions once under the control of
the Warsaw Pact — Chechnya and the Balkans,
among others. The extremes of ethnic violence
are realized when ethnic conflicts occur in regions
where there is little or no legitimate political
authority — as in Rwanda, Burundi, Congo, and
Uganda. Late in the twentieth century, ethnic
conflict between the Hutu and Tutsi led to the
slaughter of hundreds of thousands of innocents,
and early in the twenty-first century ongoing
violence, mainly against women and children, is
laying waste to villages in the Darfur region of the
Sudan. The fact that the global powers, notably
the United States, largely ignored these ethnic
wars while simultaneously seeking to manage
ethnocentrism
similar ones in Iraq among the Shi’a, Sunni,
and Kurds illustrates the role of economic and
geo-political interests in ethnic conflicts. A dominant ethnic group with the power to do so will
intervene in conflicts among other groups
only when its perceived interests are at stake.
Ethnocentrism seems, therefore, to be a naturally
occurring attribute of ethnic groups who will
engage rival groups with unusual ferocity when
their sense of ethnic privilege is threatened.
The artificiality of the analytic distinction between race and ethnicity is evident, thus, in the
degree to which the ethnic differences interact
with political realities. In the United States, for
example, people of the African diaspora were recognized as a legitimate ethnic group, AfricanAmerican, only after 1965 when the American
Civil Rights Movement forced the dominant
whites of European extraction to accept the civic
(if not social) legitimacy of blacks who, to that
point, had been defined narrowly as an excludable
racial minority. After the Voting Rights Act of
1965 in the United States, descendants of slaves
captured from West Africa as long as three centuries before increasingly claimed an African ethnic
identity of which most were necessarily ignorant.
Thus, ethnic practices can occasionally be latterday inventions intended to connect people to
a lost ancient tradition, as in the case of the
African-American Kwanzaa, a holiday introduced
in 1966 to celebrate the ancient traditions of West
Africa. At the same time, when the dominant
ethnic group or groups are forced, in times of
relative domestic or regional peace, to accept formerly obnoxious cultural differences, they will
themselves invent cultural ideals celebrating their
own civility, as in the case of expressions like
ethnic mosaic or melting pot, which serve to cover
their own history of incivility and cruelty towards
ethnic minorities.
In short, ethnicity is a sociological concept
meant to disentangle the complex historical
ties between cultural differences and political
CHARLES LEMERT
and economic power.
ethnocentrism
The seemingly universal cultural habit of considering one’s own ethnicity unique, and thus in
some sense – or several senses – special, the most
striking instance of ethnocentrism in the modern
world is that of the North American peoples in
the United States who, over more than two centuries of history, thought of “America” as exceptional for the purity and goodness of its values.
American “exceptionalism,” like most forms of
175
ethnography
ethnocentrism, has shown itself to be a plastic
cultural attitude equally capable of reference to
religious culture (as in America as the New Israel
in the seventeenth-century Puritan theory of
divine providence) as to secular principles (as in
the doctrine of manifest destiny, an expression
used to justify the appropriation of lands from
Mexico in the 1840s). More often, if less accurately,
ethnocentrism is used to describe the evident unwillingness of foreign and domestic ethnic groups
to yield their distinctive cultural practices in
order to assimilate to those of the more powerful
dominant groups in control of state or regional
power.
Analytically, ethnocentrism describes the vicious cycle of inter-group relations by which
differing ethnicities respond to contact with
each other by claiming a natural superiority for
their own cultural practice, hence for themselves
CHARLES LEMERT
as a people.
ethnography
Involving the first-hand exploration and immersive participation in a natural research setting to
develop an empathic understanding (Verstehen)
of the lives of persons in that setting, ethnography
has its origins in the nearly simultaneous emergence in the early twentieth century of social
anthropological studies of the cultures of native
peoples and the social ecology studies of city
dwellers by sociologists of the Chicago School
(Ernest W. Burgess, Robert Ezra Park, and William
I. Thomas). The Chicago School wedded Thomas’s
appreciation of the theoretical insights of Charles
Horton Cooley and George Herbert Mead to Park’s
practical experience as a journalist. Once symbolic
interactionism emerged from Chicago, it found a
natural partner in ethnographic methods,
adapted to the study of organizations and other
settings as constituted by the interactions of the
participants. Likewise, it is difficult to see how
Erving Goffman’s dramaturgical perspective could
have been developed except in the explication of
ethnographic data.
Ethnography as a method retains a commitment
to naturalistic enquiry, that is, a commitment to
richly contextualized, extended, participant-eyed
description of the setting (alias the “thick description” recommended by Clifford Geertz in The Interpretation of Culture, 1973), with a minimum of
pre-existing hypotheses and a determination to
represent the phenomena at hand faithfully.
Thick description is an outcome of the sustained
immersion in the research field alongside the
writing of detailed reflective fieldnotes, which
176
ethnography
enable the researcher to represent the culture in
a multi-layered richness that is broader and more
comprehensive than schematic grand narratives.
The ethnographic tradition does not commit
itself to a specific data collection protocol, rather
it comprises a number of different methods, the
main components being interviews, participant
observation, and documentary analysis. Indeed,
some commentators distinguish ethnography, as
the written report and interpretation of a culture,
from fieldwork, as the modes of observing the
culture. The importance of the written ethnography has led some to observe that the ethnographer’s task is story-telling through personal
narrative, alongside other tasks of theory or typology development. Participant observation is
generally considered to be central to the ethnographic method. Participant observation involves
collection of data by participating in the social
world of those being studied, and interpreting
and reflecting upon the actions, interactions,
and language of individuals within that social
group. Fieldnotes are used to record observations
and fragments of remembered speech. The use of
multiple methods within an ethnographic project
enables different insights to emerge. For example,
interviews provide access to subjects’ descriptions,
rationalizations, and reflections about their behavior, while observation provides insights, both
into non-rational behaviors that may remain
undisclosed in an interview, and into the mundane everyday activities of the habitus, frequently
taken for granted and unarticulated within
subjects’ usual reportage.
The level to which ethnographers may choose to
integrate themselves into cultures can vary considerably, from fully participating in the interaction to remaining on the periphery of the
action as an observer. Participation of the ethnographer, and engagement in (or withdrawal from)
some activities in the fieldwork setting, places the
ethnographer within certain categories used by
participants (friend, confidant, guest, and outsider). Social distance between the ethnographer
and members of the culture being studied can
result in lack of trust, a lack of understanding,
or not knowing enough about the phenomena
under study to ask the right questions.
Good fieldwork relations are crucial and ethnographers will need to consider how best to
manage their personal identity accordingly (dress,
speech, and behavior). Field relationships may also
be facilitated by the skills, knowledge, and abilities of the ethnographer, which may range from
giving advice on medical or legal problems to
ethnography
helping with daily chores. Maintaining a reflexive
awareness will also enable the ethnographer to
assess the impact of field relationships on the
data collected.
Analysis of ethnographic data should start at
the piloting stage, continuing throughout data collection where the purpose of the research is progressively focused, and into the process of writing.
Indeed, the progressive focusing that occurs as a
consequence of continual analysis and reflection
often results in a significant shift of focus in terms
of the original aims of the study. During this inductive process, the ethnographer will make analytic notes in which are recorded ideas about
emerging features and patterns (whether they be
surprising or mundane), along with ideas of how
such patterns might be explained. While some ethnographies remain mainly as descriptions or accounts of the way of life in a particular setting,
other ethnographies are more theorized accounts
which focus on specific phenomena, or aspects of
the culture.
Traditionally, ethnography has been criticized for
its lack of objectivity, scientific rigor, and generalizability, and its relevance to social and political
practice. Thus, there have been many insightful ethnographies of drug use, from Howard S.
Becker’s Becoming a Marihuana User (1953) onward,
but their contribution to the formation of national
policies on drug misuse has been minimal. More
recently, ethnography has been subject to more
varied criticisms. Thus, ethnographers have experienced “the revolt of the subject,” challenged as to
whether s/he who is not a party can ever be a judge:
persons with disabilities, for example, have questioned whether those without disabilities have the
capacity to conduct disabilities research. Furthermore, doubts have been raised about realist claims
of the author’s authority to represent the truth
about the social world. Geertz himself is among
those who have condemned the production of
“author-evacuated texts” as an implicit denial of
the necessary dependence of all ethnographic
writing on particular discursive practices for establishing their verisimilitude. These relativist challenges have allowed multiple interpretations of
social phenomena and encouraged ethnographers
to demonstrate a reflexive awareness of the researcher’s constitutive contribution at all stages
of the research – including ethnographic writing.
The resulting tension between ethnographers’ commitment to realism and their recognition of relativism has been addressed by Martyn Hammersley’s
advocacy of “subtle realism” in What’s Wrong with
Ethnography? (1992). Subtle realism acknowledges
ethnomethodology
that different and competing accounts of social
worlds may be offered by ethnographers but requires that competing claims to knowing about
social worlds must be assessed for their plausibility
and credibility.
MICK BLOOR AND FIONA WOOD
ethnomethodology
Originally developed by Harold Garfinkel during
the 1950s and 1960s in theory-laden empirical
studies subsequently published in his Studies in
Ethnomethodology (1967), ethnomethodology is an
original approach to what Garfinkel terms the
seen but unnoticed aspects of social practices.
The term ethnomethodology also refers to the
sociological community of scholars who have refined, extended, and, in one case, refashioned
Garfinkel’s theoretical position.
The ethnomethodological community came
into being with the first generation of Garfinkel’s
students, notably including Harvey Sacks, who
founded conversational analysis (commonly
called CA) as a semiautonomous theoretical position. New centers of ethnomethodological research subsequently emerged in California, on
the East Coast, and in the Midwest in the United
States, and in England and Scotland as well.
Ethnomethodologists tend to maintain deep loyalties to their position and they build their intellectual networks through ties that are stronger than
is often the case in other intellectual communities
in sociology. Though ethnomethodologists themselves often prefer to work within the boundaries
of Garfinkel’s and Sacks’s founding principles, the
ethnomethodological view of social practices has
shaped a variety of other sociological projects and
programs as well. This is especially true of the socalled strong program in the sociology of science,
which analyzes the social construction of scientific knowledge and of Anthony Giddens’s structuration theory. Neither are ethnomethodological
in the strict sense of the term, but neither would
look quite the same in the absence of Garfinkel’s
original insights.
Ethnomethodology begins with an extremely
prosaic insight: social action in context is an actively produced accomplishment. From a distance
this may seem to put Garfinkel in the company
of philosophers such as John Dewey (1859–1952),
George Herbert Mead, Ludwig Wittgenstein (in
his later works), John Austin (1911–60), and
Garfinkel’s fellow sociologist Erving Goffman.
This is not entirely a false impression. All of these
theorists reject the centrality of consciousness
in any form as the pivot of social behavior (via
such things as conscious motivation, existential
177
ethnomethodology
meaning, rational interest, emotional reactions,
or personal attitudes) and all make social practices in local contexts the center of their concern.
All of them thus break with both longstanding
utilitarian views of interest-driven action and
Immanuel Kant’s (1724–1804) views of meaning
in action, such as those adopted by Max Weber
and Alfred Schutz. Yet, on closer inspection, Garfinkel discovered a dimension of social action as
an active human accomplishment that bears little
resemblance to the moral dimension in Goffman’s
analyses of facework and other interaction rituals,
Austin’s performative analyses of speech acts, and
Dewey’s and Mead’s efforts to decenter consciousness from social praxis without losing sight of
consciousness altogether.
Garfinkel’s distinction is to be the only leading
sociologist to concentrate exclusively on how local
action is accomplished or produced. One of his
fundamental insights concerns the central role
of reflexivity in the production of action. Reflexivity, a term that has several other sociological
denotations that are irrelevant here, refers to the
fact (demonstrated in many of Garfinkel’s early
studies) that every move in a social action or interaction takes its significance from the context that
has been produced by previous moves, and, reflexively, each move sustains or alters the local context that shapes the significance of the next move.
For example, if I open an interaction by saying
“hello” in a friendly way, then this move creates
a context in which whatever my interlocutor says
will be regarded as a reply to my specific greeting.
My interlocutor may say, for example, “I have
been sick, but I am better now.” The context
has now changed and my next remark will be
significant in light of my friend’s response to my
initial greeting. I could say, for example, that a
mutual friend of ours has been sick as well, which
changes the context of conversation once again.
Even if I altogether omit the slightest allusion to
my friend’s illness, that very omission will be significant in the contextual light of the report of
illness that preceded my remark. Each move in an
action or interaction is thus constructed within
the locally produced context, and every move advances that context so that the entire sequence
unfolds as a reflexive series of contextualized
and context-producing moves.
There is a sense in which Garfinkel’s key insight
into reflexivity and contextuality invites sociologists to give careful, fine-grained consideration
to the minutiae of everyday life. For example,
the timing of responses, as measured in fractions
of a second, may make a big difference to the
178
ethnomethodology
significance of a reply. If, to provide one illustration, I greet my friend with a rapidly enacted set
of words and gestures and my friend pauses for,
say, three seconds before responding to my rapidfire greeting in any way, then this pause becomes
part of the context just as surely as if my friend
had responded instantaneously, but with a different effect on it. Ethnomethodologists typically
investigate these minute yet significant aspects
of social praxis by using video transcriptions of
interaction, which they break down into small
segments for purposes of analysis. There is now a
standardized set of ethnomethodological symbols
to record pauses, vocables (meaningless sounds
uttered during conversations), episodes of people
talking over one another, and more. Though not
as central to current ethnomethodological studies, other aspects of locally produced conduct
such as tone of voice, static and shifting body
postures, and even changes in perspiration, respiration, and eye-blink rates are open to ethnomethodological investigation insofar as they add
reflexive significance to a complex practice.
But if Garfinkel’s basic insights into reflexivity
and contextuality lead in one direction into the
minutiae of everyday life, in another direction
they lead to some of the most profound issues
not only in the sociology of action, but in the
philosophy of action as well. Consider the question of the nature of human reason, which has
been at the top of the philosophical agenda since
René Descartes (1596–1650) famously declared, “I
think, therefore I am,” and which Talcott Parsons
used as the template for his analyses in The Structure of Social Action (1937). These and other views
conceive reason as a logically structured form of
thought, replete with tightly constructed models
of means and ends in action, or axioms, deductions, and hypotheses in science. For Garfinkel,
rationality does not arise in practice as an abstract
and universally applicable form, which structures
social action. Instead, rationality is produced locally as actors reflexively produce chains of reasoning that make sense only in and through the
development of the local contexts. Can local interactions in context be logical in the more formal
sense of the term? On occasion, perhaps, say, in
the shop talk of mathematicians. But these instances in no way epitomize how other sorts of
contextual reasoning proceed. One of Garfinkel’s
early studies demonstrates how local reasoning
operates through the analysis of discussions of jurors deliberating about the case they are charged to
decide. Though the judge has instructed jurors to
reach a verdict by strict rules of reasoning based
ethnomethodology
on a given set of legal principles, the jurors actually created a form of reasoning on their own that
did not necessarily correspond to the legal statutes prescribing how jurors are supposed to reach
a verdict.
The contextually constructed nature of reason is
matched by a deeper understanding of how a
theory-laden scientific fact is constructed. In 1981,
Garfinkel was senior author on a study of conversations between scientists, taped on the evening when
they pieced together for the first time the notion of
an optical pulsar through conversations regarding
observations made by telescopes and electronic
data. Unlike others in the strong program in the
sociology of science, Garfinkel and his junior colleagues specifically affirm that physical objects
somehow are exhibited in the flow of observations.
However, it is also essential to the construction
of scientific discovery that scientists make sense of
these facts in their conversations through the reflexively unfolding process whereby participants take
turns in talking. In fact, the scientific article
reporting the results of the observation of the optical pulsar is republished as an appendix to the
ethnomethodological analysis, allowing readers to
compare how the empirical scientific discovery
was produced in conversation with the very different and far more logical way it was reported to
the astronomical community. A second study of
empirical discovery appears in Garfinkel’s reconstruction of how Galileo constructed his inclined
plane demonstration of the real motion of free-falling bodies. This study is published in Garfinkel’s
Ethnomethodology’s Program (2002).
Garfinkel writes in a profoundly idiosyncratic
narrative voice replete with etymologically obscure neologisms, technical usages of commonplace American English terms, and lengthy
cascading lists of conceptual synonyms and variations in place of a single term. Whatever Garfinkel’s motivation for writing in this way, his style
has had two consequences for ethnomethodology.
First, it has injected a certain gnostic quality into
the ethnomethodological community, making
many practitioners believe that they possess rare
insights unavailable to the uninitiated. Second,
it has confused outsiders who sometimes grotesquely misinterpret ethnomethodology’s insights and often end up feeling estranged from
not only Garfinkel’s writings but his insights as
well. It is therefore Garfinkel’s good fortune to
have had two fine exegetes, John Heritage and
Anne Rawls, who have done much to clarify
Garfinkel’s work and build original bridges to
other classical and contemporary theories.
ethnomethodology
In her perceptive and accessible introduction to
Garfinkel’s Ethnomethodology’s Program and in her
more technical theoretical essays elsewhere, Anne
Rawls derives from well-known works by Émile
Durkheim an emphasis on enacted social practices,
and via this interpretation demonstrates that
Garfinkel’s basic ethnomethodological insights
are not only consistent with Durkheim’s thought,
but expand upon some of Durkheim’s classical
themes. In Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology (1984),
John Heritage grounds Garfinkel’s insights in his
reactions to Talcott Parsons, with whom Garfinkel
trained, and Alfred Schutz, with whom he studied.
Heritage also makes a significant independent
contribution. In an early essay, Garfinkel reported
a series of experiments in trust (technically not
experiments), which demonstrated the intense attachment actors have to the enacted practices
through which they collaboratively generate their
contextually situated social reality. His strategy
was to disrupt the normal course of enactment;
his findings indicated that these disruptions produced profound reactions amounting to an implicit struggle to avoid anomie. Heritage observes
that these studies point to a cognitive problem
of order. This problem concerns not what constrains the behavior of actors outside the immediate context such that they produce social order
in society, but rather how actors produce and
sustain social order in everyday life. In developing
this theme, Heritage indicates how Garfinkel
both borrowed from and departed from Schutz’s
social phenomenology. However, though Heritage
never explicates the point, Garfinkel’s experiments in trust further demonstrate not only that
Garfinkel discovers a cognitive problem of order
but also that people will engage in sustained
struggles against anomie when order is disrupted.
This indicates a deep subconscious motivation to
produce some sense of order at all times. This
theme is further developed by Anthony Giddens
in his conception of ontological security in
structuration theory.
The branch of ethnomethodology known as conversational analysis takes the production of order
in a new direction by stressing that the mechanisms for such conversational practices as turntaking, opening, closing, and so on have formal
properties (invariant across contexts) that constrain the production of order. In turn-taking, for
example, a person may be unable to interject
remarks into a conversation at a given point, no
matter how significant their contributions may
be, since they have no immediate access to a
turn at talking.
179
Etzioni, Amitai (1929– )
Despite Garfinkel’s brilliant insights, ethnomethodology often ends up in a sociological culde-sac. As it pushes ever deeper into the details of
social praxis, it loses sight of institutional and
psychological dimensions of social life. Anthony
Giddens opens ethnomethodology to the structural conditions of social life in structuration
theory. However, no one as yet has built theoretical bridges between the enacted production of
local social order and actors’ existential experience of meaning and emotion in social life. That
bridge, when it is built, should make ethnomethodology’s profound insights intuitively more interesting to wider audiences.
IRA COHEN
Etzioni, Amitai (1929– )
Professor at the George Washington University
and Director of the Institute for Communitarian
Policy Studies, and former White House adviser
(1979–80), Etzioni is an American founder of communitarianism. He was Professor of Sociology at
Columbia University for twenty years and guest
scholar at the Brookings Institution in 1978. He
served as President of the American Sociological
Association in 1994–5, and in 1990 he founded
the Communitarian Network. He was the editor
of The Responsive Community: Rights and Responsibilities
from 1991 to 2004. In 1997 Etzioni was awarded the
Simon Wiesenthal Center Tolerance Book Award.
He has championed the cause of peace in a
nuclear age in The Hard Way to Peace (1962), Winning Without War (1964), and War and its Prevention
(Etzioni and Wenglinsky, 1970). His recent work
has addressed the social problems of modern democracies and he has advocated communitarian
solutions to excessive individualism in The Spirit of
Community. The Reinvention of American Society (1993)
and New Communitarian Thinking (1996). Etzioni has
been concerned to facilitate social movements
that can sustain a liberal democracy in The Active
Society. A Theory of Societal and Political Processes
(1968) and A Responsive Society (1991). He has been
a critic of the erosion of privacy through modern
surveillance technologies and threats to identity
in The Limits of Privacy (1999). His most recent work
was From Empire to Community. A New Approach to
International Relations (2004).
Etzioni has also contributed significantly to
the sociology of organizations in Modern Organizations (1964) and A Comparative Analysis of Complex
Organizations (1961).
BRYAN S. TURNER
eugenics
– see genetics.
180
evolutionary psychology
everyday life
The term everyday was in English usage as early as
the seventeenth century to refer to ordinary or
ongoing ways of life such as work routines and
interpersonal demeanor, as well as to items of material culture such as clothing and décor. The synonymous term quotidian had appeared in English
in the fourteenth century, with roots in earlier
French and Latin usages. Though many of these
usages imply contrasts with extraordinary situations (for example, holy days, days of mourning,
war, disaster), in sociological theory the term is
often used to refer to knowledge of ordinary and
routine ways of life. The appropriate contrast
here is with sociological knowledge that selectively abstracts and reorganizes elements of daily
life based upon theoretical concepts or empirical
methods of research. In this sense, the purest
form of the sociology of everyday life is found
in ethnographies that forgo second-order analysis for first-order verisimilitude. Clifford Geertz
produces and advocates this way of studying
everyday life.
A second denotation of the sociology of everyday life refers to the analysis of the interaction
order. The latter term, as defined by Erving
Goffman, refers to forms of activity where participants are either copresent or in immediate communication with one another. Everyday life here
contrasts with more encompassing institutional
orders (bureaucracy, markets, and states). Selective analyses of everyday life are possible in this
sense of the term. Goffman was the master of
sociological metaphors that depend upon sociological correspondences rather than literary resemblances. Ethnomethodologists also deal with
the everyday production of ordinary social events,
by focusing on carefully isolated, minute aspects
IRA COHEN
of it.
evidence-based-policy
– see social policy.
evolution
– see evolutionary theory.
evolutionary psychology
A form of psychology, this claims to explain human
behavior with reference to humanity’s phylogeny,
their evolutionary history. The brain, or mind, is
seen as having evolved to help solve the adaptive
problems encountered by our hunter–gatherer ancestors on the African savannah between 4 million
and 100,000 years ago. It was during that era,
evolutionary psychology
according to Steven Pinker in How the Mind Works
(1998), that modern humanity evolved with a
collection of devices which influence behavior to
this day.
The lifestyle enjoyed by our African ancestors
was one of hunting and gathering. The prime
requirement for such people was simply to reproduce into future generations. Mental “organs,” or
brains and minds, assisted towards that overriding goal. These early people developed a distinctive set of motives, conceptual frameworks,
emotions, and even aesthetic preferences to use
and adapt to their environment. These included,
for example, a liking for particular types of physical landscapes in which they could see potential
aggressors approaching.
Aesthetic predispositions are, however, seen as
one of the less damaging results of humanity’s
evolutionary history. Our inherited mental apparatus is seen by evolutionary psychology as generating forms of behavior which are both selfdestructive and damaging to the social order. A
demand for prestige, property, and wealth, a male
preference for young women as sexual partners, a
division of labor by sex, hostility to other groups,
conflict within groups, and a male predisposition
towards violence, rape, and murder are all damaging results of inherited predispositions which
are not easily shaken off. Similarly, stepparents
are more likely to murder their stepchildren
because they are not genetically related to them.
Evolutionary psychology therefore offers precise
and seemingly scientific insights into contemporary society and its disorders. It is a close cousin to
sociobiology, a form of biological analysis that was
extended to the human condition in the mid1970s. Two of its main advocates were E. O.
Wilson, who wrote Sociobiology: The New Synthesis
(1975), and R. Dawkins in The Selfish Gene (1976,
1989). The central claim of sociobiology was also
that an organism such as an animal or human
being has evolved to interact and compete for
resources in such a way as to maximize its “success” in spreading genes to later generations. The
prime explanatory unit in sociobiology was
the gene. Individual animals, including people,
were envisaged as “survival machines,” beings programmed by their genes towards the expansion of
“inclusive fitness.” This latter concept referred
to the sum of an individual’s fitness plus that of
other blood relatives. The concept is perhaps best
summed up by the distinguished biologist J. B. S.
Haldane who, when asked whether he would lay
down his life for his brother, replied: “not for one
brother. But I would for two brothers or eight
evolutionary psychology
cousins.” Sociobiology was also seen as solving
the puzzling problem of altruism. The reason
why an individual should assist another, apparently selflessly, is that this is the best way of
getting assistance back at a later date. It is another
unconscious way in which the genes ensure they
are reproduced. Sociobiology captured the spirit
of thrusting individualism in the neoliberalist
era of the 1970s and 1980s, though it finds little
support today.
Evolutionary psychology claims, however, to
have advanced beyond sociobiology. One of the
many criticisms of sociobiology was that it told
“just-so stories,” implying that all traits and behaviors inherited during the evolutionary process
necessarily result in a better adaptation of organism to environment. But there is a wide recognition among evolutionists that this is not the case.
Certain traits and characteristics that are nonadaptive, for example, are passed on. Some
“junk” genes are doing very little at all. Evolutionary psychology claims to circumvent these problems by focusing on what Pinker calls “reverse
engineering.” This entails identifying a goal and
specifying in general terms the kind of design that
would best meet it. The next stage is to examine
how well an organ or organism under study
actually does perform the demands made of it.
The question of “mind” is especially important
to evolutionary psychology. Sociobiology was
also often criticized for reading off “behavior”
from genes, with unsatisfactory attention to complex mental processes. Evolutionary psychology, in
contrast, focuses on “mental organs” which “generate” behavior. The mind is equated to a computer processing incoming information. But the
human computer is “preprogrammed.” It is meeting the adaptive needs of its owner; on the other
hand, it contains assumptions about the nature of
the physical world, such as the existence of material objects in three-dimensional space. Evolutionary psychology also seeks to avoid the
universalism of sociobiology. It recognizes that
behavioral propensities may well be dysfunctional
to people and societies when they encounter new
environmental and social circumstances.
The question arises, however, whether evolutionary psychology really does avoid the charge
of biological reductionism leveled against sociobiology. H. Rose and S. Rose consider some of these
criticisms in Alas Poor Darwin (2000). Explanations
of social power and social relations remain
blinkered, still focusing on the unchanged, biologically based predispositions. And, like sociobiology, evolutionary psychology systematically
181
evolutionary theory
ignores forms of biology that give much less attention to genes (though considering them important in explaining the development and
growth of the organism during its lifetime) and
much more attention to the developing organism
in its social and ecological context. P. Dickens
outlines some of these alternative perspectives in
Social Darwinism (2000).
Despite their continuing problems, evolutionary psychology and sociobiology have managed
to shake social theory out of thinking it has a
unique purchase on human behavior and that
the biological world is of no explanatory importance. The focus of future research must be that of
combining ideas from biology, psychology, and
social theory in more nuanced ways, recognizing
the complexity of their interactions. This would
certainly entail recognizing the importance of
genes and biology in affecting the overall growth
and psychic propensities of human beings. But it
would also recognize that households, educational systems, work hierarchies, and the like all
deeply affect how these biologically based tendencies work out in practice. Similarly, the human
mind is almost certainly less “hard-wired” and
inflexible than the proponents of evolutionary
psychology suggest. Different kinds of psychic
structure come into play according to the social
relations which the mind encounters and indeed
contributes to.
PETER DICKENS
evolutionary theory
Evolution and learning are two principal mechanisms of adaptive self-organization in complex
systems. Learning alters the probability distribution of behavioral traits within a given individual,
through processes of reinforcement and observation of others. Evolution alters the frequency distribution of individual carriers of a trait within a
given population, through differential chances of
selection and replication. Selection depends on
heterogeneity which is replenished by random
mutation in the face of replication processes that
tend to reduce it. Selection pressures influence
the probability that particular traits will be replicated, in the course of competition for scarce resources (ecological selection) or competition for a
mate (sexual selection).
Although evolution is often equated with ecological selection, sexual selection is at least as
important. By building on partial solutions rather
than discarding them, genetic crossover in sexual
reproduction can exponentially increase the rate
at which a species can explore an adaptive landscape, compared to reliance on trial and error
182
evolutionary theory
(random mutation) alone. Paradoxically, sexual
selection also tends to inhibit ecological adaptation, especially among males. Gender differences
in parental investment cause females to be choosier about mates and thus sexual selection to be
more pronounced in males. An example is the
peacock’s large and cumbersome tail, which attracts the attention of peahens (who are relatively
drab) as well as predators. Sexually selected traits
tend to become exaggerated as males trap one
another in an arms race to see who can have the
largest antlers or be bravest in battle.
Selection pressures can operate at multiple
levels in a nested hierarchy, from groups of individuals with similar traits, down to individual
carriers of those traits, down to the traits themselves. Evolution Through Group Selection (1986) was
advanced by V. C. Wynne-Edwards as a solution to
one of evolution’s persistent puzzles – the viability
of altruism in the face of egoistic ecological counterpressures. Prosocial in-group behavior confers a
collective advantage over rival groups of rugged
individualists. However, the theory was later dismissed by George C. Williams in Adaptation and
Natural Selection (1966) which showed that between-group variation gets swamped by withingroup variation as group size increases. Moreover,
group selection relies entirely on differential rates
of extinction, with no plausible mechanism for
the whole-cloth replication of successful groups.
Sexual selection suggests a more plausible explanation for the persistence of altruistic behaviors that reduce the chances of ecological
selection. Contrary to Herbert Spencer’s infamous
view of evolution, following Charles Darwin, as
“survival of the fittest,” generosity can flourish
even when these traits are ecologically disadvantageous, by attracting females who have evolved a
preference for “romantic” males who are ready
to sacrifice for their partner. Traits that reduce
the ecological fitness of an individual carrier can
also flourish if the trait increases the selection
chances of other individuals with that trait.
Hamilton introduced this gene-centric theory of
kin altruism in “The Genetic Evolution of Social
Behaviour” (Journal of Theoretical Biology, 1964),
later popularized by R. Dawkins in The Selfish Gene
(1976, 1989).
In “The Cultural Evolution of Beneficent
Norms” (Social Forces, 1992), Paul Allison extended
the theory to benevolence based on cultural relatedness, such as geographical proximity or a
shared cultural marker. This may explain why
gene–culture coevolution seems to favor a tendency to associate with those who are similar, to
evolutionary theory
differentiate from “outsiders,” and to defend the
in-group against social trespass with the emotional ferocity of parents defending their offspring. This model also shows how evolutionary
principles initially developed to explain biological
adaptation can be extended to explain social and
cultural change (see social change). Prominent
examples include the evolution of languages, religions, laws, organizations, and institutions. This
approach has a long and checkered history. Social
Darwinism is a discredited nineteenth-century
theory that used biological principles as analogs
for social processes such as market competition
and colonial domination. Many sociologists still
reject all theories of social or cultural evolution,
along with biological explanations of human behavior, which they associate with racist and elitist
theories of “survival of the fittest.” Others, like the
sociobiologist E. O. Wilson, believe “genes hold
culture on a leash” (On Human Nature, 1988), leaving little room for cultural evolution to modify
the products of natural selection. Similarly, evolutionary psychologists like Leda Cosmides and John
Tooby search for the historical origins of human
behavior as the product of ancestral natural selection rather than ongoing social or cultural
evolution.
In contrast, a growing number of sociologists
and economists are exploring the possibility
that human behaviors and institutions may be
heavily influenced by processes of social and cultural selection that are independent of biological
imperatives. These include Paul DiMaggio and
Walter Powell (the new institutional sociology),
Richard Nelson and Sydney G. Winter (evolutionary economics), and Michael T. Hannan and John
H. Freeman (organizational ecology). One particularly compelling application is the explanation of
cultural diversity. In biological evolution, speciation occurs when geographic separation allows
populations to evolve in different directions to the
point that individuals from each group can no
longer mate. Speciation implies that all life has
evolved from a very small number of common
ancestors, perhaps only one. The theory has been
applied to the evolution of myriad Indo-European
languages that are mutually incomprehensible
despite having a common ancestor. In sociocultural models, speciation operates through
homophily (attraction to those who are similar),
xenophobia (aversion to those who are different),
and influence (the tendency to become more similar to those to whom we are attracted and to
differentiate from those we despise).
exchange theory
Critics counter that socio-cultural evolutionists have failed to identify any underlying replicative device equivalent to the gene. Dawkins
has proposed the “meme” as the unit of cultural
evolution but there is as yet no evidence that
these exist. Yet Darwin developed the theory
of natural selection without knowing that phenotypes are coded genetically in DNA. Perhaps
the secrets of cultural evolution are waiting to
be unlocked by impending breakthroughs in
cognitive psychology.
MICHAEL MACY
exchange theory
The social division of labor is mediated by exchange. Exchange theory conceptualizes this as a
bargaining process that reflects the relative dependence of the parties involved. Not all social
interactions involve bargaining and exchange.
Peter M. Blau, who developed the field in 1964
with Exchange and Power in Social Life, warned that
“People do things for fear of other men or for fear
of God or for fear of their conscience, and nothing
is gained by trying to force such action into a
conceptual framework of exchange” (1964: 88).
Yet Blau did not regard most social relations as
outside this framework. “Social exchange can be
observed everywhere once we are sensitized by
this conception to it, not only in market relations
but also in friendship and even in love” (88). Social
exchange differs from economic exchange in
three important ways. First, the articles of exchange are not commodities but gifts. No money
is involved, nor credit, nor contract. Giving a
gift is a “selfish act of generosity” in that it creates
in the recipient the need to reciprocate with something that is desired by the giver. Both parties
to the exchange “are prone to supply more of their
own services to provide incentives for the other to
increase his supply” (89). Simply put, a gift is not
an expression of altruism; it is a way to exercise
power over another. Second, the terms of exchange are unspecified (91). One side offers something the other values, without knowing how or
when the partner will return the favor. Third, the
exchange is not instrumentally calculated. Without a quid pro quo and in the absence of explicit
bargaining, one cannot know if the gift is optimal
in a given transaction. Instead, optimization takes
place through incremental adjustments to behavior in response to experience. These need not
be conscious adjustments but could be experienced merely as feelings of satisfaction or dissatisfaction with the relationship, such that the terms
of exchange emerge as a byproduct of a learning
183
exchange theory
process. Each partner evaluates the outcomes from
the exchange relative to a “comparison level”
corresponding to what the actor expects to receive
from their best alternative relationship. When the
value falls below this standard, the individual is
dissatisfied and seeks alternative partners whose
offers are perceived as superior. On the other hand,
according to Susan Sprecher in Social Exchange Theories and Sexuality (1998: 34), “if the outcomes they
are receiving from their current relationship are
better than what they expect to receive from their
best alternative(s), they will feel dependent on the
relationship and become committed to it.”
These differences with economic exchange
make social exchange applicable to emotionally
charged behaviors where instrumental manipulation of the partner would ruin the experience for
both. Social exchanges can be experienced as acts
of generosity towards those we love and trust. In
particular, trust is necessary because of the unspecified terms of exchange. Attraction and trust
increase when the generosity is satisfactorily reciprocated and decrease when it is not.
Although social exchange lacks explicit terms
of trade, enforceable contracts, or a monetary medium, it nevertheless follows the basic principles
of economic bargaining over the price of commodities, such as the “principle of least interest,”
summarized by Karen Cook and Richard Emerson
in “Power, Equity and Commitment in Exchange
Networks” (American Sociological Review, 1978):
“The party who is receiving the least comparative
benefit from a trade has the greater bargaining
power to improve upon that trade. If that power is
used . . . then the terms of the trade will shift until
power is balanced” (724).
This theory applies to the balancing of power
in exchanges between workers, neighbors, friends,
business associates, and marriage partners, as
noted by Ed Lawler and Shane Thye in “Bringing
Emotions into Social Exchange Theory” (Annual
Review of Sociology, 1999): “Whether it is two lovers
who share a warm and mutual affection, or two
corporations who pool resources to generate a
new product, the basic form of interaction remains the same . . . Two or more actors, each of
whom has something of value to the other, decide
whether to exchange and in what amounts” (217).
One of the best-known examples of the general
principles of exchange is Gary Becker’s Treatise on
the Family (1992) which models mate selection as a
marriage market in which people exchange
status, sex appeal, wealth, or intelligence.
Although numerous studies of the “law of attraction” have found strong tendencies towards
184
exchange theory
homogamy based on age, race and ethnicity,
religion, education, and occupational status, exchange theory provides an alternative explanation. Homogamy may reflect not a taste for
similarity but rather constraints on the ability to
attract a partner who has more valued resources.
From an exchange-theoretic perspective, romantic
relationships are formed through a matching
process in which women and men look for the
best “catch.”
Exchange theory has also been applied to the
exercise of power in the family. The principle
of least interest predicts a positive effect of relative socioeconomic position on conjugal power
in decisionmaking. For example, studies show
that women in high-paying occupations are less
dependent on their husbands and thus have
more power in marital exchange than do women
without such occupations.
Marital exchange is an example of dyadic exchange. In contrast, generalized exchange involves three or more actors who each provide
valued resources to others with no expectation
of direct reciprocity. In Social Exchange Theory:
The Two Traditions (1974), Peter Ekeh distinguished
between “group generalized exchange” in which
resources are pooled and then redistributed,
and “chain generalized exchange,” which is illustrated by kula, a ceremonial exchange of wreaths
of flowers for food or betel-nut, as described
by Bronislaw Malinowski in his studies of the
Trobriand Islanders. Although both these systems
appear to depart from rationally self-interested
behavior, exchange theorists have shown that
this need not be the case, especially where reputation and status depend on exhibitions of generosity, or where gifts have far greater value to others
than to the giver.
Social networks are of central importance in
exchange systems. A variant of exchange theory,
called “network exchange theory,” predicts power
from actors’ locations in network structures. For
example, in a “3-Line” network (B1-A-B2), A has
power over B1 and B2 because A has access to multiple exchange partners, each of whom has access
only to A. But if we simply add a link between B1
and B2, A loses its structural advantage. In this
triangle network, all three actors now have equal
power because all are excluded with the same
probability. The predicted effects of network structure have been strongly supported in laboratory
studies of bargaining behavior. In Network Exchange
Theory (1999), David Willer reviews these studies
and provides an overview and history of the field.
MICHAEL MACY AND ARNOUT VAN DE RIJT
experimental method
experimental method
Experimental research constitutes a minority of all
sociological research. The experimental method is
a research paradigm borrowed from the physical
and natural sciences. Experiments are studies
employing the hypothetico-deductive method
specifically designed to determine whether there
is a cause and effect relationship between two or
more phenomena. Other forms of sociological research have accordingly divergent goals. Thus, for
instance, survey-based research is designed to provide descriptive information about a topic of interest, as it pertains to a specific sample of persons,
and ethnomethodological studies are designed to
provide formal descriptions that display the features of the cultural machinery assumed to have
produced these features.
The experimental method entails the systematic variation in the levels of one or more independent variables, and then the measurement
of the effects of this manipulation according
to one or more dependent variables. The manipulation of the independent variable is achieved
by altering the qualitative or quantitative levels
of this variable. The levels of a qualitative independent variable are often established by the presence or absence of a particular variable (for
example exposure to anti-racism training, or no
exposure to anti-racism training); or by measuring
the effects of various different kinds of training.
In all such cases, the groups in question do
not experience different amounts of the independent variable, but rather the presence or absence
of a particular treatment or experimental condition. In contrast, the levels of a quantitative
independent variable entail quantitatively different amounts of exposure to that variable. For
example, Gordon Allport’s contact hypothesis, expounded in The Nature of Prejudice (1954), would
predict that the amount of time spent exposed to
minority groups (given certain other necessary
conditions) should systematically reduce the level
of prejudice expressed towards that group. Thus,
subjects may be divided into groups that spend
one week, two weeks, and three weeks interacting
with minority group members under such conditions. The dependent variable (expressed prejudice) would be measured before and after these
quantitatively different amounts of exposure
to the independent variable. These three levels of
the independent variable are expressed according
to a quantitative dimension, time.
However, as these examples perhaps make
clear, it is only possible to infer a cause and effect
explanation
relationship between variables if all other variables remain constant. If conditions are not held
constant, an uncontrolled source of influence – or
confound – may affect the dependent variable(s),
and thus interfere with the expression of the independent variable(s) – either through offering an
alternative account for its effects, or through
masking the expression of an effect. In the social
scientific community, attention to identifying
the effects of potential confounds arguably reflects a positive level of skepticism towards too
readily inferring causal relationships between
variables.
In order to identify potential confounds, one
should pay close attention to those other factors –
besides the independent variable – that may systematically vary during the experiment (for
example, students from a particular socioeconomic area may already have experienced different levels of exposure to racism, compared to
students from a different socioeconomic area,
thus potentially confounding the effects of antiracism training).
Another major concern for experimental social
scientists is that of ecological or external validity.
This form of validity (see sampling) refers to
the ability of the researcher, on the basis of the
experimental results, to generalize from the experimental context to the equivalent real-world
situation. Further, work on the sociology of scientific knowledge has demonstrated that, in practice, the experimental method is by no means
culture-free and objective.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
explanation
Most sociologists seek to explain. Explanations
often draw on counterfactual thinking, trying to
assess the impact of x by imagining what would
have happened if x did not occur.
There are many types of explanation, and little
consensus exists as to what kind of explanation
is preferred. A common type of explanation is
a causal one, but there are various types of causal
explanation and causal inference. Some causal
explanations are mechanistic. They explain a phenomenon by referring to the fact that it was
caused by other social factors, but without a precise reference to the mechanisms or powers at
stake. For example, a mechanistic explanation
for the rise in suicide rates may refer to the rise
in unemployment figures. Alternatively, people’s
dissatisfaction at work might be explained by
reference to the technology involved in their
185
explanation
employment. Some commentators argue that such
mechanistic accounts are not explanations because they fail to answer why- and how-questions.
Rather than providing answers, they seem to beg
questions.
Other causal explanations are intentional. In
intentional explanations, people’s purposes or
reasons are treated as causes for their actions. Sociologists subscribing to methodological individualism use intentional explanations. Methodological
individualism is a research program that focuses
on how individuals act purposefully while producing not just intended but also unintended and
unanticipated effects. Max Weber and Karl Popper
are amongst the main advocates of methodological individualism. They oppose holistic forms
of explanation, which refer to systemic or societal
needs. Some methodological individualists use rational explanations. These are intentional explanations but with the added assumption that people
act rationally. People act rationally if they have a
clear preference ordering and make choices consistent with that preference ordering. In addition,
they have rational beliefs about how to get what
they want and about the costs and benefits involved. Rational choice theory (or rational action
theory as some prefer to call it) advocates rational
explanations. Within this theory, there are differences as to the universality and applicability of
rational explanations. There is also disagreement
as to whether people make conscious calculations.
Externalists like Gary Becker simply argue that
people act as if they are rational. They do not
assume that people necessarily go through a conscious decision process. Sometimes they might,
sometimes they might not.
In opposition to methodological individualism,
some sociologists are drawn to holistic forms
of explanation. Most holistic explanations are
functional. Functional explanations account for
the persistence of certain social phenomena by
referring to their (often unintended) effects for
the cohesion and stability of the broader social
system in which they are embedded. For example,
some sociologists explain the persistence of religious rites by referring to the solidarity and cohesion they create. Most sociologists occasionally
use functional explanations, but functionalism is
a sociological school that primarily and selfconsciously uses functional explanations. Robert
K. Merton and Talcott Parsons are well-known
self-proclaimed functionalists. Within this theoretical framework, there are many differences.
Earlier functionalists, like A. R. Radcliffe-Brown
(1881–1955) and Bronislaw Malinowski, assumed
186
explanation
that most, if not all, practices are functional and
indispensable. Later functionalists relaxed this
position.
Evolutionary explanations rest on a combination of causality and selection, and evolutionary
theory is a school that promotes such explanations. There are two types of evolutionary explanation. First, sociobiology uses biological factors to
explain social phenomena. For instance, it tries
to demonstrate that biological differences between sexes manifest themselves in social differences. Second, some theorists account for social
processes by drawing on analogies with biological
evolution. For instance, it might be argued that,
through time, institutions and even whole societies undergo evolutionary selection. Or it might
be asserted that certain practices or ideas are
eventually selected out, while others replicate
more easily. Some sociologists combine evolutionary analogies with methodological individualism.
This was the case for Herbert Spencer, one of the
first sociologists to employ evolutionary reasoning. Others use evolutionary analogies in conjunction with a more holistic approach. Émile
Durkheim was one of the first to do this. Since
the publication of Richard Dawkins’s The Selfish
Gene (1976), evolutionary analogies have regained
popularity in the social sciences. Examples are
Walter Garrison Runciman’s two-volume Treatise
on Social Theory (1983, 1989) and Rom Harré’s Social
Being (1993).
While there are many types of explanation, there
is also disagreement as to how to evaluate explanations. Many philosophers argue that explanations
need to have some empirical content. This led logical positivists to call for verifiability: explanations ought to be formulated so that it is
possible to find empirical evidence that supports
them. Popper suggested falsifiability: explanations
ought to be stated so that they can be refuted
on the basis of empirical evidence. Highly falsifiable explanations are preferred over cautious explanations: they are more informative and more
precise. The school of critical realism focuses on
the difference between explanations and descriptions. For a statement to be explanatory, it ought to
include precise information about the mechanisms, structures, or powers at work. These mechanisms might not be immediately accessible to
observation.
Finally, there are also different views as to how
to arrive at explanations. The inductivist tradition
insisted on the primacy of theory-independent
empirical observations. It employs induction,
whereby one generalizes from observational
explanation
statements to arrive at universal statements.
Deductivists like Popper and Carl Gustav Hempel
(1905–97) insist on the value of deduction,
whereby one starts with theoretical assumptions
and initial conditions to infer empirical hypotheses. Hempel’s view of science is known as
the hypothetico-deductive method. Different
again is the “retroduction” or “abduction” of
Charles Peirce (1839–1914) referring to the process
extended family
by which one makes sense of a new phenomenon through drawing analogies with something
familiar.
PATRICK BAERT
expressive revolution
– see Talcott Parsons.
extended family
– see family.
187
F
face-to-face group
– see group(s).
face work
– see Erving Goffman.
factor analysis
One of the most widely used, and misused, of the
complex multivariate statistics that have become
more accessible since the spread of computing
power, this can reduce a larger number of measured variables into a smaller number of latent
variables, or “factors.” It is thus a “data reduction”
technique, aimed at simplifying data while
retaining its important features.
Factor analyses take as their input a number
of different variables, usually all measuring similar related constructs (such as items in a standard personality questionnaire). The correlations
between these measures are computed, and the
number of dimensions (in a multi-dimensional
space) that one needs to extract to describe the
important variance, while screening out the error
variance, is estimated. These factors are then constructed, and rotated to facilitate their interpretation. Finally, each case can be given a score on
the newly created factors, for instance to describe
respondents’ personality along each dimension of
the model.
Factor analysis was critical to the conceptualization and development of research into intelligence
and personality in early and mid-twentiethcentury psychology. For instance, R. B. Cattell, in
The Scientific Analysis of Personality (1965), started
by extracting all of the words in the English language to describe personality. Even after removing
synonyms, there were still thousands of words. So
Cattell used factor analysis to reduce this down to
a list of fourteen personality scales, which became
a standard model for many years in personnel
selection and social research. H. J. Eysenck, in The
Scientific Study of Personality (1982), went a stage
further, and produced a model with just two dimensions, extraversion–introversion and neurotic–
stable (and later a third dimension, psychoticism).
188
The initial appeal of factor analysis is that it
would provide a scientific basis for answering
some fundamental questions, such as how many
dimensions there are to human personality or
intelligence. Unfortunately, this promise to provide a scientific objectivity has not materialized,
and in many cases different researchers, each
using factor analyses, have arrived at very different conclusions. This is largely because there are a
number of ways in which the computation of any
particular model can be influenced by fairly arbitrary decisions by the researcher. At each stage,
the number of factors extracted, the method of
rotation, and the method of separating error from
true variance are often matters of judgment by
the researcher, rather than being given by the
model. And, probably, the most contentious decision of all is how one chooses which variables to
include in the factor analysis. For instance, if one
is attempting to create a model of intelligence, we
would all agree that we should include mathematical, logical, and linguistic skills, but what about
musical ability, creativity, or coordination?
Two forms of factor analysis are currently
employed by sociologists. Exploratory factor analysis is the more common variety, typically used
(as the name suggests) to investigate the way in
which variables can be simplified into their underlying dimensions. As long as no grand claims are
made about determining the true nature of reality, researchers can avoid the controversy associated with the early uses of factor analysis, and can
pragmatically simplify the analysis of complex
datasets. The second form, confirmatory factor
analysis, works to a different philosophy, and determines how well a set of data conforms to a
theoretical model.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
falsification
What makes a theory scientific was a question
that haunted Karl Popper, and, more particularly,
how we could distinguish a scientific theory from
a non-scientific one. He argued that traditional
explanations of what made a scientific theory scientific – that it was based on careful observation
falsification
and then the formulation of laws regarding the
relationships discovered, that is induction – were
wrong. This is because, while events might regularly occur together, there is no way to establish
that they cause each other: the problem of causality. The bigger question at hand for Popper was
how to distinguish pseudo-science from science,
and in particular to demonstrate why it was, as he
thought, that Marxism and the works of Sigmund
Freud were “pseudo-sciences.” The answer was
that no evidence could disconfirm either Marxism
or psychoanalysis: if the proletariat did not rise up
in rebellion today as predicted, then they would
one day. The observation was modified to protect
the hypothesis. If the patient did not resolve their
anxiety neurosis, then it was not because their
psychoanalysis failed, but because the patient
was repressed. Thus the theories could explain
everything that did (or did not happen) and
appeared to be constantly verified. Given this,
they could continue to claim to be scientific and
no evidence could satisfactorily challenge them.
Popper argued that it was too easy to search for
verifications of theories and that a new way of
putting the question had to be formulated. Rather
than look for evidence to support it, a scientific
theory had to pose questions that could prove it
wrong, that is falsify it. So the criterion of a scientific theory for Popper is that it be falsifiable by
empirical observations. The example that Popper
uses is Albert Einstein’s prediction that light
would be attracted towards a heavy body, that is,
that it could be seen to bend as it neared the
gravitational pull of say, the sun. This was, as
Popper put it, a risky hypothesis since, if it was
not confirmed, then Einstein’s theory would be
falsified (which was not in itself a problem, since
the hallmark of good science is that it can be
falsified). However, Einstein’s theory of gravitation was confirmed in 1919 by A. S. Eddington’s
observations of the transit of Venus. So Einstein’s
theory survived a challenge that could have falsified it. While we cannot conclude that it is true,
we can now proceed to work with it as a scientific
theory. Until Marxism or psychoanalysis, like science, makes predictions that are falsifiable by evidence, then we can conclude that, whether they
are true or not, they are not scientific. However,
Popper is still left with the problem of what is to
count as an independent observation that could
falsify a prediction. As work by later historians and
philosophers of science was to show, particularly
that of Thomas Samuel Kuhn (The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 1970) on paradigms, scientific theories are self-contained, largely self-confirming,
family
sets of statements, sustained by specific scientific
communities. They establish what questions can
be asked, what will count as an observation,
and disregard non-confirming evidence. On this
ground, no theory can be scientific in Popper’s
sense.
KEVIN WHITE
families of choice
– see Family.
family
There are many sociological explanations and accounts of families, from those that concentrate
on grand theories and relate family structure to
industrial society, capitalism, and/or patriarchy,
through to those that are derived from more
ethnographic studies of everyday family interactions and negotiations. Families can be, and
have been, studied at all levels of analysis. At
times families have been seen as homogeneous
unities of people who co-reside, often with a sole
head of household, clearly defined social roles,
and a distinct division of labor. At other times
families are understood to be real or imagined
networks based on obligations and affections of
an interpersonal nature rather than being structurally determined. These differences reflect, to
a large extent, changing fashions in sociological
theorizing and enquiry. At certain times particular modes of explanation are seen as especially
insightful (for example. functionalist approaches),
while at others different issues seem more important, particularly if they have been previously
ignored or rendered invisible (for example domestic labor in the household). In more recent times,
the very prospect of a sociology of the family has
been deemed to be uninteresting and theoretically arid, and the subject has been described as
slipping into the doldrums. Indeed Ulrich Beck
and Elisabeth Beck-Gernsheim, in The Normal Chaos
of Love (1990 [trans. 1995]), suggest that it has
only recently become interesting again: “Family
research is only gradually waking up from its
drowsy fixation on the nucleus of the family.”
The core issue that all sociologies of family
life and relationships have had in common, however, has been the problem of turning the sociological gaze onto areas of life which are routine,
commonplace, and part of almost everyone’s
everyday experience. The family is a naturalized
concept, by which it is meant that it is taken-forgranted as natural – notwithstanding how much
families differ and change. The sociological task
is therefore to de-naturalize the family in order
189
family
that it may become the focus of social analysis.
It is this project of de-naturalization that links
otherwise disparate sociological approaches.
It is almost inevitable that any synopsis of
sociological work on families should start with
Talcott Parsons and Robert Bales (Family, Socialization and Interaction Process (1955). Not only did their
functionalist approach set the tone of much work
on families for generations in the United States
and the United Kingdom, but it became the standard against which more critical work later pitted
itself. Parsons and Bales broadly argued that a
sociological approach to families should construe
them, not simply as natural collectivities, but as
a social system.
There arose the tendency among functionalists
to speak of the family, because “it” was theorized
as one institution amongst several core social institutions (such as the church and the state). The
institution of the family was however, in this
schema, a relatively junior player, because its
structure and functioning was deemed to serve
the needs of other (more significant) institutions.
Indeed, Parsons and Bales argued that an indication of how “advanced” a society was lay in
whether the family was in a subsidiary status
when compared with other institutions. They
saw the decline of the significance of kinship as
indicating a cultural rise of merit over the values
of familialism. Their approach tended to suggest
that phenomena such as family size (two children
rather than ten, for example) or segregated
gender roles within the family were a result of
the needs of the economy or of industrialization,
rather than arising from the motivations or interests of the members of families. The family
was therefore depicted as the handmaiden of
larger social forces, and its core function was to
produce socially appropriate (well socialized) citizens of the next generation to take their place
in the economy and wider society. Men, women,
and children were seen as having different roles
and functions in the family, which had evolved
to meet the needs of society. Thus women were
inevitably unpaid housewives and child carers,
while men were the breadwinners because this
system produced the most stable outcomes for
society. Moreover, men were deemed to be heads
of the household, because the model of family
living deployed by the functionalist approach
presumed that authority and leadership could
only come from one source. Parsons and Bales
predicted (unwisely as it turns out) that this division of labor would remain unchanged in the
future.
190
family
There are, of course, many criticisms that can
be made of this early sociological work on the
family, and some of these will be rehearsed below.
However, it is useful to locate this work in its
own time and intellectual moment in order to
appreciate the way in which it can be given a
certain amount of credit for developing the field.
The task that Parsons and Bales set themselves
was a complex one because they saw the family
as a social system, but also as the site where individual personality was formed. They also saw the
types of personalities that were formed there as
contributing (in an iterative fashion) to the wider
culture of a given society. They were therefore
working with three main concepts. The first was
the idea of the family as a system, the second
was the idea of the personality as a system, and
the third was the wider culture – a concept which
is ultimately underdeveloped in their work. For
the latter two concepts they drew heavily on
psychoanalysis particularly the work of Sigmund
Freud, and anthropology particularly the work of
Margaret Mead), respectively. Their work brought
together quite different disciplinary approaches
which in turn gave rise to their insistence that
the family was itself a site of production of personalities and that its workings could not be conceptually reduced to the impoverished idea that
families were mere microcosms of wider society.
Notwithstanding the fact that Parsons and Bales
are largely remembered for their ideas about the
way in which the family functioned to support
other social institutions and the desirability of
the gendered division of labor, they spent a great
deal of time exploring the internal dynamics
of families and even raising the issue of sexual
relationships between spouses – something that
later sociologists conspicuously avoided.
At virtually the same time that Parsons and
Bales were producing their general theoretical
analysis of the family, Michael Young and Peter
Willmott (Family and Kinship in East London, 1957)
published their micro-analysis of changing family
life based on empirical research within workingclass communities. Young and Willmott’s study
sought not only to analyze family change but
also to allow the voices of the family members to
be heard in the text through the liberal use of
quotations from the interviews they conducted
with couples. Their approach to research and their
style of presentation was almost the complete
antithesis of Parsons and Bales’s formal and abstract interpretations. Where Parsons and Bales
ignored the extended family, focusing almost
exclusively on the ideal of the nuclear family,
family
Young and Willmott located families within kinship networks and talked about the importance
of family members helping each other and sustaining (adult) intergenerational links. The latter
did not conceptualize families as isolated from
their communities (although they did note
how things changed as neighborhoods were
demolished in the postwar era). While Parsons
and Bales’s work can now be interpreted as a
paean to the nuclear family, Young and Willmott
might be described as a hagiography of the
working-class family. Their work sought to rewrite the working-class family as a site of warmth
and mutual support between husband and wife,
and to retrieve it from the widespread belief
(generated by the writings of early feminists,
philanthropists, and campaigners against poverty) that it was a wretched place, dominated by
male violence, drunkenness, grime, and relentless
childbirth. Their vision was optimistic too. They
argued that there were far fewer broken homes
in Britain in the 1950s than in previous decades,
and they saw this as something continuing into
the future because they understood the main
cause of disruption as being the death of the
male head of household (usually in wars) or of
either parent (owing to disease). This optimistic
framework carried forward into their later work,
The Symmetrical Family (1973), in which they described the emergence of a new type of family.
This family was described as home-centered or
“privatized,” as nuclear rather than part of an
extended kinship network, and, most significantly, as having much less segregated roles for
husbands and wives. In some ways this new vision
was closer to that of Parsons and Bales, except
that the latter did not predict any change to the
rigid segregation of the male breadwinner and
female housewife. By the time The Symmetrical
Family was published, the sociology of the family
(in both the United Kingdom and the United
States) had become wedded to the idea of the
nuclear, home-loving, monogamous, heterosexual family where other family forms were dismissed as aberrant or dysfunctional. It seemed
as if there was little more to be said about families; theoretically the field was still predominantly functionalist in orientation, and empirical
research was happily documenting progress towards an egalitarian, child-centered, companionate family form in which, although there might
still be problems, progress was being made.
Beck and Beck-Gernsheim describe the sociology
of the family as becoming a zombie category, still
occupying a place in the sociological canon and
family
yet holding to ideas and conceptualizations long
dead in other fields of sociology and social theory.
Yet this criticism is only accurate if one dismisses the significance of the new feminist work
which began to dominate the field in the 1970s
in both Britain and United States. This feminist
work challenged the idea of the family as a
companionate, egalitarian institution, and sought
to understand the workings of families from the
standpoint of the women who lived and worked in
them. There were two particularly important
strands of work that developed: the first was a reinterpretation of the meaning and significance
of the gendered division of labor in the family,
and the second was the re-discovery of domestic
violence in families.
While Young and Willmott were identifying
the rise of the symmetrical family, other studies
were beginning to reveal that the movement of
married women into the labor force seemed to
be generating a double shift for women, rather
than a sharing out of paid and unpaid labor.
Empirical studies showed that husbands did not
take on more housework or child-care responsibilities, but that wives would come back from
paid work only to find that they remained responsible for all (or almost all) domestic duties. Men
might have spoken of their willingness to “help”
in Young and Willmott, but this was seen by later
feminists as merely confirming that domestic
work remained the responsibility of women. Research by feminists such as Ann Oakley (The Sociology of Housework, 1974) drew attention to the idea
that housework was “real” work and that it was,
moreover, never finished. She dismissed the idea
that modern technology had lightened women’s
load because, although the physical labor associated with each task might have become
less arduous, standards of cleanliness and child
care rose exponentially. Following Oakley’s attempt to force sociology to take “women’s work”
in the home seriously, there arose a more explicitly Marxist analysis which became known as
the domestic labor debate. In this debate, the
feminist position argued that a materialist analysis of capitalism should include consideration
of women’s unpaid labor, because housework
and child care were part of the reproduction of
labor power needed by capital to keep those in
paid employment (see work and employment) fit
and capable of working long hours in the process
of producing profit. Without women’s unpaid
labor in the family, it was argued, capitalism
could not survive, and women’s labor indirectly
contributed to the creation of profit.
191
family
Linked to this argument was the idea that
women continued to give their labor freely
because they subscribed to (or were brainwashed by) the ideology of familialism. It was
argued that ideas that women’s roles as mothers
or as housewives were a natural component of
women’s being and psyche were a kind of false
consciousness, which kept women willingly confined to economically dependent and subservient
positions in their families. Rather than seeing
women’s economic and social vulnerability as
either god-given or as functionally necessary, this
approach saw it as exploitative and oppressive.
Marxist feminist work became associated with
a profound critique of the family, and this oppositional stance is exemplified in the work of
Michelle Barrett and Mary McIntosh, Anti-Social
Family (1982).
While the domestic labor debate was about
housework, other feminists turned their attention to “care” work. This approach focused on
two aspects of hidden work in families. The first
was the work of caring for others, not only children, but also often elderly or infirm relatives.
These activities had previously been treated as
extensions of women’s natural caring capacity,
and so the process of redefining it as work was
part of a process of making it more visible and
understood as a social activity. The second approach centered more on emotional labor. This
activity was identified as women’s responsibility,
and its focus was to keep the breadwinner happy,
to attend to his emotional needs, and to provide
an emotionally comforting and restorative environment. It is interesting that, in bringing these
activities to the fore, feminists at this time used
the terminology of work or labor to give a kind of
concrete status to these otherwise apparently
ephemeral activities. But, in so doing, both care
and emotions were reduced to a form of labor
which could be measured and assessed.
Throughout this period, work on the family
therefore sought to deconstruct taken-for-granted
ideas about the warmth, love, and support supposedly found in families. Instead it focused on
power relations, something notably absent from
earlier approaches. However, because emotions
were seen as suspect, this feminist work banished
a sphere of enquiry on love, care, and attentiveness for over a generation. Indeed, it was argued
that the very term family should be avoided, and
in its place the concept of the household used,
because this was free from naturalistic assumptions about gender roles, affection, duties of
care, and unequal, heterosexual relationships.
192
family
However, the attempt to remove the term family
from the sociological lexicon ultimately failed.
The rediscovery of domestic violence (itself a
contested term) was also linked to the focus on
power relations in the family. The term was
coined to counterpoise the idea of the domestic
as an environment of harmony and safety, with
concepts typically associated with the public
sphere, namely danger and harm. It was later
criticized because it obscured the fact that this
violence was inflicted overwhelmingly by men,
and so it was seen as disguising men’s moral responsibility for their behavior. But whether the
term wife beating or domestic violence or woman
abuse was used, the focus on violence was a crucial part of the redefinition of the family as a
universally “good thing.” Feminist work sought
to explain why women had little choice but to
stay in violent relationships, and also argued
that violent men gave rise to violent sons and
intimidated daughters. Through this focus on violence it was also argued that heterosexual relationships were dangerous for women and that,
even though not all men were violent, the cultural
acceptance of male violence in the home served
to empower all men in their relationships with
women.
Research on domestic violence highlighted the
core problem of women’s economic dependence
on men, especially when they had children and
had left the labor market. It also revealed the
extent to which both criminal and family law
protected the privilege of husbands within the
privacy of the family. Assaults, which would have
led to criminal proceedings if carried out in
public, were treated as a private matter between
spouses, and there was little help an assaulted
wife could call on. When combined with the
recognition of women’s double shift, emotional
labor, and economic exploitation in families,
there emerged an argument that the monogamous, heterosexual family was an arrangement
which was highly detrimental to women, and
which reproduced the privileged position of men
in western societies. For at least a decade feminist work on family life was largely preoccupied
with these questions of power and exploitation,
and sought to challenge the idea that families
had become more democratic and egalitarian
institutions.
The feminist critique on the family is often
(rather simplistically) seen to be the cause of the
decline of the family. This is because the depiction
of the family as a poor choice for women coincided (in western societies) with a rise in the
family
divorce rate, a decline in marriage rates and the
birth rate, a rise in cohabitation and lone motherhood, and also a rise in people living alone. However, it is important to recognize the extent to
which concerns and predictions about the decline
of the family are a historical phenomenon. It is
hard to find a moment when someone was not
expressing alarm that the family was no longer
the decent, patriarchal household of the past,
with obedient children and subservient wives.
Even Parsons and Bales started their book on the
family with reference to the worry that changes
in family structure were causing in the postwar
United States. Each new generation would appear
to have identified slightly different reasons for
the perceived decline or disorganization of the
family. Some saw the shift from extended to nuclear families as a profound loss, other saw the
loss of “functions” of the family (for example education) to the state as an indication of moral decline. Yet others saw (and still see) the rise in
divorce (see marriage and divorce) as a clear indicator of decline, while opponents argue that the
high rate of divorce is a sign that people set great
store by the value of good personal relationships
and so will no longer tolerate bad, or abusive,
situations.
These concerns gave rise to the so-called ProFamily Right, predominantly in the United States,
but also to a lesser extent in the United Kingdom. In a kind of backlash against the perceived
hegemony of feminist thinking, the Pro-Family
Right depicted fatherless families as the cause of
rises in delinquency, idleness, and poverty (David
Popenoe, Disturbing the Nest: Family Change and
Decline in Modern Societies, 1988). A dystopian vision
of family life came to dominate much of this
writing with each rise in the divorce statistics or
rise in numbers of children born out of wedlock
interpreted as a nail in the coffin of the family.
As early as 1983 Brigitte and Peter Berger, in
The War over the Family, were trying to find the
middle ground between those promoting policies
to re-establish the traditional family (by which
it was meant the patriarchal breadwinner / dependent housewife model) and those who saw
the family as the site of the reproduction of both
gender and class oppressions. In the United States
the “war” was highly charged because of the direct
link with both policy and politics, which meant
that studying the family had become less an
academic pursuit than a politically fraught enterprise. This politically charged engagement suggests that the study of the family might not have
been in the doldrums as Beck and Beck-Gernsheim
family
suggest, but in fact their point still stands because
the interminable debate about family decline
was ultimately intellectually reductive and circular. The claims and counterclaims became
familiar territory, and it seemed to become impossible to move beyond this narrow conceptual
straitjacket.
In fact, sociological work on families did manage to move forwards (although not completely)
as new ways of thinking about family relationships started to emerge. A key re-conceptualization
came from David Morgan in Family Connections
(1996), where he succeeded in ultimately breaking
with the functionalist tradition of seeing the
family as an institution with its roles and core
functions, and instead saw the family as something people “did.” He coined the terminology
of “family practices.” He conceptualized the
family as a web of relationships which was created and recreated by what people did and how
they related to one another through their ordinary practices. This meant that the family was set
loose from traditional ideas that it was fundamentally about the co-residence of a man and
a woman and their children, who all occupied a
given status in relation to one another. He grasped
what is acknowledged in everyday experience,
namely that those whom people feel to be family
are family and that co-residence is not vital to
form a family, but affective (and other emotional)
bonds and everyday practices are. This conceptual
shift provided a means to think differently about
families and to start to include varieties of previously unrecognized families without constantly
comparing them to the nuclear ideal. Morgan
also rehabilitated the term family. He acknowledged that it is a problematic concept because
of the ideology of familialism which idealizes a
particular type or set of relationships. The term
family is also apparently resolutely heterosexual
in intonation; some would argue it is heteronormative, because of its focus on and privileging
of marriage and opposite sex biological reproduction. But Morgan’s work pointed to the flexibility of the concept of family in everyday usage
and the ways in which it has been stretched and
molded, notwithstanding sociology’s attempts
to fix a definition of the family as comprising
two opposite sex parents and their children.
Morgan also pointed out that the term family is
deeply culturally significant, and, even though it
may have many different meanings, it is still
meaningful and so should not be discarded, since
it encapsulates and reflects a range of cultural
values which should be the focus of enquiry. The
193
family
task for sociology, he suggested, was to explore
more imaginatively how people “do” family life.
These ideas were simultaneously being reflected in a new body of empirical research on families. Of particular significance was the work of
Janet Finch and Jennifer Mason, Negotiating Family
Responsibilities (1993), who re-incorporated ideas
about values and meaning into how people live
their family lives. They used the term negotiating
in order to express how, even in close kin relationships, people were not governed by a sense of
handed-down rigid obligations, but were guided
by their feelings about their relatives and by
their own sense of ethics, or “the proper thing to
do.” Almost all family relationships were thus
seen as negotiable and so variable. Yet they also
found that there remained an important sense
of obligation and commitment to kin. This microlevel analysis focused much more explicitly on
the values that people live their family lives by;
it looked at everyday workings and gave precedence to the meanings that family members
themselves constructed in living their families.
This focus on meanings and values in everyday
living has also been reflected in other empirical
studies which have attempted to capture the
complexity of both relationships within families
and those between generations. This greater attentiveness to the ways in which real, complex,
and multilayered relationships are lived has
finally ended the sociological tendency to speak
about the family as if it was an entity of likeminded, homogeneous people who react in a
uniform way to the “outside world” rather than
themselves being (inter)active agents. An example
of this development is found in How Families
Still Matter by Vern Bengtson, Timothy J. Bibblaz,
and Robert E. L. Roberts (2002). This is a longitudinal study of American families which focuses on intergenerational change and continuity
across time. Four generations were included in
the study, with the first generation born at the
turn of the twentieth century, the second born
around the 1920s, the third around the 1950s,
and the fourth in the 1970s. The importance of
this study is that, through its longitudinal methodology, it has been able to capture continuity
and change across generations, while also mapping such changes onto the changing historical
times through which the families lived and are
still living. The study is also able to capture individual change, for example the authors can compare what people say now with what they said
ten or twenty years ago. They can, moreover, compare what older people born in the 1950s actually
194
family
said and felt when they were in their twenties
with what twenty-year-olds now say and feel. This
move to qualitative and quantitative longitudinal
research marks an important shift in the extent
to which sociology can actually grasp family life
and also the actual processes of family and social
change. Most significantly, it is able to deal with
the problem of “golden age” thinking in which
family life of the past is always depicted as better,
more moral, more loving, and generally superior
to family life now.
Observations of the interiority of family life
have also brought a new level of imaginative
thinking to the field. John Gillis, in A World of their
Own Making (1996), has distinguished between
families we live “with” and families we live “by.”
The latter are the families in people’s memories,
hopes, and imaginations, the families people represent to themselves; while the former are the
actual co-resident families who may be far from
the ideal held in thoughts or longings. Gillis
points to the constant iteration between these
two levels of experiences of, and thinking about,
families. His focus is on myth and ritual (for
example family holidays or the ways in which
ancestors influence lives lived in the present) in
order to reveal the ways in which people live
their families in their heads, not just in the
material present. To some extent, Gillis has rehabilitated the older concept of the ideology of
the family which, when deployed by feminist
writers in the 1970s, was seen as a kind of imposed, malign influence which kept women in
their place. In other words he has reintroduced
the significance of hopes and feelings into an
understanding of families, without the prior
assumption that these are oppressive devices.
These shifts in conceptualizing families, namely
seeing families as kinship networks which need
not co-reside, focusing on negotiations, highlighting the importance of the representation of
families both culturally and personally, and the
idea that it is important to capture process and
change, rather than taking a series of snapshots,
have all produced a sociology of family life which
is far more complex and subtle than the early
functionalists were able to produce. But factors
such as gender, social class, ethnicity, religion,
and sexual orientation remain an important component of a sociological imagination about family
life. Families remain one of the most significant
means of the transmission of privilege, wealth,
and cultural capital (see social capital) across generations. The personal nature of family life which
is captured above is also part of the reason why
family
abuses of power across genders and generations
remain hidden and tolerated. Moreover, the fact
that one is born into a family (usually) and that
one’s kin is identified in advance (through blood
ties and lineage) still means that families, unlike
friendships, are imposed rather than entered into
voluntarily.
This idea that families are inevitably given,
rather than chosen, has been challenged however. Kath Weston, in Families We Choose: Lesbians,
Gays, Kinship (1991), has pointed to the growing
creation and recognition of families of choice.
The exclusion of gays and lesbians from supposedly proper (that is, heteronormative) families
in conventional thinking has led to a reclaiming
and remolding of the concept of family so that it
can be used to signify people living together in
close relationships notwithstanding the fact they
are unable to marry and are not blood relatives.
The increase in, and increasing visibility of, lesbian mothers and gay and lesbian adoption, has
profoundly affected the taken-for-grantedness of
the heterosexual family. The claim by lesbians
and gays to form families has been controversial,
precisely because the family has been seen inevitably to incorporate and promote heterosexual
privilege; however, this move can also be seen as
part of the redefinition of what families are in
contemporary society and as a blurring of the
boundaries between traditionally privileged relationships and those that were once ignored and
denigrated.
It has been suggested above that sociological
work on families operates on two levels, with
macro-theoretical work progressing in a parallel
fashion with more micro-level work. Of course
there are conversations between the two, but
there is also a tension between the more finely
tuned, nuanced work of those engaged in more
empirical work, and those who are seeking to
develop broader theories about how family life
is changing. There has been a revival in sociological interest in families at the macro level
which has not been apparent since the decline
of the functionalist perspective (if one treats the
feminist interventions as slightly separate since
they did not emerge from mainstream sociology). Social theorists who have typically dealt
with traditionally conceived big themes (such as
capitalism or modernity) have turned their interest towards families. Most notable here is the
work of Beck and Beck-Gernsheim (Individualisation, 2002, The Normal Chaos of Love) who have
returned to the perennial theme of social change
and families. As part of their overall thesis on
Fanon, Franz (1925–1961)
the rise of individualization in modern societies,
they depict the family as a site of fragmentation
and of constant (exhausting) balancing and
negotiation. They argue, “Family life no longer
happens in one place but is scattered between
several different locations . . . The lives of individual family members, with their different rhythms,
locations and demands, only rarely fit together
naturally.”
They depict a tension between individual life
projects and the collective needs of families which
are hard to resolve, and relate these trends to
wider developments in a highly individualized
society. They suggest that western societies are
moving towards a post-familial family but, unlike
others who have observed family change and
seen alarming signs of decline, their analysis
identifies a range of new family forms which do
not conform to the nuclear ideal but which will
take their place alongside the more traditional
family structure. The theoretical scope of this
work has brought families back into mainstream
sociological thinking and reconnected the sociological understanding of family life with wider
social changes. However, the tension with the
more grounded empirical work remains, especially where evidence of the changes that Beck
and Beck-Gernsheim impute to the interiority of
family life is seen as tenuous or at least is disputed. Notwithstanding this, the sociological
study of families has become reinvigorated and
has returned to a more central place in the
sociological canon.
CAROL SMART
Fanon, Franz (1925–1961)
Born in Martinique, a French overseas territory in
the Caribbean, to a middle-class family of African
origin, Fanon studied medicine and psychiatry
in France in the late 1940s. He developed an
anti-colonial political doctrine that became a
main reference point for the Third World movement. Fanon became involved in politics, both
as a writer and as an activist in the 1950s while
directing a psychiatric ward in Algeria (another
of France’s overseas territories) during the country’s war of decolonization (1954–62). Having
joined the Algerian independence movement,
the Front de Libération Nationale (FLN), he proposed a radical brand of political existentialism
in which the realization of Algerian identity necessarily coincided with the destruction of the
French presence in the country.
His Hegelian-inspired construction of the black/
colonized self through the negation of the white/
colonial presence was developed in two main
195
fascism
works: Black Skin, White Masks (1952 [trans. 1967]
and The Wretched of the Earth (1961 [trans. 1965]).
Fanon showed how structures of domination,
mediated by culture and discourse, consistently
reminded the colonized of their fundamental inadequacy in a world created by white colonizers
in their image. Hence, Fanon emphasized the
therapeutic aspect of violence by the oppressed
against their oppressor, which freed them from
their inferiority complex and restored their selfrespect. Influential in postcolonial theory despite
its controversial apology for violence, Fanon’s
work has nonetheless been criticized for over-emphasizing the racial dimension of domination
at the expense of aspects such as gender or religion. His political essays are collected in two further works: Studies in a Dying Colonialism (1959
[trans. 1965]) and Toward the African Revolution
(1964 [trans. 1967]).
FREDERIC VOLPI
fascism
Sometimes used as a word of abuse to refer to
movements or individuals who are intolerant or
authoritarian, fascism is certainly intolerant
and authoritarian, but it is more than this. It is a
movement that seeks to establish a dictatorship of
the “right” (that is an ultra-conservative position
that rejects liberalism and anything associated
with the “left”). It targets communists, socialists,
trade unionists, and liberals through banning
their parties and their members, so that these
groups cannot exercise their political, legal, or
social rights. It is anti-liberal, regarding liberal
values as a form of “decadence” and seeing them
as opening the floodgates to socialist, communist,
and egalitarian movements.
As a movement, fascism extols action and practice over ideas and theory. It uses ideas with considerable opportunism, mixing socialist ideas,
avant-garde positions, anti-capitalist rhetoric, ecological argument, and pseudo-scientific ideas to
do with race and ethnicity in a veritable potpourri.
Is it an ideology at all? Some have suggested that
fascism is too jumbled and incoherent to be called
an ideology, but, while fascism is peculiarly “flexible,” there are particular features that characterize it, so that a general view of fascism can be
created.
The term derives from the fasces – the bundle
of rods carried by the consuls of ancient Rome;
the word fascio was used in Italy in the 1890s to
indicate a political group or band, usually of revolutionary socialists. But fascism is essentially
a twentieth-century movement, although it draws
upon prejudices and stereotypes that are rooted
196
fascism
in tradition. Italian fascism saw itself as resurrecting the glories of the Roman Empire, and
Alfredo Rocco (1875–1935), an Italian fascist, saw
Niccolo Machiavelli (1459–1517) as a founding
father of fascist theory. Nazism (which is an extreme form of fascism) was regarded by its
ideologues as rooted in the history of the
Nordic peoples, and the movement embodied
anti-Semitic views that go back to the Middle Ages.
Fascism appeals particularly to those who
have some property but not very much, and are
fearful that they might be plunged by market
forces into the ranks of the working class. Fascism
is particularly hostile to Communism, since it
is opposed to the cosmopolitan contentions of
Marxist theory, and its belief in a classless and
stateless society. It is a movement that dislikes
universal identities of any kind, although of
course fascists may call for unity with kindred
spirits in other countries. Nevertheless, it is intensely nationalistic, and takes the view that the
people must be saved from enemies whose way of
life is alien and threatening. Differences are
deemed divisive and menacing, and war extolled
as a way of demonstrating virtue and strength.
The idea that people are divided by social class
is rejected in favor of the unity of the nation or
people, so that industry is to be organized in a
way that expresses the common interest between business and labor. In practice, this did
not happen, and it is arguable that fascism is
anti-capitalist only in theory, not in practice.
Fascists vary in their attitude towards the
church (extreme fascists may see religious organizations as a threat to the state), but they regard
religion in a loose sense as being a useful way of
instilling order and loyalty. Certainly, they use a
religious style of language in invoking the need
for sacrifice, redemption, and spiritual virtue, and
fascists attack materialism, consumerism, and hedonism as decadent and unworthy. Although
women can be fascists as well as men, fascism is
a supremely patriarchal creed, by which I mean
that women are seen as domestic creatures whose
role in life is to service men, to have children, to
be good mothers and wives, and to keep out of
politics.
Fascism is hostile to the liberal tradition, and
it dislikes the notion of reason. It regards the
individual as subordinate to the collectivity in
general, and the state in particular. Liberal freedoms are seen merely as entitlements that allow
the enemies of the “nation” or the “people” to
capture power. Fascist regimes are highly authoritarian, and use the state as the weapon of the
fashion
dominant party to protect the nation, advance its
interests, and destroy its enemies. They are
strongly opposed to the idea of democracy (although fascists may use democratic rhetoric to
justify their rule or use parliamentary institutions
to win access to power), and regard the notion of
self-government (the idea that people can control
their lives in a rational way and without force)
as a dangerous myth. As a movement based upon
repressive hierarchy, fascism argues that all institutions should be controlled by “reliable”
leaders, and the “leadership principle” comes to
a climax with the supreme leader, seen as the
embodiment of the nation and the people. Fascist
leaders may be civilians, but they are closely identified with the army and police, since these institutions are crucial to rooting out opponents.
Fascist movements extend beyond the state, but
the violence of these movements is condoned
and encouraged by the state; given tight control
over the media, this violence is then justified in
the light of fascist values.
Fascists see themselves as revolutionary in that
they are concerned to “rejuvenate” a tired and
decadent society, and some fascists speak of creating a “new man” in a new society. They are, therefore, anti-conservative as well as anti-liberal,
although they may form tactical alliances with
other sections of the right when they can establish momentary common ground. Many regimes,
loosely called fascist, are in fact conservative
and reactionary systems – Franco’s Spain, Pétain’s
“Vichy” France (a regime that collaborated with
the Nazis who occupied the country), Japan
under Tojo, and so forth. They may have fascist
elements within them, but they are not really
anti-conservative in character.
Postwar fascism has generally sought to distance itself from intrawar ideologies in Germany
and Italy, and has ranged from movements that
see the European Community as containing the
germ of a “United Europe” to movements hostile
to the European Union. Some fascist movements
claim democratic credentials, although these are
not really plausible, given their intense chauvinism, anti-feminism, and hostility to liberalism
and socialism.
JOHN HOFFMAN
fashion
The study of fashion in the sociological tradition
has a long history. However, it is important to
distinguish between two related approaches: (1)
an emphasis on the study of fashion as a cultural
phenomenon of modernity; and (2) fashion as
the study of clothing and the body in specific
fashion
cultural contexts. These features are often run
together although we should recognize that they
are analytically separate. The sociologist Georg
Simmel argued that fashion emerges in a society
that is built upon social and cultural change.
For Simmel, fashion is built on the impulse to
distinguish yourself from others, while also
satisfying the need for social adaptation and
imitation. Fashion is mainly structured by social
class and is caught in constant cycles of innovation and emulation. As elites attempt to
set themselves apart through observable social
markers like dress, others seek to copy the new
styles as they emerge from above. Consequently,
elites respond by inventing further new styles
and so on. Fashion in this analysis becomes a
novelty mania, where collective tastes are being
born and replaced at ever faster rates. Indeed, if
fashion becomes routinized and formalized it can
lose the charm it exercises over its consumers.
Simmel’s arguments were further developed
by Thorstein Veblen (1857–1929), who similarly
argued that the cycles of fashion were structured
by class. For Veblen what became fashionable
was largely determined by what was in short
supply and expensive. This was a way (as Simmel
also suggested) of distinguishing classes, but also
of displaying wealth and power. Fashion was a
way of making wealth visible through “conspicuous consumption” so that it might be admired
by others.
There are two main objections to such views:
(1) the analysis tends to ignore other sociological
features such as age, race, and gender, which are
perhaps even more important than class in structuring fashion; and (2) elites are no longer, if
indeed they ever were, the main purveyors of fashion. In modern societies, elites often find themselves “out of fashion” or even lagging behind
current trends.
Other studies of fashion have tended to emphasize features other than social class. Gender is
now seen as a key determinant in the study of
fashion. In Elizabeth Wilson’s Adorned in Dreams
(1985), fashion is seen to represent the Romantic
movement’s critique of the culture of instrumentality that accompanied the industrial revolution.
In this view fashion is explicitly concerned with
sensuality, aesthetics, and individualism. Further,
fashion values the life of the city by emphasizing
the spirit of play, fluidity, and performance over
authenticity. Fashion is a form of adult play
made possible by the development of modernity.
In this respect, Wilson criticizes some feminist
authors for dismissing fashion as a form of
197
fashion
masculine control, when it offers women, its main
consumers, with the potential for aesthetic
creativity.
Indeed many have argued that the “grand theorists” of fashion have mistakenly presumed it
to be an explicit product of western society. Here
the study of fashion has become the recognition
of the acceptable codes of behavior that govern
the presentation of the body. In particular these
features have emphasized the role of gender and
youth in the construction of fashion. Particularly
important here has been the shift from equating
fashion with the lifestyles of social elites and
the rise of a mass fashion industry over the course
of the twentieth century. If, in the 1920s, Hollywood helped democratize ideas of glamor and
beauty, it was the 1960s that provided the first
genuinely mass fashion. Further, the 1970s witnessed the emergence of supermodels, who were
highly paid international figures who helped
promote a certain look. Most of these developments sought to target women as the main consumers of a fashionable image, but this would
change in the 1980s. Until this period heterosexual men’s clothing was probably more conformist than that of women. This was a direct
consequence of the fact that men risked being
labeled effeminate for showing too much interest
in fashion. Expressive fashions up until this point
were mostly confined to gay men, ethnic groups,
and popular entertainers. The shift in fashion occurred during the 1980s for three main reasons:
(1) the arrival of high-street stores that explicitly
offered affordable stylish clothes for men; (2) new
visual representations of men (in particular the
softer and more caring form of masculinity that
was represented in the new man); and (3) the
arrival of new style and fashion magazines.
Other sociologists have emphasized how fashion can become a site of cultural struggle. Dick
Hebdige, in Subculture (1979), argues that the
adoption of different styles on the part of young
people can act as a form of defiance. Fashion and
clothing can become a way of subverting dominant discourses and codes that seek to regulate
acceptable behavior. Youth cultures and subcultures hold out the possibility of suggesting new
and oppositional meanings in different social
contexts. The rise of new youth lifestyles since
the emergence of rock and roll in the 1950s
offered opportunities to subvert the values and
meanings of the dominant parent culture. However, whatever the role that fashion plays in the
formation of identity, it continues to be linked to
a wider culture of modernity in a way that was
198
fatherhood/fathers
recognized by earlier classical thinkers. In particular, fashion is a requirement of the economic
system. Unless consumers are willing to buy new
things, get into debt, and give up old tastes in
preference for the new, then capitalism’s ability
to expand would be severely curtailed. If fashion
represents change and the formation of identity,
it nevertheless continues to represent the cycles
of profit maximization in an increasingly
commercial world.
NICK STEVENSON
fatherhood/fathers
In patriarchal societies fathers are a source of
both authority and power in the ordering of the
lives and social experiences of family members.
The role of fatherhood is an identity taken up
outside the workplace in the private sphere. In
industrial society the main role of the father
was to be both a provider for, and protector of,
the family. Many objected that such was the
authority of the father that the nuclear family
was actually a form of domination requiring the
subordination of women and children. Further the
image of the father proved to be a powerful one
with many national leaders earning the title
“father of the nation.” In more recent times, the
authority of individual fathers has been challenged by the development of democratic norms
(women’s and children’s rights) and the development of the welfare functions of the modern
state. In western industrialized societies, since
the 1950s, the role of fatherhood has been the
subject of transformation and change. The development of dual-labor households and new expectations in respect of intimacy have arguably
changed the role of fathers. Further, the development of lesbian and gay social movements,
feminism, and other features have all sought to
increase the diversity of family types and has
arguably unsettled previous patterns of male
dominance.
The changing roles of men and women and the
shaking of heterosexual norms have all taken
their toll on the social privileges of the father.
In The Transformation of Intimacy (1992), Anthony
Giddens has argued that families have become
more contingent social arrangements. Fatherhood
is no longer defined by economic necessity, but
has become an empty sign to be filled by the
participants within the relationship. This does
not mean that the family has become more harmonious. Indeed with the decline of overt class
antagonisms, the family is the place where most
individuals are likely to experience conflict. Yet
if the role of fatherhood is being redefined, it
fecundity
feminism
is not clear that men themselves have kept
pace with the new demands now being made of
them. In the demand for new intimate and caring
family ties, men have become “laggards” in the
shift towards more egalitarian relationships. Such
a situation has meant that traditional forms
of masculinity (and fathering) continue to exist,
as a backlash in the face of the demand for more
equal relations, mainly coming from women.
Many feminists have criticized the idea that
we are currently living through a transformation
of this type. First, many radical critics argue that
patriarchy has been intensified rather than diminished by current social transformations.
Under the hegemony of the market and masculine
values, motherhood has become a non-identity.
The care of children and vulnerable adults is
increasingly outsourced and is work of low social
status. Here the small steps that some fathers
have taken in respect of a more nurturing role
should not be allowed to overshadow more disturbing transformations. Second, other critics
have contested the view that the home has been
democratized, pointing to the slow change of masculine values and the continued subordination
of women, children, and other sexual identities.
NICK STEVENSON
fecundity
– see fertility.
feminism
Histories of feminism usually assume that feminism is a western, post-Enlightenment social
movement which has contributed significantly to
changes both in the social situation of women
and in social perceptions of women. This assumption has frequently made feminism the subject of
attacks from women in non-western cultures who
have identified the movement as pre-occupied
with western issues and unable to understand
the gender relations of other societies. Thus it is
first and foremost important to recognize the
possible ethnocentricity of feminism, while at
the same time acknowledging that feminism, in
the broadest sense of the protest of women
against a subordinate social status, is both global
and takes different forms in different cultures.
Where feminism stands universally united is on
issues of the valid claim of women to education, to
a public voice, and to equality with men in law.
The most usually recognized starting point of
western feminism is in the eighteenth century
and, in particular, the publication, in 1792, of
Mary Wollstonecraft’s A Vindication of the Rights
of Woman. This book emerged out of a number of
social and intellectual changes in the eighteenth
century: the growing assumption of the equal
rights of all individuals and what Thomas Laqueur
has described as the invention of sex in his Making
Sex (1990). From the beginning of the eighteenth
century onwards, numerous writers (including
Mary Wollstonecraft’s husband, William Godwin)
articulated what was to become the rallying cry
of the French Revolution: “Liberty, Equality, and
Fraternity.” Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–97) entirely supported the first two of these propositions but took issue with the idea of “fraternity.”
Her argument suggested that no society should
allow men to control the public space or to have
no knowledge of, or responsibility for, the private,
domestic sphere. Thus Wollstonecraft argued not
just for the education and public emancipation
of women, but also for the domestic education
and participation of men.
Wollstonecraft died the death of thousands of
eighteenth-century women when she gave birth
to her daughter, Mary Shelley. But her book was
recognized both before and after her death, and
was influential in what became known as the
domestication debates of the early nineteenth
century. Although her influence on writers is often
implicit rather than explicit, what Wollstonecraft
had done was to identify the social making of
gender: this made it possible for later writers
to suggest (as Simone de Beauvoir was to do in
the twentieth century) that women are “made and
not born.”
Throughout the nineteenth century, in both
Europe and the United States, women (and occasionally men such as John Stuart Mill) questioned
the social role of women and argued for their
greater participation in the social world and
equality of education. Perhaps inevitably, in the
nineteenth quite as much as in the twentieth
century, feminism and feminist demands were
complicated by differences between women. In
Britain these differences were generally differences of social class, while in the United States
racial and ethnic differences were to have equal
significance.
Throughout the nineteenth century, feminism,
on both sides of the Atlantic, was to constitute an
important part of social debates and the culture
which informed literature and the visual arts.
Classic liberalism, for example in Mill’s On the
Subjection of Women (1869), emphasized the importance of the education of women: this emphasis
was hugely influential and made education, and
access to education, a consistently important part
199
feminism
of feminist campaigns in both the nineteenth
and the twentieth centuries. (Indeed, in the late
twentieth century this argument still continues:
the economist Amartya Sen has suggested that
the key to reducing the birth rate, and a greater
degree of economic prosperity, lies in the education of women.) In both the United Kingdom and
the United States, white, middle-class women
campaigned for women to have access not just to
schools – which had always been allowed, if less
enthusiastically than for men – but to higher education. By the end of the nineteenth century, this
objective had been achieved in both Britain and
the United States and a very small number of
women had begun to attend university.
Feminist campaigns for education were, however, only part of feminist history in the nineteenth century, and a part which was largely the
concern of middle-class women. Of equal importance were the campaigns, often far more disruptive and socially contentious, for the right of
women to own their own property and for a
form of sexual morality which did not take for
granted male sexual rights over women. Alongside these campaigns – fought throughout the
West – were the struggles of working-class women
to secure rights in paid work. One of the longest
battles which has been fought by western feminists is that for equal pay: this battle continues
into the twenty-first century. The arguments involved have changed considerably over the past
100 years and second-wave feminism in the West
secured the greater recognition of the concept
of “equal work of equal value,” which did much
to overturn the more traditional idea of the different (and deeply gendered) value of different
kinds of work.
A second campaign fought by feminists has a
similar historical length to battles over the rewards of paid work. This is the campaign by
women for control over their bodies: a campaign
which first arose in the nineteenth century over
the question of the sexual double standard and
has continued into the twentieth and twenty-first
centuries in relation to issues related to new
forms of technology, notably contraception and
the new reproductive technology. In the nineteenth century, campaigners such as Josephine
Butler succeeded in over-turning legislation which
assumed male rights of sexual access to women.
In the early twentieth century, women such as
Marie Stopes argued for women’s right to contraception and heterosexual fulfilment. All these
debates, as much in the nineteenth century as in
the twentieth, lie within the remit of feminism
200
feminism
(since they imply an explicit commitment to the
rights of women), yet they are at the same time
complicated by the different politics of the
women involved. For example, Marie Stopes had
views about genetics and the reproduction of
“the race” which would nowadays be regarded
with some suspicion; other women involved in
campaigns around reproduction and sexuality
were committed to normative heterosexuality
and the social status quo.
It is thus that the history of feminism is complicated by the diverse politics which women (and
very occasionally men) have held. In the twentieth
century, there was a very general approximation
of the coincidence of feminist and progressive
views about women and women’s emancipation
with left-wing and radical politics. Thus the rightwing, fascist regimes of the twentieth century
(Franco’s Spain, Mussolini’s Italy, and Hitler’s
Germany) have all supported traditional views
of women and passed legislation designed to
ensure the exclusion of women from the public
world. At the same time, it is also the case that
those equally radical, although left-wing, regimes
such as that of Stalin’s Russia, while fully integrating women into paid work (and putting in
place a social infrastructure to make this possible)
have minimized sexual difference and articulated
a model of human beings as male. This eradication of gender difference has been widely questioned, and feminist writing of the late twentieth
century has claimed that feminism should be
about the recognition of the female/feminine
rather than the equalization of the female/
feminine with the male.
At the beginning of the twenty-first century,
feminist writers have come to recognize that
feminism is a broad church and that the interests
of feminism cannot be easily summarized. The
great work of twentieth-century feminism, de
Beauvoir’s The Second Sex (first published in 1949
[trans. 1972]) famously argued that women are
made by society and the social world, and that
the social world which “makes” women has a
consistent tradition of misogyny. This social constructionist view of women has been widely influential and there was little significant challenge
to the view until the publication, in 1974, of Juliet
Mitchell’s Psychoanalysis and Feminism. In this discussion of Sigmund Freud, Mitchell argued that
feminists should re-consider the impact of biological difference on behavior and our symbolic interpretation of the world. The work was extremely
influential and opened up new developments
which made feminism itself more reflective.
feminism
In large part this greater self-consciousness led
feminists to re-consider the relationship of feminism to the social world and to consider, as Sheila
Rowbotham (1943– ) has done in Hidden from
History (1973), the emergence and practice of
western feminism as part of the politics of liberal
capitalism. What this view does is to shift the
claims of feminism from those of a movement
of social transformation to those of a movement of
social integration. Without for one moment denigrating the achievements of feminism (which in
areas such as paid work, property and legal rights,
and sexual politics have been of value to all
women, regardless of class and race and ethnicity),
this argument sees feminism in wider terms and
as part of the transformation of western capitalism to a social system based on consumption.
The history of feminism is generally divided
into the first-wave feminism which extends from
the middle of the nineteenth to the early twentieth
century, and second-wave feminism which
developed from 1970 onwards. Feminism at the
beginning of the twenty-first century is often
described as part of the “mainstream” in that
many institutional contexts demand gender equality and policies which recognize the claims of
women and men to equal treatment. At the same
time, while institutional contexts have achieved
significant forms of recognition of the rights
of women, there remain numerous aspects of
social life where gender differences are still considerable. Throughout the West it is still the case that
the birth of children impinges far more on the lives
of women than on the lives of men, and women
have far less involvement in political, public
power than men. These gender differences are
clearly resistant to social change, despite the fact
that, in the United Kingdom, women over the age
of thirty have had the vote since 1918, partly as a
result of the political impact of the Suffragettes –
a social movement associated with Mrs. Emmeline
Pankhurst (1858–1928) who successfully campaigned for the enfranchisement of women.
These issues remain of consistent importance
to individual women and to those feminist groups
which campaign on specific issues related to the
situation of women. In this sense, the contemporary history of feminism is similar to its history
in the past: as a movement its concerns are
rooted in a particular historical and social context, even though the thread which unites all
feminist movements is that of the universal social
subordination of women. But what has become
a central part of contemporary feminism is
the acknowledgment that claims such as the
fertility
“universal subordination of women” are complicated by the differences between women and the
part which women themselves play in determining their own situation. Thus feminism today
recognizes the considerable degree of female
agency, with the crucial implication that this
may powerfully disrupt the idea of a single
feminist agenda.
MARY EVANS
fertility
This term refers to the actual production of children. Demographers thus distinguish between
the actual production of children and the ability
to produce children, known as fecundity. Medical
scientists do not make such a distinction, and use
the term fertility to refer to reproductive ability.
French-speaking and Spanish-speaking demographers (like their English-speaking counterparts)
also distinguish between the potential and actual
production of children, but they reverse the
English usage of the terms. Thus French-speaking
demographers use the term fertilité, and Spanishspeaking demographers the term fertilidad, to refer to reproductive ability, and fécondité and fecundidad, respectively, to refer to actual reproductive
performance.
An easily understood and interpreted method
for quantifying fertility is the crude birth rate
(CBR), that is, the number of births in a population
in a given year, per 1,000 members of the population. It may be expressed as follows:
CBR ¼
births in the year
1; 000
population at mid-year
Using data for China for 2004, the equation becomes:
CBR ¼
15; 600; 000
1; 000 ¼ 12
1; 300; 000; 000
This means that in China in 2004, there were 12
babies born for every 1,000 persons in the population. Crude birth rates among the countries of the
world in 2004 ranged from lows of 9 in several
countries, including Austria, Germany, Bulgaria,
Poland, and Greece, to highs of 55 in Niger and 51
in Malawi. The range of crude birth rates is much
greater than that for crude death rates, which in
2004 extended from a low of 2 to a high of 29.
Lay persons tend to employ the CBR more often
than any other fertility measure, but it is not the
most accurate of the measures. Its denominator
does not really represent the population exposed
to the risk of giving birth because males, pre-puberty
females, and post-menopausal females are included. Because of this overly inclusive denominator, the CBR should be interpreted with caution.
201
fertility
Demographers use more refined fertility measures, including the general fertility rate (GFR),
age-specific fertility rates (ASFR), the total fertility
rate (TFR), the gross reproduction rate (GRR), and
the net reproduction rate (NRR). The GFR, ASFR,
and TFR are increasingly more accurate measures
of the childbearing experiences of the population.
The GRR and the NRR measure not fertility but
actual reproduction.
Demographers have developed extensive theories of fertility. Prominent explanations include
demographic transition theory, wealth flows theory, human ecological theory, political economic
theory, feminist theory, proximate determinants
theory, bio-social theory, relative income theory,
and diffusion theory. The view of some that demography is void of theory is an incorrect one.
Indeed there is more theory in demography than
in most of the social sciences.
A major explanation of fertility change and dynamics has its origins in demographic transition theory (DTT), as first developed by Frank W.
Notestein in “Population – The Long View,” in
T. W. Schultz (ed.), Food for the World (1945), and
by W. S. Thompson in his article “Population”
(1929, American Journal of Sociology). Current versions of DTT propose four stages of mortality
and fertility decline that occur in the process
of societal modernization. The first is the preindustrialization era with high birth and death
rates and stable population growth. With the
onset of industrialization (see industrial society)
and modernization, the society transitions to
lower death rates, especially lower infant and
maternal mortality, but maintains high birth
rates, with the result of rapid population growth.
The next stage is characterized by decreasing
population growth due to lower birth and death
rates, which lead then to the final stage of low
and stable population growth.
DTT argues that the first stage hinges on population survival. High fertility is necessary because
mortality is high. Thus societies tend to develop
a variety of beliefs and practices that support
high reproduction, and these are primarily centered on the family and kinship systems. The
forces of modernization and industrialization
alter this state of near-equilibrium, and the first
effect is often a reduction in mortality. Indeed
the beginnings of mortality decline in many European countries were stimulated not so much by
medical and public health improvements as by
a general improvement in levels of living. This
intermediate stage resulted in rapid rates of
population growth because fertility remained
202
fertility
high after mortality had declined. In the next
stage fertility declines also to lower levels. The
causal linkages are complex. Underlying the
global concepts of industrialization and modernization are such determinants of fertility as
women’s participation in the labor force and
the changing role of the family. The normative,
institutional, and economic supports for the large
family become eroded, and the small family becomes predominant. The increasing importance
of urbanization affects the family by altering its
role in production. Also, urban families meet
considerably higher demands for consumption
from their children, especially for education and
recreation.
J. C. Caldwell, in “Toward a Restatement of
Demographic Transition Theory” (1976, Population
and Development Review), has called for a restatement of demographic transition theory. His fertility theory of wealth flows is grounded in the
assumption that the “emotional” nucleation of
the family is crucial for lower fertility. This occurs
when parents become less concerned with ancestors and extended family relatives than they are
with their children, their children’s future, and
even the future of their children’s children. He
argues that ideally there are two types of societies; the first is where “the economically rational
response is an indefinitely large number of children and the second where it is childless.” But
why from an economic view would couples want
either an unlimited number of children or none
at all? Caldwell explains that it depends on the
direction of the intergenerational flows of wealth
and services. If the flows run from children to
their parents, it is entirely rational for parents
to want to have large families. In modern societies where the flow is from parents to children,
it is rational to want small families. To say that
parents in the less developed countries are “irrational” because they continue to have large
families is to misunderstand these societies. Caldwell states that fertility behavior is rational in
virtually all societies irrespective of their levels
of development.
Two other prominent fertility paradigms are
based on human ecology and political economy.
The human ecological theory of fertility is a
macro-level explanation and argues that the
level of sustenance-organization complexity of a
society is negatively related with fertility. In
the first place a high fertility pattern is dysfunctional for an increasingly complex sustenance organization because so much of the
sustenance produced must be consumed directly
fertility
by the population. High fertility should reduce
the absolute amount of uncommitted sustenance
resources thereby limiting the population’s
flexibility for adapting to environmental, technological, and other kinds of changes and fluctuations. Low fertility is more consonant with
the needs and requirements of an expansive
sustenance organization. More sustenance would
be available for investment back into the
system in a low-fertility population than in a
population with high fertility. Large quantities of
sustenance normally consumed by the familial
and educational institutions in a high-fertility
population would hence be available as mobile
or fluid resources in a low-fertility population.
Sustenance organization in this latter instance
would thus have the investment resources available for increasing complexity, given requisite
changes in the environment and technology.
This leads to the hypothesis of a negative
relation between organizational complexity and
fertility.
The political economy of fertility is not really a
theory of fertility per se, but an investigative
framework or “analytic perspective” for the study
of fertility, according to S. Greenhalgh in “Toward
a Political Economy of Fertility: Anthropological
Contributions” (1990, Population and Development
Review). Diverse fields of knowledge are integrated into the political economy approach. It is a
“multileveled” approach, combining both macroand micro-level explanations of fertility patterns
occurring in a given locale. This means that determinants are considered and measured at
every level, including, for instance, global, international, and national forces; political, structural,
and legal shifts; community factors; and characteristics of the individual couple. Central to this
perspective is the appreciation of “agency and
structure,” or structuration, which refer to the
structural elements and stages that delineate the
existing choices people have, as well as the incentives and tactics that come into play as individual objectives are met. This framework entails
both quantitative and qualitative approaches.
A good example of a political economy approach
to fertility is Dennis P. Hogan and David I. Kertzer,
Family, Political Economy and Demographic Change
(1989), a study of Casalecchio, Italy. They tracked
one rural community over a few change-laden
decades of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, using individual-level data and directed by a
life-course perspective. They touched on often
ignored historical events, such as labor and marriage patterns, and found that fertility varies with
feudalism
the social class or occupation of the individual
family.
DUDLEY L. POSTON
feudalism
This term is used to describe forms of political,
economic, and social relationships found during
the Middle Ages, principally in western Europe
but also in Japan and sometimes China. It is
derived from the Latin term feodum and the
Germanic fief, but was not used until the seventeenth century. When defined narrowly as a legal
relationship, it refers to a set of reciprocal legal
and military obligations within the nobility between a lord and a vassal. In this hierarchical
relationship, the lord granted land, or a fief, to a
vassal through a commendation ceremony involving homage and an oath of fealty. In return for the
land and, in addition, protection from the lord,
the vassal was obliged, through the principle of
fidelitas, to provide military service and to give
“counsel” or aid to the overlord (suzerain). There
was also often a process of subinfeudation in
which a vassal would grant part of his fief to
another vassal and become a lord himself. Although having some basis in Roman times, this
system of allegiance is generally regarded as
having emerged slowly during the ninth and
tenth centuries as a means to reinstitute social
order, and to protect against further incursion,
following the Germanic incursions.
With reference to political rule, owing to poor
communications and transport, and the localized
character of the agricultural economy based essentially on a manorial system, feudalism was
characterized by decentralized institutions of
power. Although the king was generally regarded
as the chief lord, in reality governmental authority
was fragmented so that individual lords and
barons had considerable autonomy and largely
administered their own estates. Power was exercised by the lords predominantly through jurisdiction and the holding of courts to settle disputes.
This was backed by the ideological power of the
church which owned a considerable amount of
land, as did many bishops and abbots. The church
also emphasized the divinely created and hierarchical nature of a society divided into three
major social classes: those who prayed (clergy),
those who fought (nobility), and those who
worked (peasants).
A second definition of feudalism gives prominence to economic rather than juridical relations.
Here the hierarchical relationship between lord
and vassal is extended to include the socioeconomic obligations of peasants and serfs. For
203
Feyerabend, Paul (1924–1994)
fieldwork
Karl Marx, feudalism was primarily a mode of
production, which, unlike slavery and capitalism,
permitted some control over the means of production to peasants, especially through customary
rights. The dynamic underlying feudalism was
sustained through the exploitation of peasant
tenants by lords, vis-à-vis the extraction of feudal
rent, usually through labor services on the demesne (home farm). The level of feudal rent was
determined by the relative military or political
strength of the lords as compared to the serfs,
who, at minimum, had to maintain family subsistence. This antagonism was often expressed in
peasant uprisings.
Rather than the etymological question of
whether and to what extent feudalism existed,
the crucial question for many Marxists has concerned the transition from feudalism to capitalism and the role played by internal relationships
of feudalism as opposed to the external impact
of the market in accounting for the transition.
There have, however, been other more general
definitions of feudalism which have attempted
to fuse these definitions by accentuating the
social, political, and economic criteria existing
in the Middle Ages. Writing from a sociological
perspective, Marc Bloc in Feudalism (1939–40) has
argued that feudalism includes: a subject peasantry; widespread use of the service tenement
(that is, the fief) instead of a salary; the supremacy
of a class of specialized warriors; ties of obedience and protection which bind man to man
and, within the warrior class, assume the distinctive form called vassalage; fragmentation of authority, leading inevitably to disorder; and the
survival of other forms of association.
However, given the diversity of practices, types
of social relationship, and customs characterizing this period, as well as the diversity of national
and geographical differences and inflections,
medieval historians, such as Elizabeth Brown in
her essay “The Tyranny of a Construct: Feudalism
and the Historians of Medieval Europe” (1974,
American Historical Review), have argued that the
varied use of the term renders it meaningless,
and that its application to the medieval world is
confusing and inaccurate. Nevertheless, given
the existence of key characteristics and concepts
associated with the Middle Ages, the term is still
widely used in history and sociology.
STEVEN LOYAL
Feyerabend, Paul (1924–1994)
Born in Austria, Feyerabend initially studied philosophy at the University of Vienna and then at the
204
London School of Economics under Karl Popper.
He made an important, albeit iconoclastic, contribution to the philosophy of science. He initially
followed Popper’s philosophical outlook, but soon
deviated from it, embracing instead the historical
approach of Thomas Samuel Kuhn in his Structure
of Scientific Revolutions (1962). From the early 1960s
onwards Feyerabend devoted himself to exploring
the relevance of the history of science for the
philosophy of science. Feyerabend was a prolific
author; his main contribution remains Against
Method; Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge
(1975). He contributed to the debate surrounding
falsificationism. This debate is summarized in
Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (1970), edited
by Alan Musgrave and Imre Lakatos.
At the time, many philosophers, like Popper,
tried to uncover the method common to all scientific practices and which distinguishes them from
non-scientific activities. Feyerabend questioned
the validity of this philosophical enterprise. The
history of science shows that there is no single
method common to all sciences: a detailed historical outlook demonstrates that scientists operate in very different ways. The consequences
for critical rationalism were devastating. Feyerabend argued that not only did scientists not
operate in a Popperian fashion, but also, if they
had followed Popper’s prescriptions, they would
not have progressed to the same extent.
PATRICK BAERT
fieldwork
This is a broad type of qualitative research also
sometimes known as ethnography or as observation and participant observation. Regardless of
the label, the research is based upon collecting
information through observation of how people
live “real life.” Fieldwork is a qualitative technique
because the researcher is striving to obtain richly
detailed information about the social situation
they are interested in and will be using inductive
methods of analysis to generalize from the data
in order to develop conceptual ideas.
Fieldwork can be grouped into three types,
each with an increasing level of involvement and
contact between researchers and their subjects.
The observation of some ongoing social situation but without direct contact or involvement
by the researcher. For example, I am interested in
barbecue culture in the southern United States
and decide to observe the interactions between
customers and staff in Dizzy’s Bar-B-Q.
With observant participation, the researcher
begins to observe and collect information about
fieldwork
some ongoing social situation that s/he is already
involved in during their normal everyday activities. That is, the researcher has to “step outside
himself/herself” and begin to look at the everyday
social environment from a new point of view –
that of the researcher – and begin to apply techniques of observation, note-taking, and analysis.
For example, I am a regular at Dizzy’s Bar-B-Q and
decide to carry out a systematic observation of the
interactions between the manager, employees,
and customers. The advantages of observant participation are that researchers already have access
and are their own source of insider knowledge.
The disadvantage is that, unlike the observer
coming from outside, one may find it difficult to
switch to the role of a researcher. Things that have
always been taken for granted may be important
and can easily be overlooked.
Where the researcher immerses him/herself in
a social environment that is new to him/her: for
example, getting a job in Dizzy’s in order to do
research on southern barbecue culture. This immersion starts to give the researcher the same
level of access and opportunity to gain insider
knowledge but participant observation is more
than that. It is the process of gradual internalization by the novice researcher of the cultural
mores of the observed group that is the key to
true participant observation and that makes it
truly qualitative. The researcher is immersed in a
social environment that is new to him/her, and
the presumption is that they can be aware of how
their own reactions and feelings alter as they
become socialized. In effect, the researcher’s own
feelings, and how they change, become data.
A crucial decision the researcher must make
is whether to reveal to those being observed that
they are being researched – to carry out overt
research – or to keep the research subjects unaware – to adopt a covert role. The advantages of
a covert role include: (1) it may be impossible to
observe some types of behavior or groups unless
it is done covertly – when this is the case and the
topic of research is sufficiently important, this
can be a justification for covert research; (2)
access, getting permission to carry out research,
is not a problem if the research is covert – if no
one knows you are doing it, obviously there is
no problem; (3) people may behave differently if
they know they are being researched – if they
don’t know they are being observed, the problem
of reactivity is avoided.
There are a number of disadvantages to covert
fieldwork, such as the practical difficulties and
psychological costs of maintaining a front, but
firms
the main disadvantage of covert research is its
questionable ethics. The research subjects are
being deceived and their privacy may be invaded. Specifically, they obviously do not have the
opportunity to give informed consent.
ROBERT MILLER
figurational sociology
– see Norbert Elias.
firms
This is the organization of production of largescale enterprises, employing wage labor and
financed by bank-credit money, and is a typical
element of capitalism. This superseded various
forms of domestic and household production in
which work and the household are integrated,
and production is financed entirely from saved
income. There are three general theories of this
development: (1) new institutional economics; (2)
Weberian theories of bureaucracy; and (3) Marxist
theories of exploitation.
(1) New institutional economics is an attempt
to explain social institutions as the result of rational economic maximization. If, as economic
theory maintains, the market is the most efficient
form of organization, why, the Nobel prize-winner
Ronald Coase (1910– ) asked in 1935, do firms
exist? Why did the large vertically integrated
firm replace the putting-out system in which independent domestic producers were connected
and coordinated by contractual market relations?
Coase answered that firms exist when there is
a cost to using the market mechanism. In a series
of publications beginning with Markets and
Hierarchies (1975), Oliver Williamson has elaborated this insight and integrated it with Alfred
Chandler’s The Visible Hand (1977). Market relations
incur “transactions costs.” For example, there
may be only a few acceptable suppliers of raw
material (“small numbers bargaining” and “asset
specificity”) which may enable them to take advantage of a producer (“opportunism with guile”).
These market relations can be controlled only
by costly surveillance and legal contracts, which
may be more efficient to replace by internalizing
them into an integrated hierarchy. The firm replaces production chains and networks, as command and authority replace contract. Types of
firm, varying by levels of backward or forward
integration, may be placed on a continuum:
from vertically integrated bureaucratic firms
through looser structures such as franchising
or dealerships. Transactions-cost economics is
used to explain the transnational firm (see
205
firms
transnational corporations); hierarchy is less
costly than transnational contracts with spatially
and culturally distant suppliers. Several problems
persist with this analysis owing to an inadequate
treatment of “hierarchy” as a structure of power,
rather than as merely a rationally devised costreducing mechanism. Where does power to choose
an organizational form come from? Large firms are
not simply an alternative to costly market exchange, but a means of superseding the market to
make monopoly profits, as argued in Giovanni
Arrighi, The Long Twentieth Century (1994).
(2) An alternative sociological explanation of
the firm’s role in producing economic rationality
is provided by Max Weber. In General Economic
History (1927 [trans. 1981]), he contrasts the rationality of the capitalist firm with traditional
workshop production and booty capitalism. Rationality is seen as the capacity to calculate and
is linked to the use of double-entry bookkeeping to strike a balance (rational capital accounting). This capacity is structurally dependent on
the bureaucratic firm. Like the modern state, the
capitalist firm is a corporate body that becomes
structurally differentiated from household and
family, which enables the removal of arbitrary
nonrational decisionmaking based on traditional
norms and family ties. This is attributed in part
to the use of external credit finance and the
need for the precise calculation of returns due
to nonfamily, as opposed to a share in the common family pot. This occurred most clearly in
the West; for example, in trading associations –
such as the ship’s company and the spreading
of risk in commenda finance. This analysis remains
relevant for modern debates. Is oriental family
capitalism a viable alternative to the western
model, or is it crony capitalism that impedes economic rationality? Similarly, is the joint-stock
corporation, owned by outsiders, the most efficient form of organization? Weber appears to
concur with modern economic analysis that the
firm’s separation from family ownership creates
a competitive market in which a firm’s market
value, based on performance, is a means of monitoring the managerial bureaucracy.
Formal rationality (calculation of profitability)
has a substantive basis in the power and control
that comes with the complete appropriation of
nonhuman means of production and the formally free labor market. Capitalists and their
managers can freely manipulate the production
process, and hire and fire workers at will to
maximize returns to capital (see Marxist theory
below). The firm is an agency for calculation, not
206
firms
(as in economic theory) an aggregation of calculating agents. Therefore, in contrast to the view of
new institutional economics, the bureaucratic
firm is not an alternative to the market, but the
complementary location of economic rationality.
For Weber it is a question of markets and hierarchies, not markets or hierarchies.
(3) For Karl Marx, the capitalist firm exists in
order to dominate and exploit wage labor. In his
critique of classical economics, Marx made a
distinction between labor and labor-power. The
worker does not sell a fixed unit of labor input
for a wage in an equal exchange. Rather, the
worker sells, or alienates, labor power – or productive potential – to be organized by the capitalist. Labor not only exchanges effort for reward,
but submits to domination in the labor process
which enables the capitalist to extract surplus
value through exploitation. Thus, the form taken
by the capitalist firm is the means by which labor
is transformed into capital. In “What Do Bosses
Do? The Origins and Functions of Hierarchy in
Capitalist Production,” in Anthony Giddens and
David Held (eds.), Classes, Power and Conflict (1982),
Stephen Marglin argues that the division of labor
and the centralized hierarchical organization
of the firm are not determined by technology,
but by the need to create and accumulate capital.
The bourgeoisie play its historic role by exploiting the workers in order to gain a competitive
advantage and, in doing so, advances the means
of production. In Labor and Monopoly Capital
(1974), Harry Braverman distinguishes two central
features of the capitalist firm: the social division
of labor (occupations) and task specialization; and
the separation of hand and brain through the
deskilling and appropriation of the knowledge
function in a management hierarchy. Both are
determined by the need to maintain power and
control in the firm.
In Chaos and Governance in the Modern World
System (2000), Giovanni Arrighi and Beverly Silver
identify three dominant historical forms of capitalist firm. Each is associated with successive
capitalist state hegemonies: (1) Dutch and English joint-stock chartered companies in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries; (2) British
family-enterprise capitalism in the nineteenth
century; and (3) American multidivisional, multi/
transnational corporations from the early twentieth century. Each attempted global monopolization of the most profitable activities; each was
dependent to a significant degree on external
financing; and, in the development of a contradiction, each comes to depend increasingly on,
firms
but is ultimately subversive of, hegemonic state
power.
(1) Joint-stock chartered companies had their
origins in commenda-trading ship finance in Italian
city-states such as Venice and Genoa during the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The English
East India Company (1600) and Dutch East Indies
Company (1602) were granted monopoly charters
by their respective states, which were not quite
powerful enough to monopolize the trade themselves. These firms were a hybridization of capital
and coercion. They internalized their protection
costs with their own armies; but externalized
transactions costs by organizing production in
long chains of domestic production. That is to
say, unlike earlier empires, these company states
did not only exact tribute and taxes, or impose
direct controls on an economy, but also financed
and coordinated indigenous workshop/communal
production into a chain, as in the European
putting-out system. A dynamic Indian cotton industry exported to Europe. But there were two
contradictions; the increasing coercion costs were
borne by the Company, and its repatriated profits
helped to transform the British textile industry
which opposed the East India Company’s monopoly, which was consequently abolished in 1813.
(2) Nineteenth-century British family-enterprise
capitalism was based on the protection of global
networks, undertaken by imperial powers, in
which domestic production became linked to exploitation of empires’ primary products. European
domestic production was transformed by mechanization, which facilitated the reorganization
of proto-capitalist putting-out chains into factories that reduced transactions costs, and the subordination of the workers to a calculable regime
of rigorous exploitation. As Adam Smith (1723–
90), and later Marx and Engels, observed, the intense competition, unchecked by state-controlled
monopolies, and reduction of capital costs
through mechanical innovation led to falling profits and a deflationary spiral, culminating in the
sharp down-turn of the business cycle.
(3) Modern corporations emerged at the top
level of capitalist economies, most clearly in the
United States, in the last quarter of the nineteenth
century. They were large oligopolies or monopolies with bureaucratic management, separated
to some degree from owners. From their inception, the American enterprises were multidivisional and multi/transnational. Two factors were
involved. First, as Marx observed, incapable of raising enough capital for large-scale mass production
technology, family capitalism was replaced by
firms
joint-stock corporations. Second, vertical integration of production chains in large corporations
and horizontal combination in cartels were means
of avoiding the earlier competition that had reduced profits to intolerable levels. Different paths
were taken in dominant economies.
In Germany, as part of a state-building process,
there was horizontal and vertical integration in
association with the big banks. Families retained
some power via large banks and the state elite.
This path was also characteristic of Japanese
capitalism.
Britain moved more slowly towards monopoly
capitalism. A looser and more fragmented familybased structure persisted until after World War II.
The City of London remained cosmopolitan and
concerned with commercial and financial activity
of the world as explained in Geoffrey Ingham,
Capitalism Divided? (1984).
In the United States, the bureaucratic, multidivisional, multi/transnational corporations based
on mass production created a “second industrial
revolution” (Chandler, The Visible Hand, 1977).
Bureaucratic management first appeared in railroads and the telegraph, based on West Point
military hierarchical command and control. It
quickly spread to mass retail and mail order; Sears
Roebuck was processing 100,000 orders per day
by 1905. This was accompanied by the creation
of the mass consumer by advertising and the
“democratization of luxury,” according to Weber.
A populist political backlash against banking
“money trusts” produced a departure from the
path taken in Germany to the joint-stock system
of diffused mass stock/share ownership. The
“roaring Twenties” culminated in the Wall Street
Crash (1929) and were followed by the ideological
relegitimization of capitalism, as occurred after
the early 21st-century technology stock crash and
the corporate frauds in Enron, Worldcom, and
other corporations. In the 1930s, this involved
the professionalization (see profession[s]) of management in Taylorism and scientific management.
Managers were portrayed as the technically expert guardians of a “peoples’ capitalism,” in which
dispersed shareholding separated ownership from
(management) control.
These vertically integrated enterprises gained
competitive advantage by greater control and
calculation of speed of throughput, based on a
further reduction of transactions costs and an extension of control over labor by assembly-line technology. They were multinational from the outset.
By 1914, American direct investment abroad, at 7
percent of Gross National Product, was as high as
207
firms
in the 1960s; and, by the late 1920s, Ford and
General Motors had firms in Britain and Europe.
However, this mode of capitalist regulation,
based on monopoly mass production and mass
consumption could be limited, as John Maynard
Keynes realized, by a lack of “effective demand.”
The underconsumption/overproduction crises
of the 1930s were overcome by the post WorldWar-II “warfare–welfare state,” based upon state
expenditure and the United States’ bid for global
dominance in order to capture foreign markets.
For example, the United States government supported the European Common Market on condition that there was no discrimination against
US multinationals.
As before, the successful capitalist organizational innovation was emulated with varying
degrees of success by competitors with similar
results. There was an intensification of competition; but innovators of earlier developments in
industrial organization may become locked in to
a path dependency that inhibits the adoption of
the next innovation. The French were quick
learners and, under state direction, systematically
set about Americanizing its industry. In contrast,
the fate of the British automobile industry is testimony to continued difficulties with the adoption
of large-scale organization and mass production.
By the 1980s, it was argued, for example in
Michael Piore and Charles Sabel, The Second Industrial Divide (1984), that the dominance of American
“dinosaur” corporations was being overcome by
new forms of organization: first, by flexible specialization and informal networks/alliances between small and medium-sized firms in local
industrial districts; and, second, by the challenge
of East Asian forms of industrial organization, especially Japanese “relational contracting” and
“just-in-time” methods of vertically disintegrated
production chains. American corporations responded to this competition by cutting costs with
the “downsizing” and “delayering” of management and labor, in order to increase profitability
and “stockholder value.” By the late 1990s, the
large multi/transnational American enterprise had
survived as the dominant form of organization.
The modern capitalist enterprise is the site of
a struggle for its economic surplus. Reliance on
external finance from either banks or the stock
market and the growth of managerial bureaucracy have rendered this conflict more complex
than the conflict between capital and wage labor
in the nineteenth-century family-owned firm, as
outlined by Marx. This question of “ownership
and control” or “corporate governance” was first
208
firms
addressed in the stock-market-based American
economy by Adolf Berle and Gardner Means, in
The Modern Corporation and Private Property (1932).
They asserted that stock ownership in almost half
the largest American nonfinancial corporations
was so dispersed that no “dominant” ownership
interest was evident and, therefore, they must
be controlled by the managers. Coming after the
American Senate’s Pujo Committee’s (1913) critical, populist “money-trust” interpretation of
US capitalism, and the Wall Street Crash, The
Modern Corporation and Private Property conveyed a
clear ideological message. “Managerialism” maintained that managers were neutral technocratic
guardians of “peoples’ capitalism” in enterprises
in which there was no inherent conflict of interest
due to the widespread share ownership.
Marxist analyses of twentieth-century capitalism
have been influenced by Rudolph Hilferding’s
Finance Capital (1910 [trans. 1981]), which analyzed
the dominance of large banks in the German economy. Until recently, the “finance capital” interpretation was seen simply as an alternative to
Berle and Means’s “bourgeois managerialism.”
However, they are referring to two different patterns of corporate financing – bank lending and
stock markets – and their effects on corporate
governance.
Research in the 1970s lent support to the “managerialist” account of the American economy.
Echoing Keynes’s “euthanasia of the stockholder,”
John Kenneth Galbraith (1908–2006) argued in his
New Industrial State (1967) that the modern corporation was controlled by a managerial “technostructure.” Unlike owners with a direct financial
stake – that is, families, stockholders, banks, and
other financial interests – managers did not
pursue profit maximization, but, rather, growth,
sales, and prestige in order to consolidate their
power and security.
During this period of American “managed”
monopoly capitalism after World War II, financial
and creditor interests were less powerful. During
the 1970s, however, a combination of falling
profits, inflation, global recession, and a collapse
of the stock market led to a reassertion of financial interests and a rebalancing of power between creditors, stockholders, managers, and
workers. A new coalition of corporate managers,
investment-fund managers, and stockholders
aimed to “unlock shareholder value.” This new
neoliberal settlement reestablished the dominance of financial interests as outlined in Geoffrey
Ingham, The Nature of Money (2004), and Neil
Fligstein, The Architecture of Markets (2001). In a
firms
wave of mergers, acquisitions, and hostile takeovers during the 1980s, managers’ interests were
aligned with those of the stockholders with the
use of stock options as managerial remuneration.
Unsatisfactory performance brought the threat
of a hostile takeover or of a “leveraged buyout”
(LBO) by a new class of financial entrepreneurs
such as Kohlberg Kravis Roberts. The resulting
private companies fell under the financial discipline of the new owners and, with its management
holding stock options, they released the “free
cash flow” to shareholders. According to Doug
Henwood in Wall Street (1997), “An LBO is a form
of class struggle.”
In The Political Determinants of Corporate Governance (2003), Mark Roe has extended this analysis
and argued that the Anglo-American type of large
corporation based on the separation of diffuse
stockholder ownership and management control
is incompatible with social democratic political
systems based on high levels of employment security and welfare. In these circumstances,
management and workers both benefit from the
maximization of growth and employment rather
than profits. Unless the interests of shareholders
and management can be aligned as they were in
the United States and Britain in the 1980s, then,
shareholders will find it difficult to impose
the changes that might maximize “shareholder
value.” Strong social democracies, such as those
of continental Europe, with high levels of welfare,
job security, and takeover controls encourage
management to define their interests in terms
of security and the avoidance of risk and radical
change. In order to resist this alliance of management and workers, ownership is more concentrated in the hands of banks and families – as
in France, Germany, and Italy. On the basis of
empirical evidence, Roe identifies two patterns of
corporate governance and social democratic politics in the fifteen wealthiest nations during the
post-World-War-II period: (1) diffuse ownership
and low social democracy – for example, the
United States, Britain; and (2) concentrated ownership and high social democracy – for example,
Germany, Italy, France. Globalization appears to
be changing the latter pattern. The deregulation
of capital markets is leading to the erosion of concentrated bank and family ownership in national
economies and stronger shareholder interests in
the form of global investment funds. With the
intensification of global competition, shareholder
interests exert pressure to replace employment
security and social welfare with economic “flexible” labor market policies.
GEOFFREY INGHAM
flexible specialization
First Nations
These are peoples asserting a common cultural
and linguistic heritage and descent from common
ancestors who were the original and enduring
inhabitants of circumscribed territories later
absorbed into modern states. Most broadly conceived, they constitute what is often called the
Fourth World and include all of the aboriginal
populations of the Americas and of Australia;
the Inuit and Aleut peoples of the American and
Eurasian Arctic; the transhumant pastoralists of
Scandinavia, Russia, and the Balkans; minority
populations of the insular Pacific such as the
Japanese Ainu and natives of Hawaii; the Hmong
of China and Laos; peoples of Africa such as the
Pygmies, the Nuer, and the San; and many others.
More narrowly conceived, they are those Native
American peoples formerly referred to as “bands”
that the government of Canada officially recognizes as being entitled in principle to selfgovernment. The term First Nations emerged in
Canada during the later 1970s and its use is still
far more common there than elsewhere. Native
American bands began to adopt it as a selfdesignation in the course of asserting their right
to be recognized as one of the “founding nations”
of Canada, together with the English and the
French. They effectively established it as a selfdesignation at the First Nations’ Constitutional
Congress, convened by the now-defunct National
Indian Brotherhood in 1980. There are currently
more than 600 First Nations in Canada and their
numbers are likely to grow as smaller and more
scattered populations win governmental recognition in future decades. They do not, however,
and probably will never include the Metis, a large
population descending from unions between
French colonists and Native Americans that is concentrated especially in the southeast of Canada
and has episodically but enduringly cultivated
a distinctive nationalism of its own. The situation
of the Metis nevertheless points to one of the
most controversial aspects of the very concept of
“First Nations,” whether broadly or narrowly
conceived – that of what degree of cultural and
genealogical “purity” is necessary, and what other
criteria are sufficient, to establish membership.
JAMES D. FAUBION
flexible specialization
This term was introduced in the 1980s to redescribe a familiar type of labor process and to
identify a new type of economic strategy in response to the crisis of Fordism. It refers to the
209
flexible specialization
use of flexible machinery by skilled or craft labor
to produce a wide range of products to exploit
economies of scope. It is contrasted with Fordist
mass production, which involves the use of dedicated machinery and plant by semi-skilled labor
to produce long runs of standardized products to
exploit economies of scale. It would be wrong to
see these as the only types of labor process. There
are many other ways to organize this, depending
both on the nature of the products and on the
dominant social relations.
Michael Piore and Charles Sabel argued in The
Second Industrial Divide: Possibilities for Prosperity
(1984) that the growing displacement of craft production by mass production in the late nineteenth
century was more the result of a paradigm shift
produced by social and political struggles than to
inherent technical superiority. They suggested
that the crisis of Fordist mass production was
an opportunity to revive craft production in the
form of flexible specialization. And they also
claimed that success in this regard would usher
in a democratic republic of craft workers in control of their working lives, for flexible specialization reskills and empowers workers so that
they were no longer simple appendages to the
machine. This combination of advocacy and analysis has been a marked feature of the flexiblespecialization literature and makes it vital to
distinguish between: (1) the theoretical and historical claims made for flexible specialization as
an ideal type of production organization; and (2)
the normative-political claims made for it as an
idealized type of production organization that
should therefore be adopted.
Analysts and advocates of flexible specialization
normally identify three variants: (1) a small-firm
variant exemplified in the industrial districts
characteristic of the Third Italy, an industrial
region that was initially created in the 1950s and
1960s to foster co-operation between small, craftbased firms; (2) a West German model based on
internal decentralization of large firms; and (3)
the Japanese just-in-time production model based
on large firms’ sponsorship of complex, multilayered subcontracting networks. In each case,
productivity and innovation depend on collective
efficiency and economies of scope in the use of
flexible machinery and flexible labor. In the
first variant, a key role is played by local authorities and consortia of small firms. The second and
third variants, in contrast, involve the delegation
of financial, marketing, and research services
to a combination of semi-autonomous internal
business units and cooperative external suppliers.
210
focus group
These examples all involve “offensive flexibility,” that is, forms of flexibility that promote
high-quality production and high productivity.
There are also “defensive” forms that involve
hire-and-fire labor markets, flexi-wages (including
downward flexibility), and a focus on cost reductions. While offensive flexibility may prove
sustainable in the medium term, defensive flexibility is more likely to be a short-term solution.
BOB JESSOP
focus group
This research method is designed to generate
data on group beliefs and group norms by capturing intra-group interaction in specially composed
groups (a range of differently composed groups
is normally required), where the researcher seeks
to facilitate and record that interaction. Although
methods akin to focus groups were used by academic sociologists researching the persuasiveness of United States government World War II
propaganda, focus group methods are a crossover method from commercial market research.
However, as Michael Bloor, Jane Frankland,
Michelle Thomas, and Kate Robson have pointed
out in Focus Groups in Social Research (2001), there
is now a divergence between market research
and academic social research in their uses of
focus groups. The former primarily uses focus
groups as a locale for conducting group interviews. In the latter, rather than conduct a question-and-answer session with the group, the
facilitator seeks to generate intra-group discussions which are illustrative of group norms.
A focus group should also be distinguished
from a delphi group, a panel of experts which
may be repeatedly consulted or reconvened to
derive authoritative consensus statements of
group belief or policy.
Facilitators typically seek to generate a general
discussion by asking the group to perform a set
task, or focusing exercise. A common type of task
is a ranking exercise, where the group will be
asked to look at a series of statements and then
rank them in order of correctness or importance.
Fictitious vignettes may also be presented and
the group may be asked to discuss what action
the central character in the vignette should
undertake next. Analysis of focus groups is normally based on the study of transcripts of audiorecordings. Email communication has permitted
research using virtual focus groups, where the
facilitator/moderator operates a closed email distribution list. Such groups can have many more
participants than conventional focus groups
folk religion
and, of course, have no attendance and/or
transcription costs.
Focus groups are used more frequently as an
ancillary method than as the main research instrument. They are often used in pilot studies for
larger projects to collect data on group norms
and on everyday language use, in order to assist
in planning the next phase of the investigation.
Focus groups are also often used at the close of
projects to collect feedback from respondents on
preliminary research findings.
Whether or not it is preferable for focus group
members to be known to each other has been a
matter of controversy. It has been argued that,
by recruiting from pre-existing friendship groups,
work groups, and so on, focus group researchers
may be able to tap into group interactions that
approximate to naturally occurring data, which
might otherwise be only slowly accumulated by
an ethnographer. However, in research on sensitive topics there is a real danger of over-disclosure
by animated participants.
The fashionableness of focus group methods
had looked set to wane due to difficulties with
recruitment and analysis. But the development
of virtual focus groups has ensured their continuing popularity.
MICK BLOOR AND FIONA WOOD
folk religion
– see religion.
folkways
– see norm(s).
food
The economic, social, and symbolic significance
of food is a highly complex interdisciplinary topic
of study which sociology, understandably, has addressed in only some aspects, and then unevenly.
The diversity and complexity of the topic has
resulted in its analysis through many different
theoretical lenses – of political economy, structuralism, feminism, poststructuralism, actor network
theory, conventions theory – and via historical,
institutional, and developmental approaches.
For most people throughout history, food
production has involved local, small-scale organization for household consumption, with the implication that what was eaten was seasonal and
limited by geography and climate. Industrialization required, and supplied the means, to transform food production. Urban populations could
not supply sufficient of their own raw materials,
impelling changes in agricultural techniques and
processes and new means of distribution. The
food
logic of industrial production also spread to food
as a product. Now a substantial part of food production is organized on a global basis, by large
corporations, operating internationally, to grow,
process, and distribute foodstuffs. Rationalization
of production results in less employment (see
work and employment) in agriculture (a feature
of all societies undergoing modernization), larger
production units, and greater commodification
of food provision.
Contemporary agro-food studies encompass
issues associated with rural and economic sociology in western societal contexts. Interest in the
organization of rural communities has declined
with the reduced size of rural populations and
their lesser dependence on employment in agriculture. Instead attention has focused on the organization of the food industries, particularly the
feature of organization into a chain of successive,
non co-located, commercial episodes of production and exchange, of farming, processing, and
retailing, each with intermediating processes of
transportation and storage. Explaining the restructuring of these connections, which themselves vary for different types of produce, has
generated competing theoretical frameworks of
various provenance, including world system
theory, regulation theory, commodity system and
commodity chain analysis, a systems-of-provision
approach, and later hybrid accounts paying greater attention to the impact of local and cultural
diversity on food production.
One consequence of the increasingly global
span of the food chain is the greater visibility
of the unevenly developed supply of adequate
food. The highly secure, varied supply to the rich
countries contrasts markedly with continued
shortages and famines in other parts of the world.
And even within the most affluent societies,
though malnutrition as a consequence of poverty
has mostly disappeared, there remain significant
inequalities in access to diets of good-quality and
nutritious foodstuffs.
Food provision and preparation remains a key
activity of households even in the industrial and
post-industrial societies, because most eating
occurs within the home and requires much domestic labor of shopping, preparation, cooking,
and cleaning. Most work of this kind is done
everywhere by women, part of the unequal division of labor which defines gender inequalities.
Such work is integral to the reproduction and
maintenance of family relations and family life,
symbolizing belonging and care, and a source of
emotional attachment and conflict.
211
food
Eating is a fundamentally social activity; in general people have not preferred, and do not prefer,
to eat alone. Households are defined for official
purposes as those who eat together, and in societies where people live predominantly in elementary or nuclear families, the family meal has
been seen as a central temporal and social organizing principle of everyday life. The extent to
which it may be in decline has attracted much
attention. Meals away from home, in restaurants,
canteens, and other homes are also social events,
ones which increase with industrialization and
the growth of consumer services. The meal is a
major social institution. All social groups have
norms and conventions governing the social relations of commensality, concerning who should
eat together and what foods are appropriate to
which gatherings. These norms are partly definitive of relationships of intimate and distant
kinship, friendship, and interaction with strangers. Norms of hospitality vary greatly between
societies, ethnic groups, and social classes.
What is considered fit and appropriate to eat
varies between cultures and many societies have
complex culinary conventions which comprise
cuisines to which nations, ethnic groups, and
social classes have strong symbolic attachments.
Also, more elaborate cuisines develop in places
with particular hierarchical types of social structure. For example, the French royal court not
only ate differently from the peasantry but also
was central to the refinement of table manners
which Norbert Elias in The Civilizing Process (1939
[trans. 2000]) considered a key element of the
western civilizing process. Cuisine types are now
marketing devices for restaurants and cookery
books, and although isolating precisely the defining characteristics of French, Persian, or Chinese food may be difficult, national and regional
ways of selecting and preparing preferred ingredients persist, and indeed are often increasingly
valued. The symbolic aspects of food have been
most powerfully analyzed by anthropologists,
but cultural sociology and sociology of consumption has increasingly become involved. Food
preferences are made to reflect and indicate differences in class distinction and aesthetic taste,
to express ethnic group membership, and also
personal identity.
Many eating events are now more informal than
before. As foods become more highly processed
and require less preparation – as with “fast food”
and convenience foods – greater opportunities
exist for people to adopt individualized habits
of consumption. Meals are now less regular,
212
Foucault, Michel (1926–1984)
uniform, and predictable. Also, it has become
harder to justify what to eat and perhaps more
necessary to do so in the face of unprecedented
variety. This has gone along with perhaps some
greater anxiety about food, symbolized, for
example, by epidemics of anorexia and obesity.
Anxieties are also apparent as a sense of risk
arising from the technologies of food processing –
additives, genetic modification, and so on. This
has had an impact through food scares and crises
of consumer trust which have in turn led to
renewed effort being devoted by political authorities to legislation and regulation and restructuring of the activities of market actors. These
are also increasingly prompted by social movements promoting new types of diet, for instance
vegetarianism; new production standards as with
organic foods; and styles of eating, for example
the Slow Food Movement. People, either individually or through consumer associations, often
with the collaboration of niche producers, attempt to modify and regulate their food consumption in accordance with their ethical and
political principles, their attitudes towards body
maintenance, and their aesthetic preferences.
ALAN WARDE
Fordism
– see post-Fordism.
formal organizations
– see bureaucracy.
Foucault, Michel (1926–1984)
Foucault was born in Poitiers, France, and died
at the age of fifty-seven from an AIDS-related illness. He studied both psychology and philosophy
at the École Normale Supérieure and went on to
teach psychology in a department of philosophy
while also working as a researcher in a hospital
in Paris. The latter posting provided the inspiration for his first book, Mental Illness and Psychology
(1954 [trans. 1976]). Foucault continued this practice of simultaneously teaching and holding practical postings throughout his career, which
allowed him to write Madness and Insanity in the
Age of Reason (1961 [trans. 1965]), Birth of the Clinic:
An Archaeology of Medical Perception (1963 [trans.
1973]), Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison
(1975 [trans. 1977]), and the volumes that constituted The History of Sexuality, such as The History of
Sexuality Volume One: An Introduction (1976 [trans.
1978]); volume II, The Use of Pleasure (1984 [trans.
1985]), and The Care of the Self (1984 [trans. 1986]).
Foucault, Michel (1926–1984)
Foucault’s intellectual investigations originated with an inquiry into the ways in which scientific discourse shapes the boundaries between,
and relationship of, good and evil, safety and
danger, and health and illness. He observed that
the development of microtechnologies of surveillance paved the way for society to act upon these
ideas in order to control the behavior of individuals and diffuse norms among large groups. This
creates what he termed an environment of panopticism, so titled after Jeremy Bentham’s (1748–
1832) eponymous prison in which inmates were
subject to a regime of constant and complete
surveillance. Ultimately, it was therefore not
simply discourse, but the entire infrastructure of
the rational, scientific face of governance, that
was implicated in the dual processes of individuation and massing. In the twentieth century, these
processes culminated in the installation of authoritarian regimes responsible for some of the
most grievous atrocities humankind has visited
upon itself.
Equally crucial to Foucault’s thought was the
tenet that science infuses social life with particularly powerful behavioral norms, therefore equipping individuals with technologies of the self
that cause them to internalize social norms
through which they become self-policing. Thus,
even the most private acts become moments
during which people reproduce cultural understandings of the normal or the decent, and the
abnormal or the indecent. Technology permits
those dangerous individuals who are not “selfdisciplining” to be disciplined by social institutions and the state. Hospitals, prisons, and insane
asylums therefore function both to reinforce
norms for those who might stray and to discipline
the recalcitrant. Their logic and impact extends
beyond their own walls creating a carceral society
in which discipline is imposed on all individuals
privy to public spectacles of punishment.
Through his study of the natural and human
sciences, Foucault was able to reveal the capillary
nature of power. So, in his example, students
submit willingly to examinations, disciplining
themselves physically and mentally, even when
they have no expectation of immediate, coercive
punishment from a centralized authority. The
implications of the capillary nature of power also
allowed Foucault to reconceive the study of politics, and more specifically government, by indicating that it is the channels through which
power flows, and the methods by which it is exercised, that ultimately constitute power. Governmentality is a set of successful techniques whose
Foucault, Michel (1926–1984)
ultimate achievement is control and political
coordination of specific populations. In this
view, the state is only the most readily apparent articulation of the larger process of
governmentalization.
Because Foucault was committed to demonstrating the manner in which the sciences are
not abstracted academic pursuits, but rather important and unrecognized channels of power,
his substantive and methodological projects are
inextricably linked. Foucault’s most significant
methodological injunction is that meaning must
be sought by examining evidence not simply
qua evidence, but rather as composed of organic
artifacts laden with meaning beyond that explicitly stated by their authors. In the case of historical knowledge, we must be cognizant that
history is a product as much of the present in
which it is unearthed as the past that buried it.
Meaning is revealed via an intricate process of
what he initially termed archeology but later
came to be known as genealogy. The idea of a
legitimate authority of truth is debunked insofar
as knowledge and those who seek it are each
simultaneously the objects and tools of power.
This renders the concept of academic disciplines
one in which scientists discipline and are in turn
disciplined by the subjects of their inquiries.
Foucault himself rejected the claim that he was
a structuralist, though many find his approach to
show the influence of structuralist logic. Scholars
of Foucault have also engaged in a heated debate
about the intellectual coherence of his corpus.
Some have argued that, contained within the entirety of his work, is an almost Rousseauian set
of distinct and sometimes inconsistent strains of
thought: one liberal and the other radical. The
liberal Foucault views power more neutrally than
does his more radically skeptical alter ego. To
critics, this also indicates an important inconsistency in his understanding of power. Alternatively,
the disaggregation of power from domination
has the effect of redistributing the pejorative connotations others have associated with power.
This makes room for a more normatively neutral
and less fatalistic vision of human interaction,
which both rescues Foucault from internal contradiction and opens avenues for the study of
how individuals exercise power in ways that resist
domination.
Foucault attributed to his own work influences
that included Friedrich Nietzsche, Max Weber,
Theodor Adorno, and Max Horkheimer. In turn
his legacy has shaped the contributions of innumerable social scientists, notable among them
213
Frank, André Gunder (1929–2005)
Frankfurt School
Pierre Bourdieu, Anthony Giddens, Nancy Fraser, of heterodox Marxist theorists, including Theodor
and Edward Said. His intellectual presence is felt Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Herbert Marcuse, Frethroughout the social sciences and remains
both particularly strong and controversial in the
fields of cultural geography, discourse analysis,
criminology, and the sociology of medicine.
ELIZABETH F. COHEN
Frank, André Gunder (1929–2005)
Born in Berlin and educated at the University of
Chicago where he obtained his PhD in Economics
in 1957 for his dissertation on Soviet agriculture,
Frank went to Latin America in 1962 where he
taught at the University of Brasilia. In 1965 he
moved to the National Autonomous University
of Mexico, and in 1968 he was a professor of sociology at the University of Chile, where he became
involved in the social reforms of the Salvador
Allende administration, and, after the military
coup in 1973, he escaped to Europe where he
became Visiting Research Fellow at the MaxPlanck Institute in Starnberg, Germany, from
1974 to 1978. In the years leading up to his retirement in 1994, he held many professorial appointments in Britain, Belgium, France, Germany, the
Netherlands, and the United States.
Frank published extensively but his principal
contribution was to the emergence of development theory in which he was a critic of modernization. He argued that development was not a
unilinear or inevitable process from tradition to
modernity, because the developed world caused
the underdevelopment of peripheral economies
and societies. These critical assessments of the
impact of capitalism in Latin America appeared
in Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America
(1969) and Dependent Accumulation and Underdevelopment (1978). He was critical of the western bias
in economic history and historical sociology, and
in ReOrient: Global Economy in the Asian Age (1998)
he sought to re-assess the independent growth
of Asian economies before the age of western
imperialism.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Frankfurt School
Although there was no “School” in the sense of
any agreed body of theory and research, the term
Frankfurt School is associated with theorists of
the Institut für Sozialforschung (Institute of Social
Research), founded in Frankfurt in 1923 and
at first directed by an orthodox Marxist, Carl
Grünberg (1861–1940). In 1930 Max Horkheimer
assumed control and promoted interdisciplinary
research guided by a broadly Marxist social philosophy. The Institute attracted a diverse group
214
drick Pollock, Franz Neumann (1900–54), and Leo
Lowenthal (1900–93), who, between the 1930s
and 1960s, developed distinctive critical analysis
of western capitalism and culture, drawing insights from many sources, including Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Immanuel Kant (1724–
1804), Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900), Max
Weber, Georg Simmel, Sigmund Freud, and Jewish
philosophy. In 1937 Horkheimer expounded the
concept of critical theory, as a programmatic statement of his philosophy, which was to become one
of the most influential social theories of
the twentieth century. In opposition to “contemplative theory,” or detached observation of the
world, Critical Theory would seek engagement
with radical sources of critique and emancipatory
practice, building into its concepts the possibility
of a better society.
However, by the 1930s the world had changed
dramatically from that represented in the classical Marxist critique of capitalism. World War I
had demonstrated the capacity for mass destruction created by technological warfare and unsettled belief in progress though the development
of technology and science. The failure of revolutionary movements in western Europe and the
success of the Russian Revolution created a new
global polarization compounded by the consequent fission of the left into democratic socialist
and communist parties, and the dominance of
fascism over much of Europe. Further, the increasing complexity of capitalist economies, the emergence of new mass communications media (see
mass media and communications), and the increasing role of the state in the economy meant
that the Marxist notions of class formation and
class-consciousness needed rethinking. In particular these developments made the possibility
of successful proletarian revolution uncertain.
However, the “death of the proletariat” motif in
Critical Theory should not be exaggerated; in
1941 Horkheimer wrote the optimistic revolutionary essay “The Authoritarian State,” invoking
the “trailblazing” tradition of workers’ councils
going back to 1871, which was imminently to
sweep aside the authoritarian state. Even so, in
Dämmerung (1934), Horkheimer had suggested
that there were “subtle apparatuses” (education
and mass media) working to protect capitalism
against revolutionary consciousness. Indeed, in a
world dominated by totalitarianism (Stalinist
and fascist) on the one hand, and the mass culture industry on the other, any belief in the
Frankfurt School
redemptive potential of class struggle appeared
naive.
Any revolutionary cultural or political impulse
risked being incorporated and becoming itself
an instrument of domination. Thus, according to
Adorno, as the practical possibilities of emancipation are closed off, “philosophy returns to
itself.” Karl Marx’s early works such as Hegel’s
Philosophy of Right had talked about the utopian
core of Hegelian philosophy being “realized,”
that is instantiated, through the real-life struggles
of the working class. But by the 1940s the realization of this “moment” of history had been
missed and the urgent task of Critical Theory
was to keep alive the possibility of critical thought
at all, by developing perspectives that critique
the world from the standpoint of a future emancipated society. One such influential and controversial critique was that of the popular culture
industry epitomized in big band jazz and the
Hollywood cult of stardom. As culture was produced for a mass market, the commodity form
entered the very process of creation or composition of works of art, thereby undermining their
aesthetic form. This development created an uncritical and soporific culture reconciled to the
status quo that lacked the glimpse offered by
aesthetic experience into the possibility of a
non-alienated existence.
Unlike orthodox Marxism, Critical Theory
was receptive to Freudianism. A distinctive feature
of Frankfurt research was the combination of
class analysis with analysis of the psychodynamics
of the family and authority. This theme came to
the fore after 1933, when the Institute was forced
to leave Nazi Germany, and functioned in exile
in Geneva, then New York, and finally California.
Marxism and psychoanalysis were combined with
empirical social psychology to generate a new
theory of authoritarianism (the authoritarian personality) and critical reflection on the fate and
direction of western modernity. This combined
several themes of Frankfurt thinking, in particular the economic and cultural logics of late
capitalism, the psychosocial processes of authority
and family, and their relationship to mass culture
and consumption.
In Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944 [trans. 1973]),
Horkheimer and Adorno located the origins of
domination deep in human history, at the point
at which scientific calculating reason was
deployed to overcome the forces of nature, which
were often symbolized in myths. In the process of
enlightenment, on which cultural modernity is
based, instrumental calculating reason (Verstand)
Frazier, E. Franklin (1894–1962)
gained dominance over objective reason (Vernunft),
which could pose questions about the rationality
of social institutions. The consequence of this
was that ultimate questions about the worth of
human societies were deemed “irrational,” and all
values (whether fascist or liberal, for example)
became matters of personal decision rather than
objective judgment. The Culture Industry contributes further to this degeneration of public life.
By 1953 the Institute was able to move back to
the University of Frankfurt in Germany, where
Adorno assumed a co-directorship with Horkheimer in 1955. He died in 1969 and Horkheimer in
1973. The Institute of Social Research continued
but what was known as the “Frankfurt School” did
not. Critical Theory has continued as an increasingly diverse body of theory with less direct connection with Frankfurt. The most significant
figure in this phase was Jürgen Habermas, who
studied philosophy and sociology at the Institute
in the 1960s and returned to a chair at the University of Frankfurt in 1982. Over four decades of
work, Habermas has drawn on virtually the whole
corpus of social theory and philosophy to develop
a comprehensive Critical Theory that remains
critical of the commercial and technocratic colonization of the public sphere yet locates new
sources of rational critique and emancipatory
practice. In particular he has sought to defend
aspects of the Enlightenment tradition associated
with modernity that he considers to be constructive and emancipatory from what he sees as their
premature rejection by an earlier Critical Theory.
LARRY RAY
Frazier, E. Franklin (1894–1962)
In 1948 Edward Franklin Frazier was elected
President of the American Sociological Association, at a time when the United States had not
begun to deal with its racism. The high regard in
which academic sociology held this black man was
founded on Frazier’s broad learning and pathbreaking scholarship, which led to eight books,
of which two are classics, The Negro Family in the
United States (1939) and Black Bourgeoisie (1957).
Both were years ahead of their time in sociology’s
attempt to understand the strengths of the black
family and the weaknesses of the black
bourgeoisie.
After attending Baltimore schools, Frazier was
a student at Howard University (BA, 1916), after
which he taught mathematics, history, English,
and French at several schools, including Tuskegee
Institute. His interest in sociology dates to graduate work at Clark University (MA, 1919), then to
215
Freud, Sigmund (1856–1939)
further study at the New York School of Social
Work (1920–1) and the University of Copenhagen
(1921–2). Frazier then taught at Morehouse College, Atlanta University, and the Atlanta School
of Social Work. He was forced to flee Atlanta
when white racists were provoked by his 1927
essay “The Pathology of Race Prejudice.” He
then pursued doctoral studies in sociology at the
University of Chicago (PhD, 1931).
After teaching at Fisk University (1929–34),
Frazier began his long tenure in sociology at
Howard University, from which he retired in
1959. An academic at heart, Franklin always put
his learning to use in public service and race
politics.
CHARLES LEMERT
Freud, Sigmund (1856–1939)
The founder of psychoanalysis, Freud was born in
Freiberg, a part of the Austro-Hungarian Empire.
A studious child, he undertook medical training
in 1881, and subsequently pursued his clinical
interest in hysteria with a colleague, Josef Breuer
(1842–1925). Studies in Hysteria (1895 [trans. 1957]),
the book that emerged from the researches of
Freud and Breuer, developed a path-breaking
theory, one that underscored the central role of
sexual memories in the formation of mental disturbance. The work laid a skeletal structure for
the theoretical development of psychoanalysis,
which emerged in 1900 with the publication of
Freud’s The Interpretation of Dreams (1900 [trans.
1958]).
Therapeutically, Freudian psychoanalysis is
perhaps best known as the “talking cure” – a
slogan used to describe the magical power of language to relieve mental suffering. Theoretically,
psychoanalysis is rooted in a set of dynamic
models relating to the human subject’s articulations of desire. Freud’s originality is to be found
in his analysis of the unconscious as repressed. In
his celebrated essay “The Unconscious” (1914) in
The Standard Edition of the Complete Works of Sigmund
Freud, vol. XIV, he argued that the individual’s selfunderstanding is not immediately available to
itself, that the human subject is itself split, torn
between consciousness of self and repressed
desire. In discussing human subjectivity, Freud
divides the psyche into the unconscious, preconscious, and conscious. The preconscious can be
thought of as a vast storehouse of memories,
most of which may be recalled at will. In contrast,
unconscious memories and desires are cut off, or
buried, from consciousness.
We become the identities we are, in Freud’s view,
because we have inside us buried identifications
216
friendship
with people we have previously loved (and also
hated), most usually our parents – and particularly the mother. The breakup of our primary
emotional tie to the maternal body is, for Freud,
the founding moment not only of individuation
and differentiation, but also of sexual and gender
difference. Loss and gender affinity are directly
linked in Freud’s theory to the Oedipus complex,
the psyche’s entry into received social meanings.
For Freud, the Oedipus complex is the nodal point
of sexual development, the symbolic internalization of a lost, tabooed object of desire. In the
act of internalizing the loss of the pre-Oedipal
mother, the infant’s relationship with the father
(or, more accurately, symbolic representations of
paternal power) becomes crucial for the consolidation of both selfhood and gender identity.
Freud’s writings show the ego not to be master
in its own home. The unconscious, repression,
libido, narcissism: these are the core dimensions
of Freud’s psychoanalytic dislocation of the subject. Freud’s dislocation of the subject reemerges
in various guises in contemporary sociological
theory. In the critical theory of the Frankfurt
School, it is part of an attempt to rethink the
powerlessness of identity in the face of the objectifying aspects of contemporary science, technology, and bureaucracy. For Jürgen Habermas, it is a
series of claims about the nature of distorted
intersubjective and public communication as a
means of theorizing repressive ideologies. For
Jacques Lacan, it is a means for tracing imaginary
constructions of self-concealment, as linked to
the idea that language is what founds the
repressed unconscious.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
friendship
This concept played an important role in ancient
philosophy, where the virtues of loyalty and trust
were seen to be pre-eminently displayed in relations between friends. Friendship designated a
social relation that is neither instrumental nor
selfish. In contemporary philosophy, there has
been a renewed interest in the ethical nature
of friendship, for example in L. Blum, Friendship,
Altruism and Morality (1980).
In The Care of the Self (1984 [trans. 1986]), Michel
Foucault examined the Roman conception of
friendship between a man and a woman, and between men and boys. In this classical conception, a manly affection for a young boy could
exist through life, and was not subject to the
vagaries of aging. In Homeric Greek, according to
E. Beneviste in Indo-European Language and Society
(1969 [trans. 1973]), philos (friend) was closely
friendship
connected with aidos (reverence or respect), indicating that a bond of friendship was defined
by a strong sense of obligation. There was also
an obligation of friendship towards a “gueststranger” (xenos). Although in contemporary society, friendship implies an intimate, close, and
private, but not sexual, relationship, in Greek
society the word philia covered a range of relationships, including passionate and erotic ones. Aristotle distinguished between friends of utility,
pleasure, and virtue, and, in the latter, friendship
involved the whole person. In the Nichomachean
Ethics, Aristotle claimed that friendship as a universal emotion forms the basis of the polis. Plato
also saw friendship as the basis of harmony and
consensus, and hence necessary to politics. Although friendship can therefore be treated as
quintessentially ethical, political philosophy has
been primarily interested in the relationship between friendship and government. In Redeeming
American Political Thought, J. N. Shklar, in the chapter on “A Friendship” (1998), discussed the complex relations between politics and friendship,
noting that there are obvious tensions between
loyalty to a friend and to government.
With some important exceptions, such as Ray
Pahl’s On Friendship (2000), the topic has been
somewhat neglected in sociology. When friendship is analyzed by sociologists, it is typically in
the context of the study of privacy and intimacy.
For example, Barrington Moore, in his study of
Privacy (1984), examined the ambiguities of friendship in classical society. Aspects of friendship
have also been analyzed in exchange theory, in,
for example, George Homans’s Social Behavior: Its
Elementary Forms (1961) and Peter M. Blau’s Exchange and Power in Social Life (1964). In the perspective of exchange theory, people make and
keep friends because they are useful or rewarding.
These theories implicitly accepted Aristotle’s definition of friendships of utility, thereby admitting
that by the 1960s friendship had become a commodity. The corrosion of friendship in modern
society is an implicit topic of recent research on
emotions. In a consumer society, where emotional work (for example of air-hostesses) involves
the production of fleeting intimacy for cash,
friendliness is commercialized. For example, in
Postemotional Society (1997), S. Mestrovic argues
that synthetic, quasi-emotions become the basis
for manipulation in public life. The commercialization of friendship represents a form of
alienation.
In summary, friendship has been important in
philosophy but not in sociology. This neglect is
functional theory of stratification
curious given the fact that sociology is literally
the study (logos) of companionship or friendship
(socius), pointing once more to the notion that
friendship is the ultimate root of both the polity
and the community. In Latin, the idea of civis is
best translated as “fellow-citizen” or companion.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Fromm, Erich (1900–1980)
A psychoanalyst and philosopher, Fromm was
for a time associated with the Frankfurt School,
though they split acrimoniously in the early
1940s. Fromm developed a theory of the cultural
roots of personality, organized around the ideas
of freedom and autonomy. The scope of freedom
in human societies emerges historically and
appears most strongly with modern individualism,
but living with freedom is difficult and people
seek means of escape in ways that are set during
socialization. These include, first, authoritarianism, of which the most extreme forms are masochism and sadism, although milder versions are
widespread. Second, destructiveness, which can
be outwardly directed through brutality or inwardly directed in, for example, drug addiction,
alcoholism, and passive entertainment. Third,
automaton conformity escapes from freedom
through submission to social hierarchies or by
following the dictates of mass cultural forms
of fashion and style. This is the dominant form
of personality in modern society. In these strategies for escaping freedom, people become alienated from themselves. Finally, there is potentially
the productive and loving personality type in
which freedom is accepted – this would be developed in a humanistic socialist society. In later
work Fromm brought together psychoanalytical
insight and evidence from physical anthropology
to develop the concept of a “necrophilous personality” (such as Adolf Hitler [1889–1945] and
Joseph Stalin [1879–1953]), passionate to transform life into death. Major works include Escape
from Freedom (1941), Man for Himself (1947), The Art of
Loving (1956), The Sane Society (1955), and Anatomy
of Human Destructiveness (1973).
LARRY RAY
functional theory of stratification
At the heart of the functional theory of stratification is the argument that structured social inequality, that is the differential allocation of
social rewards and facilities, enhances social efficacy and social integration. This is both its (seldom
realized) “social purpose” and “social cause”;
stratification, in turn, has become universal
because it engenders “evolutionary advantage.”
217
functional theory of stratification
We owe the classical formulation of allocative
functionalism to Kingsley Davis and Wilbert
Moore. In “Some Principles of Stratification,” in
the American Sociological Review (1945), they argued
that in all complex societies the functional importance of social positions and social roles vary.
Some positions are more strategically important
than others, and they require special and rare
talents and skills. Because such talents and skills
are scarce, and because they typically require long
and costly training, there have to be incentives
for their display and cultivation. Differential rewards inherent in stratification systems provide
such incentives for cultivating knowledge, skills,
and talents. Similarly, the optimal allocation of
the best candidates to the most important jobs
and continuous motivation of incumbents to
perform well require differential rewards. Societies that fail to develop such a system of functional stratification lose efficacy, and they are in
a position of disadvantage in developmental
competition.
Thus there are a number of preconditions of
socially functional stratification – and a number
of criticisms directed at functional arguments:
(1) The reward structure has to reflect accurately
the social consensus as to which roles and
positions are more, and which less, strategically important. Critics point out that this
assumption is unrealistic.
(2) Rewards should effectively attract the best
incumbents and motivate them in their performance. According to critics, incompetent
elites prove that this condition is seldom met.
(3) The recruitment process has to be open and
merit-based. In functionally stratified systems
there is no place for inheritance, ascription,
and closure. This claim produced the most
serious bone of contention between functionalists and their critics. While Davis and Moore
recognized that inheritance and ascription
persist, and it weakens the functionality of
stratification, they nevertheless disagreed
with those critics who argued that functional
theory was unrealistic. The critics also question the functionalist explanation of the universality of stratification. Since functional
principles are similar in most societies, one
would expect to find similarities in stratification systems, at least among contemporary
societies at a similar level of development.
Yet one of the striking features of modern
societies has been a broad diversity of social
hierarchies – a fact that contradicts allocative
functionalism.
218
functionalism
These criticisms resulted in a gradual eclipse of
allocative functionalism. In the 1960s–1970s a
more sophisticated Parsonian version of integrative functionalism gained a currency among
sociologists. Talcott Parsons suggested that functionality of stratification systems consisted in
strengthening social integration around core
values. Differential rewards, according to Parsons,
contribute to such integration by rewarding
commitments to central societal values. Stratification also contributes to effective value socialization, because it increases the transparency of the
core value standards according to which social
rewards are allocated. Thus the system of structured inequalities strengthens value integration
and aids value socialization.
JAN PAKULSKI
functionalism
Functionalists argue that society should be understood as a system of interdependent parts. The
different parts of social life depend on each other
and fulfill functions contributing to social order
and its reproduction.
Functionalism can be traced to Émile Durkheim
and Herbert Spencer. The anthropologists Bronislaw Malinowski and Alfred Radcliffe-Brown (1881–
1955) drew on Durkheim to develop a distinctive
form of functionalist anthropology in the early
twentieth century. Functionalism came to prominence as a school of sociology in the United
States in the 1950s. It was associated with Talcott
Parsons and Robert Merton, although they differed in approach. From the 1960s, functionalism
was subjected to major criticism and few sociologists defended it until the 1980s when Jeffrey
Alexander identified a convergence with functionalism by erstwhile critics such as Jürgen Habermas, Anthony Giddens, and Margaret Archer.
Functionalism departs from the traditional
logic of causal argument where a cause should
precede its consequences. Functionalists identify
a causal loop or feedback linking cause and effect.
When an anthropologist asks “why do the Hopi
dance for rain?” a functionalist considers the consequence of the dance and notes that it maintains
group solidarity. The functionalist concludes
that if the rain dance did not have this positive
function it would not be reproduced.
Functionalists are aware of illegitimate teleology, arguing that the explanation of the origins
of a practice should be distinguished from that of
its reproduction. Radcliffe-Brown distinguished
sharply between diachronic and synchronic analysis, between the analysis of change in a system
and the analysis of the interaction among parts
functionalism
of a system at a moment in time. The latter was
the proper domain of functional analysis.
Malinowski argued that all societies have to
meet some universal and interconnected requirements – as well as group solidarity, economic
subsistence, social control, sexual reproduction,
socialization and education of new generations,
and the management of sickness and death –
and that these can form the basis for comparison.
Parsons was influenced by Malinowski, but
believed his identification of functions to be ad
hoc, arguing that functions must be theoretically
specified in a general framework.
For Parsons, there are four different interconnected systems bearing upon human action: the
human organism, the individual personality, the
social system, and the cultural system. The behavioral organism is concerned with the human body
as the primary vehicle for engaging the physical
environment; that of personality corresponds to
the individual actor viewed as a system. It includes
conscious and unconscious motivations (or need
dispositions). Actors respond not only to positive
rewards, but also to internalized feelings of guilt,
anxiety, and the need for approval. The social
system is a system of positions and roles organized
by expectations and maintained by sanctions;
the culture system refers to the symobls and
meanings that are drawn upon by actors in the
pursuit of their personal projects.
Parsons’s primary focus is the social system.
He proposed four functional imperatives necessary to its constitution and operation (the A-G-I-L
scheme). Adaptation is concerned with relationships to external environments and the utilization
of resources in the pursuit of goals. Goal attainment
is concerned with the direction of systems towards collective goals. Integration refers to the
maintenance of coordinated relationships among
the parts of the system, while latency, or patternmaintenance, describes the symbolic order in
terms of mutually reinforcing meanings and
typifications.
The A-G-I-L scheme also allows the classification of societies in terms of the level of structural differentiation or institutional specialization
around functions – for example, the extent to
which political institutions are separated from
economic institutions, or economic institutions
separated from the household. The idea of the
“superiority” of higher over lower stages of developmental complexity carries the implication
of evolutionary change, where better-adapted
forms are realized out of the deficiencies of
“lesser” forms. Modernity – more substantively,
functionalism
the United States, which Parsons called the new
“lead” society – is the culminating stage of development. This seemed to critics to be an extreme
form of teleology, one that revealed an ideological
bias inherent in a scheme that Parsons had presented as the “indispensable logical framework
in which we describe and think about the phenomena of action” (The Structure of Social Action,
1937: 733).
While Parsons regarded functionalism as part
of a unified general theory, Merton saw it as
an adjunct to the development of empirically
grounded theories of the middle range. His argument, originally in 1949 in “Manifest and Latent
Functions” and reprinted in Social Theory and Social
Structure (1968), was taken to be a veiled criticism
of Parsons, especially the latter’s emphasis on integration. Merton identified three unsatisfactory
postulates of functionalism: the functional unity (or
integration) of a society, universal functionalism,
and indispensability.
According to Merton, it may be that some nonliterate societies show a high degree of integration, but it is illegitimate to assume this would
pertain to all societies. It is also possible that what
is functional for society, considered as a whole,
does not prove functional for individuals or for
some groups within the society, and vice versa.
This suggests that, alongside the concept of
function, it is necessary to have a concept of
dysfunction – that is, where the consequences
of an item are negative for some individuals or
groups. For Merton, persisting forms have a net
balance of functional consequences, either for
society considered as a whole or for sub-groups.
Finally, it is necessary to distinguish between
functional prerequisites – preconditions functionally necessary for a society – and the social forms
that fulfill those prerequisites. While the former
are indispensable, it is not required that particular forms meet those functions. There are always
alternative ways of meeting any particular function. Each of Merton’s qualifications was designed
to transform the postulates into variables.
As a form of methodological holism, functionalism was criticized by methodological individualists, such as George Caspar Homans or Peter M.
Blau, working within the exchange-theory perspective. Functionalism was also criticized by conflict theorists such as John Rex and Ralph
Dahrendorf, for its neglect of power, though the
criticism was more aptly applied to Parsons and
his definition of functions in terms of the generalized collectivity. Merton’s more empirical approach had asked “functional for whom?” David
219
fundamentalism
Lockwood sought to reformulate functionalism
in order to allow a concept of system contradiction. Alvin Gouldner argued that functionalism was an ideological expression of welfare
capitalism.
JOHN HOLMWOOD
fundamentalism
Combining both political and religious radicalism, fundamentalism constitutes a distinct, specific, modern social movement and ideology,
promulgating adherence to a strict and intense
interpretation of a scripture or holy text. Although it is a reaction against the secular dimensions of modernity, it cannot be regarded as a
traditional movement. It developed in the late
nineteenth century, first in the United States,
and then spread, especially in the last decade of
the twentieth century, to a variety of Protestant,
Jewish, and Muslim communities around the
world.
Among such movements, it is important to consider the American Council of Christian Churches,
founded in 1941, and the more recent Christian
Coalition founded in 1989, the Gush Emunim
(Block of the Faithful) and various ultra-orthodox
movements (both non-Zionist and anti-Zionist) in
Israel from the 1970s onwards, and many similar
movements in the Muslim world which developed
in the nineteenth century, blossoming in the
last decades of the twentieth century. The most
successful among these movements was the Iranian Revolution (1978–9) which was led by the
Ayatollah Khomeini (1900–89).
With the exception of movements in the United
States and more recently Europe, most of these
fundamentalist movements developed in those
states which were established, like the Kemalist
government of Mustafa Kemal Ataturk (1881–
1938) in Turkey, after World War I, or in the
colonial-imperial states, which were constituted
by the various national movements after World
War II. Social groups which were dislocated from
their respective traditional settings, and drawn
into modern frameworks, formed a central component of these movements. These social groups
often advanced within a modern context – for
example, the experience of social progress among
many Muslim women in Iran, Turkey, or Egypt –
but they also felt culturally dislocated in these
settings and often alienated from them. In the
Islamic movements, the confrontation with secular modernity constituted a central component of
these movements.
In all these societies and historical settings, the
fundamentalist groups constitute what we may
220
fundamentalism
call “Jacobin movements,” that is totalistic or
totalitarian movements. These totalitarian tendencies were rooted in the Jacobin tradition
that emerged in the French Revolution of 1789,
which promulgated the total reconstitution of
man. Jacobinism, named after the Jacobin club,
was a society of deputies, which acted to concentrate power and which believed that the truth
of its vision of society was sufficient to guarantee
its authority. Jacobinism can also be seen in the
high level of political mobilization in the period
between the two world wars, which represented
a major challenge to the pluralistic constitutional regimes of the democracies. The tendency
towards Jacobinism can also be seen in various
communist regimes.
Therefore, contrary to the widely accepted
wisdom of many interpretations, these fundamentalist movements are not traditional or antimodern religions but distinctively sectarianutopian, modern, Jacobin movements which promulgate an ideological and essentialist conception of tradition.
Fundamentalist ideologies, movements, and
regimes share, with other Jacobin developments
such as Communism and utopian sects, the tendency to promulgate a strong vision or gospel of
salvation, which is combined with a total worldview, the implementation of which is to take
place in this world and in the present.
The institutionalization of such totalitarian
visions entails the establishment, through the
powerful mobilization to political action of an
existing social order, of collective and individual
symbols of identity, and the constitution of sharp
social boundaries between the pure inside and
the polluted outside. Such political actions often
involve the sanctification of violence and terror,
oriented above all against both internal and external evil forces and enemies. From the fundamentalist perspective, the enemy is typically seen
to be rooted in the secular dynamics of modern
society, that is the West, the United States, or
Israel.
This modern Jacobin mobilization of fundamentalist movements and regimes is often combined,
paradoxically, with anti-modern, or at least an
anti-liberal, ideology. This contradictory combination of the modern and the traditional is most
clearly expressed in the fundamentalist attitude
to women. On the one hand most of these movements promulgate a strong patriarchal, antifeminist attitude, segregating women and men,
and placing far-reaching restrictions on the
former. At the same time, and in stark contrast
fundamentalism
to traditional regimes, these modern fundamentalist movements mobilize women in the public
sphere through demonstrations, paramilitary organizations, and religious associations, and in the
central political arena through elections to
parliament.
Although they can often appear to be seemingly
traditional, in fact, these movements are in some
paradoxical ways anti-traditional. They negate
the living traditions of popular and folk religions, with all their inevitable cultural complexity, changeability, and heterogeneity, in their
respective societies. Instead they uphold a highly
ideological and essentialist conception of tradition as an overarching ideological principle couched in a modern idiom, with a strong emphasis
on mobilization, participation, and the organizational dimensions of modern political programs.
These decidedly modern components of fundamentalist movements and regimes can also be
seen in some aspects of their institutionalization
as regimes, namely in the continuation, albeit
with strong Jacobin components, of modern institutions such as political constitutions. The majilis
parliament in Iran following the Revolution
fundamentalism
basically had no roots in traditional Islam, and
the elections to the parliament are illustrations
of this. Thus these fundamentalist movements do
not overtly and consciously promulgate modernity, but rather attempt to appropriate modernity
on their own terms.
The approach of these movements to tradition
is also manifest in their attitudes to the more
conservative religious leaders and establishments,
as well as to the more popular manifestations
of tradition. They also typically involve some
degree of distance and separation beween young
generations of fundamentalists and their traditionalist parents or grandparents, who come to
be regarded as a cohort who are or were not pure
enough in their lifestyles and everyday life.
Although these fundamentalist movements
and regimes appear to have been politically successful in many respects, they have also faced
some distinctively modern problems, which have
attended their institutionalization. These problems are in fact manifestations of the basic tensions which are the legacy of their Jacobinism
and their acceptance of the basic institutional
frameworks of modernity.
S. N. EISENSTADT
221
G
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1900–2002)
game theory
Hans-Georg Gadamer made a substantial contribution to hermeneutic philosophy. Born in 1900
in Marburg, he studied under Martin Heidegger
and also attended the lectures of Edmund Husserl.
Gadamer’s professional life was spent mainly in
Germany, although after his retirement from his
Chair in Philosophy at Heidelberg in 1968 he
took up various visiting posts abroad. In the
course of the 1970s sociologists became increasingly interested in hermeneutics, hence there was
a growing interest in Gadamer’s writings. Gadamer’s main book is Truth and Method (1960 [trans.
1975]). In this book, Gadamer distanced himself
from the emphasis on method in nineteenthcentury hermeneutics; like Heidegger, Gadamer
heralded the “ontological turn.” He criticized
philosophers of the Enlightenment for failing to
appreciate the pivotal role of tradition in knowledge acquisition. He saw understanding as a
dialogical process in which we draw on our presuppositions to make sense of other people, but
these presuppositions are themselves affected by
this encounter. Gadamer talked about a “fusion
of horizons” to hint at the dialogical nature of
the interaction between the reader and the
text, or the observer and observed. Gadamer
applied his hermeneutic approach to medicine
and medical practice in The Enigma of Health (1996
[trans. 1993]).
In the late 1960s, Jürgen Habermas engaged in a
debate with Gadamer. For Habermas, Gadamer
was right to point out the limitations of positivism, but his plea for hermeneutic understanding
lacks a critical edge. Gadamer’s reply was that
Habermas failed to acknowledge that his own
critical standpoint is itself embedded in tradition.
Later, Richard Rorty’s argument for an edifying
philosophy, beyond epistemology, drew on Gadamer’s dialogical model. Gadamer also inspired
Charles Taylor’s philosophy of social sciences, in
particular its reflexive component.
This is a mathematical tool for modeling social
conflict and cooperation among two or more
players, where payoffs for a given strategy depend
in part on the strategies of other players. This
strategic interdependence can be represented as
a payoff matrix (the “normal form” for simultaneous moves by the players) or as a decision tree
(the “extensive form” for sequential moves).
Strategic interdependence allows for two types
of games. In zero-sum games, a gain for one player
is always a loss for the partner, which precludes
the possibility of cooperation for mutual gain. In
positive-sum games, everyone can gain through
cooperation, defined as a strategy combination
that is Pareto-efficient (see Vilfredo Pareto) (any
improvement for some would come at someone
else’s expense). Nevertheless, cooperation may fail
for two reasons: the fear of being “suckered” by
the partner and the temptation to cheat. These
failures can be avoided in two ways, through enforceable contracts that preclude “cheating” (“cooperative games”) and through collusion (in “noncooperative games”).
A cooperative game consists of a set of players
and a value function that assigns a value to every
possible coalition of players based on the total
amount of transferable utility the players of
that coalition can distribute. Sociologists such
as F. J. Bienenstock and P. Bonacich have used
the cooperative-game paradigm to study the
effects of network structure on power inequality
in social exchange (“The Core as a Solution to
Negatively Connected Exchange Networks,” 1992,
Social Networks).
Non-cooperative games are played without the
benefit of an enforceable contract, hence the opportunity for cheating. These games are generally
more interesting to sociologists because they can
be used to model social dilemmas – games in
which rational self-interest can lead players into
an outcome that is not Pareto-efficient. In a social
dilemma, mutual cooperation is Pareto-efficient
PATRICK BAERT
222
game theory
yet may be undermined by the temptation to
cheat or by the fear of being cheated or by both.
In the game of Stag Hunt, the problem is “fear,”
and in the game of Chicken the problem is
“greed.” The problem is most challenging when
both fear and greed are present – as in the celebrated game of Prisoner’s Dilemma.
Although the games vary widely, the theory
of games provides a solution concept that can
be universally applied. In Non-Cooperative Games
(1950), John F. Nash showed that every game contains at least one Nash equilibrium – an outcome
where every strategy is a “best reply” to the other
strategies played; hence, no player has an incentive to change strategy unilaterally. The Nash
equilibrium predicts mutual defection in Prisoner’s Dilemma, unilateral defection in Chicken,
and either mutual cooperation or mutual defection in Stag Hunt. Nash also identifies a Paretodeficient mixed-strategy equilibrium in Chicken
and Stag Hunt. A mixed strategy chooses randomly from all available behavioral choices following a particular probability distribution (for
example, “cooperate .45, defect .55”). Knowing
that a configuration is a Nash equilibrium means
that if this state should obtain, the system will
remain there forever, even in the absence of an
enforceable contract. However, even when Nash
can identify a unique equilibrium, this does not
tell us whether this state will ever be reached,
or with what probability, or what will happen
if the equilibrium should be perturbed. Nor
does Nash equilibrium explain social stability
among interacting agents who are changing
strategies individually, yet the population distribution remains constant, as in a homeostatic
equilibrium.
Both Chicken and Stag Hunt have three equilibria, and game theory cannot tell us which one will
obtain. Worse yet, if these games are repeated by
players who care about future payoffs in an
ongoing relation, the number of Nash equilibria
becomes indefinitely large. When games have
multiple equilibria, Nash cannot tell us which
will obtain or with what relative probability. Nor
can Nash tell us much about the dynamics
by which a population of players can move from
one equilibrium to another. Game theorists have
responded to the problem of equilibrium selection
by proposing procedures that can winnow the
set of possible solutions to include only those
that are risk-dominant (players follow a conservative strategy that earns the best payoff they can
guarantee for themselves), payoff-dominant (every
other equilibrium is less preferred by at least
game theory
one player), and subgame-perfect (all nodes
along the equilibrium path can be reached in
the extensive form). However, these equilibrium
selection methods are theoretically arbitrary (for
example, there is no a-priori basis for payoffdominant or risk-dominant behavior) and they
often disagree about which equilibrium should
be selected (for example, in Stag Hunt, payoff
dominance and subgame perfection identify
mutual cooperation while risk dominance points
to mutual defection).
These limitations, including concerns about the
cognitive demands of forward-looking rationality,
have led game theorists to explore backwardlooking alternatives based on evolution and learning. Evolutionary game theory allows for the
possibility that players rely on cognitive shortcuts
such as imitation, heuristic decision making,
stochastic learning, Bayesian updating, best reply
with finite memory, and local optimization.
Evolutionary models test the ability of conditionally cooperative strategies to survive and reproduce in competition with predators ( John
Maynard-Smith, Evolution and the Theory of Games,
1982). Biological models have also been extended
to military and economic games in which losers
are physically eliminated or bankrupted and to
cultural games in which winners are more likely
to be imitated (Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of
Cooperation, 1984; Jürgen Weibull, Evolutionary
Game Theory, 1995).
Evolutionary game theory is based on the consequentialist assumption that strategic choices can
be explained by the associated payoffs. The payoffs
that matter are those that have already occurred,
not those that a forward-looking optimizer might
expect to obtain in the future. Repetition, not
calculation, brings the future to bear on the present, by recycling the lessons of the past. Through
repeated exposure to a recurrent problem, the
consequences of alternative courses of action can
be iteratively explored, by the individual actor or
by a population. Iterative search relaxes the highly
restrictive cognitive assumptions in analytical
game theory, thereby extending applications to
social and cultural adaptation by highly routinized actors, such as bureaucratic organizations
or boundedly rational individuals whose behavior
is based on heuristics, habits, or norms. The game
paradigm obtains its theoretical leverage by modeling the social fabric as a matrix of interconnected agents guided by outcomes of their
interaction with others, where the actions of
each depend on, as well as shape, the behavior of
those with whom they are linked. Viewed with
223
gangs
Gans, Herbert J. (1927– )
that lens, game theory appears to be especially
relevant to sociology, the social science that has
been most reluctant to embrace it.
MICHAEL MACY AND ARNOUT VAN DE RIJT
gangs
This term refers to a group of individuals collectively engaging in social activities that are often
deviant or criminal. While the term has been used
to label a wide range of criminal or deviant
groups, criminology has more narrowly focused
on gangs that reflect the findings of the first systematic study, The Gang (1927), by Frederic M.
Thrasher. According to Thrasher, gangs, usually
composed of male adolescents, form in urban
areas and function as a primary group based on
strong loyalty and a clear territorial focus.
Thrasher’s colleagues at the Chicago School account for a number of theories aimed at explaining gang-based deviant behavior. E. H. Sutherland
in his textbook Principles of Criminology (1939) developed the notion of “differential association”
which explains criminal activity in the immediate
social context of various subcultures in society.
Criminal activities are thus peer-group-induced.
Albert Cohen’s Delinquent Boys (1955) describes
gangs as working-class subcultures engaging in a
deliberate rejection of middle-class values. Drawing on Robert Merton’s functionalist approach to
crime, Cohen ascribed the formation of delinquent subcultures such as gangs to the frustration
of working-class youths over their lack of social
status and mobility.
The work of another sociologist associated with
the Chicago School, Howard S. Becker, was instrumental in the foundation of labeling theory.
According to Becker, in Outsiders (1963), deviance
is a relational, socially constructed label through
which powerful sections of society exercise control: “deviancy is not a quality of the act a person
commits, but rather a consequence of the application by others of rules and sanctions to an
‘offender.’”
The significance of social class in the formation
of gangs is highlighted further by studies in New
Criminology, closely associated with the Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies.
New Criminology portrays deviant gang behavior
as a deliberate act of resistance by working-class
youths to the existing social and economic order.
Ian Taylor in Football Mad (1972), for instance,
explains the rise of hooligan gangs as a result
of excessive social control and the inequalities of
postwar capitalism in Britain. However, these
approaches have been criticized for insufficiently
224
accounting for the victims of gang-related activities, which, as in the case of inner-city street
gangs and hooligans, are often found among
other disadvantaged sections of society. Moreover,
in light of the deterritorialization of social identities and subcultures, the strong emphasis on
local working-class culture seems increasingly difficult to maintain.
The sociological study of gangs also raises important methodological questions. As gangs naturally shield at least part of their activities from
the public gaze, participant observation is the
only qualitative method promising detailed data
on gangs. Such qualitative research, however,
involves immediate dangers and ethical pitfalls
for the researcher (by becoming a victim or complicit to criminal behavior) and the researched
(through the exposure of their activities and possible legal repercussions). With their entry into
the field, researchers are also forced to take sides
in relation to the gang’s struggle, a theme pursued by Becker in Whose Side are we on? (1967) and
Ned Polsky in Hustlers, Beats and Others (1967).
CORNEL SANDVOSS
Gans, Herbert J. (1927– )
Born in Cologne, Germany, Gans migrated to the
United States in 1940, and gained his MA in social
science at the University of Chicago, and his
PhD in city planning from the University of
Pennsylvania. His research reflects interests in
both sociology and urban planning. He was a
professor of sociology at Columbia University,
and 78th President of the American Sociological
Association in 1988.
He has made significant contributions to sociological debates about poverty in The War against the
Poor. The Underclass and Antipoverty Policy (1995). In
More Equality (1973), he challenged the cynical view
that the poor are valuable clients for professional
groups such as social workers, family lawyers
and doctors, and the owners of pawn shops and
brothels. There is also an economic argument that
the poor are useful in prolonging the life of certain commodities such as day-old bread or secondhand clothing. In arguing for more equality, Gans
argued that much dirty work should be done by
automation and that higher wages could be given
to the poor for dirty but necessary work without
damage to the economy.
Gans also contributed to the development of
urban sociology in The Urban Villagers. Group and
Class in the Life of Italian-Americans (1962) and The
Levittowners: Ways of Life and Politics in a New Suburban Community (1982), and to the sociology of the
Garfinkel, Harold (1917– )
media and culture in Popular Culture and High Culture (1974), Deciding What’s News (1980), and Democracy and the News (2003). Gans’s basic argument is
that news is top-down, favoring high-ranking government officials over low-ranking officials, government agencies over opposition groups, and
organized groups over unorganized individual
citizens. The concentration of the ownership of
the news and the pressure to increase profitability
compromises the independence of journalism and
corrodes audience confidence. Finally, Gans has
been an important critical observer of American
life in Making Sense of America (1999). Finally, he
published a collection of essays in honor of David
Riesman in On the Making of Americans (1979).
BRYAN S. TURNER
Garfinkel, Harold (1917– )
The originator of ethnomethodology, Harold Garfinkel has made original contributions to how
sociologists understand the production of social
action. Along with George Herbert Mead, John
Dewey (1859–1952), and Erving Goffman, Garfinkel was one of the initiators of the shift from
definitions of social action in terms of subjective
consciousness and existential meaning to definitions in terms of enacted social practices.
Ethnomethodology, a neologism Garfinkel coined,
refers to the methods people use to produce conduct in local settings. As demonstrated by essays
in his two major books, Studies in Ethnomethodology
(1967) and Ethnomethodology’s Program (2002),
Garfinkel investigates the accomplishment of
social action in minute and pains-taking detail.
His investigations reveal a realm of what he
terms seen but unnoticed practices that contribute to the constitution of local action. Garfinkel
is also famous – many would say notorious – for
his convoluted narrative voice. Once one masters
his style, Garfinkel appears to be profoundly selfconscious about the precision of his prose. However, even his staunchest supporters admit to
being daunted by their first encounters with his
works. All stylistic matters notwithstanding,
Garfinkel’s contributions remain fertile ground
for new developments, and his writings on ethnomethodology will influence sociological theory
for many years to come.
Garfinkel was born in 1917 and raised in
Newark, New Jersey, where his father owned a
small furniture business. He graduated from the
University of Newark (unaccredited then but now
a large campus of Rutgers University) in 1939. He
completed his master’s thesis in sociology at the
University of North Carolina in 1942. After serving
gay studies
in the military for several years, Garfinkel enrolled at Harvard University from which he
received his PhD under the nominal supervision
of Talcott Parsons in 1952. Garfinkel, however,
was already an original thinker and he was inclined to follow a non-Parsonian position from
the start. His main influences were social phenomenologists, including two internationally wellknown scholars, Aron Gurwitsch (1901–73) and
Alfred Schutz, who provided Garfinkel with
intellectual support. In 1954 Garfinkel took a position at the University of California, Los Angeles
(UCLA), and this became his base for the rest of his
career.
Garfinkel has never acted as a solitary, inimitable thinker in the manner of Georg Simmel or
Goffman. At UCLA he has been blessed with successive cohorts of loyal, gifted graduate students,
including many who are now senior scholars of
distinction in their own right. This list includes
Aaron Cicourel, Harvey Sacks, David Sudnow, and
Emmanuel Schegloff. Sacks and Schegloff are well
known for conversational analysis, which is a
semiautonomous offshoot of Garfinkel’s original
program. Over the half-century since Garfinkel
moved to UCLA, ethnomethodology has grown
into an international movement with centers
in Great Britain and elsewhere, as well as across
many departments of sociology in the United
States, including Boston University and the University of California, Santa Barbara. Garfinkel’s
writing style demands clarification and it
has been Garfinkel’s good fortune to have fine
exegetes such as John Heritage in Garfinkel and
Ethnomethodology (1984), and Anne Rawls.
IRA COHEN
gay rights movement
– see social movements.
gay studies
The study of the culture, history, and character of
gay sexuality and gay identity, this is associated
with the social movement for gay and lesbian
liberation. The gay rights movement was influenced by the riots that followed the police
raid on the Stonewall Inn in New York in 1969,
when the New York Gay Liberation Front was
formed. The Front rejected the conventional social
roles and gender definitions of mainstream or
“straight” society. The first Gay March took place
in 1970 and was quickly imitated in other countries, from European capitals to Sydney, Australia.
The self-recognition of homosexuality came to be
known as “coming out,” an expression taken from
225
gay studies
the American notion of “coming out of the closet”
or rejecting the stigma of hidden or concealed
sexual identity. This process of coming out was
given its definitive expression in Eve Kosofsky
Sedgwick’s Epistemology of the Closet (1990).
Gay studies eventually emerged in university
curricula where they were modeled on lesbian
studies, gender studies, and women’s studies.
There are many journals related to gay culture
and experience, such as GLQ – A Journal of Lesbian
and Gay Studies (1994– ), Sexualities (1998– ), and
Journal of Homosexuality. The diversity and depth
of journals, conferences, study programs, and
institutions relating to gay studies were explored
in Ken Plummer’s Modern Homosexualities (1992).
The development of gay politics in Britain from
the nineteenth century to modern times was
described by Jeffrey Weeks in Coming Out (1977).
In 1991 the Center for Lesbian and Gay Studies
was founded in the Graduate Center of the City
University of New York to study the cultural and
political issues that are important for lesbian, gay,
bisexual, and transgender individuals.
Professional mainstream sociology has somewhat neglected the study of human sexuality.
There are of course some classic illustrations of
research on same-sex behavior and practice, such
as Laud Humphrey’s Tearoom Trade (1975). There
has also been some research on sex re-assignment
surgery, for example Frank Lewin’s Transsexualism
in Society (1995), but we know relatively little
about the long-term health-care needs of transsexuals. Sociology became heavily involved in
the study of the HIV/AIDS epidemic mainly
through the study of networks. Because gay men
often have friends and lovers who have predeceased them, they are often in a chronic state
of grieving or “bereavement overload” and may
experience “survivor guilt.” These traumatic
experiences have contributed to a variety of selfhelp movements and have generated a new gay
consciousness, as documented in, for example,
R. A. Isay’s Becoming Gay: The Journey of Self-acceptance
(1996) and E. Rofes’s Reviving the Tribe: Regenerating
Gay Men’s Sexuality and Culture in the Ongoing
Epidemic (1996).
In British sociology, the work of Ken Plummer
on narratives such as Telling Sexual Stories (1995)
has represented an innovative approach to human
sexuality. The Handbook of Lesbian & Gay Studies
(2002), edited by Diane Richardson and Steven
Seidman, is a valuable guide to this diverse field
of research. Jeffrey Weeks also produced a series of
influential studies, such as Coming Out, Sex Politics
and Society (1990), and Against Nature (1991).
226
Geertz, Clifford (1926– )
Some gay activists have, however, come to the
conclusion that gay studies was merely a strategy
for co-opting a more radical aspect of gay politics,
thereby making gayness a dimension of more conventional sexual identity. In addition, the gay
movement came to be stigmatized once more by
the HIV/AIDS epidemic in the 1980s. In response to
these changing circumstances, queer theory
emerged, in which a stable homosexual identity
was rejected in favor of the notion that gay was
really an epistemological critique of stable categorization, and hence queer theory adopted
elements of postmodernism and postcolonial
theory. One example of these developments is
Queer Theory / Sociology edited by Steven Seidman
(1996). The work of Michel Foucault played a major
part in rethinking sexual identity as an aspect of
the struggle over the relationships between power
and knowledge in different historical settings.
Foucault demonstrated that homosexuality was a
building block of male friendship in classical
Greece in The Use of Pleasure (1984 [trans. 1985]).
Foucault, who died of an AIDS-related illness in
1984, became an icon of politics relating to men’s
health and his role has been defended and celebrated by David Halpern in Saint Foucault. Towards
a Gay Hagiography (1995).
In sociology, queer theory and Gay Studies have
influenced the ways in which masculinity as a
sexual identity is conceptualized. In particular,
social constructionism rejected essentialism and
claimed that, while homosexual feelings or practices had always existed, “the homosexual” was
a construct of a particular time and place. These
approaches rejected the conventional psychological view that homosexuality was an illness or
a form of social deviance. Gay studies are therefore concerned to reject these negative labels and
to explore the complex historical manifestation of
homosexual identity, culture, and institutions.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Geertz, Clifford (1926– )
Among the most eminent American anthropologists of the latter half of the twentieth century,
Clifford Geertz has made many contributions to
diverse areas of anthropology and to the social
sciences more broadly. These contributions include the ethnography of Java, Bali, and Morocco,
and, as much outside anthropology as within it, to
the theorization of religion, of politics, and of
culture itself. Though a student of Talcott Parsons,
he gradually moved away from a merely functionalist treatment of culture and, by the middle
1960s, had begun to piece together, from the
Gehlen, Arnold (1904–1976)
thought of Max Weber, Ruth Benedict, Bronislaw
Malinowski, Gilbert Ryle, Suzanne Langer, and
Ludwig Wittgenstein, among others, an “interpretive anthropology” of “the native’s point of view”
that cast culture as a loosely integrated totality of
institutionally and perspectivally specific systems
providing models of and models for the world and
life within it, whose constituent symbols acquire
their meanings from the contextually specific
occasions of their use. Geertz followed many of his
American predecessors in presuming the diverse
expressions of culture to be sufficiently bounded
for any one of them to be readily distinguished
from the next. He shared their tendency to privilege the broadest collective themes of a culture over
their more idiosyncratic refractions. He departed
from them, however, in arguing that the key to
human nature lay not in the cross-culturally
universal but, instead, in cross-cultural diversity
itself. His major works include Peddlers and Princes
(1963), Islam Observed (1968), Negara (1980), and two
volumes of essays, The Interpretation of Cultures
(1973) and Local Knowledge (1983).
JAMES D. FAUBION
Gehlen, Arnold (1904–1976)
A member of the Nazi movement in Germany,
Gehlen was a philosopher, anthropologist, and
sociologist whose work was influenced by Hans
Driesch, Nicolai Hartmann, and Max Scheler. He
joined the Nazi party in 1933, and his career benefited from opportunities for advancement created
by the removal of Jewish and anti-Nazi academics
from universities in the Third Reich. His work
during this time attempted to create a “National
Socialist philosophy” (Der Idealismus und die Gegenwart, 1935). His major work was Man: His Nature
and Place in this World (1940 [trans. 1980]) in which
he developed a philosophical anthropology based
on Nietzsche’s idea that humans are “not yet finished animals”: they are dependent on society and
culture for a long period of maturation; they have
“world-openness” because of a lack or deficit of
instincts; thus modern life is precarious and
humans require a secure political and social environment to provide discipline. Human dependence
on social institutions and culture creates ontological frailty and existential precariousness. A meaningful life can be lived only through conformity to
institutions; thus emancipatory efforts (such as
those of Enlightenment critique) are risky because
institutions are easily destroyed but difficult to
establish. Gehlen was therefore highly critical of
the radical social movements of 1968. The ideas
of ontological frailty and precariousness have
Gellner, Ernest (1925–1996)
been influential in sociology, for example in the
work of Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann (Social
LARRY RAY
Construction of Reality, 1966).
Geisteswissenschaften
– see human sciences.
Gellner, Ernest (1925–1996)
Formerly Professor of Anthropology at Cambridge
University, Gellner made significant contributions
to the study of Islam and nationalism. In his Saints
of the Atlas (1969), Gellner contrasted the puritanical religion of the towns, in which the authority
of the Qur’an was paramount, and the mystical
religion of the Sufi saints in the countryside,
where their personal charisma (or baraka) was
sought after by their disciples. While urban religiosity stressed the equality of believers, the Islam
of the Sufi saints was hierarchical. Gellner
employed this model of religion in his subsequent
work on the political structure of North African
societies. He developed a theory of elite circulation, which he adopted from Ibn Khaldun. The
tribal groups of the countryside have greater
social solidarity (assabiya) than the towns, and
they periodically replace the urban elites that
have become weak, fragmented, and corrupted.
This circulation of elites explains the periodic intrusion of nomadic tribes into urban civilization.
This pattern has, however, been transformed by
modern technology which has allowed the towns
to control the hinterland more effectively, and has
also allowed the spread of puritanical, Quranic,
egalitarian Islam into the interior. Gellner thus
developed, in Muslim Society (1982), an early appreciation of the importance of fundamentalism in
modern politics.
Gellner was also concerned, in Thought and
Change (1964), to understand the force of nationalism in modern societies. He regarded nationalism
as a product of modern societies, arguing that
nations are invented. In modern democracy, there
is a demand to be ruled by our own ethnic group
(see ethnicity and ethnic groups), and hence national identity becomes a major issue of modern
democratic politics.
Gellner was, in Legitimation of Belief (1974), a
critic of trends in cultural anthropology, because
he was hostile to cultural relativism. He defended
the idea of rational criticism against relativism,
which Gellner thought was self-defeating. He
was consequently, in Postmodernism, Reason and
Religion (1992), critical of the impact of postmodernism on modern anthropological theory,
and defended traditional ethnographic methods
227
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft
against
postmodern
emphasis
gender
on
narrative
of femininity, but diverse conditions relevant to the
deconstruction. In The Psychoanalytic Movement particular situation of an individual woman. But
(1985) he brought his critical perspective to
bear on Freudian (see Sigmund Freud) therapy,
which he dismissed as incoherent and ineffective.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft
– see Ferdinand Tönnies.
gender
For many students of society, gender is the most
important form of social division, far more important than social class or race and ethnicity in
the impact that it makes on individual lives. Yet
the history of the concept of gender is not a long
one; unlike the concept of class, the idea of gender
does not have roots in the nineteenth-century
origins of sociology, and it is since the mid-1960s
that the question of gender has come to be central
to discussions of social life. In large part, the
emergence of the concept of gender owes much
to second-wave feminism, which drew attention to
sexual divisions in society and to the patterns of
social difference and inequality that arose. But
what differentiated the concept of gender from
the concept of sex was work by feminists in the
1970s that took issue with the idea of essentialist
explanations of sexual difference. These interventions, for example by sociologists such as Ann
Oakley, pointed out that biological sex differences
did not in themselves lead to differences in behavior between the sexes. Oakley, in common with
other sociologists and anthropologists, pointed
out that across cultures and historical periods
there were very considerable differences in the
ways in which women and men were expected
to behave. What persisted were biological differences of sex, but what differed were social constructions of masculinity and femininity, namely
constructions of gender. Gender, it became
accepted, was the articulation of social expectations about how a person of a particular biological sex should behave, but that performance
of gender could differ significantly across time
and space.
What this separation of gender and sex did was
to establish the idea that there was no such thing
as naturally male or female behavior. Simone de
Beauvoir had famously written in The Second Sex
(1949 [trans. 1972]) that women are “made and not
born” and it is precisely this view which is at the
heart of contemporary understandings of gender.
De Beauvoir argued that feminine behavior has
numerous aspects to it; there is no one condition
228
in all cases, for de Beauvoir, the specific femininity which women display places them as the other
in human society. The male, and masculinity, constitute the norm and it is from this that women
deviate. De Beauvoir’s view has been hugely
influential because it challenges the assumption
that the categories of women/femininity and men/
masculinity are fixed and static. Although much
recent work on gender has been initiated by feminist debates and feminist writers, it is also
the case that the challenge of the idea of gender
has made a considerable impact on conventional
assumptions about men and masculinity.
Although de Beauvoir was critical of much of
Sigmund Freud’s work and was skeptical about his
theories of sexual development, one similarity in
the work of both these writers is the acknowledgment that sexual identity is not fixed but can be
changed by circumstance and even, on occasion,
by choice. But what both Freud and de Beauvoir
are working with is the post-Enlightenment recognition of the difference between male and female
biology. To modern students of gender, this is now
a taken-for granted assumption, but a crucial part
of the history of the idea of gender is the recognition that it was not until the eighteenth century
that the physical differences between the sexes
were fully recognized, and even then it was not
until the twentieth century that the extent of
hormonal differences between male and female
were more fully investigated. Thomas Laqueur in
Making Sex (1990) has pointed out that it is only
recently that sex, as a stable biological attribute,
has existed. Laqueur argues that human biology,
that is the stable, ahistorical, and sexed body, has
to be understood as the “epistemic foundation”
for prescriptive rather than descriptive claims
about the social order. Before this agreement
about biology, the social identity of being a
woman or a man depended on social factors and
the division between male and female was not a
binary division but one in which “maleness” and
“femaleness” could be greater or lesser according
to the particular situation of women.
But by the nineteenth century most of Europe
had come to accept a division between male and
female, a division which, in the majority of
human beings, was visible at birth and which
was then made the basis for social divisions.
Women in the nineteenth century were expected,
in order to meet middle-class norms of femininity,
to show distinct patterns of behavior from those
of men. The social reality of nineteenth-century
gender
Europe was such that this norm was meaningless
for the majority of women who spent their lives in
agricultural and/or domestic work, but social
expectations about biology had been established.
It was those norms which women such as de Beauvoir challenged: forced by economic circumstance
to provide for herself, de Beauvoir lived out the
contradictions of gender and indeed protested
against them.
In her own life, and in her writing, de Beauvoir
demonstrated an iron determination to claim for
herself the same rights to an intellectual life as
those of men. In this sense, much of her work is
not about claiming a different form of femininity
but about being allowed to occupy the same space
as men. This reaction to gender stereotyping implies an internalized sense of a division between
male and female, a sense which is powerfully present in de Beauvoir’s account of her childhood,
Memoirs of a Dutiful Daughter (1958 [trans. 1959]).
What de Beauvoir tells readers about in this, the
first volume of her four-volume autobiography, is
the process of becoming a girl, and the way in
which the acquisition of that identity inhibits
various kinds of activity. The book provides an
excellent example of the complex way in which
children acquire a sense of the social implications
of their physical sex; it is not just for de Beauvoir
that the passage to an adult sexual identity is
riven with difficulties and contradictions. But
what de Beauvoir encounters in her childhood
and adolescence is a contradictory set of social
expectations about her possible gender. As a bourgeois girl in France in the first half of the twentieth century, de Beauvoir, like others of her class, is
not expected to entertain educational ambitions,
still less to study a subject – philosophy – which is
associated with anti-clericalism and often a critical attitude to social convention. But as a poor
bourgeois girl, the only way out of penury is either
to marry or to study. Lacking the personal inclination, or social attributes, that might have made
possible an advantageous marriage, the option for
de Beauvoir was to study and to learn to provide
for herself. The expectations of gender had to be
surrendered to those of class.
The autobiography of the author of The Second
Sex – a woman always claimed as the greatest
feminist writer of the twentieth century – provides an outstanding example of the way in which
gender identity can be both subverted and
changed, while also being maintained. The “bonds
of femininity” were, for de Beauvoir, always bonds
which could be broken, and much of her fiction is
concerned with the stories of women who cannot
gender
break those bonds or re-interpret femininity in
other ways. At the same time, the case of de Beauvoir provides for us an example of the impact of
social conditioning on a particular individual: the
hurdles faced by de Beauvoir in her educational
career were not fantasies of her own making, but
real difficulties in the social world. Thus, the evident strength of social mores can be seen in the
cases of de Beauvoir and of other women of her
generation. We know, from this individual case
and from all information about more general situations, that all societies organize social life on the
basis of sex differences, and that constructed ideas
of gender play a considerable part in the maintenance of these differences. It is now well known
that, in the United Kingdom in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries, many people, including
medical specialists, took the view that women
should not be over-taxed by intellectual work,
lest this damage their reproductive systems. This
notion, hardly relevant to the majority of the
female population who were engaged in arduous
manual work, was just one of the many nineteenth-century views of femininity, albeit one
which attracted both derision and support.
Since the late twentieth century, we have come
to regard with some suspicion ideas about differences between male and female which support
theories about distinctions between the male
and female brain. In Biological Politics and Sexual
Divisions, Janet Sayers (1982) has outlined much
of the literature on the physiological differences
between the sexes, particularly in terms of the
differences, if any, in the brains of women and
men. But the point of this literature, as Sayers
argues, is not only the actual conclusions about
differences in the brain, but the social structures
which are built on them. From the eighteenth
century onwards, a consensus developed about
the existence of differences in physical strength
between women and men; at the time, these differences had a relevance to the labor market and
underpinned the sexual exclusivity of certain occupations. The changes in the European labor
market of the late twentieth century have largely
marginalized the potential impact of differences
in physical strength, but what has become more
important has been identified as the persistence
of gender differences which persistently advantage men and disadvantage women.
It is at this point that academic debates about
gender encounter the reality of the social world.
Since the 1970s, and the impact of second-wave
feminism on academic debates, the question of
the construction of gender has become central to
229
gender
both the academy and the wider social world.
Following the tradition (albeit a tradition with its
own internal differences and contradictions)
which included Freud and de Beauvoir, a consensus emerged in which it was generally agreed that
gender was socially constructed out of biological
sex differences. The emphasis (as suggested above)
was initially on the social construction of femininity, but by the 1980s authors such as Victor Seidler
and Jeffrey Weeks had demonstrated that, just as
femininity was socially constructed, so the same
was true of masculinity. In short, our social/sexual
selves were as unstable as Freud had assumed and
what could be demonstrated – and was demonstrated, for example by Ken Plummer in work on
homosexuality – was the strength of social norms
to create individual sexual persona. This academic
work became part of more general social concerns
about gender stereotyping.
Thus by the end of the 1980s there was, throughout the West, a general consensus that recognized
the way in which all societies made, of sexual
difference, differences of gender. Anthropologists
demonstrated that qualities associated with men
in some societies (for example competence in the
economic market) were of little value in others,
and that the meaning of masculinity and femininity in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries was
as variable as it been in previous centuries. The
view of “natural” attributes of male and female
had little credence in academic circles. It was at
this point that a book by Judith Butler, Gender
Trouble (1990), was published, which pushed the
debate on gender even further towards the conclusion that all gender attributes are constructed
and, as Butler describes it, “performed.” For
Butler, gender is the defining division of the social
world and debates on this issue with Nancy Fraser
have involved numerous participants. But Butler’s
central case - since developed in Bodies that Matter
(1993), Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative
(1997), The Psychic Life of Power (1997), and Antigone’s
Claim: Kinship between Life and Death (2000) – has
become a central part of the analysis of gender.
For Butler, gender is a strategy, a “corporeal
style” which individuals pursue, because if they
do not they are punished by society. For example,
one of the reasons Joan of Arc was condemned was
that she wore men’s clothes. This is an extreme
example, but in other cases social sanctions are
still present and societies overwhelmingly police
the correct “performance” of gender. But, so far,
this idea of people being coerced into behaving in
ways that are deemed to be appropriate for a
member of their physical sex is not in itself
230
gender
innovative or radically different from anything
that has been said before. What makes Butler’s
argument different is the suggestion, in Gender
Trouble, that people are not copying an original
or correct model of gender behavior since no
such original exists.
It is in this way that Butler’s work differs from
that of Harold Garfinkel, who, in the study of the
young person named Agnes, had demonstrated
that individuals could very convincingly do gender and thus make others believe in whichever
gender was chosen. In her argument, Butler has
recognized the existence of individuals such as
Agnes in the history of gender (and indeed the
history of – literally – the wardrobe of gender).
But she has also insisted that each generation, in
putting together a gender identity, is not using
the original but only the various forms in which
gender had so far been performed. One of the
strengths of Butler’s argument is her recognition
of the way in which dress (for both sexes) has
always had a rich vein of both parody and subversion. Equally, one of the problems with Butler’s
argument is the question of what becomes chosen
as the norm at any place or time: there might well
be a huge amount of choice in modes of dress, but
there are always limits to social toleration and a
point at which the welcome for the new turns to
the condemnation of the bizarre.
Butler’s work has been influential across a
number of disciplines, in both the social sciences
and the humanities, since what she offers is a way
of seeing gender as always and inevitably radically
unstable. She does not regard cross-dressing or
drag as necessarily radical or subversive, for the
very good reason that both these forms simply
invoke and confirm gender stereotypes. Thus her
work is less a celebration of popular forms of
subverting fixed gender identities (these, in her
view, merely re-inforce existing expectations of
gender) but rather a method of studying the ways
in which, in social life, literature, and the visual
arts, gender is constantly being re-made. But the
social world, which prefers the order of fixed
gender identities, works against subversions of
gender, because it is fixed distinctions of gender
which, to Butler, maintain the social world. It is
here that her work has led her to conflict with
those critics (for example Martha Nussbaum and
Nancy Fraser) who have argued that the social
world of late capitalism can function perfectly
well, whatever the politics of gender. The idea
of a world without gender, Butler argues, would
be a world in which there would be no expectation
of “feminine” qualities of care or masculine
gender
attributes of “strength” but only the recognition
of human qualities. Those industries related to the
various forms of the manipulation of the body
(fashion, health and beauty, and cosmetic surgery)
and indeed the expected tensions of much popular entertainment (how the couple of either
homosexual or heterosexual desire is going to be
formed) would collapse, Butler suggests, if we did
not have fixed gender identities to maintain.
For many sociologists, Butler’s work, while recognized as important, is regarded as somewhat
removed from social reality, in which sexual difference still plays a crucial role in the determination of social identity. Beverley Skeggs, in
Formations of Class and Gender (1997), and Linda
McDowell, in Gender Identity and Place (1999), have
argued that both femininity and masculinity are
not just attributes of a particular sex, they are also
constructed in different contexts of class. Skeggs
has shown how, for working-class women, maintaining that sense of femininity which prioritizes
the care of others (both personally and professionally) is an essential part of what they see as their
best hope of an advantageous marriage; McDowell
has suggested that, for middle-class men, the demonstration of the supposedly female qualities of
“caring” and co-operation with others is a highly
positive attribute, whereas supposedly “masculine” characteristics in women do not receive the
same approval. What both authors are able to
show is that constructions of gender differ from
social class to social class, but a model of behavior
which accords with traditional expectations of
femininity is of positive social value for middleclass men, but of negative social value for
working-class women.
These possible differences in the social value of
different gender identities open up a further question about the relationship of gender to the social
world. Many writers have seen the Enlightenment,
and modernity itself, as an inherently “masculine”
project. Although there is considerable evidence
to suggest that the question of gender was important to writers in the Enlightenment, and that the
writers were both male and female, what has
emerged as the dominant view of the Enlightenment is that of a way of looking at the world
which values reason above feeling, the rational
over instinct. That binary division (the association
of women with nature and men with culture) has
long been assumed to be at the heart of the Enlightenment. But if we can observe the increasing
social value of the attributes of the feminine, we
also have to remember that this greater social
value is only gained by men rather than women.
gender
Thus, although the postmodern might include the
blurring of gender boundaries (and the concomitant furious resistance in some quarters to these
newly apparent forms of sexuality and gender
identity), what does not appear to be taking place
is any realignment in the hierarchies either of
class or of gender identity that is related to biological difference. Hence some men can, to their
advantage, do femininity, but women cannot do
masculinity.
For many writers on gender, however, shifts in
the social construction of gender identity, apparent and important though they may be, break
down when confronted by actual biological differences between the sexes and the impact that these
differences have on individual lives. For biological
determinists, there are (as there always have been
in different ways) differences between women and
men which are fixed and both transhistorical and
transcultural. At the same time Freudian psychoanalysts would resist any attempt to eliminate
biological sexual differences from either the study
or the understanding of the human. Empirical
sociological investigation has also demonstrated that, although men, particularly middle-class
men, may be willing to do femininity in certain
aspects of employment, their willingness – in
common with that of working-class men – to
take over female responsibilities in the household
or in caring work is still extremely limited. In
these circumstances, the gender politics of everyday life demonstrate a resistance to the re-thinking of gender which is very marked, as do various
forms of social reaction to behavior in women
(for example what is seen as the excessive drinking of alcohol) which is more generally associated
with men. Arlie Russell Hochschild is among those
sociologists who have investigated the present
ordering of gender relations in the private space
of the home and found that traditional patterns of
gender persist.
This continuing inequality in gender relations
(and the theories such as that of Anthony Giddens
in The Transformation of Intimacy (1992) which
argue that gender relations in the private sphere
are shifting to a more egalitarian model) is explained by L. McNay, Gender and Agency (2000),
following Pierre Bourdieu, in terms of a challenge
to the cognitive, reflexive, and deliberate refashioning of gender identity which Giddens assumes.
Bourdieu’s concept of habitus is used to explain
the indeterminacy of gender and embodiment.
Social ideas and expectations about gender are
enacted at a pre-reflexive level: what is being suggested here is that individuals have certain deeply
231
gender
held, often unconscious, investments in conventional patterns of masculinity and femininity, and
these patterns are not easily over-turned, either by
objective decisions or by social situations in which
the rejection of these norms might appear to be
the socially meaningful and rewarding choice.
Thus, while gender identity is not an immutable
or essential pattern of behavior, McNay suggests
that there are many pre-reflexive aspects of masculine and feminine behavior which call into
question the idea of reflexive identity.
Crucial to all these theories about gender, and
the ways in which we acquire our gender identity,
is our understanding of language. All language is
saturated with meaning: the very terms man or
woman carry all kinds of embedded knowledge
that we seldom voice but nevertheless use in our
social existence. It is for this reason that the use of
language, particularly language about gender, has
become such an important issue in both the academy and practical politics. In the mid-1960s, the
term people was quite widely used to refer only to
men; today the term is used to make explicit the
absence of bias towards male or female in particular situations. Traditional terms such as husband
or wife have been replaced by the term partner, a
term which ironically carries with it associations
of the formal relations of the marketplace. But in
contexts other than the everyday world, language
is also crucial for theories of gender, because it is
through language that we achieve the means to
express our understanding of the symbolic meaning of our bodies. The writer who has contributed
most influentially to this debate is the French
psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan in his Écrits (1966
[trans. 1977]), who has argued that a child has to
recognize sexual difference before becoming a
speaking subject; it is only through recognizing
both absence and presence of the phallus that a
child can make the necessary progress towards
both language and an understanding of the symbolic world. Feminist writers (most particularly
the French writer Luce Irigaray) have challenged
this idea by arguing that what children primarily
experience is the “discursive” sexuality of their
mothers. For Irigaray it is not male sexuality which
constitutes the primary means of entry into language but that of the female. With Irigaray’s thesis
in “When our Lips Speak Together” (1980, Signs)
comes the view that femininity resides in female
biology: it is a view which has been accused of
biological essentialism and it is, of course, very
different from the ideas of Butler.
Whatever the different views of various writers
about the relationship between language and the
232
gender
formation of gender identity, all writers agree on
the centrality of the body to theories about
gender. Here the spectrum of writers ranges
from those who see the body, and its physical
characteristics, as definitive in the making of individual identity, to those who would question the
idea that the body has a sex at all. This very radical
view might seem to challenge all taken-forgranted assumptions about the social world, but
the idea is supported by evidence from diverse
communities which suggests that our western
ideas about gender, and gender difference, are
not necessarily as straightforward as we might
like to suppose. Thus anthropologists (for example
Henrietta Moore) have pointed out that male and
female are not necessarily the fixed and certain
categories that we might suppose but differ
between societies and cultures. If the physical definition of the body can be questioned, then it is
inevitable that gender identity then becomes a
matter of uncertainty and negotiation. This thesis
alters our relationship to the body: it is no longer
the fixed starting point but actually the unknown,
fluid starting point of attempts to define gender.
Seen in the light of this, it is possible to surmise
that gender identity is as rigid as it sometimes is
because what Freud recognized as the “polymorphous perversity” of the psyche is as true of the body
as it is of the mind. In his work on the history of the
body, Bryan S. Turner in The Body and Society (1984)
has emphasized the importance of working with
an understanding of the “lived body,” an approach
which opens up the possibility of seeing the body
itself as a production of the social world rather
than as a fixed constituent of it.
All theories of gender work with the paradox
that they begin with the recognition of the impact
of gender difference in the social world and then
attempt to show that this difference, having been
produced, can also be dissolved. The politics of
gender have come to be recognized as central to
the organization of social life, not because these
politics have been articulated for the first time in
the latter part of the twentieth century but because gender, and gender identity, has always
played a crucial role in the history of the social
world. The Bible begins with the drama of the
recognition of sexual difference (implicitly suggesting that the concept of sexual difference was
created through knowledge rather than corporeal
reality) and Homeric epic is organized around the
mistaking of the identity of the mother. Both
these examples might serve to remind us that
the question of gender, and gender identity, is as
old as civilization itself.
MARY EVANS
gender studies
gender studies
This area of interdisciplinary research is concerned with understanding the biological differentiation of male and female, the gender roles
that express that differentiation in society and
culture, the development and expression of different types of human sexuality, the political representation of gender in feminism, and the modern
expression of sexuality such as lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transsexual identities. Women’s studies
and gender studies are interdisciplinary fields of
contemporary scholarship that are devoted to the
study of women and gender in different historical
and social contexts. These areas of study stress the
gendered nature of social life.
In sociology, social constructionism has argued
that gender is not a naturally occurring phenomenon but has to be socially produced and sustained.
Sociologists
are
concerned
with
understanding how people do, rather than have,
gender – that is, by what processes of socialization
do people learn the practices, attitudes, and behavior through which distinctive gender identities are
expressed. For example, masculinity is itself not a
uniform expression of male identity. In Gender
and Power, R. W. Connell (1987) has argued
that masculinity and femininity are normalized
gender identities that are hegemonic in modern
society. Gender studies are concerned to understand power and inequality in terms of gender
differences.
There are a huge array of gender studies and
women’s studies programs, especially in higher
education in the United States. There are innumerable journals, research centers, and institutions devoted to this field of study, and gender
studies in many respects provided a model for
the development of lesbian studies and Gay Studies. Some leading feminist journals include Signs,
Feminist Review, Feminist Studies, differences: a journal
of feminist Cultural studies, and Hypatia.
Gender studies is in large measure the academic
consequence of feminism and related social movements that campaigned for gender equality. The
success of feminism and its internal political and
cultural divisions are also manifest in different
forms of gender research. Gender studies was
introduced into universities because it was argued
that higher education was dominated by men and
that the academic disciplines ignored women,
gender, and sexuality. There has been a substantial debate about whether gender studies is a
special field of research or whether gender as an
issue should be part of the mainstream of every
generation(s)
discipline. Gender studies have been important in
promoting research on the family, marriage and
divorce, nature/nurture (see environment), patriarchy, private and public spheres, and women
and work. Through feminist social theory, it has
been critical of biologism and essentialism. Feminist theory has often been associated with postmodernism by challenging many of the takenfor-granted assumptions of social science. The
study of gender has had a significant impact on
the development of the sociology of health and
illness (for example Ann Oakley’s Women, Medicine
& Health, 1993), the sociology of the emotions (such
as Arlie R. Hochschild’s The Managed Heart, 1983),
and the sociology of the body, in which Emily
Martin’s The Woman in the Body (1987) was important. The study of gender has been significant
in sociology, but it has often found a more secure
home in literary studies and Cultural studies,
where the traditional canon has been transformed
by the impact of feminist theory.
BRYAN S. TURNER
generation(s)
This term is used in different and sometimes inconsistent ways by social scientists. There are at
least five ways in which the term is employed: (1)
to designate levels in extended kinship structure;
(2) to designate the general stage or segment in
the life-course that a group occupies (for example
the current generation of college students); (3) to
refer to those who experienced a common historical period (for example the Depression generation, the Sixties Generation, or Generation X);
(4) to refer to a subset of a historical generation
who share a common political or cultural identity;
and (5) to denote a circumscribed age group in
the population. The fifth use is closest to what
developmental scientists call a “cohort.” The concept of cohort refers to an aggregate of individuals (generally defined on the basis of birth
year) whose lives move together through a historical time. Given these varied meanings, it is important to trace the way the various concepts are
measured and used.
The confusion of generation and cohort has led
some scholars to insist that generation should only
be used to designate a kin relationship and genealogical linkage (for examples, parents and children or grandparents and grandchildren). As D. L.
Kertzer, in Generation as a Sociological Problem (1983),
points out, there is often substantial overlapping
of age among (kin) generations, and it would
be impossible to characterize the generations
233
generation(s)
properly in terms of their common characteristics
vis-à-vis other generations. A generation might
consist of several cohorts, each of which has encountered different historical experiences that
have affected its life-course. Therefore, to examine
change over time in generational relations it is
necessary to compare cohorts not generations.
With the revolutionary changes in longevity in
the advanced industrial world, there is far greater
co-survival of generations and this has led family
researchers to examine the consequences in terms
of intergenerational family solidarity and conflict.
Much of the contemporary research suggests that
obligations are giving way to more negotiation
among the generations. Yet, while intergenerational support has been shown in both the United
Kingdom and the United States to be more a
matter of negotiation than of prescription, there
is little evidence to suggest that intergenerational
family relations are of less importance than in
the past.
The distinction between generation and cohort
has been further blurred by the political debates
in many western nations about generational
equity, a concern about whether the distribution
of resources and power in society among different
age groups (cohorts) favors one generation to the
detriment of another. This debate was spurred by
the United States demographer Samuel Preston’s
article, “Children and the Elderly: Divergent Paths
for America’s Dependents” (Demography, 1984), in
which he claims that elderly people receive more
than their fair share of the federal budget, particularly in light of their economic status, and they
ultimately receive these benefits at the expense of
groups that are more needy and deserving, especially children. Notions of the Third Age, a time of
personal fulfillment after retirement, have helped
fuel labels like “the SKI generation” (Spending the
Kids’ Inheritance). The crucial point is about the
just distribution of wealth between age groups
which, according to historical demographer Peter
Laslett’s A Fresh Map of Life (1996), is one of the
most urgent issues of contemporary society.
It is the problem of social change that has
informed much of sociology’s concern with generations. Karl Mannheim, in his essay “The Problem
of Generations” (1928), posed the thought experiment of how human social life would be if one
generation lived on forever and none followed to
replace it. It was the linkage between “generational replacement” and social change that
Mannheim explores in his famous essay.
According to Mannheim the biological process
that defines generations creates the potential for
234
generation(s)
the development of a shared consciousness that
unites and motivates people. It provides them
with a similar location, much like social class,
but does not guarantee that they will form a “generation as actuality.” For a generation to trigger
social change, they must forge an additional bond
that allows a shared consciousness that underpins
what he calls a generational unit. Of course, not
all respond to historical circumstances in the
same way, and the same historical period may
provoke different generational units who take
quite contrary stances. However, once adopted,
consciousness is resistant to revision. Thus societal change takes place partly as a result of cohort
replacement, the process by which the older generation dies out and is replaced by the new.
Some forty years later, Norman Ryder, in his
article “The Cohort as a Concept in the Study of
Social Change” (1965, American Sociological Review),
revisited Mannheim’s analysis. Ryder substituted
the concept of birth cohort for Mannheim’s generation and largely jettisoned the notion of shared
consciousness and the distinction between “generation” and “generation as actuality” that was central to Mannheim’s view of the structural linkage
between agency and social change. Ryder argues
that a comparison of different cohorts is a powerful analytical strategy for studying social change.
Cohorts describe age-homogeneous groupings
that are clearly bounded. A whole industry of
social research (predominantly North American)
has grown up looking at cohort change in attitudes and behaviors. However, the definition of
cohorts according to birth year is convenient but
problematic. When we examine the question of
why a particular span of years is important in
the life experiences of individuals, we are back
into the thorny issues of how biography and history intersect. This was the issue that C. Wright
Mills, in his book The Sociological Imagination (1959),
identified as the crucial concern of the social
science.
Social research on generations, aging, and lifecourse interconnect in ways that defy any simple
overview of sociological work on generations.
Glen Elder, in his classic study of Children of the
Great Depression (1974), makes use both of generations (in the kinship sense) and of birth cohorts
to track the influence of the economic crisis of the
1930s on the life-course of two cohorts of children
born just eight years apart. He shows the importance of familial processes for mediating the
impact of socioeconomic change. As John Clausen
stated in his preface to Elder’s book, “we
know that ‘life chances’ depend on historical
genetic engineering
circumstances and one’s location in the social
structure but we are only beginning to formulate
the nature of the linkages between particular
kinds of experiences located in time and place,
adaptive responses to these experiences and longterm outcomes.”
Generational reproduction is a complex process,
regardless of whether we are looking at kinship
relations or societal change. The various meanings
of the term generation do at least serve to remind
us that biological, biographical, social, and historical reproduction crucially interrelate. This was
one of the central insights of Mannheim’s essay
which has stood the test of time.
JACKIE SCOTT
genetic engineering
– see genetics.
genetics
A branch of biology, genetics is concerned with
the study of heredity and the variability of organisms. The twentieth century has been described
by Evelyn Fox Keller as The Century of the Gene
(2000). From the discovery at the turn of the twentieth century that Gregor Mendel’s laws of inheritance could also be applied to those of human
heredity, to the recent successful completion of
the human genome project identifying all the
genes in the human body, developments in genetics have accelerated so that they now dominate
the science arena. If the field of nuclear physics
dominated post-World-War-II science, it is the
fields of genetics and genomics that have come to
supplant it. These fields are often referred to as
“big science,” a term used to describe both the scale
and complexity of large-scale post-World-War-II scientific endeavors. Commentators have suggested
that genetics is not only influential in shaping
ideas about human identity, but also a powerful
economic and political force aligning considerations of health and wealth and generating new
forms of biocapital. As we move into the twentyfirst century, genetic science and its associated
technologies seem likely to have an even greater
impact on society and upon understandings of
what it is to be human.
The idea of eugenics, a process for selectively
breeding humans in order to preserve and promote “desirable” characteristics, was first formulated by scientist and cousin of Charles Darwin,
Francis Galton (1822–1911). In 1904 at a meeting
of the Sociological Society, Galton is reported to
have said that, “Eugenics is the science which
deals with all influences that improve the inborn
qualities of a race; also with those that develop
genetics
them to the utmost advantage.” Eugenics was defined by Galton as the study of agencies under
social control that may improve or impair the
qualities of future generations either physically
or mentally. He intended eugenics to extend to
any technique that might serve to increase the
representation of those with “good genes,” in
this way accelerating evolution. A major motivation of many eugenicists was an idea of human
progress. The idea of progress was based not
solely on the advancement of scientific knowledge
but also on genetic improvement. This was supported by Darwin’s evolutionary theory, wherein
the survival of the fittest was equated with the
survival of the best. The best were thought to be
the best people to cope with modern life. Galton
tended to equate people’s genetic fitness with
their social position. Social Darwinist ideology
provided a good climate for eugenic thought,
and many qualities such as intelligence, temperament, and behavior were believed to be inherited.
Galton proposed that the human race might be
improved by eliminating society’s so-called undesirables and multiplying its so-called desirables.
Such ideas became increasingly popular in the
political sphere with both democratic and totalitarian regimes.
The eugenic movement was supported by the
upper-middle classes, with scientists and geneticists in particular playing an important role in
this movement. Research into human heredity
was carried out in scientific laboratories to develop eugenically useful knowledge. A human
genetics program emerged, focusing on the analysis of various conditions, particularly those seen
to be creating a social burden for society. The socalled feeble-minded were a particular focus.
Psychologist and eugenicist Henry Goddard was
of the opinion that “feeble-mindedness” was a
hereditary condition of the brain that made those
who had inherited such a condition more prone to
becoming criminals, paupers, and prostitutes. Societal problems such as poverty, vagrancy, prostitution, and alcoholism were understood by
eugenicists as primarily the outcome of a person’s
genetic inheritance rather than emanating from
social, political, and economic factors. The mental
and behavioral characteristics of different “races”
were also a focus of the eugenic movement, and,
in genetic science in northern Europe and the
United States, eugenics was frequently used to
support ideas of the existence of a superior white,
middle-class Protestant elite, such as the so-called
Aryan race. Beginning in 1907, compulsory sterilization laws were passed in many states in the
235
genetics
United States, with Denmark and Germany passing such measures in the 1930s. While these countries adopted compulsory sterilization programs
designed to prevent the continued breeding of
those deemed to be undesirable, the eugenic
movement in Nazi Germany led not only to
the sterilization of hundreds of thousands of
individuals but ultimately to the death camps
where millions of Jews and “undesirables” were
murdered.
The story of eugenics is not only characterized
by such negative aspects; the eugenic program
also included many initiatives that were classified
as “positive.” Galton originally classified eugenics
as consisting of two types: positive and negative.
While negative campaigns were concerned with
getting rid of the “undesirables,” positive eugenics
involved the promotion of “desirable” human
stock. In Britain, positive eugenic campaigns
sought to encourage the middle classes to breed
through a system of tax concessions and grants,
and in the United States the American Eugenics
Society sponsored Better Babies competitions and
Fitter Families contests as part of their positive
eugenic campaign. Beginning in the 1950s, there
was a rise in nondirective genetic counseling in an
attempt to dissociate the field from the negative
eugenics of the Nazi regime. Such measures were
based on the understanding that couples wanted
healthy children, and such interventions were
seen as important in providing impartial advice
to enable couples to make choices concerning
reproduction.
Scientific endeavors to discover the chromosomal location of genes and their relation to
each other initially began slowly at the start of
the twentieth century. Scientists understood that
a gene was a single unit located on a chromosome,
passed from one generation to the next, and that
this material was coded in cells determining how
an organism looked and behaved. In 1913, the first
genetic map appeared, identifying the relative location of six genes on one chromosome. In the
following decades, this process remained painstakingly slow and difficult. In 1953, two Cambridge
University scientists, James Watson (1928– ) and
Francis Crick (1916–2004), made what is considered to be a landmark scientific breakthrough
by discovering the physical structure of DNA
(the molecular structure that holds genetic information). Nevertheless, scientists still faced a
daunting task in identifying all the genes of the
human body, particularly as it was incorrectly
assumed that there were likely to be in excess of
100,000. However, by the 1980s, genetic maps
236
genetics
were good enough to allow scientists to go
“hunting” for genes among families of people
with inherited diseases such as Huntington’s disease and cystic fibrosis. In the 1980s, with the
invention of a new technology called PCR (polymerase chain reaction) that enabled DNA to be
replicated and amplified, and the availability of
new high-speed computer-sequencing technology,
scientists began to consider a global endeavor to
map and sequence the entire human genome –
that is, to identify the now more accurately
assessed 20,000–25,000 genes of the human body
and determine the sequences of the 3 billion
chemical base pairs that make up human DNA.
The human genome project marks the entry of
genetics into the realm of big science and officially began in 1990 with the aim of completing
the genetic sequencing of certain forms of bacteria, yeast, plants, animals, and ultimately
human beings. It was anticipated that a complete
human sequence would be produced by 2005. The
scale of the project was such that it was as much a
political endeavor as a scientific one. In the United
States, the project was headed by James Watson,
who played a key role as both scientist and political lobbyist. Although the majority of the research was undertaken in the United States, the
project became an international collaboration, involving twenty research groups from six countries. The intention was to divide the mapping of
the twenty-four human chromosomes among
some dozen or so laboratories around the world.
One-third of the human genome was sequenced in
the United Kingdom at the Sanger Institute. The
scale and cost of the project was huge. It is estimated that work carried out in sequencing the
single gene responsible for the disease cystic fibrosis cost between US$50 million and US$150
million.
The human genome project has political dimensions, as could be expected for any project requiring so much funding, with huge potential
rewards for the biotechnology industry in terms
of the possible application of genetics to medicine
and agriculture. The enormous expense of this
project was justified primarily on the basis of the
likely medical benefits. There was also an implicit
understanding that such an enterprise would
have economic benefits by helping to fuel a growing biotechnology sector. Indeed, as the project
progressed, many countries involved, including
the United Kingdom, were quite explicit in their
plans to use genomics to help generate national
wealth. The International Human Genome Consortium (the group which coordinated and
genetics
managed the human genome project) made extravagant speculations about the practical importance of their work for human health, claiming
that the human genome project would lead to
profound long-term consequences for medicine,
by enabling an understanding of the underlying
molecular mechanisms of disease and the design
of drugs and other therapeutics targeted at those
mechanisms. As the project developed, so too did
the “hype,” with many speaking of genetics as the
key to unlocking the secrets of life and providing a
genetic blueprint of what it is to be human.
Many scientists involved were also keen to
ensure that scientific competition would not
undermine or delay the project. In particular,
there was concern that the granting of patents
allowing exclusive property rights over data
would undermine international collaboration. It
was therefore agreed that this worldwide, multibillion-dollar project would be funded solely from
public funds and medical charities such as the
United Kingdom’s Wellcome Trust. Furthermore,
information on the sequencing of all human
genes was to be made freely available via the
internet. The ethos of the policy of publicly
funding the human genome project is that it is a
democratic resource intended to maximize the
benefits for society as a whole. Nevertheless, commercial companies were involved in a race to map
and sequence the human genome, and the American company Celera Genomics developed a rapid
gene-sequencing technique and subsequently took
out commercial patents in order to profit from
this work. In response, work being undertaken
on the human genome project accelerated and a
race between these two groups to be the first to
announce the completion of an initial draft of the
human genome developed. In June, 2000, President Bill Clinton of the United States and Prime
Minister Tony Blair of the United Kingdom made a
televised announcement that the work of the
human genome project was almost complete.
The announcement was made five years before
the original estimate of completion, and it was a
further two years before the project was officially
declared complete. The announcement made
headline news around the world and was surrounded by much media-fueled hype, with politicians and scientists variously describing it as the
most wondrous map ever made and more important than the invention of the wheel.
The human genome project and recent developments in genetics are surrounded by triumphalist
accounts of scientific progress. While there has
been little in the way of sociological theory to
genetics
explain the phenomenon of hype that pervades
this field, some have noted that such hype plays
an important role in generating the necessary
funding and investments for projects such as the
human genome and other biotech endeavors.
Alongside the creation of high expectations that
genetics and associated technologies will bring, it
is recognized that developments in genetics also
raise new ethical problems. While this new form
of scientific knowledge has promised to bring
about cures for many diseases, and the elimination of inherited disabilities, genetics is also
understood to raise new ethical issues and fears
about the social consequences of such
interventions.
Concerns were voiced from the outset about
the ethical, legal, and social implications of the
human genome endeavor. In the United States,
James Watson successfully argued for the case
that 5 percent of the total science budget should
be set aside to study and address these issues.
There has also been a growing expansion in the
funding of similar projects in other countries.
These initiatives are understood as playing an important role in the governance of genetic developments. Critical questions have been raised about
whether such new technologies for reading our
genetic constitution would challenge human
identity and freedom, create unjust discrimination, and invade our privacy. Although many
sociologists are now working in the field of bioethics alongside philosophers and lawyers, this is an
uneasy alliance. There is a growing sociological
critique of bioethics, which maintains that bioethics involves a narrowing of debate, is focused too
much on individuals at the expense of the social,
and too often readily legitimizes genetic developments. Sociologists have in general been more
critical of recent developments in genetics. Some
have suggested that developments in genetics are
promoting a return to eugenic practices and generating genetic determinism. Others are less critical and, while acknowledging that genetics is
extremely powerful in shaping ideas, see the
emergence of new kinds of identities, forms of
personhood, and social relations developing. Various surveys carried out to ascertain public opinion
on developments in genetics indicate that, while
there is widespread support for developments related to improvements in health, there is also
widespread concern about scientists “tampering
with nature.”
Advocates of projects to map the human
genome claim that the information produced
will illuminate the causes of human disease,
237
genetics
improve treatment, and, in general, increase our
health and well-being. Certainly there are now
tests available for detecting over 1,000 genetic
diseases and conditions. Although not all of these
are readily accessible in the clinic, the availability
of such tests is growing at a rapid rate. Tests are
used variously: to diagnose those suspected of
having a genetic disease, to predict the likelihood
of the existence of genetic disease in asymptomatic individuals with a family history of genetic
disorders, and to identify carriers of a genetic
disease (that is, those at risk of passing the disease
on to their children but who do not themselves
have susceptibility to the disease). Tests are also
carried out during pregnancy and after birth. Prenatal testing is performed during a pregnancy to
assess the health status of a fetus. Such tests are
offered when there is an increased risk of having a
child with a genetic condition due to maternal
age, family history, or fetal ultrasound examination. Preimplantation testing is performed on
early embryos resulting from in vitro fertilization
(IVF) in order to decrease the chance of a particular genetic condition occurring in the fetus. It is
generally offered to couples with a high chance of
having a child with a serious disorder. Newborn
screening identifies individuals who have an
increased chance of having a specific genetic
disorder so that treatment can be started as soon
as possible. Nevertheless, while the human
genome project has helped to identify a number
of genetic conditions, there are only a few treatments available. Most genetic conditions cannot
be treated and the reduction in the numbers
of individuals being born with such conditions is
a result of pregnancy terminations or through
the selection of healthy embryos identified by
genetic testing during IVF. There have also been
a number of educational programs aimed at raising awareness among certain ethnic groups (see
ethnicity and ethnic groups) that have been identified as having increased susceptibility to certain
genetic conditions. Those of eastern European
(Ashkenazi) Jewish descent, for example, are often
targeted, as chances of being a carrier of Tay
Sachs disease are significantly higher in these
populations.
A number of commentators have expressed concern about the commercialization of genetic tests
and testing services. The biotech company Myriad
Genetics, for example, has taken patents out on
the genetic codes relating to the two genes most
commonly associated with hereditary forms of
breast cancer and has been successful in creating
exclusive rights over these genetic tests. Many
238
genetics
other genetic tests are now readily available over
the internet, with tests such as those used for
establishing paternity being increasingly used in
disputes between parents as well as by agencies
involved in determining child support.
Many critics of contemporary genetic practices,
such as Troy Duster, suggest that the introduction
of clinical testing and genetic screening programs
that have steadily increased since the late 1980s
have created a Back Door to Eugenics (1990). Duster
clearly warns against the dangers of prenatal detection of birth defects, gene therapies, and genetic solutions to problems associated with various
racial minority groups. He also documents an increasing propensity to see crime, mental illness,
and intelligence as expressions of genetic dispositions. Feminists and disability scholars, too, have
expressed concern about the social implications of
genetics, especially its reliance upon abortion to
prevent the occurrence of genetic disease. In Genetic Politics (2002), Ann Kerr and Tom Shakespeare,
while acknowledging that the recent implementations of practices and policies related to genetic
technologies are very different from those in the
past, also warn that there is a fine line between
contemporary policies and practices on abortion
and diseases and the past practice of compulsory
sterilization for deviancy. They argue that genetics reinforces medical-genetic definitions of
disability, makes judgments about the social
worth of disabled persons, and ultimately involves
decisions about what kinds of persons ought to
be born.
A number of scholars have criticized the costs of
mapping the human genome and the possible
discriminatory and eugenic applications of the
information it will provide. They have raised concerns such as the implicit assumptions in the biomedical discourse in which the “benefits” of
genetics are proposed, and the ways in which genetic tests shape definitions of illness and health,
normality and abnormality. The terms geneticization and genetic determinism were first coined in
the early 1990s to refer to the ways that social and
other environmental conditions that shape the
manifestation and meaning of bodily characteristics and behavior have been ignored in preference
to biological and genetic understandings. Abby
Lippman is credited with first using the term
geneticization to build upon the concept of medicalization, whereby people come to perceive the
body in conformity with biomedical categories.
From this perspective, genetics is highly problematic, as it is based on false biological reductionist
and deterministic assumptions which generate a
genetics
sense of fatalism. In a similar vein, Dorothy Nelkin
and Susan Lindee in The DNA Mystique (1995) argue
that the gene has become a very powerful cultural
icon and that a process of genetic essentialism is
occurring whereby what it is to be human is increasingly understood in genetic terms. Such
geneticization, these critics argue, stems from
highly exaggerated claims made by scientists and
the ways in which powerful metaphors such as
“genetic blueprint” and the “book of life” have
been used to describe the human genome. The
media in particular are seen to play a vital role
in conveying and proliferating the iconic status of
the gene.
Nevertheless, concerns about geneticization
and a return to eugenics are not shared by all
scholars in this area. Nikolas Rose and Carlos
Novas, for example, maintain that such approaches oversimplify the shifts in the form of
personhood that arise as a result of the growing
awareness of genetic risk. They claim that the new
genetics does not so much result in individuals
seeing themselves and their lives along predetermined genetic lines, but rather that knowledge of
genetic risk transforms their identities and relations with medical experts in novel and unexpected ways. The growth in various forms of
patient activism – such as those coalescing around
web-based forums and patient organizations that
not only raise funds to find cures for genetic diseases, but also help direct scientific agendas – are
evidence, they argue, of a more active self-actualizing form of personhood.
There has been a great deal of research within
the field of medical sociology examining the experience and understandings of those who are
understood to be genetically at risk of disease.
The new genetics is based primarily on those selfidentifying, and being identified, as at risk. Much
of this work is based on a phenomenology approach, focusing on descriptive analyses of the
procedures of self-, situational, and social constitution of those who have experienced genetic
testing or understand themselves as living with
an increased risk of disease. While much of this
work, too, highlights the ways in which individuals’ knowledge of genetic risk may generate a
sense of responsibility towards others, in particular family members who may also be at risk, such
research also demonstrates the difficulties and
dilemmas faced by those at risk.
Risks in the form of the consequences of genetic
engineering or genetic modification of human
and other living organisms have also been a subject of debate for scholars.
genetics
There is concern that genetic engineering of
humans, where faulty genes are either repaired
or replaced, might alter the germline cells (those
cells that have genetic material that may be
passed on via reproduction to a child) and irreversibly alter the genetic makeup of future generations. In The Future of Human Nature (2003),
Jürgen Habermas argues that positive eugenics
such as genetic engineering, along with other
forms of genetic enhancements, should be forbidden. The reason for forbidding such interventions
is that they undermine what it is to be human by
ignoring the autonomy of future generations and
their standing as moral agents. Drawing upon
Max Weber’s notions of rationality, John Evans,
in Playing God! (2002), examines bioethics and
policy debates about genetic engineering. Evans
demonstrates that many such debates, although
initially broad-ranging, quickly tend to become
narrowly defined, focusing more on how best to
achieve the scientific aims rather than on the
desirability or otherwise of the aims themselves.
Developments in the new genetics raise profound questions about democracy and citizen
rights. Fears about the undesirable social consequences of developments in genetics have
prompted governmental and international regulations and statements.
In 1997, for example, the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization
(UNESCO) drew up a Universal Declaration on the
Human Genome and Human Rights. The declaration
affirms the human dignity of each individual, regardless of his or her genetic endowment, and sets
out ethical principles for the conduct of research,
treatment, or diagnosis related to characteristics
of a person’s genome. It calls upon states to
outlaw discrimination based on genetic characteristics if such discrimination would have the effect
of “infringing human rights, fundamental freedoms and human dignity.”
Many indigenous peoples and environmental
nongovernmental organizations oppose the granting of patents on biological materials such as
genes, plants, animals, and humans. Some commentators suggest that we are witnessing new
forms of “biopiracy” and the colonization of life
itself. The Human Genome Diversity Project, which
proposes to collect blood and tissue samples from
hundreds of different indigenous groups worldwide for genetic study, has been severely criticized
by indigenous communities and human rights advocates. They have raised questions regarding
both ownership of the genetic samples and who
stands to profit from the commercialization of
239
genocide
genocide
products derived from the samples. Concerns have
also been raised in relation to the collection, storage, and ownership of DNA for the growing
number of national genetic databases.
The creation of genetic databases has been surrounded by controversy and debate, attracting
worldwide media attention and significant financial investment by both public and private bodies.
At national and international levels, policymakers
have sought to define and engage with what they
see as the considerable social, ethical, and legal
issues at stake. These include informed consent,
commercialization, ownership, privacy, confidentiality, and public confidence in the governance of
research. Many of these are longstanding areas of
public policy in relation to the new genetics and
more broadly.
An Enlightenment model of progress underpins
much of this scientific endeavor with an everincreasing control of nature through culture. At
the same time, a number of commentators have
noted that culture is becoming increasingly biologized. Paul Rabinow, for example, has coined the
term “biosociality” to refer to the new forms of
subjecthood and social and political practices that
are emerging, which he sees as providing a possible basis for overcoming the nature/culture split.
OONAGH CORRIGAN
genocide
While mass killing has been a perennial aspect of
human societies, the term genocide is a relatively
new concept. It was coined by the Polish jurist
Raphael Lemkin in his Axis Rule in Occupied Europe
(1944) as the legal term to describe the atrocities
committed by the Nazis in World War II. Lemkin’s
effort aimed to provide a legal category to make
such acts justiciable under international law (see
law and society). In Lemkin’s view, genocide is a
coordinated plan that aims to destroy national
groups, in whole or in part. This plan includes
not only physical destruction, in the form of
mass murder, but also the destruction of the
group’s culture and collective identity.
Lemkin’s definition has served as the conceptual foundation for practically all subsequent
efforts to define genocide, including those by sociologists. Among sociologists, there is considerable
conceptual confusion about how to define genocide. Some sociologists adhere rather closely to
Lemkin’s definition and/or legal definitions, while
others seek more expansive sociological definitions, which outline the general structural elements of genocide. Legalistic definitions, however,
make it difficult to engage in systematic socio240
logical research and theorizing about genocide.
There is some general consensus among sociologists that genocide is the killing of substantial
numbers of people by an institutionalized, superordinate form of power, generally a state in conjunction with military power. The victims are
generally subordinate, both in a material sense
(lacking the means of self-defense) and in a symbolic or ideological sense (they are socially constructed as “threatening,” “evil,” or “dangerous”).
For many legal scholars, genocide is characterized
by what is called dolus specialis, or special intent,
but this is a difficult category to conceptualize
within existing sociological theory. Homicide is
the killing of one person, but genocide is the
killing of a number of people. There is, however,
no consensus, either among legal scholars or sociologists, as to what the numerical threshold for
genocide is.
Much of the social science literature on genocide relies on a naturalistic and positivistic frame
of reference that aims to predict and prevent
genocide. Barbara Harff and Ted Gurr in Early
Warning of Communal Conflicts and Genocide (1996)
have developed an “early warning” model that
provides a series of indicators that aims to predict
the occurrence of genocide. Such predictions,
however, are not at present tied closely to the
institutional means of prevention. In recent
years, genocide has occurred in Iraq, Bosnia and
Herzegovina, Rwanda, and Sudan. Owing to the
modern mass media, these genocides were widely
observed, but were not prevented. This fact indicates that the phenomenon of “bystanding” is also
an important aspect of any definition, empirical
research, or theory of genocide in the modern
world.
For some sociologists, the relationship between
modernity and genocide is highly significant. In
his Modernity and the Holocaust (1989), Zygmunt
Bauman argues that the scale of mass killing in
the Holocaust was enabled by the very forms of
bureaucratic rationality and instrumental reason
that characterize modernity. Bauman’s sociological view focuses less on the intent and agency
of actors or institutions and more on the power of
social roles and institutionalized practices that
enable ordinary people to become perpetrators of
extreme violence. Michael Barnett in Eyewitness to a
Genocide (2002) notes that the inability of institutions of global governance to prevent genocide is
related to bureaucratic decisionmaking procedures, which stress organizational norms and
imperatives to the detriment of more global ethical norms and genocide prevention.
gerontology
ghetto
Since World War II, when the term genocide
was coined, there have been numerous genocides,
which indicates that this remains a perennial
aspect of human collective behavior in the
modern world. A recent example of genocide is
in Darfur, Sudan, where as many as 300,000
people have been killed in a campaign of mass
murder and cultural destruction. This event was
recognized by the world community as genocide,
but no decisive action was taken to stop it.
TOM CUSHMAN
gerontology
The study of processes of population and individual aging, this draws upon a wide range of
perspectives, including disciplines such as biomedicine, the social sciences, and the humanities.
Gerontology is typically concerned with understanding aging, first, as a biological and social
process affecting individuals across the lifecourse; second, as a process influencing social
change through the movement of birth cohorts;
thirdly, as a significant issue for the development
of health and social policy.
Interest in the nature of human aging is longstanding, reflected in studies of longevity and related themes from Francis Bacon (1561–1626)
onwards. Gerontology as a discipline first emerged
at the end of the nineteenth century, notably
through investigations by Jean-Martin Charcot
(1825–93) into the relationship between old age
and illness, and the development of theories of
aging by Elié Metchnikoff (1845–1916), based
upon his work in medicine and biology. The study
of aging from social as well as biological perspectives took longer to develop, but expanded rapidly
from the 1940s – driven by awareness of the economic impact of aging populations. Professional
associations concerned with research into aging
developed around this time, including the Gerontological Society of America (established in 1945)
and the International Association of Gerontology
(1948). Key figures in the development of social
and psychological studies of aging, from the
1950s onwards, included James Birren, Bernice
Neugarten, Clark Tibbitts, and Matilda White Riley
in the United States, and Peter Townsend in the
United Kingdom.
Sociological and social policy perspectives in
gerontology were extended during the 1980s
with a combination of critical perspectives on
aging and fresh investigations into the family
and community life of older people. The former
(notably through the work of Carroll Estes and
Alan Walker) challenged prevailing views about
old age as a “problem for society,” highlighting
structural pressures and constraints affecting
older people. The latter confirmed the diversity
of social ties in later life, and the continuing centrality of family and friends through all stages of
the life-course.
Longitudinal research in gerontology has confirmed the complex mix of factors influencing the
experience of growing old. On the one hand, interactions between social, psychological, and biological characteristics influence key aspects of
aging. On the other hand, these are embedded
within the particular historical and cultural experiences of successive birth cohorts. Membership
of a cohort may, for example, greatly influence
health and financial status as people mature into
later life. This point is reflected in approaches
such as cumulative advantage/disadvantage
theory, which examines the extent to which early
advantage or disadvantage may be accentuated
over time leading to increased inequality at later
stages of the life-course. Through models such as
these, gerontology has challenged assumptions of
homogeneity among old people, with research evidence suggesting that people become less alike
with age, given long-term interactions between
genetic endowment, social inequalities, and cultural and historical events.
Major influences on gerontological research in
the twenty-first century are likely to include the
challenge of globalization and the impact of population aging on poorer regions of the world.
Hitherto, studies of growing old have been dominated by a focus on older people in western society.
Global society comprises, however, a range of
demographic processes with variations in the experience and likelihood of growing old. Studying
such differences and inequalities across the world
will undoubtedly produce major challenges and
questions for gerontological research over the
next phase of its development. C H R I S P H I L L I P S O N
ghetto
This term comes from the early modern Italian
practice of setting aside urban neighborhoods
for Jewish people. Over time, the term retained
its association with the enforced segregation of
Jews in Europe, but in the United States in the
twentieth century, ghetto was generalized to
other social groups against which a collective
prejudice was directed – notably urban blacks confined economically and socially to an isolated residential area. By the early 2000s, the term had
entered common language to be applied to any
social group cut off from common social life,
241
Giddens, Anthony (1938– )
sometimes by its own preferences (for example,
“the academic ghetto” or “the gypsy ghetto”).
With respect to urban enclaves of ethnic groups
(see ethnicity and ethnic groups) other than Jews
or blacks, the term ghetto is commonly replaced
by expressions like Chinatown or Little Italy.
Whether imposed on the segregated by the wider
society or assumed by those who cut themselves
off, the term generally retains its original pejorative connotation, as in “ghetto-blasting” in reference to the loud music outsiders associate with
the cultural tastes of black ghetto youth. In academic sociology, “ghetto” may occur as a quasitechnical term borrowed from common language,
but it is more accurately used to denote the social
practice whereby social groups tend to associate
with others of like kind, usually (but not always)
residentially, occasionally by their own choice,
but usually by force.
CHARLES LEMERT
Giddens, Anthony (1938– )
Born in 1938 in north London, the son of a clerk,
Giddens has had two careers, the first as one of the
most influential social theorists of our time, the
second as a public intellectual both in Great Britain and on the global stage. Giddens was trained
as a social theorist at the London School of Economics, to which he returned as Director from
1997 to 2003. From 1970 to 1997, Giddens taught
at the University of Cambridge where he became a
professor and life fellow of King’s College. He is
the author or editor of over thirty books. He was
made a life peer and took his seat in the British
House of Lords in 2004.
As a social thinker, Giddens has an exceptional
ability to reconcile and synthesize leading arguments drawn from disparate and often rival
schools of thought. In doing so he produces
novel analytical frameworks and concepts that
preserve the strengths of a vast array of sources.
Proceeding in this way, Giddens has done as much
as any single thinker to set the agenda for an
entire generation of sociologists. He first rose to
prominence in 1971 when he published Capitalism
and Social Theory. At a time when Anglophone
social theory was still ill informed about European social thought, Giddens provided surehanded commentaries on the depth and breadth
of works by Max Weber, Émile Durkheim, and
especially Karl Marx, whom Giddens did much to
legitimate for sociologists who previously had
avoided his works.
In the next phase of his sociological career,
Giddens created a new analytic framework he
dubbed structuration theory. Structuration theory
242
Giddens, Anthony (1938– )
is a sociological ontology, that is, a set of concepts
that propose generic assumptions about the
nature of social life that sociologists draw upon
when they first think about social life in any given
historical, cultural, or local domain. When developing structuration theory, Giddens absorbed
the lessons of Harold Garfinkel, Erving Goffman,
and the later philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein,
all of whom concurred on the fundamental importance of enacted practices in social life. It is in
part thanks to Giddens’s structuration theory that
social practices are now regarded as basic units of
analysis in sociology. When Giddens first began
developing structuration theory at Cambridge in
the mid-1970s, social action was almost always
defined in terms of the subjective meaning the
actor gave to his/her own acts. Like Garfinkel,
Goffman, and the later Wittgenstein, Giddens recognized that it is what actors do and how they
perform that constitutes social conduct.
But Giddens was quite critical of sociologists of
practice (also known as sociologists of everyday
life) for their unwillingness to take on board the
reflexive association between enacted forms of
conduct and the larger structural properties and
morphological patterns of relations in society. In
his central concept of the duality of structure,
Giddens proposes that structural properties of
larger and enduring social groups are carried by
actors as forms of competencies that enable them
to act in specific ways in appropriate situations.
Actors in such situations may reproduce the general form of the practices they have learned in
the past, or they may alter that form in some way.
While no single act may sustain or change the
structural properties of a culture or a group in
itself, the manifold reproduction or alteration of
practices by numerous actors over extended
periods of time will either reproduce the characteristic structured features of a culture or group,
or more or less substantially revise the structure
of that group. In much the same way, enacted
practices may either reproduce or alter the networks of contacts and relations, and the more
integrated systems, that provide the morphological patterns for society.
In structuration theory, Giddens also offers
a new theory of power in society. Like Weber,
Giddens distinguishes forms of domination from
the forms of social power in everyday life. Concentrating on the latter, Giddens breaks sharply with
Michel Foucault and others who see pervasive
domination in social life. In his concept of the
dialectic of control, Giddens proposes that in
principle all actors, save perhaps for those who
gift
Gilroy, Paul (1956– )
are physically disabled, have at least two options,
namely to comply or resist the orders of others.
Given that the dominant typically require compliance from the dominated, Giddens proposes that
dominated groups always have some ability to
carve out spheres of autonomy for themselves,
however modest or expansive they may be. Recent
works by Michael Mann and Charles Tilly expand
upon this point, though only Mann directly
acknowledges a debt to Giddens in this regard.
Modernity is the theme in the third phase of
Giddens’s sociological career, a phase marked by
three publications: The Consequences of Modernity
(1990), Modernity and Self-Identity (1991), and “Living
in a Post-Traditional Society,” in Ulrich Beck, Giddens, and Scott Lash, Reflexive Modernization (1994).
As the Soviet Union imploded and the information age was about to dawn, Giddens pointed
out that dramatic cultural, political, economic,
and technological change has been characteristic
of modernity since its inception. This did not
make the new wave of changes any less disruptive
and disorienting. Indeed, Giddens mainly concentrates his attention on the existential problems
and the difficulties in maintaining personal relationships that have beset modern western
societies since the end of World War II. Two disruptive forces of particular note are, on the one
hand, the eclipse of time and (to only a relatively
lesser degree) space as barriers to the expansion of
social systems and, on the other hand, the erosion
of local authority and culture by abstract economic and informational systems. But Giddens
also notes the countervailing trend of the reappropriation of abstract knowledge by actors in their
everyday lives.
As a public intellectual, Giddens is best known
as the originator of The Third Way, a set of leading
ideas for social policy associated with the Labour
government of Prime Minister Tony Blair in Britain and several European governments as well.
Giddens has published several books for general
audiences including The Third Way (1998) and
Runaway World (2000).
IRA COHEN
Americans in which a chief might display his
power through a ritual destruction of his possessions. This example demonstrates the contradictory nature of gift giving, both creative and
destructive.
In the social philosophy of Jacques Derrida
(1930–2004), the study of gifts is related more
broadly to hospitality and friendship. Derrida has
drawn on Emile Benveniste’s Le Vocabulaire des institutions Indo-Europeenes (1969) in his Of Hospitality
(2000). In the study of reciprocity, Derrida showed
that in a variety of European languages there are
important etymological connections between
“stranger,” “enemy,” and “guest.” Latin hostis indicates the notion of a stranger who has an irresistible claim on our hospitality, specifically a claim
against the master of the household. While people
who dwell outside may be enemies, the guest who
has entered our dwelling to sit by the fireside has
significant rights and can claim our protection.
This analysis of the origins of “guest” demonstrates how notions of reciprocity and exchange
between the master of a household and the guest
emerge from expectations about hospitality. Any
consideration of the stranger/guest relationship
must take into account the wider realm of gift
exchange, and the duties that attach to giving
and receiving.
Derrida was influenced by Mauss’s discussion of
“primitive exchange” in The Gift, in which the
word pharmakon means both poison and cure. In
Mauss’s analysis of the potlatch ritual of the
Native American communities of the northwest
coast, it is evident that the gift-exchange is typically a challenge that creates a destructive social
relationship. In connection with social relations,
the gift is both corrosive (poison) and therapeutic
(cure). In reflecting on “Plato’s Pharmacy” through
Mauss’s analysis of the pharmakon, Derrida used
this etymological analysis of the ambiguity of the
gift to show in effect that all ethical behavior
involves hospitality, because ethics are about the
claims which the stranger might have on our
society.
BRYAN S. TURNER
gift
gift relationship
The giving of gifts has been analyzed as an aspect
of social exchange. Gifts generally create or reinforce social solidarity by creating obligation,
but they can also be used aggressively to demonstrate superior social power. In his The Gift, Marcel
Mauss (1923 [trans. 1983]) treated gifts as a form of
social exchange which reinforces social solidarity,
creating a duty to reciprocate the original gift, but
he also examined the “potlatch ritual” of Native
– see gift.
Gilroy, Paul (1956– )
Influenced by the Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies, since 1999 Gilroy has
been Professor of Sociology and African-American
Studies at Yale University. His PhD thesis, “Racism,
Class and The Contemporary Politics of ‘Race’ and
‘Nation’” (1986), focused on the British situation
243
Glazer, Nathan (1924– )
and culminated in his first book, There Ain’t No
Black in the Union Jack (1987). His work has been a
consistent attempt to combat “raciology” by emphasizing the diasporic character of racial categories of identity, solidarity, and resistance. The Black
Atlantic (1993), Against Race (2000), and Between
Camps (2004) reject essentialist approaches to ethnicity in favor of a post-identity form of doubleconsciousness that seeks to acknowledge the
hybrid form of the various versions of white
supremacy and black power. The Black Atlantic
reveals the authoritarian connection between
sovereign territory and national consciousness
and the contradictions thereof. It argues that for
150 years black intellectuals in the West have been
diasporic and struggled with the dilemmas
involved in being simultaneously black and
western. Gilroy’s sociology makes an explicit link
between the quest for territorial sovereignty,
racism, and fascism. At the level of material
culture, Gilroy has examined black vernacular
and popular cultures through black music, film,
and literature to demonstrate the articulation of
diasporic, hybrid forms. His recent work has
been concerned with examining the meaning of
multiculturalism and elaborating non-racial democracy. This has climaxed in the concept of “planetary humanism” which he develops from Aimé
Césaire and Franz Fanon. This rejects liberal humanism on the grounds that it is complicit with
racism and calls for an inclusive, global, anti-racist,
anti-militaristic, and environmentalist humanism.
By arguing that racial politics must transgress
the color line and incorporate a critical stance on
essentialist thinking per se, Gilroy shows that he
is au courant with postcolonial thought and the
post-identity thinking found in the work of his
old Birmingham School mentor, Stuart Hall. But
critics have questioned whether his politics of
double-consciousness and planetary humanism is
CHRIS ROJEK
practically viable.
Glazer, Nathan (1924– )
Formerly Professor of Education and Social Structure and currently Professor Emeritus, in the
Graduate School of Education, Harvard University,
and the co-editor of The Public Interest, Glazer has
been an influential figure in American public life
in terms of his writing on race relations and
multiculturalism. He has been closely associated
with the so-called New York intellectuals who included such figures as Daniel Bell. He was, as a
student, a follower of L. Trotsky, the Russian revolutionary. After the Depression, Glazer, like many
Jewish intellectuals, came to regard capitalist
244
Glazer, Nathan (1924– )
America as a successful democracy in which each
successive wave of migrants could eventually be
incorporated into America, despite discrimination.
His first publication was on the topic of his dissertation, The Social Basis of American Communism
(1961), and he collaborated in David Riesman’s
The Lonely Crowd (1950). He came to the attention
of the academic community through his publications on race and ethnicity. He wrote the influential American Judaism (1957) and, with D. P.
Moynihan, he published Beyond the Melting Pot
(1963) and Ethnicity. Theory and Practice (1975). His
essays on these issues were published as Ethnic
Dilemmas 1964–1982 (1983).
Glazer has emerged as a controversial figure in
American politics because he has questioned affirmative action programs, for example in support
of black Americans. These arguments were presented in Affirmative Discrimination (1975) – a collection of essays that date back to the early 1970s.
Critics of Glazer, for example S. Steinberg (2001)
in Turning Back. The Retreat from Racial Justice in
American Thought, have argued that, not only has
he abandoned the socialist principles of his youth,
but also it is hypocritical of a person from a migrant Jewish background to criticize black activists for demanding support for their aspirations to
succeed in American society. For example, Glazer
was a student at City College New York in 1940
when tuition was free – a form therefore of affirmative action. Critics claim that his policy prescriptions are justified by apparently scholarly
arguments from, for example, Beyond the Melting
Pot, where Glazer argued that, because black
Americans had suffered so profoundly in the past
from slavery, they have not experienced the
upward social mobility enjoyed by other ethnic
communities who have prospered in the American
Dream. Glazer argues that repairing this historical
problem of black Americans is beyond the scope of
current social policy.
Glazer argued that, despite the civil rights movement, the gap between white and black Americans
has persisted, and this inequality is associated with
declining inner-city schools and the unravelling of
the black family. He has recently been critical of
liberal policies, especially in schools towards a
multicultural curriculum, in We Are All Multiculturalists Now (1997) and Sovereignty under Challenge
(J. D. Montgomery and N. Glazer (eds.), 2002), in
which he is concerned that multicultural education subverts the truth and undermines national
unity by the “Balkanization” of the American
republic. Glazer and his generation believed
that Americanization was unproblematic because
globalism
ethnic minorities would eventually be assimilated
and benefit from growing economic prosperity.
However, that optimism has been questioned by
the fact that black progress appears to have come
to an end in the 1970s. For his critics, Glazer
apparently offers black youth a bleak choice:
either negative social conflict and disharmony,
or passive acceptance of inclusion into American
society (on white terms). Despite criticisms, the
quality and importance of Glazer’s scholarship
remains unquestioned.
BRYAN S. TURNER
globalism
– see globalization.
globalization
Described as a new world order, some scholars
argue that globalization is an unprecedented
21st-century reorganization of time, space, people,
and things. It is variously portrayed, sometimes as
“globalism” by advocates and promoters, or as a
postmodern form of unrestrained capitalist expansion and imperialism by members of antiglobalization movements. In both instances, the
object of support or resistance is a global system
of interconnected communication and transportation networks, economic markets, and persons,
covering almost the entire planet. An essential
feature of this system is that it is deterritorialized,
that is, the connections and collectivities exist
primarily in electronic networks of communication. Some authors, such as Arun Appadurai in
his “Disjuncture and Difference in the Global
Cultural Economy,” in Public Culture (1990), refer
to this as a form of pan-locality, with multiple
nodes of transaction or “scapes” – ethnoscapes,
technoscapes, finanscapes, mediascapes, ideoscapes, linguistically echoing the notion of landscape for segmented networks in this now
deteritorrialized, fluid, transnational, global
social organization. Through the electronic connections and diverse scapes, elements of human
culture move around the globe separately from
geographic, institutional, or relational contexts.
A scientific–technological account of globalization describes a world engirded by a finely
wrought network of cables, satellites, air, and sea
lanes, as well as old familiar land routes, that
transport information, things, and people from
one place to any other on the globe in anything
from a minute to a day. This is a world in which
boundaries that once had been created by time
and space have been eroded by scientific and technological developments, especially in communication and transportation.
globalization
These innovations have roots in ancient times
when exploration and trade by land and sea was
apparent in the Mediterranean basin and Asian
seas, and in medieval and Renaissance times
when scientific and technological innovations
began to spread around the globe. Scientific and
technological development escalated noticeably,
however, during the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries, and, with exponential rates of both
invention and social change in the twentieth
century, the spatial and temporal distances that
had historically moored distinct populations,
languages, cultures, markets, and political
systems have been made porous through regularized and continual communication. In this
techno-scientific account, emphasis is placed on
the cumulative effects of the Enlightenment, and
how humans slowly accumulate the knowledge
and ability to produce ever increasingly rational
forms of social organization and technological
innovation, in the end overcoming ignorance,
superstition, myth, religion, and scarcity to create
relative abundance, human freedom, and worldwide mobility. The mixing of peoples, languages,
and cultures has brought about what is now a
transparent hybridity in human groups and cultures. While few human cultures, in history
or contemporary times, have been unaffected
by exchange with others (enemies or friends),
the degree of hybridity and technologically driven
hybridization is at a scale and pace heretofore
unknown.
A political-economic account of globalization
places less emphasis on the technological sources
of globalization than on the political and normative claims of capitalist investment. Rather
than being a portrayal of the success of science
and technology, a political-economic account
describes the historic triumph of the market
economy. It is an account of how the market – as
a means of coordinating production and distribution – is now worldwide, after more than a
century of being confined within national and
regional boundaries. This view of globalization
depicts markets as both the engine and product
of human energy and imagination, now in the
twenty-first century overcoming what is described as backward and inefficient systems of centralized planning and socialized ownership that
governed a good part of the globe during the
twentieth century.
Some accounts of globalization emphasize the
international coordination of scientific research
to control disease, prolong lifetimes, and improve
conditions of everyday life. Others focus on the
245
globalization
transnational flow of people, goods, and capital
that creates a global division of labor with an
equally global diffusion of material and cultural
goods. For example, goods produced with Korean
or Chilean labor, from materials mined in Zaire or
grown in India, are sold in the shops in Paris,
Los Angeles, or Tokyo. People born and raised in
Mexico, Guatemala, Turkey, Algeria, Ethiopia, or
Zimbabwe travel north to find work to sustain
families left behind. At the same time, music
from American urban ghettos is played in the
shops in Japan and Australia or the streets of
Budapest and Russia, portable telephones manufactured in Finland adorn the hips of laborers
from Santiago to Cape Town, and television stations around the globe fill their schedules with
the product of Hollywood studios while munching
on American-style fast food of Big Macs and
French fries.
As the same time as local sites become linked
in a global circulation of people, signs, materials,
and goods, globalization is understood to be
reshaping the parts of the world now joined
communicatively and economically. While some
people and phenomena are ripped from spatial
and territorial moorings, others – for example,
social groups based on ethnic, linguistic, or religious practices – become re-territorialized, making claims to specific pieces of geography with
newly recognized boundaries as the ground of
their participation in the global world order.
While some localities experience a marked increase in standards of living (measured in terms
of reduced infant mortality, longevity, education,
and calories consumed), others experience an
equally marked decline in material, psychological,
and sociological conditions of everyday life. In the
techno-science account, the global community is
linked internally by its actively shared cultures
and externally through its collective scientific
exploration beyond this globe.
Rather than a portrayal of the success of science
and technology, the political-economy account
emphasizes the virtues of flexible production,
worldwide sourcing, and low-cost transportation
and communication. Just as the boundaries between time, space, people, and things are erased
in the techno-science account, the economic account emphasizes the erasure of traditional distinctions among market tools – between banking,
brokerage, insurance, business, politics, and consumer credit – and the promotion of strict boundaries between economics and politics. Global
capital is financialized, that is, like social transactions dis-embedded from geography and social
246
globalization
relations, capital accumulation is also de-territorialized, mobile, residing nowhere more than in
cyberspace. Ever liquid, new financial instruments
are created as well as markets in these instruments, new markets in commodities, as well as
markets in currencies and debts. The capital that
fuels the global circulation of goods, services, and
people is therefore faceless and rootless, free of
national or geographic identity, ever mobile,
moving from one locale to another, as efficiency
and profit demands.
The global markets create both dispersion and
integration. Global dispersion is typified by the
creation of new producers and sites of production
within nations and transnationally. Large and
small companies increase their subcontracting,
and do so with several geographically distant
subcontractors for the same product. Industrial
homework spreads into the hinterlands of remote
parts of the world at the same time as highly
skilled cognitive (mind-work) laborers and professionals move their work from office to home,
sometimes also at great distances from the centers
of control and management. This diffusion of
worldwide outsourcing – fueled by low transportation costs and computerized communication
linkages – creates flexible production and higher profits for corporate managers and owners,
while relegating labor and suppliers to hypercompetition and insecure income.
The territorial dispersion is accompanied by a
parallel concentration of centralized control to
manage and finance the dispersed production.
The remotest sites of individual production are
tied by centralized management through closely
linked chains of financial and design control finding their apex primarily in the global cities such
as Tokyo, New York, and London. The global cities
produce the specialized services which, according
to Saskia Sassen in The Global City (1991), are
“needed by complex organizations for running
spatially dispersed networks of factories, offices,
and service outlets,” as well as the “financial innovations and the making of markets . . . central
to the internationalization and expansion of the
financial industry.”
The dual processes of dispersion and integration are joined in processes of what some term
“glocalization,” a neologism joining globalization
and localization to describe the customization of
globally produced products or services for local
cultures and markets. It is also used to refer to
the use of global networks, for example in cell
phones, to provide local services. It refers in addition to identity marketing that fetishizes local
globalization
places for the purpose of product branding, associating, for example, coffee with a particular
Colombian farmer, or a unique island with the
home of a generic product. According to Roland
Robertson, who is credited with popularizing the
term, glocalization describes the tempering
effects of local conditions on global pressures. At
a 1997 conference on “Globalization and Indigenous Culture,” Robertson said that glocalization
“means the simultaneity – the co-presence – of
both universalizing and particularizing tendencies.” The term, first used by Japanese economists
in the 1980s, is also used prescriptively in business
circles to emphasize that the globalization of a
product is more likely to succeed when the product or service is adapted and tailored specifically
to each locality or culture in which it is marketed.
Examples of glocalization display the selfconscious cultural hybridization that is at work
in global marketing. For example, the American
fast-food chain McDonald’s replaced its mascot,
the clown Ronald McDonald, in French advertising with Asterix the Gaul, a popular French cartoon character.
Accompanying the techno-scientific and economic accounts of globalization, there are political and moral claims about the necessity of a
rule of law (see law and society) and, at the same
time, the inefficiencies of legal regulation. In the
political–legal account of globalization, national
boundaries are described as inefficient and should
cease being barriers to trade: all national economies should be open to trade. In this moral
universe, all exchanges, transactions, and engagements should be signaled solely through market
prices, which are conceived as the only legitimate
form of social control for rewarding good action
and punishing bad. Public regulation of private
enterprise, as an alternative to price regulation,
is the enemy of the global economy and its moral
universe. As a corollary to the dominant role of
prices as the major form of communicating participation in the market economy, domestic prices
are supposed to conform to international prices
and monetary policies are expected to be directed
to the maintenance of price and balance-ofpayment stability. These are the basic universal
principles of market economics promoted by the
International Monetary Fund, the World Bank,
and neoliberal economists promoting market
globalization.
Although markets depend on law to provide a
stable normative environment, ensuring security
of property and contracts, the global “marketeers”
insist that the law do no more. Beyond the
globalization
assurance of mutual trust and normative order,
the market or neoliberal account of globalization
demands that the rest of economic affairs remain
entirely matters of market (price) decisions rather
than the consequences of political organization or
legal processes. The market version of globalization urges use of law to police a fixed boundary
between public and private, between economics
and politics. Although national legal orders in
western Europe and the United States have, for
more than 100 years, created various adjustments
to counteract market instabilities and imperfect
competition, a key feature of globalization at the
end of the twentieth and beginning of the twentyfirst centuries is the fury of its critique of legal
intervention and its insistence on a natural and
necessary divide between public and private, economics and politics. Historical experience and
legal precedents notwithstanding, the global marketeers insist that the private law regime of property and contract, at both the national and
international levels, is an apolitical realm, merely
supportive of private initiative and decision,
immune from public or political contestations
and without significant or problematic redistributive consequences.
Some observers argue that the global system –
embodied primarily in the communication networks – allows direct cultural and economic relationships that bypass and/or subvert – depending
on the point of view – traditional power hierarchies like national governments, or markets. There
are some who see in globalization the possibilities
of a new democratic transformation. Some stress
that the circulation of capital and culture is –
as the phrase suggests – a circulation, not solely a
movement from the center to the peripheries. By
dissolving political, temporal, and spatial boundaries, the technological revolutions underwriting
this transnational exchange create capacity for
movement in all directions and with less investment than was heretofore possible. From this perspective, as illustrated in Boaventura de Sousa
Santos’s Toward a New Common Sense: Law, Science
and Politics in the Paradigmatic Transition (1995),
globalization enables more diverse participation
and more sources of influence – forms of enfranchisement – throughout the world-system. Those
at the geographic peripheries of the world-system
welcome the chance to be regular and possibly
influential participants in the virtual global
community. In the global networks of communication and exchange, human creativity can be
unleashed from traditional cultural and material
constraints to find new forms of expression in
247
globalization
what seems like an unbounded space of possible
interactions and connections. Here, observers
point to the importance of human rights discourse, in contrast to the economic rights discourse of marketeers, in shaping actual, not
merely a virtual, community, and the empirically
documentable changes that discourse has
wrought in heretofore authoritarian regimes.
Similarly, some note the growing significance of
environmental concerns in mobilizing social
movements across traditional national, political,
racial, and gender boundaries. For optimistic observers, globalizing markets pose an opportunity
and challenge.
In contrast, others view globalization as a historic process leading to a more one-way relationship between the global realm, inhabited by
multinational corporations, global finance, the
entertainment industry, international broadcasting, the worldwide web, amoral secular humanism, and a subjugated “local” realm where the
identity-affirming senses of place, neighborhood,
town, locale, ethnicity, religion, and morality
barely survive against the global onslaught of
globally circulated, professional produced-forprofit identities. Some claim that the technoscientific account of globalization is a saga of
disenchantment, as Max Weber predicted. Noting
the immediacy with which persons, goods, information, and technologies move across vast
distances, and the expanding breadth and accelerating pace of consumption, critics of globalization, in anti-globalization movements and
elsewhere, emphasize how the loss of sacred
illusions and embedded identities has left a corrosive absence at the center of human life where
“all that is solid melts into air” (Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (1848
[trans. 1968]). Critics note the bombardment by
stimuli, the neurological overloads, and the homogenizing consequences of the escalating circulation of signs and symbols removed from local
experiences and interpretive frameworks. Globalization seems to be characterized by isomorphisms, convergences, and hybridizations that
create a sense of pervasive sameness across heretofore-diverse cultures. Some anti-globalization
movements emphasize this emptying out of meaning and morality in the global markets, actively
seeking a return to a religiously guided morality,
politics, and economy – sometimes violently,
such as in Islamic Jihadist groups (such as the
Taliban in Afghanistan) or some anti-abortion
movements in the United States, sometimes peacefully, such as among Christian fundamentalists.
248
Goffman, Erving (1922–1982)
Other anti-globalization movements emphasize
and attempt to resist the growing inequality and
erosion of economic security that had been promoted by the twentieth-century welfare politics.
Some observers go so far as to describe globalization as a form of postmodern colonialism,
where the worldwide distribution and consumption of cultural products removed from the contexts of their production and interpretation are
organized through legal devices and markets to
constitute a form of domination, as argued by
Susan Silbey in “Let Them Eat Cake: Globalization,
Postmodern Colonialism, and the Possibilities of
Justice” (1996, Law and Society Review). In postmodern colonialism, control of land or political
organization or nation-states is less important
than power over consciousness and consumption,
much more efficient forms of domination. This is,
for anti-globalization critics, the consequence of
advanced capitalism and technological innovation
seeking a world free from restraints on the opportunity to invent and to invest. In this most critical
account, globalization describes a world in which
size and scale in terms of numbers of persons (who
can produce), and in numbers of outlets (to
disseminate and place products), and capital (to
purchase both labor and land) determine the
capacity to saturate local cultures. Advocates of
free-market capitalism worldwide acknowledge
the inequalities produced, urging “measures that
enlarge the scope for wage differentials without
making it socially unacceptable” (Y. Kosai,
R. Lawrence, and N. Thygesen, “Don’t Give Up on
Global Trade,” in the International Herald Tribune,
1996). The processes of global economic differentiation have led to increased income for some previously poor workers at the peripheries of the
system, but also for significant transfers of
income from workers to upper-level managers and
investors. Alongside the economic differentiation
is a division of intellectual labor: the new systems
that organize work and production are designed
by relatively few highly educated, technically
trained specialists, with labor and repetitive,
minimal skill well distributed across the globe.
SUSAN SILBEY
glocalization
– see globalization.
Goffman, Erving (1922–1982)
One of the most original, influential, and exciting
sociologists, Erving Goffman found systematic
order and moral meaning in the momentary gestures of individuals in the presence of one another
Goffman, Erving (1922–1982)
that seem at first glance to be nothing more than
unreflective conformity to local custom and cultural etiquette. Goffman characterized this realm
of phenomena “the interaction order,” and in his
essay by that name, published in American Sociological Review (1983), saw it as comprising all that
is socially structured whenever actors are in
sufficiently close proximity to be aware of one
another’s presence. (He termed this the condition
of copresence.) Focused conversations are the
most obvious phenomena in the interaction order.
However, the interaction order also includes the
less involving, small gestures through which
actors acknowledge or avoid one another in everyday life. At the boundaries of the interaction
order, Goffman includes the ways people respect
one another’s privacy in public settings and the
ways people maneuver so as to maintain order on
crowded city streets.
Readers almost unanimously experience a
special sense of discovery in reading Goffman’s
work. He was outstandingly blessed with the ability to find order and significance in everything
from small shifts in body posture to a conversational pause that continues only slightly beyond
cultural expectations. But Goffman did not couple
his deep insights with sociological breadth. He
assumed a controversial theoretical position by
maintaining that there is only a loose coupling
between the interaction order and larger institutional orders such as the worlds of work, commerce, and government.
Goffman was born in 1922 in the Canadian province of Alberta to parents of Jewish-Ukrainian
descent who immigrated to Canada prior to World
War I. He was educated in sociology and anthropology at the University of Toronto and began his
graduate studies in anthropology at the University
of Chicago, where he received his doctorate in
1953. His doctoral research, conducted during
eighteen months of fieldwork in the Shetland
Islands, yielded the data analyzed in one of his
most prominent books, The Presentation of Self in
Everyday Life (1959). Goffman took his first major
academic position at the University of California,
Berkeley, in 1958, and moved to the University of
Pennsylvania in 1968. At the time of his death
from cancer in 1982, he was President of the
American Sociological Association.
Goffman, together (though not in direct association) with George Herbert Mead, Alfred Schutz,
and Harold Garfinkel, transformed the study
of social action by shifting from a Weberian
(and ultimately Kantian) emphasis on subjectivity,
motivation, and the ascription of meaning, to
Goffman, Erving (1922–1982)
an emphasis on the enacted performance of social
practices. He summarized this shift in a famous
apothegm, “Not men and their moments. Rather
moments and their men” (Interaction Ritual, 1967:
4). By this, he meant that social action in
local situations is structured by cultural rituals
rather than by the psychological motives of
individuals.
The majority of Goffman’s publications from
1956 to 1971 have a special richness in this regard.
Transforming Émile Durkheim’s insights in completely unanticipated directions, Goffman demonstrated that apparently inconsequential aspects of
social etiquette have deep-seated moral significance. One of his great achievements was to
transmute Durkheim’s philosophically inspired
insights into the cult of the dignity of the individual into studies of facework (that is, the ways in
which individuals establish their identities during
social interaction). Though Goffman never strayed
into the analysis of the culture of individualism at
large, he seemed to have a deep intuitive understanding of the fragility of social face within the
culture of modernity, where interaction rituals
and social identities shift from one context to
the next. He was keenly aware of the possibilities
of error, playfulness, and even attacks upon others
during the course of facework. He was extremely
sensitive to the structured avenues available in
interaction for the protection and repair of one’s
own face and the defense and repair of others. But
these vulnerabilities impressed Goffman less than
the fact that interaction rituals generally produce
order in everyday life. For example, Goffman
understood conversation to create an unio mystica,
that is, a shared involvement that transcends all
other concerns.
But Goffman’s interest in order, which is one of
his great sociological strengths, is the source of
his greatest weakness as well. Other than embarrassment, an emotion that he could not ignore,
Goffman studied the interaction order by bracketing the actor’s existential and emotional experiences. Hence, despite the stunning brilliance of
his insights into morally meaningful interactions,
his works sometimes lack sufficient human depth.
For example, in Stigma (1964), Goffman analyzed
the nature of profoundly damaged identity in
social interaction with no more than perfunctory
acknowledgments of the dramatic inner experiences of stigmatic individuals.
In 1974, Goffman published Frame Analysis, a
sprawling book in which he tried to draw together
a systematic approach to the structured enactment of meaning in social life. However, the
249
Goldmann, Lucien (1913–1970)
work is more valuable for its remarkable insights
into specific forms of interaction than for its
theoretical structure at large. Goffman’s genius,
and the word is used purposefully here, resided
in his ability to find order in the seemingly improvised nature of social action. His methods
make reading his work a special delight, thanks
in particular to his skill in drawing metaphors from contexts such as religious rituals,
dramatic performance, and games, seen as idealized instances of the deeper and more general
properties of social practice he wanted us to see.
But if his imaginative recourse to these and a
profusion of other metaphors to find the order
in interaction sets him apart, Goffman stands
out as well for his ability to sustain a systematic
analysis while allowing for the contingencies
available as an interaction scene unfolds. No
other sociologist of action has managed to find
the balance between order and contingency in
local situations nearly as well. When classical
social theory is redefined to include the twentieth century, Goffman will be one of the first
IRA COHEN
nominees.
Goldmann, Lucien (1913–1970)
Born in Romania, Goldmann spent much of his
adult life in Switzerland and France. He is best
known for his contribution to the study of literature and philosophy and in particular to the discussion of the ways in which literary and
philosophical works are related to their social
context. Goldmann was much influenced by the
Hungarian Marxist Georg Lukács and the Swiss
psychologist Jean Piaget; the work of both men
encouraged Goldmann to attempt to find a way
of explaining cultural form without reverting to
either materialism or idealism. The fruition of
Goldmann’s work was his study of Pascal and
Racine, The Hidden God (first published in 1956),
in which he argued that complex cultural phenomena are formed through what he described
as “homologous structures,” essentially similar
patterns of thought between relatively unformed
ideologies and more complex and finished intellectual works. For Goldmann, the study of culture
was not about the identification of “influence” or
“context,” since this enterprise isolated social
patterns; Goldmann argued for a method which
maintained a “conceptual oscillation” between
the parts and the whole. Goldmann wrote widely
on seventeenth-century France, the Enlightenment, the method of the social sciences, and
cultural change in the twentieth century. In the
latter context he is well known for his assertion
250
Goode, William Josiah (1917–2003)
that in modern western societies the great
political battles are for the control of consciousness rather than the control of the means of
production.
MARY EVANS
Goldthorpe, John (1935– )
A British sociologist, Goldthorpe is best known for
his empirical and theoretical contributions to the
study of social mobility and social class, and his
trenchant critical essays on a wide range of topics
in contemporary sociology. At the center of much
of Goldthorpe’s work on topics in social stratification has been a critical empirical assessment of
modernization and industrialization theories.
Goldthorpe’s first major work, the three-volume
The Affluent Worker (1968–9), examined the extent
to which the best-paid segment of the working
class was undergoing a process of embourgeoisement, concluding that this core claim of
industrialization theory was for the most part
unsustainable. From a base at Nuffield College at
Oxford University, beginning in the early 1970s,
he produced important work on occupational
sociology (The Social Grading of Occupations, 1974)
and the patterning of social mobility in Britain
(Social Mobility and Class Structure in Modern Britain,
revised 2nd edn., 1987 [1980]). Goldthorpe led a
pioneering effort to examine systematically the
patterns of social mobility cross-nationally in the
so-called CASMIN project. The major work of this
project, The Constant Flux (1992), was co-authored
with Swedish sociologist Robert Erikson. It challenged the view that all societies are on a unilinear path of increasing social mobility. The
“EG” class schema presented there and in earlier
writings has become virtually standard in most
contemporary cross-national work on classes in
capitalist societies and has even been adopted
by the British government. Goldthorpe has also
penned a series of sharply and widely debated
critical essays on the practice of qualitative and
comparative-historical sociology, class analysis,
feminism, and Marxism. Many of these are collected in On Sociology (2000). These critiques have
in common an insistence upon the importance of
rigorous empirical evidence and data analysis in
developing and evaluating sociological theories,
an approach Goldthorpe has consistently applied
in his own research across his long career.
JEFF MANZA
Goode, William Josiah (1917–2003)
Emeritus Professor at Stanford University, former
President of the American Sociological Association, President of the Eastern Sociological
Gouldner, Alvin (1920–1981)
Society, and an assistant director of the Bureau
of Applied Social Research, Goode made major
contributions to the cross-cultural study of marriage and divorce, and to the theory of social
control systems of prestige, force, and love. Goode
taught at various universities in the United States:
Wayne State, Columbia, Stanford, Harvard, and
George Mason. His Columbia dissertation was published as Religion Among the Primitives (1951), which
remains a brilliant introduction to the sociology
of religion. His World Revolution and Family Patterns
(1963) set the research agenda on the family in
twentieth-century sociology by examining the
rise of distinctive family patterns in fifty societies
during the process of industrialization. His other
major publications in this field were After Divorce
(1956), The Family (1982), and World Changes in Divorce Patterns (1993). Goode developed the theory of
social role in his Theory of Role Strain (1960) and of
social status in his The Celebration of Heroes (1978).
He contributed, with his co-author, Paul K. Hatt, to
the teaching of methodology in Methods in Social
Research (1952). Underlying much of his work was a
theory of social exchange in which he was particularly interested in the role of third parties.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Gouldner, Alvin (1920–1981)
Gouldner made a significant contribution in several areas of sociology, most notably to the understanding of the sociological enterprise itself. In his
most important work, The Coming Crisis of Western
Sociology (1970), he advances the case for a reflexive sociology which, he felt, would address
the shortcomings of existing “conservative” and
“Marxist” traditions.
Gouldner’s most important early work, Patterns
of Industrial Bureaucracy (1954), deals with conventional themes in industrial sociology and organization theory. The influential Wildcat Strike (1965),
meanwhile, focused on a case study of employer–
employee relations from which Gouldner constructed a theory of group tensions.
By the 1960s, he had turned his attention increasingly to theoretical commentary on traditions of social theory and to its reconstruction.
Taking a long time-span, he turned, in Enter Plato
(1967), to aspects of the legacy of ancient Greece
that he saw as having value in the contemporary
world. Closer to home in The Coming Crisis, he
argued against the adequacy of both structural
functionalism and Marxism as models for the
sociological project. The former, as exemplified
by Talcott Parsons, was regarded as conservative, accommodating sociology to new realities of
Gouldner, Alvin (1920–1981)
power and inequality. Since it is hard for social
theorists to reconcile new forms of power built
around corporations and the professions with
norms of goodness, Gouldner felt that the conservative option found ways of representing power as
positive, changing norms to accord with reality.
He rejected this, having more sympathy with radical alternatives that provided a critique of power,
and gave a positive normative loading to thoughts
and feelings unpermitted by mainstream opinion.
Gouldner’s commitment to theoretical renewal
also led him to found the influential journal
Theory and Society in 1974.
Marxism was a possible alternative source of radical inspiration, though this had a further difficulty,
namely that it was more successful in criticizing
other traditions than criticizing itself. In this respect, Gouldner thought of himself as an “Outlaw
Marxist.” Instead of asking social theorists to
choose between “conservative” sociology and “radical” Marxism, Gouldner projected reflexive sociology as an alternative standpoint. This idea was
designed as a way of reconstructing the vocation of
intellectual in a general way, and of sociology in
particular. While intellectuals should promote a
culture of critical discourse, the reflexive sociologist should rise above the role of technical specialist.
Reflexive sociology was to be defined not in terms
of scientific objectivity towards its subject matter,
but in terms of a critical stance to the social and
political context in which the sociologist operated.
Soul-searching was better than soul-selling.
This position is in one sense a product of its
times, sociology seemingly oscillating between canonical (Parsons) and iconoclastic (Gouldner)
moments. Marxism, as Gouldner was later to
argue in The Two Marxisms (1980), contained these
tensions within itself, manifested in the contrast
between Marxism as science and Marxism as critique. While reflexivity is now very much a mainstream idea – seen in the concept of reflexive
modernity – Gouldner’s emphasis on social emancipation via critical intellectuals and the culture
of critical discourse, advanced in The Future of Intellectuals and the Rise of the New Class (1980), has been
undermined by the class-like inequalities associated with knowledge holders.
Gouldner’s project of a sociology based on critical analysis from a moral standpoint is again a
fairly widely held presupposition. Yet he failed to
provide much epistemological depth on how a
critical position can be reconciled with a realist
approach to social analysis. His legacy is therefore
a somewhat fragmented one, perhaps as befits a
would-be outlaw.
ROBERT HOLTON
251
governmentality
governmentality
This encompasses a set of practices, institutions,
technologies, and sciences that enable the exercise
of political power over a population of individuals.
The contemporary study of governmentality derives from the work of Michel Foucault whose
oeuvre sought to uncover the microsocial processes, techniques, and knowledges associated
with governmentality. In his essay “On Governmentality,” which appears in The Foucault Effect (1991),
edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and
Peter Miller, Foucault dates the origins of the concept to the sixteenth century when self-conscious
investigations of the “art of government” were
initiated.
Governmentality came to involve by the eighteenth century an economy of politics over a population. This relationship between government and
governed evolved out of a pastoral model of the
family, in which a head of a household claimed
responsibility for the well-being of its members.
The welfare of the population is the end of governmentality. To seek the common good is to ensure
that laws (see law and society) are obeyed and order
maintained. Governmentality is therefore distinguished from other reasons of state, in particular
the religious and the Machiavellian. While governmentality is associated with a pastoral relationship
of shepherd and flock, it explicitly rejects the possibility that a Christian kingdom dedicated to the
glory of God could realize governmental sovereignty. Any religious doctrine in which moral or
divine ends supersede the rationally understood
good of the people will by necessity contradict
governmental reasons of state. This lends a distinctly economic character to the notion of the
good. The logic of governmentality also eschews
Machiavellian premises insofar as it insists that
government exists for the sake of the population,
and not the power of its leader(s). Economic, familial, and political governance are continuous enterprises that share a triangular relationship in
which none is ever entirely subject to either or
both of the other two. Therefore, a politics in which
a leader occupies a singular position and wields a
unique form of power through channels over
which he maintains a monopoly cannot support
governmentality.
Implicit in a governmental approach to politics
is the conclusion that sovereignty is defined primarily by dominion over a population rather than
a geographic territory. A population of individuals
simultaneously provides a government with both
its greatest source of power and gravest potential
threat. Therefore the means through which a
252
governmentality
government can control its population are crucial
to asserting governmentality. This requires the
regulation of individuals through the threat of
direct physical coercion implied by an omnipresent police force as well as indirect and even
internalized means of enforcing social norms.
The apparatuses, technologies, and sciences
capable of controlling a population and realizing
the goals of governmentality developed alongside
modern politics. Insofar as governmentality prioritizes an economic reason of state, it inevitably
relies upon scientific understandings of the population being governed. The good, having been construed in material rather than metaphysical or
otherwise transcendent terms, can only be arrived
at upon close inspection of those whose good is
sought. Thus the science of demography, and
statistical knowledge more generally, are crucial
technologies of governmentality. Because both
political and social security are essential to the
success of government, a symbiotic relationship
develops between the sciences from which statistical knowledge of the population can be gleaned
and the military technologies whose purpose it is
to ensure the safety of the population. Detailed
scientific assessments of the contours and characteristics of a population facilitate the degree
of surveillance necessary to identify, inhibit, and
punish deviance.
A range of forces collude to cause citizens to
recognize their identity as political beings
belonging to specific communities to which they
owe certain obligations and from which they need
and will receive protection. In the modern liberal
context, civil society becomes the terrain upon
which negotiations between government and the
governed occur. This implicates an almost endless
array of social and economic institutions in the
process of asserting governmentality. It also suggests that a significant challenge of governmentality will be the reconciliation of social and economic
justice. The notion of justice exists to distinguish
those who recognize and abide by social norms
from those who do not, and who consequently
must be isolated from the rest of society and/or
reeducated. Law provides an articulation of the
responsibilities of individuals to society, and vice
versa. However, within liberalism, various interpretations of economic logic yield vastly disparate
notions of these responsibilities, in no small
part because social and economic justice are not
simply distinct but often contradict one another.
Thus social and civil rights often come at the cost
of one another and hence obstruct both the expression and realization of a conception of justice.
Gramsci, Antonio (1891–1937)
Governmentality is a broader political concept
than either the Weberian notion of legitimate
authority or the Marxian concept of the state
within any given mode of production (see Karl
Marx). It is broader than legitimate authority
because it embraces processes both within and
beyond the administrative apparatus of the state.
Foucault explicitly addressed himself to Marxist
critics whose work he believed falsely assumed the
state to be the inevitable locus of political power
in all modes of production. The core concept of
governmentality contradicts the Marxian thesis,
instead offering a vision of politics in which power
constitutes and expresses itself through multiple
sources, of which the state is merely one. The
confluence of the pastoral model of politics, specific diplomatic and military techniques, and the
development of a police force is responsible for
the governmentalization of the state. The state in
this view, while perhaps uniquely successful, is
simply one instrument and manifestation of
governmentality.
ELIZABETH F. COHEN
Gramsci, Antonio (1891–1937)
Gramsci was one of the most influential Marxist
theorists of the twentieth century. After graduating from Turin University in 1915 he worked as a
journalist and regularly spoke at workers’ studycircles on novels, the Paris Commune, the French
and Italian revolutions, and Marxism. In 1919 he
was one of the founders of the revolutionary
weekly paper L’Ordine Nuovo, in 1924 was elected
to the Chamber of Deputies for the Italian Communist Party, and became General Secretary of
the Party. But after the fascist takeover Gramsci
was imprisoned in 1926, and during the following
ten years in confinement wrote copious notes on
theory and strategy, that were published in translation as Selections from the Prison Notebooks (1971).
Gramsci was concerned to eradicate economic determinism from Marxism and to develop its explanatory power with respect to cultural and
legal institutions. He argued that class struggle
must always involve work against the dominant
hegemony of bourgeois ideas and ideologies, so
that creating alternative cultural forms was essential to the struggle for socialism. He stressed the
role performed by human agency in historical
change since economic crises by themselves would
not subvert capitalism. As opposed to a war of
maneuver (a frontal attack on state power, such
as the Bolshevik Revolution), a war of position
may be more appropriate for liberal-democratic
societies, which would involve a long struggle
across institutions of civil society. Gramsci’s
Granovetter, Mark (dates unknown)
thinking was influential in the postwar Italian
Communist Party and in western Marxism –
especially in developing theories of Cultural studies, for example by Stuart Hall.
LARRY RAY
grand theory
– see C. Wright Mills.
Granovetter, Mark (dates unknown)
A leading American contributor to the study
of economic sociology and social networks,
Granovetter has been responsible for major innovations in thinking about the strength of weak ties
in economic life, and about the embeddedness of
economic relationships in wider social arrangements, both in non-market and in market-based
economic systems. His work moves economic sociology beyond the pioneering formulations of Karl
Polanyi and beyond the generalized emphasis on
normative rules in the work of Talcott Parsons
and Neil Smelser, while remaining distinct from
the predominant focus on power relations within
political economy.
Granovetter’s initial empirical work published
in Getting a Job (1995) focused on how professional,
technical, and managerial workers found new
jobs. His evidence demonstrated the importance
of personal contacts. Granovetter pursued the
characteristics of these contacts, and developed
in the process a theoretical account of the significance of “weaker” ties with individuals not well
known to each other, as compared with “stronger”
and closer ties between those who interact frequently. In a major paper “The Strength of Weak
Ties” (1973, American Journal of Sociology), he argued
that such weak ties were especially salient in situations where communities contained several ways,
rather than one distinct way, in which individuals
might interrelate. This made a significant opening
for a new kind of micro–macro network analysis,
in contrast with the primarily micro focus of
existing network theory.
Granovetter’s seminal contribution to economic sociology was made in another paper, “Economic Action and Social Structure: Problems of
Embeddedness” (1985, American Journal of Sociology).
This engaged with Polanyi’s celebrated discussion
of the relations between economy and society. For
Polanyi, most economic arrangements across history operated through the embedding of economic
transactions and price mechanisms with broader
social, political, and cultural arrangements. The
exception was found in modern capitalist
economies, where, for the first time, according
to Polanyi, the economy became profoundly
253
Graunt, John (1620–1674)
differentiated from society, around notions of
economic freedom or laissez-faire. This, however,
threatened social cohesion and the protection
of social cohesion, and the pendulum swung
back in the epoch of welfare states towards a
reembedding of markets in political institutions.
Many economists have criticized this view by
arguing that markets through history have been
far more autonomous than Polanyi proposed.
Rational choice theory, even more radically, proposed that a logic of rational choice underlies
social action across history, rendering the past
almost entirely similar to the present. Granovetter, by contrast, took a rather different view. For
him, all economic arrangements, markets included, are embedded in wider social arrangements, and in this respect the idea of laissez-faire
is a misnomer. This conclusion followed from his
earlier work on job search and social networks. In
later work in the 1990s he developed this line of
thinking regarding all economic institutions as
socially constructed, arising as “congealed networks,” assisting in flows of information and the
creation of trust. The social dimension here is,
however, a very broad one, in which a complex
mix of expressive and instrumental aspects of life
are included.
Granovetter’s ideas have developed one line
of thinking about economy and society in very
striking directions. What remains unanswered is
quite what the social means within a network
context, and why it is that markets, networks,
and formal organizations have emerged as distinct forms of social life.
ROBERT HOLTON
Graunt, John (1620–1674)
A draper and haberdasher, and merchant and citizen of London, Graunt was born in that city on
April 24, 1620, to Henry and Mary Graunt. He died
in London in poverty, of jaundice, on April 18,
1674. Although lacking higher education and not
trained in the sciences and mathematics, he was
an active participant in the intellectual life of
London and was a charter member of the Royal
Society of Philosophers. He published in 1662 the
first known quantitative data analysis of a human
population, Natural and Political Observations Made
Upon the Bills of Mortality. This small and very influential book has led some to recognize Graunt as a
founder of both demography and statistics.
The “Bills of Mortality” were weekly accountings and reports of the London parish clerks of
all the deaths and christenings. The reports were
started in response to the plagues of the late
sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries and
254
grounded theory
were published in a nearly unbroken series for
decades. Merchants used data from the “Bills” as
a rough gauge of the likelihood of their clientele
to flee to the countryside during epidemics.
Graunt studied this mass of data searching for
regularities. He is credited with being the first to
recognize that more males are born than females,
and that females have greater life expectation
than males. He also was one of the first to recognize the phenomenon of rural to urban migration.
He also developed a crude mortality table that
eventually led to the modern life table.
In addition to the above four substantive contributions, Graunt also set a precedent for one of
demography’s oldest traditions, namely, the thorough evaluation of data to learn the extent,
types, and probable causes of errors. P. Kraeger,
in “New Light on Graunt” (1988, Population Studies),
writes that he “carefully evaluated the bills for
their numerical consistency and reliability of compilation, and presented his evidence at length so
that his readers might judge it independently.”
Although Graunt died in obscurity, his lasting
monument is his Natural and Political Observations,
a book which to this day is a joy to read.
DUDLEY L. POSTON
grounded theory
Developed by Barney Glaser (1930– ) and Anselm L.
Strauss this theory, put forward in The Discovery of
Grounded Theory (1967), argues that sociological
research should be based on the close observation
of social life – participant observation, in-depth
interviews, and focus groups – to allow the experience of social life as understood by the actors
to emerge out of the data. This contrasted with
Talcott Parsons’s “grand theory” – in which the
sociologist derived hypotheses about social life at
his or her desk, and then gathered data to test them
according to the hypothetico-deductive method –
and with Robert K. Merton’s middle range theory,
which sought to examine ways in which specific
social structures (for example religious beliefs)
constrained individuals in their actions. For
Glaser and Strauss, sociology could not proceed
by deduction, nor did an independent social reality
or set of social forces exist apart from the individual and his or her interactions. Thus, grounded
theory aims to generate theory rather than to
verify it. Hence grounded theory was an important
early reaction to positivism in American sociology
and gave impetus to the resurgence of qualitative
research in sociology in the mid-1970s.
In what we might call the “strong version,”
grounded theory argued that sociologists should
grounded theory
group(s)
shed all preconceptions about social life before
entering the field and allow the data to shape their
developing theory. Moving between the data
and the explanation of what was going on – the
constant comparative method – was the only way
to produce valid sociological knowledge, which
would provide an adequate account of people’s
understanding of their social situation. Glaser
and Strauss developed a system for the close reading of interview and field notes. Open coding is
the initial sorting of the material to identify what
is going on in a given situation; axial coding is
drawing the different codes together and relating
them to each other; and, in the final stage, in
selective coding, one key category, the core, is
identified and ties all the others into it. In addition, they argued that sampling strategies should
be driven by the theoretical concerns that emerged out of the research (this contrasts with the
random sampling of the hypothetico-deductive
method). Once no new data were being found –
when the researchers had reached saturation in
data collection – then the writing-up of the study
could start. Ultimately the research should have a
practical outcome and a positive impact on the
subjects’ understanding of their situation and experiences. The problem with the strong version of
this theory is that, without pre-existing hypotheses, research data cannot be gathered or classified. A second problem is that, in the search to
provide an emic account (that is, one from the
subject’s perspective) of social reality, sociologists
would only reproduce and record the respondent’s
views and understanding of reality.
In subsequent developments, major differences
emerged between Glaser (Basics of Grounded Theory
Analysis, 1992) and Strauss (Strauss and Corbin,
Basics of Qualitative Research, 1990). While Glaser
remained committed to a qualitative account of
social life, emphasizing a flexible use of qualitative research methods, Strauss moved to codify
explicitly the steps researchers must take to
ensure that they were doing grounded theory. In
Strauss’s approach, the emphasis came to be based
more on traditional concepts of positivistic social
research, emphasizing generalizability, replicability, and theory verification. Glaser objected that
Strauss was “forcing” the development of theory
rather than allowing it to “emerge” from the data.
KEVIN WHITE
group dynamics
The group dynamics approach to small groups
research was perhaps the most influential attempt
to analyze the processual quality of group life. The
approach was first articulated by German émigré
Kurt Lewin (1890–1947) in the 1930s and 1940s,
and became institutionalized by Lewin, his students, and colleagues, notably at centers of small
group research, such as Michigan, Harvard, and
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, in the
1950s.
The group dynamics approach attempts to
examine the processes through which group activity occurs. The claim is memorialized in Lewin’s
famous equation, B = f(PE): behavior is a function
of personality and environment. Lewin treated the
relations of people within group settings using
the dynamics model of physics, and developed a
set of concepts – force fields, vectors, valence –
that detail this metaphor.
Lewin’s metaphor proved difficult to operationalize precisely and many subsequent experimental researchers used the label while jettisoning the
connections to physical forces. The group dynamics tradition was also enriched by Freudian theory,
as in the interaction process analysis work of
Robert Freed Bales, whose approach owed much
to both Sigmund Freud and the Parsonian tradition of the general theory of action. In all cases,
the group dynamics tradition attempts to incorporate theoretical models of larger units, bringing
them into the action arena of the small group. The
leading text treating the approach is the edited
collection of Dorwin Cartwright and Alvin Zander,
Group Dynamics: Research and Theory, first published
in 1953 at the height of the movement.
Today, remnants of the group dynamics tradition are evident in expectation states theory, as
it was developed at Stanford by Morris Zelditch,
Joseph Berger, and Bernard Cohen, who trained in
social psychology at Harvard during the heyday of
the group dynamics approach. Expectation states
bring in social categories from outside group life –
gender, social status, or race – examining how
they are exemplified in behavioral arenas.
GARY ALAN FINE AND KENT SANDSTROM
group(s)
The term group(s) is widely used within sociology,
and the social sciences. However, the referent of
the term may vary, according to whether or not
people interact as groups, or share a feeling of
group membership, or unity. Social scientists
have long recognized the distinction between “a
group defined by outsiders” which has no social
reality for its members and groups that have
social and psychological reality as such, for their
members. Henri Tajfel (1982, Annual Review of
255
group(s)
Psychology: 1–39) notes that there are two distinct
theoretical senses of the term:
(1) objective collections of similar individuals as
defined by outside observers, that is, objectively defined groupings that may be statistically significant to the researcher, but not
subjectively significant for their members
(that is, some sociological category, such as
single-income families in rural areas).
(2) groups defined as such by their members
through patterns of interaction and shared
representations, that is, a dynamic social process in which the capacity of people to represent themselves as members of social
categories is part of the process by which sociological categories may become meaningful
social groups.
Charles Horton Cooley’s distinction between “primary groups” and “secondary groups’ or nucleated groups is also a key distinction in sociology.
Primary groups are defined by close, face-to-face
interaction, unlike secondary or “nucleated
groups,” which tend to be larger and less congruent. Members of such groups (for example, political parties, and trade unions) are seldom in direct
contact, in contrast to members of primary groups
(for example, friendship networks, families) who
are in regular contact.
A further distinction may be made between
closed groups and open groups. This distinction
refers to the relative permeability of the boundaries of social groups. Open groups have relatively
permeable boundaries, and few barriers to interactions with outsiders, while closed groups have
impermeable boundaries, and have little interaction with outsiders. Thus, ostensibly similar
social groups (for example clubs or religious sects
(see church–sect typology) may be distinguished
by being either open or closed. Further, group
membership may be either ascribed and relatively
fixed (for example, by race and ethnicity, or
gender), with little possibility of movement out
of the group (save in cases of surgical reassignment, gender identity “disorder,” or divorce), or
relatively flexible, with the possibility of movement between groups (such as occupational
groups or nationalities).
Peer groups are collections of individuals who
define themselves, and are recognized by others,
as a distinct social group. Peer groups may also
define themselves through shared social characteristics such as age, gender, sexuality, occupation, or
ethnicity and ethnic groups. Such groups have
shared norms, culture, and rituals and socialize
new members according to these. Existing
256
group(s)
members may be excluded from the peer group
with reference to a breach of these group norms
and sanctions.
The dynamics of peer groups, and other face-toface groups, is the subject of both social psychology and sociology. Within sociology, notable
contributions to the study of group dynamics
have been made by Talcott Parsons (see, for
example, Family, Socialisation and Interaction Process,
1955, and Working Papers in the Theory of Action,
1953); within social psychology, Robert Bales
made significant foundational observations (see,
for example, Interaction Process Analysis: A Method for
the Study of Small Groups, 1950; and SYMLOG: A
System for Multiple Level Observation of Groups, 1979).
Pressure groups are a particular kind of social
group characterized by a common purpose – to
put pressure on governments and decisionmaking
bodies, and to influence public opinion, such that
their aims are supported. These aims may be
either for significant reforms to a current system,
or for the maintenance of the current or previous
status quo. Pressure groups may be distinguished
from other groups united in a common interest,
such as political parties, in that they aim to influence public opinion, and government decisions,
rather than to govern and make such decisions
per se. However, the relationship between pressure groups and political parties is often symbiotic, and certain pressure groups have close
relations with particular political parties – for
example, the relationship between the trade
unions and the Labour parties of Australia and
Britain; and the relationship between fundamentalist Christian groups and the Republican party
of the United States. Further, pressure groups may
develop into political parties – for example, the
Family First party in Australia – and enter into
politics and decision-making proper.
There are two general types of pressure groups –
broadly, “protective” and “promotional” groups.
This distinction is intended to highlight the divergent aims of some pressure groups. Protective
pressure groups are united in their aim to protect
existing and affiliated members of that group –
for example, trade unions and professional associations. By contrast, “promotional” groups seek to
promote a cause, rather than to defend a defined
group. Promotional groups include the RSPCA,
and other societies bound by a goal to promote a
cause – for example, environmental groups; proor anti-censorship groups; pro- or anti-choice
groups. However, this distinction is not always
clear-cut. Thus, professional associations have
joined with other groups in condemning prejudice,
Gurvitch, Georges (1894–1965)
Gurvitch, Georges (1894–1965)
war, and violence, for example; and the public in 1935. He spent the years of World War II in
interest lobby for an increase in the national minimum wage – a public cause – is a key task of the
trade unions in defending their members, and
others.
SUSAN HANSEN AND MARK RAPLEY
Gurvitch, Georges (1894–1965)
Born in Novorossisk, Russia, Gurvitch closely observed the Russian Revolution, met V. I. Lenin, and
knew Leon Trotsky (1879–1940). In 1917 he published a work on Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78)
and agrarian rights and became a lecturer at the
University of Leningrad. He was made a professor at
the University of Tomsk in 1919, but in 1920 he left
Russia. Between 1921 and 1924 he worked in the
Russian Department at the University of Prague,
and was particularly influenced by the work of
Johann Fichte (1762–1814). Indeed, in 1930 he
published in France Les Tendencies actuelles de la
philosophie allemande: E. Husserl, M. Scheler, E. Lask,
M. Heidegger. In 1925 he moved to France, and
became a lecturer at the University of Strasbourg
the United States, and his Déclaration des droits
sociaux (1944) was a socialist analysis of selfmanagement.
Returning to Strasbourg, Gurvitch edited
Twentieth-Century Sociology (1945) with Wilbert
E. Moore; although based in France, he was a
visiting professor in Brazil, Argentina, Japan,
Canada, North Africa, and the Near East, as well
as Europe. He was a passionate opponent of French
government policy during the Algerian war, and
founded the Centre d’Études Sociologiques. He
also created the journal Cahiers Internationaux
de Sociologie, and started the Bibliothèque de
Sociologie Contemporaine (Library of Contemporary Sociology). He was concerned with the preservation of the French language. He published La
Vocation actuelle de la sociologie in 1950, and in 1962
his most complete work, Dialectique et sociologie
appeared. He spent much of his time battling
over the question of dialectics. His Les Cadres
sociaux de la conaissance (1966) was published posthumously.
JOHN HOFFMAN
257
H
Habermas, Jürgen (1929– )
Often regarded as the most influential German
social theorist of the second half of the twentieth
century, Habermas belongs to the Frankfurt
School, a group of neo-Marxist intellectuals who
pursue a critical theory of society. Habermas
belongs to the so-called second generation of the
Frankfurt School; the first generation consists, for
instance, of Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno and
Max Horkheimer. He initially worked under Adorno’s supervision, but soon developed his own version of critical theory.
Habermas’s project differs from Adorno in a
number of respects. First, whereas Adorno’s critique was directed at the Enlightenment project,
Habermas emphasized its positive features. He
recognized the problematic nature of the current
sociopolitical constellation, but he insisted that
these problems were not intrinsic to modernity.
He argued for recognition of the liberating features of the shift towards modernity, and the central nature of these features to any critical theory.
Second, whereas Adorno’s notion of rationality
was still embedded in the “philosophy of consciousness,” Habermas sought to ground reason
in the intersubjective context of daily linguistic
usage. For this, he drew partly on the speech act
theory of J. L. Austin (1911–60) and partly on the
theory of psychological development of Lawrence
Kohlberg (1927–87), who published Stages of Moral
Development (1971).
The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere
(1962 [trans. 1988]) was Habermas’s first book,
and it already expressed his belief in the importance of unconstrained, open debate amongst
equals. He called this the ideal of a “discursive
will-formation.” Habermas argued that the emergence of bourgeois society made possible the potential for realizing this ideal. With the advent
of bourgeois society, a public sphere emerged:
people openly discussed political issues, which
appeared in newspapers and magazines. Modern
society has not fulfilled this potential, partly because of the way in which the content and role of
the media have changed. Several commentators
258
criticized Habermas for overestimating the existence of the public sphere in the nineteenth century. They pointed out that several sections of
society were excluded: notably working-class
people and women. Some feminist authors add
that the emergence of a private sphere for women
was constitutive of the public sphere for men.
In Knowledge and Human Interests (1968 [trans.
1971]) and other methodological writings, Habermas draws on the pragmatism of Charles Peirce
(1839–1914) to criticize positivism. Positivist epistemology tends to reduce knowledge to one type:
empirical-analytical knowledge, directed towards
technical control and prediction. Habermas insists
that other types of knowledge are also valid; they
simply aim at different cognitive interests. Interests
are “basic orientations” based in “fundamental conditions” of reproduction and self-constitution of
the human species. Besides empirical-analytical
knowledge, there is also hermeneutics and critical
theory. Whereas the empirical-analytical approach aims at nomological knowledge, hermeneutics insists on the qualitative differences between
the natural and the social sciences. Hermeneutic
authors insist that the main objective of the
social sciences is to provide understanding – to
make sense of different practices or cultural artifacts. Critical theory consists of a combination of
empirical-analytical and hermeneutic knowledge,
but it is ultimately directed neither towards control, nor towards understanding. Its main goal is
emancipation and critique. It seeks to question
what was previously taken for granted and it
intends to reveal and uplift psychological dependencies and sociological obstacles. Once these
are removed, emancipation becomes a realistic
political target.
In the early 1970s, Habermas turned his interest
towards the question of how governments are able
to find legitimacy within capitalism. In Legitimation Crisis (1973 [trans. 1975]), Habermas set out
to explain the problems capitalism faces. Capitalism tends to justify itself as a highly efficient
socioeconomic system; it avoids referring to
higher political, spiritual, or religious values. In
Habermas, Jürgen (1929– )
reality, however, capitalism faces recurrent economic problems. These economic crises are inherent to the capitalist mode of production. Because
capitalism justifies itself mainly in terms of instrumental rationality, these economic crises
easily lead to a “legitimation crisis.” Governments
find it difficult to sustain themselves in the light
of an economy of boom and bust, especially given
that their legitimacy relies on their ability to solve
technical, economic problems.
Towards the mid-1970s, Habermas developed a
growing interest in the accomplishments of the
linguistic turn in philosophy. This led to his theory
of universal pragmatics, which forms the core of
his Theory of Communicative Action (1981 [trans.
1984]). Central to his universal pragmatics is the
idea that, whenever people talk, they make a
number of validity claims. Validity claims are presuppositions such as intelligibility, truth, moral
rightness, and sincerity. For instance, when I explain to a student how to get to a lecture hall, it
is implicit in my account that the instruction is
intelligible and that it is correct – that is, it is the
right way to reach the lecture hall. Also implicit in
it is the assumption that I am morally justified to
provide it, and that I am being sincere – I am not
explaining the way in order to deflect attention
from something else. Habermas talked about undistorted communication in which people can
openly criticize each other (and openly defend
themselves) with regard to the validity claims.
Habermas coins the term ideal speech situation
for when there are no obstacles whatsoever in the
way of such an unconstrained debate. Although
the ideal speech situation never exists in reality,
it is a yardstick for a critical theory of society.
It allows the critical theorist to judge and
compare real settings and to criticize distorted
communication.
Habermas used this communication-based approach to tackle various issues. In The Philosophical
Discourse of Modernity (1985 [trans. 1987]) and The
New Conservatism (1985 [1989]), he defends Enlightenment principles against postmodernism and
conservatism. In Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (1983 [trans. 1990]) and Justification and
Application (1991 [trans. 1993]), he applied the
theory of universal pragmatics to the ethical
domain. Discourse ethics treats normative claims
like truth claims: they are considered as having a
cognitive meaning. Discourse ethics assumes that
the grounding of norms requires a dialogue. As
such, moral judgments are not simply conclusions
reached by isolated individuals (as in the formal
approaches), nor do they simply reflect social
Halbwachs, Maurice (1877–1945)
codes (as in the communitarian perspectives). In
Between Facts and Norms (1992 [trans. 1996]), Habermas took the position that legal and political
issues should not be left in the hands of the
experts. These issues should be subjects of an
open discussion, which includes as many people
as possible. In his proposal for a “discursive democracy,” norms are valid if they are accepted by
the individuals who are potentially affected by
these norms, and if this acceptance followed
procedures of communicative rationality.
PATRICK BAERT
habitus and field
Pierre Bourdieu’s sociology of structured inequality pivots on these two concepts. (See Bourdieu’s
“Structure, Habitus, Practices,” in his The Logic of
Practice, 1980 [trans. 1990].) Habitus, the more
widely known term, refers to a system of lasting
dispositions which integrate past and present perceptions, appreciations, and actions, and also facilitate the achievement of an open-ended array of
diversified tasks. It constitutes a component of a
field of objective relations, where the term objective signifies independent of the individual’s consciousness and will. The objectivity of fields is
provided by the distribution of different species
of power, which Bourdieu characterizes as economic, cultural, and social capital. To each field
corresponds a tacit struggle over these resources.
Fields determine relational positions which
impose present and future situations on their
more or less powerful occupants. A given population may occupy positions in multiple fields. Multiple fields may impose more or less consolidated
relations of domination and subordination.
For fields to operate there must be agents with
the appropriate habitus, which operates tacitly
(see David Swartz, Culture and Power, 1997). Like
Émile Durkheim, Bourdieu sees the dispositions
which constitute habitus as acquired in primary
socialization. The originality of the idea of habitus
stems from its positioning in fields of struggle.
This allows Bourdieu to investigate the tacit ways
in which the dominant perpetuate their own domination or, in Bourdieu’s terms, commit symbolic
IRA COHEN
violence on themselves.
Halbwachs, Maurice (1877–1945)
A French sociologist who was much influenced by
Émile Durkheim, but who modified and extended
the claims of the Durkheimian paradigm, Halbwachs was an accomplished social statistician,
and, in his book Les Causes de suicide (1930), he
introduced major new findings that Durkheim
259
Hall, Stuart (1932– )
missed. For example, suicide rates differ between
rural and urban communities, such that those in
more placid and religious rural settings have lower
suicide rates than those in densely populated
urban agglomerations. Halbwachs was also one of
the first French sociologists to write systematically
about the nature of social class. In his study of the
working class he showed that Friedrich Engels’s
Law, according to which low-wage groups spend
a larger proportion of their income on food than
other classes, applies far more widely. He argued
that perception of human needs is determined by
class position. His representation of the working
class, however, is too inflexible to be of much use
to contemporary class analysts.
Halbwachs’s most influential and innovative
work concerns collective memory where he goes
far beyond Durkheim’s concept of collective representations. Halbwachs’s thesis is that human
memory can only function within a collective context. He shows how collective memory is always
selective, and how various groups of people have
different collective memories which in turn give
rise to different modes of behavior. Halbwachs
was the first sociologist to stress the important
insight that memories of the past are essentially
reconstructions in the light of the present. His
work has important implications for contemporary studies of the role of collective memory (and
collective forgetting) in continuity and social
change.
JACKIE SCOTT
Hall, Stuart (1932– )
Born in Kingston, Jamaica, Hall migrated to the
United Kingdom in 1951 to study as a Rhodes
Scholar at the University of Oxford, and is widely
regarded as Britain’s leading public intellectual.
He is sometimes erroneously called “the father of
cultural studies.” Actually, he belongs to the
second “New Left” generation that took the cultural turn, following the mold-breaking work of
Richard Hoggart, C. L. R. James (1901–89), Raymond Williams, and Edward Thompson. Hall’s
contribution has been built upon a consistently
inventive and exhaustive reading of western Marxism, post-structuralism, post-colonialism, psychoanalytic theory, and feminism. He has combined
this with political activism and various media
contributions. Hall’s ideal for intellectual activity,
borrowed from Antonio Gramsci, is the organic
intellectual, who combines the latest cuttingedge ideas with effective political action.
In 1964 he was invited by Hoggart to join the
newly founded Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies, where he became Director
260
Haraway, Donna J. (1944– )
in 1974. In Birmingham, Hall’s work attempted
to fuse central elements from the thought of
Gramsci with the Marxism of Louis Althusser to
elucidate the interpellation of subjects under advanced capitalism and the unfolding crisis of the
“representative–interventionist” British nationstate (Hall et al., Policing the Crisis, 1978, and Hall
et al., On Ideology, 1978). This involved an ambitious
reformulation of the operation of ideology, hegemony, and normative regulation. Not the least
achievement in this respect was his encoding/decoding model of mass communications that purported to reveal how “preferred readings” of news
items are orchestrated in the process of political
and cultural reproduction. Hall’s work on the
crisis was based in a trenchant analysis of the
roots of welfare interventionism that he traced
back to the 1880s, and which he presented as a
constant “war of maneuver” designed to co-opt
the working class (Hall et al., Crises in the British
State, 1985).
Writing before the rise to power of the New
Right, Hall accurately predicted the drift towards
the “law and order” society and a form of democratic state control organized around authoritarian populism (The Hard Road to Renewal, 1988; Hall
and Martin Jacques, New Times? 1990). In 1979 he
was appointed Professor of Sociology at the Open
University, where he remained until 1997. Hall’s
later writings focused on questions of multiculturalism, new ethnicities, identity slippage, and
black aesthetics, raising a series of urgent questions about identity and belonging in the age of
globalization, but casting doubt on the political
realism of his project.
CHRIS ROJEK
Haraway, Donna J. (1944– )
A cultural theorist and scientist concerned with
the relations among humans, technologies, and
animals, Haraway, during her early career studying primate behavior, engaged in a number of
feminist debates, and published critical accounts
(Primate Visions, 1989) of the activities of her male
colleagues in the biosciences, ascribing to them
the behaviors they ascribed to primate bands,
such as competition, aggression, and the pursuit
of dominance. Her “A Manifesto for Cyborgs”, first
published in Socialist Review in 1985, has become
one of the three most cited articles in the humanities. In it she constructs a socialist-feminist
case against essentialist feminisms, those that describe femininity as an unchanging quality, often
with mystical connections. Instead, through the
use of the metaphor of the “cyborg,” she argues
for a feminist, hybrid cybernetic organism. This
health
health
imaginary creature (which nonetheless has some
practical existence, for example, in wearers of
pacemakers and contact lenses) is a construct
built from existing components. By analogy, new
genders may be constructed from the components
with which we are surrounded. Rather than embrace a mystical essence, Haraway recommends
building new identities: “I would rather be a
cyborg than a goddess.” Though her essays collected in Simians, Cyborgs and Women (1991) were
especially influential in the first generation of
critics responding to the emergence of the worldwide web in 1993 as they began to describe virtual
worlds and identities composed of material and
electronically constituted components, Haraway
herself pursued her interests in the life sciences
to produce significant critiques of genetic engineering techniques from socialist feminist perspectives (Modest Witness @ Second Millennium, 1997).
In her most recent work, she has begun a critique
of human–animal relations, initially through
an analysis of “companionate” (pet) animals and
the institutional discourses that surround them
(The Companion Species Manifesto, 2003).
SEAN CUBBITT
health
The sociology of health was originally known as
medical sociology, emerging as a specialized area
in the 1950s. “Sociology of health and illness” is
now the preferred term, suggesting a wider canvas
than the purely “medical,” though medical sociology is still often used for convenience. Despite its
youth – little more than half a century – it rapidly
became one of the most important of the subdisciplines of sociology, in terms of numbers of practitioners, volume of research, and specialized
journals.
In part, this is because of the recognition by
medicinal authorities of the importance of a sociological perspective on health and illness in helping
general practitioners to understand better their
interaction with patients. The subject is now
almost universally taught in medical schools and
in the education of nurses and other health
professionals.
Originally a distinction was made between sociology in medicine and sociology of medicine. The
first described the use of sociology in solving medically defined problems, such as the social distribution of disease (covered by social epidemiology),
the self-definition of illness which brought people
to seek medical help, and illness behavior. The
sociology of medicine is seen as less oriented to
the professional interests of medicine, and treats
the concepts of health and illness as problematic
and constructed. Medicine itself is studied as an
institution and practice, and there is concern with
the issue of power relations between doctors and
patients. The larger term, the sociology of health
and illness, defines the concept positively, and
includes not only the profession of medicine,
but also the whole range of caring occupations
and activities, and not only the identification,
treatment, and experience of illness, but also
health-related lifestyles and health as general
well-being.
What is called, in its stereotypical form, the
biomedical model has been the basic paradigm
of medicine since development of germ theory in
the nineteenth century. At the beginning of this
modern period, medicine was based almost entirely on the methods and principles of biological
science. Four postulates were seen as its basis:
(1) the doctrine of specific etiology, that is the
idea that all disease is caused by agents which are
at least theoretically identifiable – germs, parasites, trauma, bacteria. Ideally, the search is for
single causes;
(2) the assumption of generic disease, that is the
idea that each disease has its distinguishing features that are universal within the human species;
(3) the model of ill-health as deviation from the
normal, with health defined as equilibrium and
disease as a disturbance of the body’s functions;
(4) the principle of scientific neutrality, that is,
the belief that medicine adopts the values of objectivity and neutrality on the part of the observer,
and sees the human organism as the product of
biological or psychological processes over which
the individual has little control.
The actual practice of medicine, as knowledge
advanced and medical institutions became more
differentiated and complex, threw up many problems relating to these postulates. In his book Man
Adapting (1966), René Dubos (1901–82) asked, for
instance, why infection does not always produce
disease. It was realized that for many diseases
there are multiple and interacting causes, rather
than single ones. The principle of single causes is
more easily applicable to acute conditions and
infections than to the chronic diseases that
became more important in the twentieth century.
The assumption of generic diseases stumbled
against the realization that diseases are differently defined in different cultures, and medical
definitions are not simply a matter of advancing
knowledge but also of professional choice. Diseases tend to be those things which, at any given
time, medicine is able to treat or wishes to
261
health
treat. Deviation from the normal, though still a
foundation of much medical investigation and
categorization, is complicated by the fact that it
is often unclear where normal variation ends and
abnormality begins. What is defined as the
normal range (of body mass index, of lung function, of birth weight, of liver function, of blood
pressure, and so on) has to be a choice, even if it
is one which is scientifically informed. Finally,
scientific neutrality was questioned, since the institution of medicine is always embedded in the
larger society and subject to social, political, and
cultural pressures.
Residues of these postulates can be found in
modern medical practice. However, the advance
of science has directed attention to necessary
and sufficient rather than single causes, and biomedicine now stresses multiple and interactive
causes, including the state of the body’s own defenses. The rise of psychology was influential in
altering a purely mechanistic model of illness. The
medical model current in medical practice should
not be presented as separate or in opposition to
the social model of health.
The clearest dissatisfaction with the dominant
model offered by biomedicine arose around the
mid twentieth century. A mechanistic view of
human health, together with the rapid rise in
knowledge, had resulted in an ever-increasing
use of medical technologies. Dubos described the
Mirage of Health (1959), whereby we are led to believe that science can produce a utopia of diseasefree life: scientists look only for a “magic bullet.”
The American philosopher Ivan Illich (1926–2002),
in his Medical Nemesis (1976), argued that medical
practice had transformed the human condition
of pain, illness, and death and dying into merely
a technical problem. As a result, medicine had
prevented people from dealing with these threatening circumstances with autonomy and dignity.
Medicine had parodoxically created a new kind of
“unhealth” (1974, Lancet).
Anton Antonovsky, in Health, Stress and Coping
(1979), was influential in pointing out that this
means more attention to disease than to health –
“We do not ask about the smokers who do not get
lung cancer, the drinkers who stay out of accidents, the Type As who do not have coronaries” –
and advocated thinking “salutogenically,” that is,
focusing on what facilitates health, rather than
what causes or prevents disease.
The focus on stressors as causes of ill-health has
led to much study of the mechanisms and possible
buffers, such as coping resources and social support networks. This literature has shown clearly
262
health
that social integration is positively linked with
mental and physical health and with lower mortality. The most powerful form of support is intimate relationships, and emotional support can
provide protection against adverse life events.
Most recently this has been associated at the societal or group level with theories of social capital.
The concept of social or holistic health is more
than simply the recognition that social factors
such as poverty or behaviors have to be included
in any model of the causes of ill-health. It locates
biological processes within their social context,
and considers the person as a whole rather
than a series of bodily systems. It is organic rather
than mechanistic and reductionist. Human beings
are living networks formed by cognitive processes and purposive intentions, depending on
the meanings ascribed to bodily phenomena, not
simply machines.
The development of the social model has been
accompanied, among the public, by a growing
enthusiasm for alternative and complementary
therapies, which tend to be more holistic. These
have also been incorporated to some extent into
mainstream medicine. In the social model, health
is a positive state of wholeness and well-being,
associated with, but not entirely explained by,
the absence of disease or mental or physical impairment. The concepts of health and ill-health
are not simply opposites.
In 1948 the World Health Organization defined
health as “a state of complete physical, mental
and social wellbeing, and not merely the absence
of disease or infirmity,” and this is generally held
to epitomize the social definition of health. This
definition has been criticized as difficult to measure and impossible to achieve, and as promoting
the medicalization of all aspects of daily life. However, it draws attention to the holistic and socially
conscious definition of health which is most
favored in contemporary western societies and
medical systems.
Whether health is considered negatively, in
terms of disease, or positively, in terms of holistic
health, it is necessary to distinguish between objective and subjective health. In English-speaking
countries it is usual to give different meanings to
the words disease, illness, and sickness. Disease is
the medically defined pathology. Illness is the
subjective experience of ill-health. Sickness is the
social role of those defined as diseased or ill.
There are problems about this usage, since not
every language has equivalent words, but it has
value in emphasizing that these concepts are not
the same.
health
People may be ill, that is, feel themselves to
have something wrong with them, without
(known) disease. In the doctor’s office, the person
with an illness may be transformed into a patient
with a diagnosis, that is, a disease. It is possible to
be subjectively ill or to be medically diagnosed as
having a disease without adopting the role of the
sick person – that is, without assuming or seeking
permission to give up normal roles. People may
have a disease, or be injured or functionally incapacitated, without being ill or claiming to be sick. It
is very common, in surveys of self-defined health,
to find people with severe disability claiming that
their health is “excellent.” Moreover, it has been
noted that modern medicine produces many liminal states which are neither ill nor well – potentially ill, but at present well, in remission but not
cured, at known risk of disease which has not yet
developed. A commonly cited epigram is “disease
(and trauma) is what doctors treat, illness, is what
patients experience.” Though attractive, this is
somewhat facile: doctors do treat illness, even in
the absence of anything that can be diagnosed as
disease, and patients do subjectively perceive and
self-define disease.
The distinction between disease, illness and
sickness is paralleled by the usage, in the field of
disability studies, of the terms impairment, disability, and handicap, as promulgated by the
World Health Organization in their “International
Classifications” of disabling conditions.
In the early days of medical sociology, the
American sociologist David Mechanic, in his Medical Sociology (1968), defined illness behavior as the
way in which “symptoms are differentially perceived, evaluated and acted upon (or not acted
upon) by different kinds of people and in different
social situations.” The concept included, as well as
what Irving Zola called the pathway from person
to patient, the whole process of seeking help, including the “lay referral system.” Classic work,
particularly in the United States, mapped out the
way in which groups in society might differ in
their responses. The concept became extended to
include their perceptions of the illness and its
treatment, and their heath-promoting or healthharming lifestyles. Many models, largely variants
of the “health belief model” described by Irwin
Rosenstock (Health Education Monographs, 1974),
were used, especially in health psychology, to formalize the processes by which perceived illness is
translated into sickness, and offer explanations of
actions taken, or not taken, to promote health.
Certain disease labels carry with them public
stereotypes. More generally, in early medical
health
sociology the work of Talcott Parsons, defining
illness as a form of deviance which disrupted the
social system by interfering with normal role performance, gave rise (particularly in the United
States) to a body of theory analyzing illness as
deviance. Labeling theory was applied to the secondary deviation resulting from the identification
as being ill, especially for particular disease labels
such as epilepsy. Thomas J. Scheff, for instance, in
Being Mentally Ill (1966), claimed that labeling was
the single most important cause of the manifestations of mental illness. The work of Erving
Goffman on Stigma (1964) was also very influential. These concepts are still important in disability and impairment and are relevant in specific
conditions such as HIV/AIDS.
The psychological models of health beliefs and
behavior have, in more recent decades, been criticized as abstracted from social settings, and the
term illness behavior has become somewhat outmoded. Studies of the perception and experience
of illness, based on phenomenology and the
methods of qualitative research, are seen as moving
away from the medical model, and turning to the
patient’s perspective.
The influence of social constructionism has
become strong in the sociology of health, especially in many countries of Europe. It is argued
that medical knowledge is produced by and reflects the society in which it is found. What counts
as disease or abnormality is not given in the same
sense as a biological fact is given, but depends on
cultural norms and shared rules of interpretation.
It is, as the Polish medical philosopher Ludwik
Fleck (1896–1961) suggested, a product of the
“thought style” of a particular community of scientists and practitioners. In the version of constructionism most favored in the sociology of
health, it is not suggested that diseases and pathogens are not “real,” but that health is, like other
human experiences, at the same time a socially
constructed category. Much of the understanding
of how people act in illness began to come from
studies of groups suffering from particular
chronic conditions, including especially diabetes,
asthma, hypertension, heart disease, and epilepsy.
Self-regulation and control, and adjustment to
illness within a family and social context, are
prominent themes, as is illness as biographical
disruption, that is, the place of ill-health in the
lifecourse. Interest has increased in the analysis
of illness narratives, in which, as Arthur Frank
notably described in The Wounded Storyteller
(1995), individuals make sense of their experience
and create new identities.
263
health
The search for meaning, or the answer to what
the French social anthropologists Claudine Herzlich and Janine Pierret in Illness and Self in Society
(1987) called the “Why me? Why now?” question,
became a focus of research. Associated themes
are moral discourses of health, lay explanations
of disease, and particularly the question of selfresponsibility. An earlier, and more specifically
psychological, model of attitudes to health as
either “internal” (health as the outcome of individual behavior) or “external” (health as the consequence of outside influences or simply chance)
has, largely, been abandoned. Contemporary discussion still very much emphasizes the question
of agency and structure, however: the debate
about the extent to which people can, or feel
themselves able to, exercise individuality and
free will or are subject to various kinds of constraint. Max Weber had provided a theoretical
background for these discussions, distinguishing
the two concepts of life conduct and life chances.
The interplay of these is a dominant theme because of its practical and political importance
in the fields of health promotion and health
inequalities.
Relevant to this issue is the popular theme of
the commodification of health. This emphasizes
the range of dietary, leisure, slimming, and body
maintenance and decoration products which
modern commerce and culture provide, and the
emphasis on the young and fit body as a fashionable ideal.
Theorizing health as consumption owes much
to Pierre Bourdieu, who extended analysis to the
explanation of class and group differences in
health behavior. Individual practices are connected to culture and structure, and ultimately
to power, through the concept of habitus.
The consultation, as a basic unit of the interaction between health professional and patient,
is a topic of particular interest in the sociology
of health. A distinction has been made between
“doctor-centered” consultations, traditionally
paternalistic and controlled by the doctor, and
“patient-centered” ones, with greater patient involvement and a more mutual relationship. These,
and other suggested models, such as the consumerist relationship which may be applicable in
particular circumstances, can be appropriate to
different stages and types of illness. Different
patient characteristics are also shown to be associated with their willingness to assume a
participative role.
Within the earlier and more medical model,
there had been many studies of compliance, or
264
health
whether the patient accepts the doctor’s instructions or takes medication as prescribed. This approach, it was suggested, ignored the lay
meanings of medications, and their place in the
individual life, and the term adherence began to
be preferred, implying a more active, collaborative
activity. Non-compliance was demonstrated to be,
often, a rational response to experience. Concordance is an alternative term especially popular in
primary care, suggesting a course of action agreed
upon in negotiation between patient and doctor.
Doctors’ communication skills are an important
topic in teaching and in research, as are decisionmaking principles and practice, and the characteristics of health care systems which may affect
interaction and the outcome of consultations.
The role of patients in decisionmaking about
treatment is an active theme in contemporary
western health systems, since the right of patients
to be involved in making informed choices is an
increasingly promulgated value.
At a more theoretical level, the relationship of
health to social systems has always been one of
sociology’s major interests. Most of the significant
differences in health between countries and
groups within countries are not biologically inevitable, but bound up with the particular society,
its place and time, its politics, administration, and
health services. At the same time, the relationship
is reciprocal: the health of a population has economic consequences. Health is part of a society’s
capital. Two of the most influential founding theorists on the relationship of health and society
were Émile Durkheim and Parsons, offering “functional” models of society. Durkheim emphasized
the importance of societal structures, and norms
and processes which were outside the individual
but integrated them into the structure. In Suicide
(1897 [trans. 1951]) he used the example of rates of
suicide, developing a three-fold typology of egoistic, where the individual was detached from society; anomic, due to a state of normlessness; and
altruistic, a purposive choice. The prevalence of
this very individual act of suicide was shown to
be determined by ties to society. The concept of
anomie, in particular, proved of lasting importance in theories about health and society.
The American sociologist Parsons, influenced by
Durkheim and by Weber, as well as by early psychoanalytic theory, was concerned to explain
value consensus, social order, and stability. In
the major work The Social System (1951), using the
medical profession as a model, he analyzed the
needs of the system, expressed in the duties and
reciprocal entitlements of both doctor and
health
patient. For the doctor, the pattern variables of
universalism, performance, or achievement,
rather than ascription, specificity, and affective
neutrality, were appropriate. The rights, obligations, and privileges of the sick role described
the norms of being a patient. This ideal-type contract was what would, theoretically, identify medicine as functional in maintaining equilibrium in
society and maintaining social order.
However, structural functionalism lost influence as a theoretical position in the 1960s and
1970s. The emphasis on consensus seemed to favor
the status quo and the domination of the powerful, and the approach was found inadequate in the
explanation of change. Social conflict theory, with
its roots in Karl Marx, suggested that society was
not held together by shared norms and values, but
by those imposed by economically powerful
groups. Weber added that social differences are
based not only on economic factors, but also on
status and other forms of influence. Conflict
theory turned attention, especially, to the sources
of ill-health in the economic environment.
In the later decades of the twentieth century,
the power and pre-eminence of medicine as an
institution, combined with some disillusion
about the actual effects of increasingly hightech medical science, led to an emphasis on a
degree of conflict between the interests of
patient and of doctor, and on medicine as an
instrument of social control in society. The medicalization of society became a popular topic of
medical sociology.
A separate strand of theory relates to the relationship of economic development to health. This
turns attention from the possibly oppressive
effects of the system of medicine to its undoubted
positive successes, together with economic development, in prolonging life. Obviously, in the long
term, the health of populations increases with
economic development: even in the already developed nations, life expectancy at birth usually
still increases from one generation to the next. At
present, two or three years are added with each
decade that passes. The causes include not only
improving material standards of living, but also
changing disease patterns (especially the relative
disappearance of infectious disease), advances of
public health and hygiene, and the non-material
advances in, for instance, education associated
with economic progress. How much is due to the
advances of medical science or improvements in
health care is disputed. Once a certain state of
development has been reached, the proportion of
Gross National Product spent on medical care, or
health
the way in which care is organized, does not seem
to have any clear association with differences in
the longevity of populations.
Expectation of life has been markedly influenced by the steep fall in infant mortality in the
developed world, rather than by much extension
of life in old age: this fall has now reached a stage
where little more is possible. The possibility of
treating ever more diseases does, however, alter
the health profile of populations. The shift from
acute (infectious, commonly fatal) disease to
chronic (long-term, to be controlled rather than
cured) means that longer life may mean an increase in the actual experience of ill-health. This
has an effect on the burden placed on health
services.
A corollary of the political and economic view of
the relationship of health to social structure is
that capitalism necessarily creates inequalities between sections of populations. The minimization
or correction of these inequalities is a major concern of western health systems, and inequality in
health has been one of the most active areas of
research and discussion in medical sociology for
some three or four decades.
Obviously, simple equality in health is impossible to achieve in any society: differences associated with genetic inheritance, the geographic
environment, or pure chance (and of course age)
are part of the human condition. The patterning
of inequality shows that the issue is not related
only to the extent of economic deprivation, with
deficiencies in such things as food, living environments, or medical care. In effect, the term “inequality in health has come to mean a special
sort of difference – that difference between individuals or groups which is: socially determined,
rather than due to biological factors; felt to be
unjust and inequitable, and not the individual’s
own responsibility; held not to be inevitable,
that is, it could, with current technologies and
knowledge, be alleviated.
Thus the concept of equality in western societies is highly constructed and dependent on the
progress of science and on ethical positions. It is
more than equity of health-service provision,
though “equality of provision for equal need” is
a common way in which policy tries to find a
services-relevant description.
The measures of equality most often used are
rates of death or life expectancy. Since life expectancy at, say, age 65 and at birth may be differently
patterned, years of healthy life, or potential years
of life lost (PYLL) before the age of 70, are measures
which can be used. Inequalities may also be
265
health
measured in absolute terms (simple differences
between two groups) or in relative terms (for instance, the ratio of death rates in the lowest social
group to those in the highest). The latter may
appear to exaggerate inequality if rates are low.
Approaches to the problem of inequality in
health vary widely throughout the world. In lowincome countries, the causes may clearly be material and the urgent questions may be political
and economic ones, including the provision of
health care. A strong emphasis on equality of
access is also found among some of the wealthiest
nations, such as the United States, with largely
privatized health services. Countries with large
ethnic or indigenous groups may also be particularly concerned with the health care of different
races.
In the United Kingdom there has been a tradition of public concern about unequal health ever
since the mid nineteenth century, when pioneers
such as Edwin Chadwick (1800–90) described the
living conditions of the poor and noted their low
expectation of life. Concern about inequality
remained in the early years of the twentieth century, and was offered as one major justification
for the setting up of the National Health Service in
1948, following the Beveridge Report of l942. The
rediscovery of inequality was marked by the
Report of the United Kingdom Department of
Health (known as the Black Report) in 1980, and
in the following decades many other countries,
especially those of western Europe, took up the
issue, and the theme was one of those around
which the World Health Organization has based
its strategies.
The field has been primarily occupied with
understanding why differences linked with socioeconomic status arise, persist, and even grow
greater. In Europe, it has been usual to rely on
occupation-based measures of social class to demonstrate this. In the United Kingdom this classification has been used, sometimes collapsed into
the two classes of manual and non-manual, for
almost a century, to measure differences by class
in mortality rates. Increasingly, however, the classification scheme is seen to have problematic features in modern society, and others are being
developed for the purpose of health statistics.
The experience of illness health also varies by
social class, though not as strongly or as regularly
as mortality. Other dimensions of inequality in
health include ethnicity and region. Certain
regions within countries show consistent health
disadvantages over others, associated with, but
in addition to, their economic or social class
266
health
composition. Everywhere, minority or migrant
ethnic groups tend to show higher rates of many
sorts of ill-health than the native population.
Two aspects of the statistics on inequality have
attracted particular attention in recent decades.
One is that, measured by social class and by death
rates, inequality appears to be growing in many
developed nations. The second issue relates to
what is known as the “continuous gradient” or
“fine grain” of inequality. The “threshold model,”
suggesting that inequality only occurs at a level of
deprivation below which health is likely to be
affected, does not seem to be correct: there is no
sharp discontinuity between the minority who
lack the basic needs of life and the majority whose
living conditions meet at least minimum standards. Rather, a straight line relationship between
socioeconomic status and health is found
everywhere.
The main issue of debate in inequality studies is
about causality, and especially causes of the apparent increase in inequality in developed countries.
The 1980 Black Report in the United Kingdom
discussed three types of explanation of real inequalities, if the social class differences were not,
as is generally agreed, simply artifacts of statistics
and the changing composition of social classes
over time. These explanations were: natural and
social selection and mobility (the healthy move up
the social scale and the unhealthy suffer occupational disadvantage); the lifestyles and healthrelated habits typical of particular groups (in particular smoking, or general lack of health awareness or preventive behavior); the direct materialist
effect of living and working conditions.
It is now generally agreed that the types of
explanation are interconnected, and each makes
a contribution. Simple models stressing only the
importance of behavioral patterns, for instance,
have to allow for the fact that lifestyles depend
on social relationships and the cultures of areas
and of groups. Cohort studies, following populations from the day of their birth, have demonstrated in Britain and in other countries how the
causes of unequal health begin at birth or even
before, and can accumulate through the lifecourse. A poor start in life, associated with poorer
family circumstances and vulnerability to illness,
can be reinforced throughout childhood by inadequacies in education and thus lower adult socioeconomic success, less healthy behavior, and
poorer health.
This overview has shown that the sociology of
health and illness is multifaceted, ranging from
the statistical to the qualitative and philosophical,
health
and from concern with social structures and historical processes to individual experience and
social psychology.
Subspecialities flourish, some with their own
institutions and journals. Some of the most
important topics have been noted, but others include: the sociology of nursing and the professions
allied to medicine; social pharmacy; the sociology
of mental health; media and cultural studies of
medicine and health; community care; death
and dying; the sociology of reproductive behavior
and the social epidemiology of fertility; health
promotion; and health service organization and
evaluation.
Discourses of risk are pervasive in health, as in
other areas of life. Risk assessment is a key element of public health, and the perception and management of voluntary risks to health, and the
relative importance of lifestyle factors and environmentally and socially imposed risks, are central
questions of health promotion. Expert and lay
concepts of health risk are a topic of particular
sociological interest, and Ulrich Beck’s Risk Society
(1986) [trans. 1992] has been influential in discussions of attitudes and responses to global ecological, genetic, nuclear, and economic risks to
health.
Currently, sociological research and discussion
focuses especially on the consequences of the explosive rate of change and development in medical science and technology. Techniques such as
microsurgery and nanotechnology (technology at
the level of molecules), and new technologies of
imaging, change attitudes to the body. It has been
argued that the image is becoming privileged over
the actual body: simulations have come to constitute reality. Other technologies which are
changing the practice of medicine relate to the
information revolution. Telemetry (the transfer
of measurements at a distance) and telemedicine
(distant, or even automated, contact between patient and professional), alter the doctor–patient
relationship.
The application of genetics is a very important
topic. There is, for instance, much discussion of
predictive genetic testing for disease as an ethical
issue, how it is perceived by the public, and what
changes it may bring to medical practice, family
life, and social relationships. Developments in reproductive technology call into question when a
new life commences. Technologies such as in-vitro
fertilization, cloning, surrogate motherhood or
the use of fetuses for genetic therapy raise questions about the family and person-hood. At the
end of life, modern techniques of keeping alive,
health care systems
especially in the context of transplant surgery,
blur the boundaries between life and death. The
replacement of body parts, including xenotransplantation (where animals are bred to carry genes
from another species) and stem cell technology
(which is capable of supplying transferable tissue),
also blur the distinction between the body and
not-body and call human identities into question.
The integration of machine parts into the body is
sometimes called cybermedicine.
MILDRED BLAXTER
health care systems
Health care can be divided into primary care,
taking place in the community as a point of first
contact, and secondary care, usually taking place
in hospitals and delivered by specialists. The term
tertiary care is sometimes used to indicate rehabilitation, or restorative rather than curative
care. Community care is used to indicate care
provided outside institutions, not only by doctors
but also by social carers. Preventive care systems
(such as immunization) are also distinguished
from curative care. A distinction is also made between personal clinical health care, provided for
the cure or care of the individual, and public
health, directed at populations.
The ways in which health care is organized, in
different societies, range from the extreme of a
pure market system in which health is treated as
any other commercial commodity, to universal
free services provided entirely by governmental
funding. In most nations of the world, however,
the distinction is becoming increasingly blurred.
Patterns of health provision are converging, because aging populations, changing disease patterns, advances in biotechnology, growing public
expectations, and increasing costs, all introduce
common pressures. Market systems have to make
provision for those who cannot pay, as in the
Medicare for old people or Medicaid for the poor
in the United States. In wholly or predominantly
state-organized systems, there is a tendency to
shift some costs onto the consumer, and introduce
types of rationing. In order to gain some of the
advantages of a market system, “free at the point
of need” services may introduce elements of managed competition, separating the funding of services from their supply while retaining universal
access, as in the internal market of the British
National Health Service.
In most systems, insurance of various forms acts
as the buffer between provider and consumer.
Health insurance is commonly obtained through
employers’ schemes, and in some countries these
267
health inequalities
hegemony
are compulsory. Insurers can limit consumer
choice by cost-contained health services, as in the
Health Maintenance Organizations of the United
States.
In recent decades, all industrialized nations
have tried to reform health care. Growth in expenditure, commonly exceeding growth in Gross
Domestic Product, has created a heightened interest in efficiency and effectiveness. There is also
general interest in increasing patient choice and
public participation in the organization of services. A further factor in change is some dissatisfaction about the priority given, in the past, to
hospital services at the expense of community
care and public health.
However, a wide range of international studies
(notably from the regular publications of the
World Health Organization and the Organization
for Economic Cooperation and Development) suggest that the way in which services are organized,
and indeed the level of provision, have little effect
on the health status of populations, once a country has reached an advanced stage of development. This is not because medical services are
ineffective, but is thought to be due to the overwhelming weight of other, principally economic
and social, factors. Nevertheless, the equity and
efficiency of services, patterns of patient usage,
and medicine as an institution, are important
topics within the sociology of health.
MILDRED BLAXTER
health inequalities
– see health.
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
(1770–1831)
Born in Stuttgart, the son of a government clerk,
Hegel studied theology at the university in Tübingen, working as a private tutor in Berne and
Frankfurt, before becoming a university lecturer
at Jena, a post he held until 1807.
It was here that he published The Phenomenology
of Mind (1807 [trans. 1931]) – a work generally
regarded as his masterpiece, in which he argued
that the power of reason itself is unlimited. While
reality is the entire development of everything, it
consists ultimately of a world soul or mind. In The
Science of Logic (1812 [trans. 1929]), which he published in 1812, he elaborated upon the dialectical
categories through which this absolute reality
passes.
He edited a newspaper during the Napoleonic
occupation and was headmaster at a school in Nuremburg until 1816. Hegel was appointed Professor
268
at the University of Heidelberg for two years in
1816, and then acquired the Chair of Philosophy
in Berlin that he held until his death in 1831.
He published the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical
Sciences in three volumes (1817, 1827, and 1830
[trans. 1927–30]), and his lectures on history, philosophy, and religion were published posthumously. But arguably his most important work
was The Philosophy of Right, which appeared in
1821 (trans. 1942). Here he built upon his earlier
philosophical work to argue that the modern state
is an ethical entity. The state incorporates the
altruism of the family and the self-interestedness
of civil society, and its universal outlook is guaranteed by a hereditary monarch, by an assembly
representing social interests, and by a civil service
that constitutes a “universal class.” Hegel’s philosophy of history had a profound influence on the
sociology of Karl Marx.
JOHN HOFFMAN
hegemony
The process by which a ruling group secures the
consent of the ruled, this term is identified with
the Italian Antonio Gramsci. Writing in prison
under Benito Mussolini (1883–1945), Gramsci
employed an idiosyncratic vocabulary to avoid
censorship. However, this term proved a viable
alternative to the more commonly used term
ideology, because it describes a process rather
than a result of rule. Faced with the question,
“Why has the Italian working class accepted fascist rule?” Gramsci outlined a process of negotiation between rulers and ruled. To secure power,
rulers may use coercion, but to maintain it they
require the active participation of the ruled in the
processes of economic and, in many instances,
civil life.
With the exception of periods of revolutionary
activity, societies are characterized by dynamic
equilibria in which, normally, one hegemonic
group holds sway over several subaltern groups.
Subaltern groups may be formed from the residues of a previously hegemonic social class or
classes, from newly emergent social groups such
as the proletariat that emerged during the industrial revolution, or from class fractions striking
alliances either against some abuse of power
or to gain a particular goal. Hegemony passes
through cycles of emergence, establishment, renewal, and decline, and the hegemonic process
will necessarily involve alliances and therefore
compromises with groups outside the hegemonic
class itself. Typical alliances struck by Mussolini’s
fascist party included those with the Catholic
Church, with residues of semifeudal landowners,
heredity
heredity
with the military, with the civil-service bureaucracy based in Rome, and with some elements of
the skilled working class, all in the interests of the
industrial bourgeoisie of northern Italy. Compromises included recognition of religious values,
protection of inherited property rights, extensive
military expeditions and budgets, and enhanced
employment prospects.
Gramsci’s term was initially specific to the political life of society. The word was taken up, after
Gramsci’s notebooks were translated as Selections
from the Prison Notebooks in 1971, in British cultural
studies. In the Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies especially, cultural life
could be examined as a dynamic equilibrium in
which mass media offered entertainment in exchange for loyalty to the nation and a sense of
belonging. At the same time, television and popular music provided subaltern groups with the
means to assemble alternative and competing
subcultures. In certain instances, these subcultures served the purposes of hegemony by encouraging disaffected school students to opt for lowpaid employment. In others, cultural resistance
formed social bonds that allowed emergent subaltern groups, such as black Britons, to articulate
their social and political interests. The concept of
rule as dynamic equilibrium also served as a
powerful analytical tool in analyses of education
policy, sports studies, and gender studies. A more
political variant appeared in the Indian journal
Subaltern Studies, notably in analyses of the way
in which Hindi nationalist histories of the
struggle for independence from Britain subordinated non-Hindi and working-class achievements,
in the interests of securing the postindependence
hegemony of the ruling bloc. Similar concerns
engage the Latin American Subaltern Studies
Group. The theoretical turn of cultural studies in
the 1990s displayed some return to ideological
determinism, in Gayatri Spivak’s query in her article “Can the Subaltern Speak?” from Cary Nelson
and Lawrence Grossberg (eds.), Marxism and the
Interpretation of Culture (1988), rather than a dynamic process of ideological exchange. Some of
the most trenchant contemporary scholarship
describes hegemony as that which is taken for
granted, uncontested, and unnoticed in social
life, leaving ideology to describe the active contests
over meaning and interpretation.
SEAN CUBBITT
heredity
This incorporates the idea that characteristics
such as intelligence, strength, or criminality have
a biological basis and can be transmitted between
generations. Some versions, following the pre-Darwinian biologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–
1829), suggest that acquired characteristics can
be inherited. The idea was highly influential in
early forms of sociology, such as the social Darwinism promoted by William Sumner and Herbert
Spencer, the latter emphasizing transmission of
acquired characteristics. Heredity remains significant today in the social sciences, though it is
widely considered an ideology justifying the social
order as natural. There is still no evidence of
genes directly affecting intelligence or behavioral
characteristics.
In 1865 a Moravian monk, Gregor Mendel
(1822–84), established the key principles of genetics. He discovered that when plants are crossed
the outcome is not simply a blending of characteristics. Discrete characteristics are passed on down
the generations, resulting in, for example, a
purple plant transmitting inherited white characteristics from future to later generations. Some
twenty years later, though not having encountered Mendel’s work, Charles Darwin’s cousin
Francis Galton (1822–1911) coined the term eugenics, derived from the Greek “good in birth.” This
new science appeared to show that intellectual
success runs in families; the Galton, Darwin, and
Wedgwood families, for example, producing a
relatively large number of offspring that were
“brilliant.” Such insights led to proposals for the
active management of human reproduction. This
would favor the reproduction of the fittest and
discourage the reproduction of the less fit.
The new science received widespread support
(including encouragement from a broad range of
political opinion) during the late nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries. Some branches of contemporary social science incorporate, at least
tacitly, a notion of heredity as the basis of social
structure. R. Herrnstein and C. Murray’s The Bell
Curve (1994) was, for example, highly influential
and generated considerable debate among those
exploring links between genes and intelligence
(see, for example, R. Sternberg and E. Grigorenko,
Intelligence, Heredity and Environment, 1997).
As a political practice, eugenics reached its most
horrific conclusion with the Nazi mass extermination of the Jews. The killing of thousands of
Croats and Muslims by a Serbian elite in the early
twenty-first century shows that eugenics persists
as an idea. But, despite its deeply sinister history,
it would be wrong for sociologists to completely
reject biological understandings of heredity.
There is, for example, some evidence of genes
269
hermeneutics
generating predispositions to certain afflictions,
such as Huntington’s disease and cystic fibrosis.
And some biologists – for example, E. Steele, R.
Lindley, and R. Blanden in Lamarck’s Signature
(1998) – claim that certain forms of immunity
(even acquired immunity) can be genetically transmitted. Meanwhile, more mainstream epidemiological work – for example, D. Barker in The Best
Start in Life (2004) – is showing that bad health can
indeed be inherited, but as a result of undernutrition in utero, rather than the passing on of specific genes. Genes, according to this literature, are
important in terms of governing overall developmental processes. Illnesses are mainly a product of
environment, especially as encountered in the
earliest stages of life, combined with genetically
driven processes of development. P E T E R D I C K E N S
hermeneutics
The art of interpretation, hermeneutics was originally meant to adjudicate disputes concerning the
authenticity of religious texts. Later, its role was
extended to a method or set of tools that help to
understand writing in general. Later, again, hermeneutics dealt with the understanding of any
type of human action – not just writing.
In the nineteenth century, hermeneutics
became a prominent philosophical tradition in
Germany with central figures like Friedrich
Schleiermacher and Wilhelm Dilthey. Influenced
by Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), Herder, and
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, hermeneutic
authors emphasized the differences between the
study of historical, social phenomena and the natural sciences. The former deal with the understanding (Verstehen) of unique events, whereas
the latter aim at explaining (erklären) and generalizing. The reliving (Nacherleben) of people’s aims
and assumptions is crucial in the understanding
of historical phenomena. The nineteenth-century
hermeneutic authors became involved in the wellknown Methodenstreit over the method of the
historical sciences. Influenced by positivist views,
the opposite camp advocated a unity of method
between the social and the natural sciences. Max
Weber was influenced by hermeneutics but took a
balanced view in the debate. For Weber, social
scientists need to rely on Verstehen (or “interpretative understanding”) but this re-enactment of
individuals’ purposes and assumptions does not
exclude the possibility of causal analysis. He was
also skeptical of the view that the emphasis on
understanding makes history or social science a
hopelessly subjective endeavor. Although historians and social scientists always adopt a selective
270
hidden curriculum
viewpoint, this does not make their research less
objective.
Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Truth and Method (1960
[trans. 1975]) heralded a major shift in philosophical hermeneutics. Influenced by Martin Heidegger, he criticized Enlightenment philosophers for
failing to acknowledge the pivotal role of tradition. In contrast with nineteenth-century hermeneutics and its emphasis on methods, Gadamer was
more preoccupied with ontology. He suggested
that we conceive of understanding in a dialogical
fashion: we cannot help but rely on our presuppositions to make sense of what we encounter, but
the very same presuppositions are also affected by
this interaction. In Philosophy and the Mirror of
Nature (1980), Richard Rorty refers extensively to
Gadamer’s dialogical model to back up his notion
of an edifying philosophy beyond epistemology.
For a long time, social scientists ignored the
importance of hermeneutics, especially in the heyday of structural functionalism. Since the 1970s
sociologists have shown a growing interest in interpretative philosophies, including hermeneutics. Anthony Giddens’s New Rules of Sociological
Method (1976) and Zygmunt Bauman’s Hermeneutics
and Social Science (1978) were crucial in drawing the
attention of social scientists to hermeneutics. In
Constitution of Society (1984), Giddens suggests that
the way forward is the structuration theory, an
attempt to integrate interpretative philosophies
with structuralism. Structuration theory conceives
of social order as continually produced by “knowledgeable” individuals in everyday settings. In
Knowledge and Human Interests (1968 [trans. 1971]),
Jürgen Habermas demonstrated the importance of
hermeneutics to critical theory: his notion of
critical theory draws on a combination of empirical-analytical knowledge (directed towards prediction and control) and hermeneutics (directed
towards understanding) and is ultimately aimed
at self-emancipation.
PATRICK BAERT
hidden curriculum
In 1971 B. R. Snyder published The Hidden Curriculum, containing a chapter by the American sociologist of higher education, Martin Trow, on
“distraction and the expropriation of learning.”
Snyder’s book was the outcome of research in
which, as a student of psychiatry, he investigated
in the early 1960s “the paths that students followed
during four years at the Massachusetts Institute of
Technology.” His findings were also informed by his
subsequent experience as a senior administrative
officer in a university. This was a period in the
history of American higher education in which
historical materialism
the system seemed to be dominated by regulation
and bureaucracy, associated with a technocratic
model of education and with credentialism. In a
context of precise regulatory control, Snyder
argued that students adopt coping mechanisms
which involve acting on the basis of their calculations of what is actually required to succeed and
secure accreditation rather than what is officially
required. These mechanisms involve restricting
study only to those elements of curricula which
are assessed and also ensuring that extra-curricular behavior is socially or politically acceptable
to the institution. Trow’s argument suggested
that similar circumstances push staff towards
equally “instrumental” rather than “expressive”
behavior. Snyder argued that acknowledging the
operation of a hidden curriculum recognizes
social and cultural factors in learning ignored
by rational planners. Arguably, subsequent higher
education reforms have sought to make the
hidden curriculum more visible and have thus
subjected the informal in teaching and learning
to more insidious regulation.
DEREK ROBBINS
historical materialism
Materialism and idealism offer two contrasting
ways of understanding the social world. The
former emphasizes the causal primacy of material
forces such as climate, technology, economic resources, and the institutional arrangements
within which they are organized and applied.
The latter emphasizes the primacy of ideas and
the meanings given by human actors to their
actions. Historical materialism, associated with
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, is a particular
form of materialism designed to account for
long-term processes of social change across time.
It was first articulated during the 1840s, in The
German Ideology. German idealism, as reflected in
the work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and
his successors, had seen historical development as
the progressive realization of the ideas of reason
and freedom in human activities. This position
was criticized for ignoring the differing material
contexts within which individuals lived, the
changing patterns of power and exploitation built
into human institutions, and social conflicts between exploiting and exploited social classes evident through time. Meanwhile, existing forms of
materialism were generally ahistorical and often
contemplative in function.
For Marx, the agenda for social theory was both
to understand and to change the world. This required an activist materialism, in which human
actors helped make the world and emancipate
historicism
humankind from exploitation, though not
through the simple imposition of progressive or
utopian ideas on the conditions of social existence.
The task was rather to bring ideas into harmony
with material possibilities. This shifted the burden
of human emancipation from philosophers to
exploited social classes whose interest lay in overcoming the forms of material exploitation in
which they lived.
Within historical materialism the mode of production is the key concept through which the
material conditions of existence are articulated.
This includes two main elements: the productive
forces, such as technology, and the social relations
of production, referring to the prevailing form of
property rights in human labor and other economic resources. Such rights included slavery,
feudal land tenure, and the capitalist wage-labor
relationship. Under the capitalist mode of production, the exploited working class would be the
bearer of social change through class conflict
leading to a socialist and communist future, where
labor and property were owned in common.
Historical materialism has received significant
criticism, and has been subject to revision and
reformulation from those more sympathetic to
the underlying project. Critics such as Max Weber
argued that the approach offers far too crude an
approach to the interaction of material and ideal
elements in social change, as well as downplaying
the motivating role of ideas, as proposed in
Weber’s Protestant ethic thesis on some origins
of the spirit of modern capitalism. Historical materialism also overemphasizes class institutions
and class struggle over other social cleavages,
and downplays the autonomy of political institutions and structures of legitimate domination.
Capitalism, meanwhile, has proven far more
robust, a reflection in part of periodic surges of
productive new technology, and in part of
working-class incorporation into consumer society.
Attempts to reformulate historical materialism
to take these trends into account remain haunted
by the failure of material existence to restructure
social consciousness in ways that generate revolutionary struggle rather than social passivity.
ROBERT HOLTON
historicism
Deriving from the German historismus, this concept has two broad meanings. First, it refers to
the belief that social structures, events, and texts
should be understood within the context of their
historical formation and the social conditions
within which they arose. Every age and each
271
Hochschild, Arlie Russell (1940– )
Hoggart, Richard (1918– )
historical situation, it is argued, can only be
understood in its own terms. The applicability of
the concept is usually restricted to the social sciences and humanities. In contrast to an emphasis
on ahistorical universalist assumptions or nomothetic forms of explanation, which are used in the
natural sciences, the focus is, as Friedrich Meinecke (1862–1954) argues, on the essential individuality, contingency, and uniqueness of social
phenomena. This has two implications: (1) since
events are unique and there is no independent
means for comparing phenomena, this implies a
form of relativism; (2) that in order to understand
social phenomena a form of empathetic, hermeneutical understanding, or what W. Dilthey and
Max Weber call Verstehen, is required. For Karl
Mannheim in “Conservative Thought” in his Essays
on Sociology and Social Psychology (1952) the origins
of the term historicism, and a stress on historical
explanation, have their roots in the conservative
and Romantic reaction to the Enlightenment, especially in Germany in which a dynamic historical
philosophy of life confronted a static philosophy
of reason.
Second, the term has been employed by Karl
Popper to designate explanations of the social
world which advocate fixed long-term laws of historical development and argue for their predictability. For Popper, the chief exponents of such a
misconceived view were Plato, Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich Hegel, Auguste Comte, Karl Marx,
Oswald Spengler (1880–1936), and Arnold Toynbee
(1889–1975). He argued that such views of historical inevitability were imbued with totalitarian
overtones and were, in addition, unscientific.
STEVEN LOYAL
Hochschild, Arlie Russell (1940– )
Hochschild received her undergraduate degree
from Swarthmore College and, in 1969, her PhD
in sociology from the University of California,
Berkeley. She joined the Berkeley faculty in 1971,
and is currently Professor of Sociology. She has
made significant contributions to the sociology
of the family and gender, and to social psychology.
In The Managed Heart (1983), she develops the
notion of emotional labor. According to Hochschild, in the increasingly service-oriented economy of the postindustrial world, more and more
occupations require that emotion be a part of the
service offered. Emotional labor demands that the
worker produce an emotional state in another
person, as workers in jobs from waiting tables to
flight attendants are increasingly called upon to
create good feelings in their customers. Moreover,
272
the employer increasingly exercises a great degree
of control over his/her employee’s emotions.
Hochschild has also explored the intersection of
work and women (see women and work), gender,
and family as an increasing number of American
women enter the workforce outside the home. In
The Second Shift (1989), she shows that women are
still responsible for housework and child-care, the
“second shift,” even if they work outside of the
home. In The Time Bind (1997), she demonstrates
that, often, family-friendly policies enacted by corporations fail because people are becoming more
comfortable with their work life, finding home
life increasingly hectic. In particular women
have little “quality time” to spend with their families. Hochschild’s most recent research documents the difficult plight of immigrant care
workers in the United States. K E N N E T H H . T U C K E R
Hoggart, Richard (1918– )
A lecturer in English at the University of Leicester
(1959–62) before gaining the Chair in English at
Birmingham University (1962–73), he founded the
influential Birmingham Centre for Contemporary
Cultural Studies in 1964. He left in 1971 to become Assistant Director-General of UNESCO and
Warden of Goldsmiths College, University of
London (1976–84).
Hoggart’s origins betray and compromise much
about his position on the register of cultural
theory. His hometown was Leeds, and the
working-class districts of Chapeltown and Hunslet
supplied the data and inspiration for his most
famous book, The Uses of Literacy (1957). In its day,
this volume was a much-lauded work. Progressive
sections in both the media and the redbrick universities regarded it as holding a set of refreshing
insights into working-class life, not least the injunction to take working-class culture seriously.
Today, it is chiefly regarded as a somewhat nostalgic, impressionistic, introspective study, that
retains its place in the canon for its historically
important, unapologetic insistence that workingclass culture matters.
This is unjust. In founding the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies at the University of
Birmingham with a self-ordained tripartite brief
to study the historical-philosophical, literary-critical, and sociological aspects of culture, and
gaining private funding from Sir Allen Lane of
Penguin Books to finance the project, there is
reason to claim that Hoggart made a seminal contribution to the development of Cultural studies,
especially in the two volumes of Speaking To Each
Other (1970 and 1972). Further, he turned the
Homans, George Caspar (1910–1989)
rejection of the elitist view of Mathew Arnold and
F. R. Leavis – that culture is the best that can be
thought and done – into a cause célèbre. Against
this, his revisionist approach sought to recognize
that important new cultural forms were emerging
around media culture and to honor the value of
non-elite cultures.
His work emphasized the policy dimension of
Cultural studies, for example in The Future of Broadcasting (with Janet Morgan, 1982), British Council
and the Arts (with others, 1986), and The Idea of
Europe (1987). With deep roots in adult education,
Hoggart made a virtue of unostentatious, practical criticism and forms of cultural theory
based in realistic involvement with society and
culture. This emphasis is now associated with
anti-theoretical overtones in his work.
CHRIS ROJEK
Homans, George Caspar (1910–1989)
Between 1939 and 1941, Homans taught sociology
at Harvard, then served for four years as a naval
officer, and finally returned to Harvard where he
made significant contributions to exchange
theory in The Human Group (1950), Social Behavior:
its Elementary Forms (1961), Sentiments and Activities
(1962), and The Nature of Social Science (1967). He
became a full Professor of Sociology at Harvard
between 1955 and 1980. He was elected to the
National Academies in 1972. He was 54th President of the American Sociological Association
and his presidential address was published as
“Bringing Men Back In” (1964) in the American
Sociological Review, in which he argued that social
phenomena are to be explained in terms of the
characteristics of individuals rather than social
structures. Homans developed a range of propositions that draw on social psychology to examine
the ways in which individuals are connected to
social groups. These propositions (relating to success, stimuli, values, satiation, and aggression)
explain how social exchange functions at the level
of the individual. Homans was critical of what he
regarded as the abstract sociological theory of his
day, and especially the work of Talcott Parsons,
because it could not be adequately tested by empirical research. Homans insisted on the importance of developing testable hypotheses that
explain basic social processes in small groups.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Horkheimer, Max (1895–1973)
For many years Horkheimer served as Director of
the Institute for Social Research and, with Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and
Hughes, Everett C. (1897–1983)
others, helped develop the critical theory of society. In “Traditional and Critical Theory” (1937
[trans. 1972]) in Critical Theory, Horkheimer argued
that “traditional theory” (which included modern
philosophy and science since Descartes) tended to
be overly abstract, objectivistic, and cut off from
social practice. Critical theory, in contrast, was
grounded in social theory and (Marxian) political
economy, carried out a systematic critique of
existing society, and allied itself with efforts to
produce alternatives to capitalism and bourgeois
society (then in its fascist stage in much of
Europe). The goal of critical theory is to transform
these social conditions and provide a theory of
“the historical movement of the period which is
now approaching its end.”
A collaborative work with Adorno, Dialectic of
Enlightenment (1947 [trans. 1972]), sketched out a
vision of history from the Greeks to the present
that discussed how reason and Enlightenment
became their opposite, transforming what promised to be instruments of truth and liberation into
tools of domination. Under the pressure of societal systems of domination, reason became instrumental, reducing human beings to things and
objects and nature to numbers. While such modes
of abstraction enabled science and technology
to develop apace, they also produced societal
reification and domination, culminating in the
concentration camps that generated an instrumentalization of death.
Horkheimer’s Eclipse of Reason (1947) presents a
popularized version of Dialectic of Enlightenment for
an English-speaking audience, and Critique of Instrumental Reason brings together Horkheimer’s
key essays since the end of World War II. Some of
Horkheimer’s most important writings are collected in Critical Theory (1972) and Between Philosophy and Social Science (1993).
DOUGLAS KELLNER
housework
– see women and work.
housing classes
– see social class.
Hughes, Everett C. (1897–1983)
A Methodist minister’s son from small-town Ohio,
Everett C. Hughes rose to lead the “Second Chicago
School.” Like his mentor Robert Park, his primary
impact on sociology was by challenging and inspiring graduate students. Inspired by Georg
Simmel, he specialized in dazzlingly insightful
miscellany.
273
human capital
The method Hughes preferred was “the intensive penetrating look with an imagination as
lively and as sociological as it can be made.” He
directed his own sociological imagination to the
areas of work and professions, race relations (see
race and ethnicity), and such topics as social
movements, migration, and social institutions.
His sociological eye often reframed subjects in
subversive ways – for example, showing how psychiatrists and prostitutes share the problem of distancing themselves emotionally from situations
that are highly emotional to clients, or by spotlighting the dark side of respectable occupations.
Hughes delighted in locating social facts in larger
contexts of meaning. His stream-of-consciousness
lectures sparkled with insights drawn from family,
fieldwork, and friendships. Participant observation was the keystone of his research ingenuity.
He developed and passed on to devoted generations of students, including Erving Goffman, a
range of techniques on how to do and to interpret
fieldwork. Symbolic interactionism stemmed from
the ideas of Hughes and his colleague Herbert
Blumer.
His academic works include French Canada in
Transition (1983), Where Peoples Meet: Racial and
Ethnic Frontiers (with Helen MacGill Hughes,
1981), Men and Their Work (1958), Education for the
Professions of Medicine, Law, Theology, and Social Welfare (1973), and The Sociological Eye: Collected Papers
(1984). In 1994, Lewis A. Coser edited a selection of
his writings, On Work, Race, and the Sociological Imagination.
DONALD LEVINE
human capital
– see social capital.
Human Genome Project
– see genetics.
human needs
These have two related but different definitions.
One is grounded in psychology and the other in
sociology and social welfare. The difference in the
two perspectives is the unit of analysis. The psychological approach to human needs focuses on
the individual and the sociological and social welfare perspective attends to the needs of the family,
group, and society.
The task of psychology is to understand behavior by linking it to the organism’s primary needs
and the environmental conditions relevant to
them. Other approaches have added to this line
of inquiry by concentrating on psychological
274
human needs
rather than physiological needs. In the 1950s
psychologists developed a model in terms of eight
levels. The first four are: physiological needs,
safety needs, belongingness and love, and esteem
needs. Once these needs are met, individuals seek
self-growth by addressing the next four levels of
needs: need to know and understand, aesthetic
needs, self-actualization, and transcendence. Selfactualized people are characterized by: (1) being
problem-focused; (2) incorporating an ongoing appreciation of life; (3) being concerned about personal growth; and (4) having the ability to enjoy
peak experiences. The most recent psychological
work on human needs is self-determination
theory which defines needs as innate psychological nutriments that are essential for ongoing
psychological growth, integrity, and well-being.
The psychological concept of human needs has
served as a means of organizing and integrating
a wide range of research related to social contexts,
motivational orientations, goals, healthy development, high-quality performance, maintained
behavior change, and mental health.
The sociological and social welfare perspective
defines human needs in terms of what the family,
group, or society needs to enjoy a humane and
high quality of life and to have fundamental
human rights. These discussions are often
couched in terms of: avoiding violence and social
conflict (stability, security, and peace being desirable); disparities between racial/ethnic groups,
sexes, or age cohorts; social justice; equal opportunity; free trade; immigration; citizenship; taxes
and social welfare (redistribution of resources)
policies. The Coalition on Human Needs in the
United States, for example, is an alliance of national organizations working together to promote
public policies that address the needs of lowincome and other vulnerable populations, such
as children, women, the elderly, and disabled
people. Human Rights Watch and Amnesty International are two international human rights organizations that monitor human rights abuses
around the world. They publish their findings
and use publicity to focus the world’s attention
on human rights abuses. Most of these organizations base their work on the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights which was adopted by the United
Nations General Assembly on December 10, 1948,
and which declares:
Whereas disregard and contempt for human rights
have resulted in barbarous acts which have outraged
the conscience of mankind, and the advent of a
world in which human beings shall enjoy freedom of
speech and belief and freedom from fear and want
human relations
has been proclaimed as the highest aspiration of
the common people. Whereas it is essential, if
man is not to be compelled to have recourse, as a last
resort, to rebellion against tyranny and oppression,
that human rights should be protected by the rule
of law.
GARY L. ALBRECHT AND MARK SHERRY
human relations
– see management.
human rights
– see rights.
human sciences
This term has its origins in the work of Wilhelm
Dilthey (1833–1911), who, in his 1883 Introduction
to the Human Sciences, argued for a conception of
the human sciences that contrasted with existing
perspectives and practices in many parts of the
humanities and nascent social sciences. He argued
for an interpretivist and hermeneutic approach to
socio-historical studies, seeing them as united
under the heading Geisteswissenschaften, in contrast
to Naturwissenschaften or the natural sciences. Central to this was his emphasis on the meaningfulness of human lived experience and its primacy in
the genesis of human action. Thus the psychology
of the individual and individual consciousness are
seen as part of broader historical inquiry and
many traditional boundaries that now exist between disciplines are avoided. A central part of
Dilthey’s work was an attempt to provide a secure
philosophical foundation for the Geisteswissenschaften that would afford them the same integrity and
status as Naturwissenschaften.
In conducting social-historical research, Verstehen was afforded a central role, and a wide variety
of materials and sources were brought within the
purview of this kind of inquiry. Verstehen is a
German word which may be roughly translated
as “the understanding of meaning,” and as a
method it has been described as seeking the empathic understanding of the outlook and feelings
of others. As an approach and a philosophy,
this work has its clearest descendants in social
anthropology and interpretative sociologies.
In contrast to Dilthey’s original definition, the
term human sciences is used very broadly and
loosely, and most commonly in the name of university faculties, departments, and research
groups. Typically these uses do reflect his desire
to bring together the different parts of the humanities and social sciences. A number of them
also include various parts of the biological
hybridization
sciences too, but rarely do they follow the philosophical and methodological precepts which
Dilthey sought to establish.
DAVID GOOD
hybridity
The synthesis of different cultures or social identities, resulting in a new third form, this term
originates in horticultural studies to refer to the
crossbreeding of two different species which produces a new species. In the nineteenth century,
the term was sometimes used to refer to the
mixing of races, synonymous with miscegenation.
Typically it had a negative connotation. In the
early twentieth century, the negative connotations were shed by anthropologists who used it
as a descriptive category. Some anthropologists
claimed that the mixing of races produced a new
“social type” which they called the “hybrid.”
In linguistics, hybridity is used to refer to the
combination of languages. Examples include
“pidgin” and “creole” languages. The most recent
uses of the term in social analysis have been partially influenced by the work of Mikhail Bakhtin
(1895–1975). He argued that linguistic difference
also corresponded to differences between forms of
social consciousness and social classes, such that,
in his view, a hybrid refers not only to the combination of linguistic elements but to the social
elements as well. Hybrids mark innovation, creativity, and change in social spaces. Bakhtin’s
idea has been expanded to encompass not only
linguistic combinations but also combinations of
social identities, ideas, and cultures, typically produced through cultural encounters during colonialism or through globalization. Culture theorists
like Stuart Hall have tried to shed the negative
connotations of the term and replace them with
positive meanings. In this use of the term, hybrids
reveal the inadequacy of essentialism. The underlying idea is that all cultures and identities are
hybrids. There is no such thing as a completely
unified culture or identity; they are always
formed by a process of negotiation or interrelationships between differences or opposed terms,
categories, or ideas. Hybridity therefore emerged
as an important analytic concept in culture theory
because it highlights that identities and meanings
are formed relationally. Some strands of postmodernism and postcolonial theory have also used the
term to show the importance of cultural difference without falling into the trap of essentialism.
JULIAN GO
hybridization
– see globalization.
275
hypothesis
hypothesis
– see hypothetico-deductive method.
hypothetico-deductive method
This method is in fact a theory of how science is
supposed to work. The scientist makes hypotheses
about reality and then tests them by looking for
evidence to confirm these hunches. That is, a scientific hypothesis must be testable and based on
observable empirical data. We deduce from a hypothesis what we should be able to discover as an
explicit observable feature of reality. If observed,
then the hypothesis is supported; if not, then
the hypothesis must be given up. The immediate contrast is with the inductive method that
suggests that science proceeds by collecting
empirical instances of an event and then producing a hypothesis about what was going on
(induction).
276
hypothetico-deductive method
However, the hypothetico-deductive method
does not resolve problems of what constitutes a
scientific explanation. In the first place, what is to
count as an observation is not clear, and scientists, when confronted with disconfirming evidence, can dismiss it on other grounds, such as,
for example, that the measuring instruments are
wrong. Following the work of Thomas Kuhn on
paradigms, it is now clear that scientists actively
work to protect their theories from disconfirming
evidence, rather than actively working to falsify
them. The strongest rejection of the hypotheticodeductive method was put forward by the philosopher of science Karl Popper. In his account, for a
theory to be scientific, any hypotheses it produces
must specify explicit observable outcomes that are
capable of falsification, rather than searching for
data that are able to verify the original set of
hypotheses.
KEVIN WHITE
I
ideal type
All religious attitudes, conventionally underMax Weber defined the nature and use of the ideal stood, are idealist in character, but they can be
type, though many of the elements of his discussion originated with his colleague Heinrich Rickert (1863–1936). Ideal types are pure concepts
that make no claim directly to describe or explain
empirical events. They are constructed by social
scientific investigators as conceptually pure benchmarks for contrasts and comparisons with facts
collected from historically specific cases. Thus,
one may use several different ideal types to specify
the historical significance and cultural meaning
of any given constellation of events. For example,
in studying socially disadvantaged groups in a
modern nation-state, one might use ideal types
of both social class and social status.
According to Weber, sociology as a discipline
devotes itself to the construction of ideal types.
Though sociological ideal types can make no empirical claims, they gain the advantage in conceptual precision on the level of meaning. Weber’s
compendium of ideal types in Economy and Society
(1922 [trans. 1978]) demonstrates this advantage.
Each ideal type includes actions defined by typical subjectively assigned meanings, all of which
are logically integrated into a complex concept.
Beyond conceptual precision, distilling ideal types
from historical sources requires great erudition.
Ideal types may be developed on many levels of abstraction. Weber’s well-known ideal type of social
action is historically unlimited. His ideal-typical
model of the routinization of charisma is applicable only in a particular range of situations, and
his ideal type of the Protestant ethic applies
only to a small group of early modern religious
IRA COHEN
confessions and sects.
idealism
A view of the world that sees reality as ultimately
composed of ideas rather than a realm existing
outside human consciousness, idealism reaches
this conclusion on the grounds that, without
ideas, humans could not function. Because human
activity is conscious activity, the world itself is
ultimately composed of ideas.
described as forms of objective idealism. Objective
idealism does not doubt the existence of a reality
outside the individual mind, but sees the real
world as the creation of gods or God, so that
worshipping God or appeasing the gods is essential for human control over nature. In its “deist”
form, objective idealism argues that, while the
world is ultimately created by God, science studies
its regularities and character without assuming
any further divine intervention.
Objective idealism needs to be distinguished
from subjective idealism. Subjective idealists argue
that the real world is created by individual ideas.
Since all data must be processed by the human
mind, it is impossible to prove that there is a
world beyond these data. It is difficult to see how
subjective idealism can rebut the criticism that it
leads to a paralyzing skepticism and an inability
to distinguish the subjective from the objective.
Idealism in general is unable to provide an analysis of how consciousness itself is a product of
history.
JOHN HOFFMAN
identity
The idea of human beings having an identity or
identities has come to replace previous notions
of character. Whereas identity is assumed to be
socially constructed and invented, character signified individual attributes that were fixed and permanent. Identity then has an intersubjective
dimension. In the social sciences, the view of
George Herbert Mead that identity is dependent
upon the recognition of others introduced more
complex forms of understanding. Mead argued
that human identities develop out of a three-way
conversation between the I, Me, and generalized
Other. It is by “taking the attitude of the other”
that we learn reflexively to monitor our identities
and present them to others. Identity is formed
out of the constant ebb and flow of conversation
between ourselves and others. When there is a
conflict between the demands of the community
and the self, individuals are thrown back on
277
identity
themselves in a reflective attitude, thereby examining whether their values and beliefs are in
need of revision. On this reading all identity is
reflexively produced.
If all identity is produced in the context of community, many have sought to look at the ways
society seeks to regulate and manage its production. Many have sought to criticize Mead’s views
for neglecting the role of power and culture in
helping shape identity. The modern state has
been involved in the regulation and monitoring
of identities through a number of institutions,
from prisons to the courts and from the education
system to border controls. Further, these features
of identity are related to the rise of identity politics over the course of the twentieth century. In
opposition to the way many of the dominant features of modern societies have sought to police
and control identities, many have used claims to
identity as a means of organizing themselves politically. The most prominent amongst these movements has been feminism, which has historically
sought to deconstruct overtly masculine assumptions about human identities, while promoting
new forms of inclusion and respect for women.
On the other hand, other social movements have
more explicitly sought to claim an absolutist identity as a means of engaging in politics. The politics
of identity includes a number of social movements and networks, some of which provoke critical questions, while others defensively reaffirm
communal connections.
The impact of more complex models of identity
in the wake of Mead (not forgetting the impact of
psychoanalysis) and identity politics has led to a
growing appreciation of the complexity of identity.
Indeed many now prefer the term “identities,” signifying the idea that no one source can explain the
complexity of the modern self. Modern selves are
the product of a range of shifting and diverse social
and cultural categories and identifications that are
rarely stable. For many the capacity to have an
identity means the ability to be able to tell a story
about the self and related communities. An identity is like a narrative that has to be constantly
retold and reformulated in the light of new circumstances. If social and cultural change in respect of
globalization and technology has aided the reflexive capacity of identities, it has also increased the
capacity of many to claim more fundamentalist
versions of identity. The rise of the internet and
new forms of communication have offered new
opportunities for new forms of identity conflict
and contestation that are no longer contained by
the nation-state.
NICK STEVENSON
278
ideology
identity politics
– see identity.
ideology
Generally used to point to the ability of ideas to
affect social circumstances, the function of ideology has thus been described as the capacity to
advance the political and economic interests of
groups or social classes (Karl Mannheim, Ideology
and Utopia, 1936; Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,
The German Ideology, 1846), or, alternatively, the
capacity to produce cohesion (N. Poulantzas, State,
Power, Socialism, 1978) and resolve social strain
(Talcott Parsons, The Social System, 1951). In Marx
and Engels’s early formulations, ideology belonged
to the cultural superstructure of social formations
while material forces of production were described
as the foundation or base. Contradictions in the
mediation between base and superstructure were
understood to be signs of strain and class conflict
that in turn produce social change. This general
notion treated ideology as materially effective
representation, although it often carried with it a
connotation of false representation and concealment of power. Ideology was associated with
systems of beliefs that naturalized inequality
through false consciousness. So powerful was the
association between ideology and political mobilization that, by the end of World War II, writers
such as Daniel Bell (in The End of Ideology, 1960)
described the ensuing period of conformity and
political quiescence in some advanced capitalist
societies as the eclipse of ideologies, post-political
politics, broad social consensus, and the emergence
of the administrative state organized for efficiency
rather than contests between opposing claims
concerning power and justice.
Few contemporary scholars claim that ideology
is a grand set of ideas that in its seamless coherence imposes belief. It is not a system of ideas
that strictly determines what people think, their
consciousness, false or otherwise. The most promising formulations propose that ideology is not a
body of abstracted ideas at all (static, coherent,
or otherwise). Rather, ideology is a complex process “by which meaning is produced, challenged,
reproduced, transformed” (M. Barrett, Women’s
Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis, 1980; M. M. Bahktin, The Dialogic Imagination,
1987; M. Billig, Ideology and Opinions, 1991). Ideology as a process of meaning making is not, however, to be equated with culture or structure in
general, or with social constructionism as a transactional process in general. An ideology always
embodies particular arrangements of power and
ideology
affects life chances in a manner that is different
from some other ideology or arrangement of
power.
Within this constructivist or constitutive framework, consciousness and ideology are understood
to be part of a reciprocal process in which the
meanings given by individuals – in transactions
with others – to their world become patterned,
stabilized, and objectified. These meanings, once
institutionalized, become part of the material and
discursive systems that limit and constrain future
meaning making.
Meanings can be said to be ideological only
insofar as they serve power; thus ideology is not
defined by its specific content but by its contextual construction and function (P. Ewick and S. S.
Silbey, The Common Place of Law, 1998). This view
recognizes that ideology continues as in the nineteenth century to be associated with power, inequality, and domination, but is not simply a
tool to hide or create a distraction from the real.
Rather, the social meanings we define as ideological are constitutive of domination; they are
ideological precisely because they appear to be
non-ideological (P. Ewick, Consciousness and Ideology, 2004). Ideologies vary, however, in the degree
to which they are apparent, contested, or conventionalized. Thus, ideology can be understood in
relationship to hegemony as the ends of a continuum. At one end of the continuum, the visible
and active struggles referred to as ideology. At
the other end, the term hegemony refers to situations where these struggles are no longer active,
where power is dispersed through social structures, and meanings are so embedded that representational and institutional struggles are no
longer visible (J. Comaroff and J. Comaroff, Of Revelation and Revolution, 1991). Although moments of
resistance may be documented, in general subjects do not notice, question, or make claims
against hegemony.
In Ideology and Modern Culture (1990), J. B. Thompson offers a useful typology of how ideology generates meaning and truth claims by creating
ways of knowing and not knowing by suppressing
alternative meanings. Focusing on ideology as process and technique, Thompson suggests that ideology produces legitimacy, authorizing, sustaining,
and reproducing social relations and organizations. By drawing boundaries around objects and
processes, ideologies both unify and fragment coalitions and groups, creating and suppressing
opportunities for action. Most importantly, ideological processes also reify and deceive. Ideology
reifies social relations by masking their social and
imagined communities
historical character, treating as concrete what is
an ongoing process in the making. By naturalizing
and thus making inevitable what is a human
process of social construction, ideology not only
reifies social relations but also deceives and is
mobilized to sustain or achieve domination.
SUSAN SILBEY
imagined communities
A theory of nationalism, the phrase entered the
lexicon of modern sociology through B. Anderson’s Imagined Communities. Reflections on the Origin
and Spread of Nationalism (1983). Anderson argued,
on the basis of a historical study of the struggle for
Javanese independence from Japan in Java in a
Time of Revolution (1972), that nations are created
or imagined rather than naturally occurring entities waiting to be discovered. Although nationalists typically like to think of their nation as
existing from the dawn of time, nations are the
products of modern revolutions. He defined a
nation as an “imagined political community”
that is both limited and sovereign.
It is imagined because, even in the case of
small nations, the fellow-members cannot know
or meet each other, but they consider themselves
or imagine themselves to be members of the
nation. This community is limited in having
boundaries, and it is sovereign, because the state
attempts to assert its legitimate power over a territory. Finally, it is a community, because irrespective of social class divisions, members of a
nation imagine themselves to be what Anderson
calls a “horizontal community.” For example, Indonesians, who occupy a complex and sprawling
archipelago of islands with diverse cultures and
religions, have acquired a national consciousness
as a result of their struggle against Japanese and
Dutch occupation. The Indonesian nation is an
imagined community in this sense.
Anderson also argued that the spread of print
culture and the growth of literacy in modern
times have facilitated or made possible a situation
whereby people can imagine themselves as part of
an integrated, horizontal, political community.
The growth of the novel (in the eighteenth century) and the spread of the mass newspapers (in
the nineteenth century) were both important in
the spread of the political imagination of the
nation. The Protestant Reformation was especially
important in the growth of a literate population
who consumed print (for example in copies of
sermons), and which contributed to the triumph
of vernacular languages over the Latin of the
Catholic Church.
279
imperialism
With Anderson’s thesis the idea that nationalism produces rather than discovers nations
became the common assumption of sociological
and political discussion.
BRYAN S. TURNER
imperialism
In an article on the “Sociology of Imperialism”
(1919), Joseph Schumpeter defines imperialism as
“the objectless disposition on the part of a state to
unlimited forcible expansion.” In this sense, “imperialism” describes the common tendency of a
political unit to grow until it encompasses the
earth. In so far as the purpose of any political
unit is expansion, all polities are either potentially
or actively imperialist. But polities do not all try to
expand in the same manner or to the same extent.
Only empires aspire to expand themselves indefinitely: both city-states and nation-states are based
on a territorial sovereignty, while empires aim
directly at a universal sovereignty, a dominium
over the whole of humanity.
At its best, imperialism is a noble disposition to
create a political structure that is both universal
and concrete, a desire to unify humanity. At its
best, imperialism is also a just disposition: not a
disposition to conquer out of an unhealthy libido
dominandi, but for the sake of peace, for the sake of
an equivalent of the pax romana which political
unity makes possible. However, imperialism has
often been seen as problematic. In the book of
Genesis, God condemns the project of building a
tower “with its top in heaven,” Babel, by halting
this symbol of human over-reaching with “the
confusion of tongues,” thereby dividing humanity
into many nations, making human attempts to
build imperial projects to unify humanity more
difficult. Genesis associates imperialism with
hubris and pride, with a vain and evil desire to
be like God.
Our present unease with imperialism has at
least two specific roots. The first is the non-democratic character of empires. In an empire, a ruling
individual or a ruling oligarchy imposes its will on
the rest of the empire. Empires are built around
the opposition of a core and a periphery, the periphery being subordinated to the core. In contrast, city-states and nation-states are not built
around the distinction core/periphery but around
an opposition between internal and external, with
more firmly defined boundaries: these political
forms are compatible with the idea of a unified
people of equal citizens. Whereas empires exclude
democracy as a political regime, city-states and
nation-states are compatible with democracy;
they are not necessarily hierarchical. A second
280
imperialism
root of our contemporary discomfort with imperialism is cultural relativism. In order to justify their imposed order, empires tend to claim
that they stand for a higher degree of civilization,
that this gives them a right to rule “barbarians.”
In a world like ours, which considers itself to be
disenchanted with any claim about the superiority of any aristocracy or civilization, empires
appear to be lacking in legitimacy.
According to Schumpeter, imperialism is an
irrational inclination towards war and conquest,
and one which he associates with the survival
of residual political structures: imperialism
belongs to a pre-capitalist era and is an atavism
destined to disappear. In order to defend their
social position, a ruling class (see social class)
foments a jingoistic mood in which ideas such
as national honor and prestige play an essential
part. But, according to Schumpeter, a purely capitalist world can offer no ground for imperialist
impulses. Schumpeter belongs to a tradition illustrated by Auguste Comte and Thorstein Veblen
according to which commerce will replace war –
a tradition analyzed in Raymond Aron, War and
Industrial Society (1958). One dominant contemporary version of this theory, a theory of globalization, has two roots: a belief that commerce will
replace war, and an argument turning the ideals
of the Enlightenment, ideals which underpinned
European imperialism, against imperialism itself.
However, imperialism should not simply be
confused or conflated with an old-fashioned spirit of conquest, an anti-capitalist and an antidemocratic inclination. Not all empires have been
tyrannies, not all empires belong to a pre-capitalist
and pre-democratic age. Another school of explanation of imperialism stems from Vladimir Ilich
Lenin’s analysis of imperialism as the “highest
stage of capitalism.” The claims of this school are
the converse of Schumpeter’s: the accumulation
of wealth will not be enough to get rid of war, as
war is a necessary consequence of economic inequality. This argument and its posterity are described in Wolfgang J. Mommsen, Theories of
Imperialism (1977 [trans. 1980]). The preservation
of capitalism requires expansionist opportunities.
Imperialism is due to the acute competition of
surplus capital which did not find profitable
employment on the home market.
Lenin’s theory echoes Machiavelli’s political
philosophy perhaps even more than Marxism.
According to Machiavelli, imperialism is favored
by all those who try to avoid the conflict between
the haves and the have-nots, the oligarchs and the
people. Imperialism reorients the activity of the
income
city or state in a way which enables it to avoid
imploding through civil war. On this account, the
sociology of international relations cannot be separated from the sociology of social classes and
political sociology. As Machiavelli puts it in his
Discourses On the First Ten Books of Titus Livius (1531
[trans. 1996]) (an analysis of Rome’s imperial past),
the passions of those who want to acquire and of
those who do not want to lose combine to form a
communal passion to acquire the world. The quarrel between the poor and the rich frees an energy
that helps in building up the power necessary to
conquer. Imperialism sublimates class conflicts
into wars of overseas conquest and external
expansion.
One can reconcile in part Lenin’s and Schumpeter’s teachings by noticing that there are various types of empires and imperialisms. Empires
are more or less military and more or less formal.
Although Britain built the immense empire that
became the empire par excellence in modern
times, the nation’s power was ordinarily exercised
in an indirect way that made it easy to rule with a
comparatively small army and civil service – Niall
Ferguson’s Empire (2003) offers an introduction to
its history. In its weakest form, imperialism can be
a form of loose economic hegemony. Today,
deepening the spirit of commercial societies, the
United States of America seem to have superseded
the indirect character of the British Empire in
exercising their empire without the real burden
of an empire.
Imperialism is not necessarily incompatible
with capitalism and democracy: it can be a product of both. Western nations ruled the world because their individual members set sail for
science, victory, and gain. The extension of political and economic liberty at home went hand in
hand with the extension of the power abroad. The
great discovery of Machiavelli, both a republican
and an imperialist, is that freedom is not an
enemy of power, but what produces it. The acquisitive passion is equally at work in democracy,
capitalism, and imperialism: it leads the have-nots
to impose their own regime (democracy), a regime
that will allow them to acquire more goods
(capitalism) and more territory (imperialism).
É M I L E P E R R E A U - S A U S S I N E
income
In commonsense terms, income refers to the
wages that an individual earns through gainful
employment (see work and employment) over
time. In more technical language, it refers to the
flow of money, goods, or services to an economic
income
unit, which may be an individual or more typically a household. Personal disposable income
refers to the income available to a household after
taxation and national insurance contributions.
The national income refers to the aggregate
incomes of the residents of a society in a given
period of time. Incomes in this national calculation include all payments for the factors of production, that is wages, salaries, profits, rent, and
income from abroad.
In economic distribution theory, the incomes of
land, labor, and capital are determined by the
demand and supply for them. This way of looking
at income was an aspect of the classical political
economy of David Ricardo (1772–1823) who sought
to determine the economic laws that regulate the
distribution of the produce of industry between
different social classes, namely landowners, capitalists, and workers. In developing these ideas,
Ricardo created a theory of income distribution,
that is an analysis of the share of the economic
output that went to landlords, capitalists, and
workers. Whereas landlords depended on rent
from land, capitalists seek profit on industrial
investments, and workers exist on wages. Ricardo
anticipated Karl Marx in recognizing the fundamental conflict of interest between these three
classes. Ricardo recognized that the value of any
commodity will be determined by the amount of
labor invested in it, and therefore capitalists have
an interest in controlling wages to increase their
profits. Capitalists will attempt to replace labor
with machinery, because capital-intensive goods
will be cheaper than labor-intensive goods. Ricardo’s theory of the dynamics of capitalism was
similar to the demographic theory of Thomas
Malthus (1766–1834). Ricardo argued that when
wages rise above the subsistence level, workers
respond by increasing the size of their families.
As population grows, the supply of labor will increase, there will be downward pressure on wages,
and as family size increases the standard of living
declines. However, population growth increases
the demand for land and increases rent. This Ricardian distribution model described the inherent
contradictions of capitalism, thereby anticipating
the Marxist theory of capitalist crisis.
Sociologists have been primarily interested in
the distribution of income as a measure of social
inequality. Richard Titmuss in Income Distribution
and Social Change (1962) showed that in Britain
the problems of income distribution and taxation
were poorly understood, and that social workers
had been too concerned with the basic problem
of poverty to the neglect of relative income
281
income
inequality. Titmuss’s research was intended to
examine whether there had been any equalization of incomes in the postwar period. This question has given rise to much debate, but there is
some consensus that, with neo-liberalism, income
inequality has increased.
Sociologists typically measure income inequality in terms of the gini coefficient. This coefficient is based on the Lorenz curve which shows
the extent of inequality in terms of a frequency
distribution by reference to personal income. A
Lorenz curve is a graphical representation of inequality in which the cumulative percentages of
a population of taxpayers are plotted against the
cumulative percentage of incomes. A straight line
rising at an angle of 45 degrees from the base of
the graph will show perfect equality. For example,
if 10 percent of the population earned 10 percent
of the national income, and 20 percent earned
20 percent, and so on, there would be perfect
income equality. When a curve is traced below
the 45 degree line, the degree of curvature measures the degree of inequality. The gini coefficient
is measured as
G¼
Area between Lorenz curve and 45-degree line
Area above the 45-degree line
Where the frequency distribution is equal, then
G ¼ 0.
As the welfare state expanded in the postwar
period, Britain was characterized by a considerable degree of income equality in the 1950s and
1960s. However, the gini coefficient showed that
in the mid-1980s income inequality began to increase, and from the late 1980s it increased rapidly. Taxation has an important role to play in
income distribution, and with the reduction in
direct personal taxation the income of the rich
has increased significantly. The number of millionaires in Great Britain has increased dramatically since the 1980s. Sociologists are interested in
income distribution because it provides a proxy
measure of social class, and the conflict between
wages and profits is an indication of the extent
of class struggle. Furthermore, income inequality
is closely associated with poor health. In Unhealthy
Societies (1996) Richard Wilkinson showed how improvements in mortality rates in Great Britain
had slowed down after 1985 as income inequality
increased.
The economic theory of income distribution
assumes perfect competition between factors of
production and, in a free market, labor, land,
and capital will be fully and efficiently employed.
Sociologists have, however, been interested in
282
individualism
conditions that limit perfect competition such as
the growth of trade unions, wage bargaining, the
institutionalization of social conflict, and monopolies over profit. Economic theories of perfect
competition between factors of production with
constant returns to scale and zero profits have had
difficulties explaining such phenomena as waste.
Such theories are also limited by their inability to
calculate the value of the black market (or informal economy) and crime to economic activity, because such activities are not or rarely subject to
taxation, and hence are not easily measured.
BRYAN S. TURNER
income equality
– see income.
independent variables
– see dependent/independent variables.
indexicality
– see ethnomethodology.
individualism
There are two general perspectives on individualism. First, it is a political doctrine associated with
liberalism that emphasizes the autonomy, importance, and freedom of the individual in relation to
the state. Second, it is a particular type of culture
associated with private property rights, personal
consumption and individual autonomy. It is typically assumed to be an important aspect of western
culture as a whole, having its historical roots both
in Greco-Roman antiquity and in the Christian
religion. However, individualism had its modern
origins in the theology of seventeenth-century religious sects, and it is often held to be the dominant ideology of capitalism. In political theory, John
Stuart Mill claimed that the individual is sovereign, and in economic theories of entrepreneurship, Robinson Crusoe in Daniel Defoe’s novel is
seen to be the quintessential hero of individualistic capitalism. Individualism is also thought to
be a defining characteristic of western culture, in
contrast with the emphasis on the family and the
collectivity in eastern cultures. In Essays on Individualism (1986), Louis Dumont contrasted the hierarchical caste society of India, with its emphasis
on the social over the individual, with modern
western society where society is subordinated to
the individual.
Individualisme was employed in France as condemnation of the rational individualism of the
Enlightenment and the French Revolution. For the
individualism
eighteenth-century English philosopher Edmund
Burke (1729–97), individualism and the promotion
of individual interests would undermine the commonwealth and create an uncivil, unstable, and
repressive society. Nineteenth-century French sociology can also be seen as a powerful criticism of
individualism, and in the notion of the social sociologists emphasized the importance of social solidarity against the negative impact of egoistic forms
of individualism. Émile Durkheim developed a sustained intellectual attack on utilitarian individualism as represented by Herbert Spencer. While the
analysis of individualism has played a significant
role in the development of sociological theory, the
ideological and intellectual relationship between
individualism and sociology is often ambiguous.
As a result, understanding the relationship between “the individual” and “the social” remains a
perennial issue in sociological theory.
The development of individualism corresponds
closely with the emergence of western capitalism
from the early seventeenth century. Max Weber,
in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
(1905 [trans. 2002]), showed how Calvinism challenged traditional authority by claiming that the
salvation of the individual could not be guaranteed by the institutions of the church, such as the
Sacraments. Each individual would stand alone
before God on the Day of Judgment, and would
be held responsible for his or her sins. Protestantism created a radical version of religious individualism that profoundly shaped western attitudes
towards political and social institutions. The emphasis on the isolated individual and the anxieties
surrounding uncertain knowledge of salvation
was part of a “tragic vision” that in France characterized the Jansenist sect, the philosophy of
Pascal, and the tragedies of Racine. In early
modern history, the Protestant Reformation was
a critical turning point, because it made salvation
potentially available to everybody, regardless of
his or her social standing. This theological differentiation of the individual from society is an important component of the historical development
of religion.
In theoretical terms, individualism is subject to
considerable confusion. It is important to establish a clear distinction between four separate
issues. We can distinguish an emphasis on the
individual as an autonomous agent with a distinct
identity as part of the western tradition. Then
there is individualism as a social and political
ideology with various national traditions. Third,
in European thought, individuality was a romantic view of the uniqueness of the person and is the
individualism
product of a long process of education and cultivation. Fourth, in modern societies, there is individuation as a process whereby people are
standardized by the bureaucratic processes of the
modern state. Finally there is in addition an epistemological theory called methodological individualism that argues that all sociological
explanations are reducible to the characteristics
of individuals.
The development of sociological theory has involved various attempts to resolve this dilemma of
collective and individual concepts of social institutions. Weber, for example, has been criticized
for an artificial and historically static construction of the individual and society. In The Society of
Individuals (1991), Norbert Elias criticized Weber
for his inability to reconcile the analytical tensions between the individual and society. This failure to deal successfully with this artificial division
is a general weakness of sociological theory. Elias
offered a solution in which we analyze the two
concepts of individual and society as historical
constructs that arise from social processes. The
balance between society (We) and the individual
(I) is not fixed, and hence what he called “processual sociology” or “figurational sociology” was
designed to explore the We–I balance in different
social configurations, such as feudalism or bourgeois society.
In American sociology, there has been a persistent theme claiming that nineteenth-century individualism was undermined by the growth of mass
society. The debate starts with Alexis de Tocqueville who, in Democracy in America (1848 [trans.
1968]), believed that the lack of centralized, bureaucratic government in America had encouraged
individual initiative and that voluntary associations had flourished to solve local, community
problems. Civil society required these associations
to flourish, and as a result individualism had not
been crushed by centralized administration. However, the emphasis on equality, while a revolutionary doctrine, also threatened the individual with
mass opinion. Tocqueville’s fears for individual
opinion in a mass democracy influenced liberals
such as Mill towards universal suffrage in Britain.
Critical theorists in the twentieth century
continued to study the impact of mass society
on individuals. C. Wright Mills, in The Power
Elite (1956), claimed that individuals were increasingly manipulated by public opinion in a society
where elites controlled the channels of information. David Riesman, in The Lonely Crowd (1950),
analyzed the American personality as the otherdirected character, because it depends on
283
individualization theory
constant approval and affirmation from others.
Other-directed personalities are conformist, and
hence American culture was stagnating. In The
Organization Man (1956), W. H. Whyte described
the company executives, who are mobile, disconnected from their local communities and families,
and dedicated to personal achievement within the
organization. These organizational commitments
encouraged social conformity. In Habits of the
Heart (1985), Robert N. Bellah and his colleagues
undertook an influential study of contemporary
attitudes towards politics that was intended to
replicate Tocqueville’s study. They discovered
that Americans were alienated from politics and
political institutions, but their commitment to
society was expressed through a multitude of local
and informal associations.
In the 1950s sociologists created a theory of
social standardization and conformity that apparently undermined the raw individualism of early
capitalism. Contemporary sociological studies
have drawn on the theory of postindustrial society
to argue that modern patterns of employment, for
example in the service sector, are fragmented, and
employment does not require loyalty to the company. In the 1990s, work and employment have
become casualized, part-time, and discontinuous.
The alienated individual of mass society has been
replaced by a work force that has no sense of
identity with the company, and many people no
longer have an experience of a life-time career.
Richard Sennett, in Respect (2003), argues that
casualized workers have low self-esteem. The implication of these studies is that the rugged individualism of the American frontier is decaying.
BRYAN S. TURNER
individualization theory
Individualization concerns the conversion of identity into a task to be achieved. Life is increasingly
lived as an individual project. The decline of class
loyalties and bonds (along with growing income
inequalities) means that individuals are increasingly thrown back on their own biographies,
with human relations increasingly becoming susceptible to individual choice. This does not mean
that the self is being increasingly determined by
market individualism or by social isolation. In Risk
Society (1992), Ulrich Beck argues individualization
means the disembedding of the ways of industrial
society and the reinvention of new communal ties
and biographies. As more areas of social life are
less defined by tradition, the more our biographies
require choice and planning. Individuals are “condemned” to become authors of their own lives.
284
industrial democracy
The partial disintegration of the nuclear family
and rigid class hierarchies means we are all
released from the structures of industrial society
into the uncertainties of a world risk society.
There are two main criticisms of these views. (1)
The individualized self is dependent upon access
to material and symbolic resources that are unevenly distributed in modern industrial societies.
The argument here is that the individualized
self is a middle-class rather than a universal social
condition. (2) This view seriously underestimates
the extent to which ordinary lives and sensibilities have been colonized by the imperatives of
economic reason.
NICK STEVENSON
induction
– see explanation.
industrial democracy
This phrase refers to worker participation in
management as both a historical and institutional development within industrial relations.
The theory of industrial democracy summarizes
a range of participatory practices induced by
workers, trade unions, state legislature, or management. Common organizational forms are
worker self-management, cooperatives, codetermination, work councils, and shop-floor programs
(for example autonomous work groups). Participation can be indirect (for example representation
through trade unions or work councils) or direct
(for example individual worker involvement in
teamwork schemes). Politically, the term symbolizes ideological commitment to social rights and
economic or industrial citizenship as dimensions
of so-called organizational democracy. Towards
the end of the twentieth century, the European
Union developed a range of industrial democracy
initiatives, thus creating legislative support for
European employee rights.
Collective bargaining by trade unions (to determine wages and conditions) is still the dominant
form of industrial democracy, but there has been
a decline in the strength, scope, and scale of union
action, as well as in the role of the state in industrial relations. Changes in production technologies and production organization as well as
changes to firm and market structures, in the
context of the ongoing globalization of the economy, have also affected nationally instituted
structures and produced different sets of actor
choices and opportunities. Diverse organizational
forms and actor constellations now exist, in
which individual-employee participation represents both more direct participation and leverage
industrial relations
industrial relations
for managers to bypass labor representatives and
collective agreements. Although the power balance is generally understood as shifting in favor
of management, industrial democracy remains a
salient public issue.
Crucial to understanding contemporary industrial democracy is the recognition that worker
participation is no longer confined to labor interests. Worker involvement has been developed
as a programmatic component of management
theory and practice, and implemented through
so-called human resource management (HRM).
This form of management helps institute worker
participation through widespread practices of
worker consultation, without intending to advance democracy. Compared with actual collaborative decision-making and participation in
ownership and profit-sharing, this weaker form,
generally welcomed by employees and their representatives, has also been analyzed as undermining
the more far-reaching, encompassing, or radical,
goals of trade unions and collective action by
labor movements more broadly.
Distinct national models of industrial democracy exist. There are clear differences between
the Anglo-Saxon and German varieties of capitalism. For example, in the United States and
the United Kingdom, economic competition from
Japan led to experiments with high levels of worker participation (for example so-called quality
circles and total quality management) and, from
the 1980s, financial participation (for instance,
profit-sharing and stock-ownership extended to
employees). Germany’s system of industrial relations, on the other hand, involves a dual system of
interest representation, with collective bargaining
between unions and employer representatives at
the industry level that is kept separate from codetermination (Mitbestimmung) at the level of the
firm. Legal regulation supports industry-level bargaining, determining the practices of negotiation
and arbitration without direct state intervention.
Work councils on the firm level are increasingly
taking over the role of the unions on the industrylevel of negotiation, but the essential feature of
capital–labor co-determination remains.
ANN VOGEL
industrial relations
These are concerned with the relationship between employers and employees, with its regulation, and with the social, legal, and economic
influences that shape it. The subject first received
systematic study in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries, notably with the work of
Beatrice Webb (1858–1943) and Sidney Webb
(1859–1947) in the United Kingdom, and of John
Commons (1862–1945) in the United States. Their
interest was a response to the contemporary rise
of trade union power and to the industrial unrest
that increasingly disrupted the developed world.
An underlying concern of the subject was, and
remains, collective employee behavior and its
regulation. The employment relationship was
seen to be inherently conflictual because of the
open-ended nature of the employment contract,
and the imbalance of power between employer
and employee. This distinguishes the subject
from personnel management and human resource
management, for which the frame of reference is
the management of individualistic relationships
with employees.
For most of the twentieth century, and for most
industrialized market economies, the driving
force behind the regulation of terms and conditions of employment was formal bargaining
between employers and the trade unions representing their employees. This regulatory process, called collective bargaining, gave rise to a
patchwork of industrial agreements within countries. Trade unions were seen to play an often
controversial role in exacerbating inflation, in
encouraging or impeding industrial efficiency,
and in upholding decent labor standards. Governments, to varying extents, and with varying
degrees of political support from trade unions,
legislated a procedural framework for collective
bargaining. This provided constraints to strike activity, means (such as conciliation and arbitration)
for conflict resolution, and rights to trade union
organization. Towards the end of the twentieth
century, collective bargaining became eroded by
intensified national and international competitive pressure for goods and services. As a result,
in most market economies, trade union membership and strike action diminished, and concern
with industrial relations declined.
In the decades after World War II there was
substantial sociological interest in industrial relations. Academic theorists sought to ground their
policy prescriptions in sociological analysis – for
example, John Dunlop drew on the work of Talcott
Parsons for his Industrial Relations Systems (1958)
and Allan Flanders’s influential analyses of the
breakdown of the British system used conceptions
of legitimation and anomie taken from Max
Weber and Émile Durkheim. Ethnographic studies
such as Alvin Gouldner’s Patterns of Industrial Bureaucracy (1955), Melville Dalton’s Men who Manage
(1959), and Michel Crozier’s The Bureaucratic
285
industrial society
Phenomenon (1964) inspired a generation of industrial sociologists to explore informal processes
and power relationships in industrial relations.
Studies such as Alan Fox’s Beyond Contract: Work,
Power, and Trust Relations (1974) and Eric Batstone
and his colleagues’ Shop Stewards in Action (1977)
did much to shed light on the rational bases of
what was popularly conceived to be the irrational
exercise of union power. In the British context,
such studies played an important part in drawing
attention to the managerial weakness that lay
behind disorderly workplace industrial relations,
and thereby facilitated its elimination. The economic pressures of subsequent decades have
tended to eclipse the pursuit of sociological
explanations of industrial relations behavior.
WILLIAM A. BROWN
industrial society
Modern society is industrial society. When a society undergoes industrialization, it tends to take
on the following features. It has an economy in
which power-driven machinery replaces human
and animal power, and steam, gas, or electricity
replaces wind and water as sources of power.
Handicraft production in the home or small workshop gives way to mechanized production in the
factory. The majority of the adult population
work in manufacturing or services, rather than
agriculture. Work is based on a complex division
of labor, involving generally a considerable degree
of mechanization and automation and a strict
separation of manual and mental labor. Its organization is based on Fordism (see Post-Fordism) and
Taylorism. The industrial way of life also tends to
involve a strict separation between home and
work, and between work and leisure. For Karl
Marx, such features of industrialism give rise to
a high degree of alienation.
The industrial population is urban, that is to say
that a majority live in towns of over 20,000 inhabitants, and many in towns of over 1 million people. Even rural dwellers are dependent on the city,
either for work or for most of the required services
and amenities.
Industrial life also tends to be secular, with
religion playing a diminished role in the life of
societies. As emphasized in the work of Max Weber,
industrial society is increasingly rationalized
and bureaucratized. For many nineteenth-century
sociologists, such as Ferdinand Tönnies, such features of industrial society lead to fragmentation
and a loss of community.
The first society to industrialize was that of
Britain in the early nineteenth century, as a result
286
inequality
of its "Industrial Revolution." Industrialism gradually spread to the rest of western Europe and, by
the late nineteenth century, to America, Japan,
and eastern European countries such as Russia.
By the mid twentieth century, industrialism had
become worldwide, and commentators were beginning to speak of a second industrial revolution
and the movement to a postindustrial society in
the developed world.
Industrial society has been, in the main, capitalist society. That, for Marx, was its most important
feature, leading to the development of social
classes based on ownership or non-ownership of
the means of production, and involving more or
less permanent class conflict. Eventually, Marx
thought, such conflict would lead to socialism
and a more stable form of industrial society.
That has not happened yet in any advanced industrial society, though a number of less developed
countries, such as Russia and China, have tried,
with considerable success, to industrialize under
the banner of socialism or Communism. Liberal
thinkers past and present, such as Herbert Spencer, Émile Durkheim, and Talcott Parsons, have
taken a more optimistic view of industrial society
and its future, arguing that the early conflicts and
discontents would give way to a more orderly
integration as social groups adjusted to each
other and a normative system governed by fairness and justice gradually established itself in the
workplace and in the society at large. As industrial
society has globalized, largely under capitalist auspices, the socialist dream has largely faded and
some form of liberal democracy has increasingly
become the norm.
KRISHAN KUMAR
industrialization
– see industrial society.
inequality
The unequal distribution of opportunities,
rewards, and power among and between individuals, households, and groups is a defining feature
of all known societies. The study of such differences, or inequalities, is a core concern of much
sociological research. The subfield of social stratification has as its main task the description and
analysis of inequalities, or the makeup of the
stratification system of any given society. Many
other subfields of sociology also examine particular kinds of inequalities (for example, political
sociology examines inequalities in the distribution of power, cultural sociologists study the unequal distribution of cultural capital, and so
forth). Inequalities can be seen most clearly in
inequality
two distinct allocations – who gets what? (inequality of outcomes) and who does what? (inequalities
of opportunities) – and across four distinct
social levels (individuals, groups, organizations
and institutions). The interaction between allocation processes and the social levels at which they
occur defines the contours within which sociological research on inequality proceeds. Sociologists have also paid considerable attention to
the consequences of inequality, and the ways in
which inequalities are reproduced and transmitted from generation to generation. Finally, it is
important to keep in mind that research on inequality may concern either the distribution at
one point in time or dynamic or intergenerational
processes.
The most basic question about inequality concerns the uneven distribution of rewards. Inequalities of income and wealth are central, but these
are fundamentally different concepts. Income
refers to the receipt of money or goods over a
particular accounting period (such as hourly,
weekly, monthly, yearly, or over the life-course).
For most individuals and households, it is their
earned income that primarily defines their wellbeing and capacity to acquire goods and service.
The choice of time period for studying income is
important. Take lifetime income flows: the young
generally receive little or no income; income typically peaks in middle age, declining later in life.
But such generalizations cannot take into account
short-term shocks (unemployment, health problems, macroeconomic conditions, the birth of a
child, good or bad luck) that may radically alter
income level at any particular point in time. The
use of averages over longer periods (such as yearly)
tends to obscure certain kinds of inequalities. For
this reason, analysts have typically considered
income insecurity an important supplement to
analyses of income inequality.
There are multiple possible sources of income:
earned income from a job, income received from
investments or ownership of income-generating
properties or business, income transfers from
the government, income received from family or
friends, and illegal or “underground” earnings
(such as from crime or informal services provided
outside a formal labor contract). The source of
income is a critical distinction. Individuals who
rely solely on paid employment or government
transfers have neither the security nor typically
the amount of income relative to those who receive income from multiple sources. One may lose
a job or a government entitlement and be without
income altogether for some extended period of
inequality
time. For these reasons, analysts of inequality
must pay attention to the source of income as
well as the amount.
In studying income flows, sociologists have
highlighted the importance of occupations and/
or aggregations of occupations known as social
classes. Occupations vary widely in the level of
income they provide to their incumbents; professional and managerial occupations provide far
greater incomes and employment security than
do routine “white-collar” jobs or skilled and unskilled manual jobs. Occupations are powerful
predictors of income, intergenerational social mobility, attitudes, voting behavior, and friendship/
marriage patterns.
Within a single “occupation” (however defined),
there is wide variation in the types of labor performed and in the compensation provided. The
primary alternative analytical method is to examine classes, broad groupings of occupations and/or
individuals with similar life chances. Research on
class-based inequalities has been a hallmark of the
sociological tradition since Karl Marx. Class analysis provides a different way of examining the
impact of inequalities across a wide range of
social domains. A variety of different types of class
schema have been developed as analytical tools.
Among the most prominent of these in contemporary sociology are the models of John Goldthorpe,
notably in The Class Structure in Modern Britain
(1980), and Erik Olin Wright, Classes (1985). The
Goldthorpe class scheme is built around an analysis of employment relations (such as the degree of
trust associated with particular kinds of occupations), while the Wright scheme focuses on the
differential distribution of assets possessed by different classes (principally skill and organizational,
and property, assets).
A different perspective on class inequalities
emerges when analysts focus on wealth. Wealth
refers to the total stock of capital resources possessed by an individual or family. The most
important types of wealth possessed by most
households are their homes, while a much smaller
subset of the population owns net financial assets
(NFAs) in addition to property. Home ownership is
the most widespread type of wealth ownership
in the developed capitalist world, and, since
homes tend to appreciate over time, home ownership has been one way that modest households
accumulate wealth. (The difficulties in securing
legal title to property and the barriers to wealth
accumulation this posed has been identified as
one critical source of slow economic growth in
less-developed countries.) Significant net financial
287
inequality
assets (the total value of savings, investments, and
other convertible assets, less outstanding debts),
in contrast, are far less widely held. Upper-class
families possess vast NFAs, while many families
possess little or no NFAs. Wealth is a critical
source of intergenerational inequality, something
which affluent parents can pass on to their children to provide them with important starting
advantages. Wealth differences between individuals and groups are often far larger than income
differences, and the sources of wealth inequality
has been an increasingly important topic of investigation in recent years. Of particular note is the
role of wealth assets in cushioning families
against unanticipated crises such as sudden job
loss or health catastrophe.
Less commonly thought of in relation to inequality of outcomes is status inequality. Inequality on the basis of status refers not to the amount
of income, but rather the prestige of a particular
social location. In primitive societies, for example,
the social position of “medicine man” or tribal
elder meant high social prestige even if there
was relatively little extra reward associated with
possession of that title. In modern societies, status
attaches to particular occupations (occupational
status), fame (celebrity status), successful performance within a social location (heroic status), and
power. While any of these statuses may be associated with substantial rewards, it is not necessarily
the case. For example, the President of the United
States commands a very modest salary in comparison with heads of most large corporations, but
has infinitely more status. Occupational prestige
is an important area of investigation in relation
to status inequality. In the influential research
of Donald Treiman and his colleagues, most
notably in Occupational Prestige in Comparative
Perspective, scales for ranking occupations according to the social prestige accorded to them by
a cross-section of survey respondents was developed. A robust finding is that, over time and
across societies, occupational prestige rankings
are remarkably consistent.
Much research on income and wealth inequalities has focused on examining trends over time.
One conclusion that is now universally agreed
upon is that intracountry inequalities are growing, albeit at different rates in different countries.
There are a number of different theories about
why inequalities in the postindustrial capitalist
world are growing. Among the leading explanations are rising returns to education (with the
gap between college-educated and non-collegeeducated citizens growing), changes associated
288
inequality
with economic globalization in the late twentieth
and early twenty-first centuries (including
rising levels of trade and more rapid movement
of capital across borders), declining union strength, and the decline of medium-wage manufacturing jobs. Although inequality has risen, rates
of poverty have not significantly increased in
most countries, as social provision through the
public sector continues to play an important
role in shoring up the well-being of low-income
households.
A focus on income or wealth inequality is but
one side of the sociological examination of inequalities. All known societies are characterized
by a division of labor in which individuals and
groups are vested with different responsibilities
and powers in the reproduction of their lives and
societies as a whole. This division of labor defines
a second-core allocation of inequality, the question of who does what. Two types of human labor
are fundamental in defining who does what: work
(including paid employment) and household labor
(housework; see women and work). In the Marxist
tradition, this distinction is known as production
versus reproduction, and feminist sociologists
have brought the study of the latter into the heart
of the sociological study of inequality.
At the top of any division of labor are social
positions imbued with power. In such positions,
incumbents are in a position to make decisions
that others have to follow whether they want to or
not. The most important types of power reside in
organizational position (such as in government,
the military, or corporate hierarchies), or in command over investment decisions (afforded by the
ownership of great wealth). But decision-making
power can also exist in much smaller units, such
as heterosexual families (where men typically
exert far greater influence over household
decisions than women).
Autonomy is a second critical concept in defining who does what, especially in the world of
work. Occupational hierarchies produce wide
variation in the level of autonomy provided to
individuals. In high-trust occupations, incumbents work without much supervision and are
free to define the pace of their work effort. By
contrast, in low-trust occupations, continual
monitoring of effort and lack of autonomy are
defining features of the daily grind. These issues
are core questions in the sociology of work and
employment.
Another critical source of autonomy comes from
the ownership of assets, which can be invested to
create opportunities for self-employment (or,
inequality
in cases of extreme wealth, provide for a life of
leisure free from involuntary toil). However, only
at the top of the occupational structure is selfemployment a vehicle for control over one’s working life. High levels of self-employment in many
developing countries, and also in some developed
countries like the United States, are frequently
associated with long hours, low wages, and
high levels of income insecurity. In the developed
countries, self-employment is often dominated by
immigrants seeking a toehold in the economic
order.
The division of housework has been a second
vital area of inquiry concerning who does what.
Feminist sociologists have established that the
narrow focus on the world of work, so characteristic of sociologists in the first half of the twentieth century, ignored a second important dimension
of who does what in the family. Wide disparities in
the division of labor on the “second shift” between
men and women, in terms of childcare, elder care,
cooking, routine housework, and other household
chores, constitute a powerful source of genderbased inequality. Recent debates over whether
the distribution of household tasks between men
and women have become more egalitarian suggest
some evidence of convergence, but in most families women still do far more routine and caring
work than men.
The link between inequalities in families and
inequalities in the workplace has been a widely
debated topic. While human capital theorists have
postulated that women choose to prioritize family
over work and women’s smaller incomes and occupational choices reflect those preferences, feminist sociologists have developed alternative
theories which emphasize that women’s subordinate roles in heterosexual families are disadvantaging women in the workplace. These arguments
go beyond sexist attitudes to attribute part
of gender inequalities to the disruptive aspects of
child-rearing (and care-giving for parents) for
women seeking to maintain career tracks.
Research on inequality frequently starts from
the analysis of the difference between individuals.
In the classical “status-attainment” model of
social mobility, associated with the work of
Peter Blau and Otis Dudley Duncan (The American
Occupational Structure, 1967), individual inequalities in opportunity and reward reflect family
background, individual attainment (such as education), and sociodemographic attributes (such as
race / ethnic group memberships), or even such
idiosyncratic factors as physical attractiveness. All
of these characteristics and attainments inhere in
inequality
concrete individuals. Some of these characteristics
are rooted in ascribed characteristics fixed at
birth. Other characteristics are achieved (such as
an individual’s level of educational attainment).
But later work has argued that this model does
not fully theorize the impact of social groups,
organizational settings, and welfare states in
structuring and altering individual-level attributes. Group membership is in many societies a
critical source of advantage or disadvantage.
Being a member of a high-status group in a society
typically eases access to opportunities. Analyses of
the distribution of income frequently draw upon
the idea of social closure, or the means by which
groups protect access to certain scarce resources,
to account for why groups are able to gain and
maintain advantages over time. Max Weber
argued in chapter 1 of his Economy and Society
(1922 [trans. 1968]) that the monopolization of
opportunities and/or rewards by particular groups
is a vital source of inequality. Examining the history of group-based inequality, Weberians have
shown that one of the ways in which groups
achieve power is by maintaining formal and informal systems of social closure. Formal systems include legal barriers to entry such as occupational
restrictions, while informal systems involve
less explicit but nonetheless powerful forms of
discrimination.
The organizational structure and types of social
provision are both a locus of inequality and a
potential source of their amelioration. Major institutions such as schools, the health-care system,
and the legal system all tend to reinforce the
advantages of powerful individuals and groups.
For example, public health care or education
systems rarely can provide the same quality care
or learning as can be acquired by those with the
means to acquire private health services or to
send their child to private schools. However,
public institutions on balance significantly reduce
inequality through the welfare state. Welfare
states include principally state institutions that
provide income transfers on the basis of either a
social-insurance model or means-tested benefits
based on income or other personal or family attributes. A consistent body of evidence demonstrates
that welfare states reduce poverty and inequality,
smooth out income fluctuations, and reduce oldage poverty and equalize health-care outcomes,
with higher-spending countries (such as the Scandinavian social democracies) getting more of
these outcomes than lower-spending countries
(like the Anglo-American liberal welfare states).
In many postindustrial capitalist countries,
289
infant mortality rates
market-based inequalities are growing sharply but
these continue to be reduced by welfare state
interventions.
Finally, it is important to underscore the global
character of inequalities. Individuals and households are embedded not just in local and national
economies, but also in a world-system that significantly influences the patterns of inequality.
The global economy is based on an unequal set
of trading relationships between countries
that makes some countries far richer than others.
However, the most careful recent research
(adjusted for demography) suggests that intercountry inequalities are declining, as previously
poor but very large countries like China move
closer to the global mean. The patterns of global
capital investment are also changing in ways that
encourage firms to seek profitable sources of investment outside the core developed countries.
Globalization may also set limits on the capacities
of welfare states to reduce intracountry inequalities, although thus far the impact on welfare
effort in the developed capitalist countries has
not been manifested in the way anticipated by
some globalization theories.
JEFF MANZA
infant mortality rates
– see mortality.
inflation
This refers to an overall increase in the price of
goods and services so that the purchasing power
of money declines. It is an episodic feature of
capitalism, but became a focus of sociological
debate in the 1970s when inflation in many
advanced capitalist economies exceeded 10 percent per annum. This tended to redistribute purchasing power between social groups in ways that
lacked obvious legitimacy, fueling competition
between them (though anti-inflationary state
policies could have similar repercussions).
Economists offer varied analyses of inflation.
These highlight the role of increases in raw materials prices; the capacity of workers or trade unions
to gain wage increases above productivity growth;
the market power of employers to pass on costs
through increased prices; or the role of the state
in increasing the money supply to fund state
expenditure. Neo-classical economists, however,
often view the collectively organized, institutional
features of these processes (especially state policies
and union leverage) as illegitimate distortions
of market mechanisms. By contrast, economic
sociologists (and some political economists)
argue that analyses of normative orientations, in290
influence
stitutional frameworks, and forms of collective
organization must be integrated with analyses of
market mechanisms to provide adequate accounts
of inflationary processes.
Thus, M. Gilbert, in Inflation and Social Conflict
(1986), compared different advanced capitalist
societies in terms of normative expectations, institutional arrangements, productive capacities,
and power relations, tracing their implications
for the generation, escalation, or mitigation of
inflation. Such analyses lead into wider debates
about the character, scope, and limits of alternative variants of capitalism, reviewed by D. Coates
in Models of Capitalism (2000), where inflation
and anti-inflationary state policies are analyzed
within a more encompassing international and
comparative political economy.
TONY ELGER
influence
A form of power, influence arises in the context of
relationships, between individuals, within an individual, and between individuals and the wider
world of nature.
Influence (when placed in a purely human context) can be defined as a pressure that gets someone to do something that they otherwise would
not have done. But the problem with a broad
definition like this is that it does not distinguish
between the threat of force and social pressures to
which people tacitly comply without necessarily
being under duress. It is extremely difficult to
distinguish sharply between different forms of
power since all pressures, short of force, require
agency on the part of the recipient. Technically,
when asked for “your money or your life” by the
proverbial highway robber, a choice is given and
the victim must choose. Force is qualitatively different from power, since when force is implemented the recipient becomes a “thing” and no
agency is involved.
Influence can be more precisely defined as pressures that get someone to do something they
would not otherwise do, when this “someone”
acts in a conventionally voluntary manner. When
we say that a doctor influences a patient, we
mean – on this argument – that they employ persuasion rather than the threat of force, so that
the person thus influenced believes that they are
acting with autonomy. It is complicated by the fact
that, whereas a doctor does not threaten force of a
kind that he or she would use, it would be wrong
to say that no force of any kind is involved. After
all, illness can threaten a person’s life, and a
doctor might warn that, unless a dangerous operation is undertaken, then force of a “natural” kind
informal economy
would ensue. Hence, what makes influence persuasive is that sanctions would certainly follow,
even if they are not sanctions that a doctor has
deliberately and intentionally orchestrated.
Hence, influence need not be intentional. A
newspaper editor might not intend to influence
readers in the way they vote, but this might be the
result, nevertheless. Indeed, we are becoming increasingly aware that malign influences on the
environment, for example, arise although the
people causing them did not intend them to be
such.
Indeed, it could be argued that, given the fact
that we live in a society, it is impossible for an
individual to undertake any action that does not
influence another. Is it then possible to distinguish between positive and negative influences?
The only coherent way of addressing this problem
is through an ethic of development – that which
influences a person positively is a pressure that
enables them to develop, as opposed to a negative
pressure that distorts and arrests development. An
ethic of development needs to be tied somehow
to a concept of autonomy and self-government, so
that, rather than imagine that individuals can
exist without influence, it should be acknowledged that we are influenced and influencing
all the time. The question that arises is basically:
do these influences help or hinder us in governing
our own lives?
JOHN HOFFMAN
informal economy
This refers to aspects of economic activity that lie
outside visible, official, and legally recognized
forms of production, distribution, and consumption. While the existence of this kind of activity
has been known to social investigators since the
nineteenth century, the term informal economy
first entered the social scientific vocabulary in the
late 1960s.
Sometimes known as the black, shadow, or cash
economy, this sector of economic activity generally operates outside forms of legal regulation
affecting company registration, taxation, and
workforce protection. It may involve illegal activity and forced labor, though this is not a necessary feature since forms of cashless exchange and
community self-help have also been included
under the umbrella term. The term informal economy has therefore been applied to a very diverse
range of activities in terms of employment status,
sectoral location, and geographical incidence. It
embraces forms of self-employment as well as
wage labor and applies to survival activities such
as rag-picking and scavenging, as well as domestic
information
service work, small-scale manufacturing, and
illegal people-smuggling and criminal extortion.
The scale of the informal economy is hard to
determine precisely because it remains unregulated and, to a degree, invisible. Variations in definition also complicate analysis of its spatial
distribution. International Labour Organization
data from the late 1990s suggest that the highest
levels of informal employment occur in West and
East Africa, South East Asia, and Latin America, at
levels of from 30 to 70 percent of total employment. However, informal activity has also been
identified with many unregulated or deregulated
economic sectors in western Europe and North
America, notably in larger cities. Much of this is
associated with sweatshops and low-grade service
work, employing both native-born and (often illegal) immigrant labor.
Geographically, then, the informal economy
applies to the developed as well as developing
worlds, though in both cases it is associated with
significant inequalities of income and lack of
access to social regulation and protection. Its ubiquity has prompted some analysts to see it less as
a marginal feature of the capitalist periphery, and
more as a key feature of capitalism – both historically and contemporaneously. What has come to
be seen as informalization emerges wherever producers seek to evade or bypass a regulatory framework to reduce costs and optimize profits. Just as
much production in early modern Europe was
informally “ruralized” to escape urban guild regulation, so a good deal of contemporary production
and service work has been informally “urbanized”
in small to medium-sized inner-city locales largely
hidden from the gaze of national regulators of
large-scale public enterprises. Access to the informal sector is therefore often through networks
rather than publicly available information.
Contemporary informalization is also disproportionately concentrated among women (see
women and work) and ethnic minorities. It is
thereby indicative of inequalities that markets
have helped to create rather than alleviate. Overall, the persistence of the informal economy
renders problematic theories of capitalism that
focus solely on large rationalized production units
and the public world of organized interests.
ROBERT HOLTON
information
Information may be considered on three different
levels: (1) uncertainty reduction, (2) patterned abstraction, and (3) knowledge. The term connotes
the recognizing, creating, encoding, transmitting,
291
information
decoding, and interpreting of social patterns – in
a word, communication – and often involves technology in some way. Information also may be considered at a meta-level: how and for whom the
information is created, to what uses it may be
put, and with what consequences.
By creating, modifying, and framing information, people can use it to alter the opinions and
actions of others, and thus future states. Archeological and ancient textual evidence demonstrates
that an enduring concern of rulers and sages alike
has been the crafting of messages to achieve desired effects. Aristotle and other ancient Greeks
systematically analyzed the social context of information construction and delivery as well as its
anticipated effect, including how various groups
might be served or disadvantaged by its forms of
public presentation. Many ancient elites, perhaps
as much as modern ones, realized that information exists not as an essence but within a context.
In contrast to rhetorical analyses, Paul Lazarsfeld’s empirical studies of information transmission among groups in The People’s Choice (1944)
must be considered foundational. He held that
there was a two-step flow in interpersonal influence related to political opinions, with local opinion leaders playing a pivotal role. Lazarsfeld and
long-time collaborator Robert K. Merton emphasized, in Social Theory and Social Structure (1949), the
importance of Weberian concepts of social location, social class, religion, opportunity structures)
over mass mobilization processes in political
decisionmaking. The dynamic tensions between
personal and public information, on the one
hand, and social and political structures on the
other, have been profitably investigated by Harold
Lasswell in World Politics and Personal Insecurity
(1935), Hugh Duncan in Communication and Social
Order (1962), and Walter Lippmann (Barry D. Riccio, Walter Lippmann – Odyssey of a Liberal, 1994).
These scholars have shown how power and leadership influence what comes to be considered knowledge from among various possibilities, and the
importance of framing information.
From a quite different (and highly technical)
tack, Bell Labs mathematician Claude Shannon
characterized information as being measured in
bits and probabilities. He defined information
theory as the problem of “reproducing at one
point either exactly or approximately a message
selected at another point.” Information therefore
reduces uncertainty, and the more uncertainty
that is removed, the more information any signal
or piece of data contains. Shannon helped spawn
several domains of inquiry, including theories of
292
information
encryption and data transmission, and also
showed how a variety of technical factors (such
as bandwidth, reliability, channel numbers, and
signal-to-noise ratios) limited certain system
functionalities.
An essential part of Shannon’s analysis was the
concept of entropy in communication systems. He
demonstrated that, as the amount of uncertainty
that exists in a communication channel increases,
the amount of information that can be transmitted also rises (and that the inverse also applies).
His work has proven invaluable in information
theory for helping determine optimal technical
designs for communication technology systems
under various practical scenarios. His ideas influenced control theory, which emphasizes coding,
sender, receiver, noise, and feedback. Yet Shannon
is far more cited than understood in the social
sciences, and his definition of information is too
technical to be of substantial interest to the sociologist. Yet his parsimonious notions, so elegantly
proven in mathematical terms, have some intriguing implications for the social sciences, a point
returned to at this entry’s conclusion.
Turning to the social structural and process
levels, information is also linked to the notion of
change – in theory and practice. Information alters
lived reality. Information works to reduce uncertainty and thereby increases control over environments, both natural and social. On a macro-level,
Manuel Castells in The Informational City: Information Technology, Economic Restructuring, and the
Urban–Regional Process (1989) links informationprocessing to culture, seeing it as symbolic manipulation. Information technologies are the systems,
devices, and techniques that produce and augment relationships among culture, productive
forces, and scientific and other knowledge,
and they operate within a cultural or mental
setting.
Fritz Machlup in The Production and Distribution of
Knowledge in the United States (1962) emphasizes the
distinction between transmission (information)
and understanding (knowledge), yet this traditional distinction has come under siege by some
in the Cultural Studies movement who see knowledge as power – power invoked not by Plato’s
benign philosopher-king but by exploitative interests. These interests are often exercised along the
lines of militarism, capitalism, gender, and social
class, and are exploited along the lines of decomposition (Horowitz, The Decomposition of Sociology, 1994) and statism. Mark Poster holds that
“information has become a privileged term in our
culture . . . and society is divided between the
information
information rich and the information poor” (The
Mode of Information: Poststructuralism and Social Context, 1990). In a related vein, Jean-François Lyotard
asserts, in The Postmodern Condition: A Report on
Knowledge (1979 [trans. 1984]), that information is
not simply scientific knowledge but also encompasses narrative knowledge.
Although Peter Nilsson in “The Distortion of
Information,” in J. Berleur, A. Clement, R. Sizer,
and D. Whitehouse (eds.), The Information Society:
Evolving Landscapes (1990), links information to
change on the level of either real-life practice or
thought patterns, it is because information is
affecting processes within the human mind. For
Castells in The Informational City (1989), information is intrinsically linked to culture because information-processing is actually the symbolic
manipulation of existing knowledge.
Communication theorists deal with information as a substance that, like other forms of discourse and nonverbal communication, conveys a
meaning. For the 1969 Japanese Information
Study Group, information “was not merely what
is in print, but also any symbol, signal, or image
having meaning to the parties at both the sending
and receiving ends” (Y. Ito, “The ‘Johoka Shakai’
Approach to the Study of Communication in
Japan,” in G. C. Wilhoit and H. de Bock [eds.],
Mass Communication Review Yearbook, 1981). In addition, information has a directional utility. Nilsson in “The Distortion of Information” defines the
goal of electronic and communication systems as
providing quality information, or useful information “in a given problem area for a given subject
and all effects on any subject and/or object.” As
with the socio-cultural definitions, information is
again held to be a social factor that expresses a
particular worldview and has discernible effects
on social actors.
If knowledge is to serve as an intermediary in
contemporary society, then the information that
it interprets must be transferable. James Boyle
argues in Shamans, Software, and Spleens: Law and
the Construction of the Information Society (1996) that
the easy conversion from one form into another is
a central marker of an information society. Ironically, though, Boyle says that, as information
expands to include “anything,” it is commoditized
to restrict its dissemination and manipulation.
While digitalization in theory allows for infinite
copies that are identical to the original, copyright
laws and technical enhancements can restrict and
possibly prevent such copying, and what one has a
right, ability, and permission to do continue to be
tested.
information
The two opposing views concerning the ability
to copy and reuse information are drawn from a
similar inspiration: that society should be regulated to advance the interests of society as a whole
and that intellectual property laws should return
the greatest good possible to society. Thus the
length of time that a copyright restriction may
be in force is checked, and some fair use is allowed
even of copyrighted material. As an inducement
for investing effort to create valuable intellectual
property, however, those who create the works are
rewarded for their efforts and control the copying
and use of their creations.
From a social-relativistic view, justice demands
that those who are least able to pay for materials
ought to be able to use those materials. Advocates
often argue that the poor would not have bought
the intellectual property anyway or that another
digital copy can be made cost-free. These arguments are often used by students or by people in
less-developed countries to justify making copies
of software. Advocates of copyright-free approaches also hold that worthwhile intellectual
property should be created for its own sake and
that society benefits by not having barriers to
information.
This argument for copyright-free reproduction
is countered by those who feel that those who
create works should decide who gets to use
them. Without some incentive, effort (and investments), which allow information to be brought
forth to the public, would not be made. In the
area of computer operating-system software, one
company (Xerox) created approaches that another
company (Microsoft) later reengineered and used,
leading to the birth of one of the world’s largest
commercial empires. But at the same time, open
systems that are based on freeware (Linux) have
been used on a no-cost basis and a proprietary
basis (Red Hat). This area will undoubtedly continue to be contested.
No single definition of information society has
been universally accepted, but there is convergence on several elements. The term itself seems
to have originated in Japan. A society generally is
characterized as an information society when information becomes its most significant product.
According to a 1997 report by the IBM Community
Development Foundation, The Net Result: Social Inclusion in the Information Society, an information
society has high levels of information usage by
people in their ordinary lives and in most organizations and workplaces; uses common or compatible technology for a range of personal, social,
educational, and business activities; and has a
293
information
widespread ability to transmit, receive, and exchange digital data rapidly between places irrespective of distance.
For most of human history, societies have been
concerned with subsistence or, if they were fortunate, with material pursuits. Technological limitations made moving information from one place to
another difficult. Many societies were nonetheless
deeply concerned with patterned abstraction in
the form of religious practices and beliefs, as the
great pyramids of Teotihuacán and Egypt attest.
Institutions of major religions, such as the Catholic Church, were centrally concerned with pattern interpretation and the communication and
reinforcement of these interpretations, and they
devoted enormous human and material resources
to that end. However, manuscript copying, messengers, heralds, and fire towers were cumbersome systems for distributing information and
gaining feedback on that distribution.
Technological innovations have yielded tremendous advances in the way that information is produced, processed, and consumed, with important
economic, political, and social ramifications.
Notably, they have enabled information to be
moved more easily (that is, communicated), which
has allowed the creation of markets to supply the
information and the means for its transmission.
By strategically controlling the creation, transmission, and application of information, enormous
commercial empires could develop in the fields
of telegraphy, telephony, newspapers, television,
and radio. Secondary markets quickly developed
to use information to adjust for risk; today these
take the form of the stock markets and the insurance industry. Tertiary markets also opened to
gather and apply information in the institutions
of scientific research, higher education, financial
accounting, and consultancies. These yielded quaternary markets – including the byproducts of
transactions (such as frequent-flyer programs)
and location information (such as mobile telephone monitoring systems) – that can be useful
for applications including marketing and law
enforcement.
The most important questions concerning social
equity in the information society involve the
digital divide – the division between those with
and without access to digital data. Increasingly,
the utility of information and thus the quality of
its meaning are coming to be measured in its
price. At the same time, there is continuing policy
pressure to adjust marketplace dynamics in light
of concerns over differential access to information
and to what extent information equity across
294
information
demographic groupings should be a target of
governmental (by nation-state or international
bodies) action.
Lyotard, like Poster, sees a progression in the
function of knowledge and predicts the increasing
commodification of knowledge, losing its “usevalue” to become an end in itself. He goes so far
as to claim that learning will circulate as money.
In a parallel vein, Lawrence Lessig in The Nature of
Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
(2001) and other theorists write that technology
does not directly lead to the production of original knowledge but creates more paths and links
between information – such as linked webpages or
Wikipedia functions online – which becomes the
source of new knowledge.
Indeed, it is possible that the personal, mediated communication typical of the internet, especially when it is further enhanced with mobile
applications, will be a qualitative change of a
magnitude that equals the change from the industrial era to the information society. In this regard,
Irwin Lebow’s criticism in Information Highways and
Byways: From the Telegraph to the Twenty-First Century
(1995) that the phrase “information superhighway” confuses “information” with “communication” is worth noting: networked information
access actually includes communication and entertainment, and from the user’s viewpoint these
applications are often the central attractions.
The following section highlights some major
theoretical perspectives on the social role of information. Of course the various perspectives may be
classified in a number of different ways. One general way is to look at information within the context of its ambient society. Alistair S. Duff in
Information Society Studies (2000), for instance,
examines the information sector, the information
explosion, and the information technology diffusion, which contribute to his methodology for
finding valid grounds for the phenomenon of
the information society. Another general way is
to focus on information in a societal setting,
that is, in the “Information Society.” Thus Frank
Webster in his article “What Information Society?” in Information Society (1994) isolates five
analytical approaches to defining the information
society (their theorists are in parentheses): technological innovation (Williams, Measuring the Information Society: The Texas Studies, 1988; Michael
J. Piore and Charles F. Sabel, The Second Industrial
Divide: Possibilities for Prosperity, 1984), economic
means (Machlup, The Production and Distribution of
Knowledge in the United States, 1962; Porat, “Communication Policy in an Information Society,” in
information
G. O. Robinson (ed.), Communications for Tomorrow:
Policy Perspectives for the 1980s, 1978), occupational
breakdown (Daniel Bell, The Coming of PostIndustrial Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting,
1973), and spatial (Goddard, “Networks of Transactions,” in K. Robins (ed.), Understanding Information:
Business, Technology and Geography, 1992) and cultural definition (Baudrillard, In the Shadow of the
Silent Majorities, 1983; Poster, The Mode of Information). In a blended approach, eight classification
categories are used below to sketch understandings of how information shapes and is shaped by
social forces.
The economic approach, as its name denotes,
defines information and the society in which it
exists through a lens that emphasizes production,
market, and consumption aspects. Researchers
pursuing this approach highlight the rapid expansion of the number of people who work in the
information sector of the economy. F. Machlup
introduced this approach with his study of national data, where he defines knowledge as a state
of knowing that “is produced by activities such as
talking plus listening, writing plus reading, but
also by activities such as discovering, inventing,
intuiting.” Knowledge producers transmit or communicate information, receive and process information, invest knowledge, and create instruments
for the production of knowledge (such as typewriters, photocopiers, and computers). As a result,
according to Machlup, the information industry is
composed chiefly of workers in the educational
sphere, other white-collar-industry workers who
participate in managerial tasks, and some bluecollar workers (such as pressmen, lithographers,
and typesetters). Machlup’s 1962 seminal contributions have yet to be superseded.
Expanding on Machlup’s argument for socioeconomic transformation through information, theorists have formulated the idea of the
“postindustrial society.” Its two most widely recognized proponents – Alain Touraine, The Post-industrial Society: Tomorrow’s Social History – Classes,
Conflicts and Culture in the Programmed Society (1969
[trans. 1971]), and Bell, The Coming of Post-industrial
Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting (1973) – are
influenced by Marxist interpretations of class
movement and hold that, in the postindustrial
society, the production and processing of information are core activities that are engaged in at
all levels of production, distribution, consumption, and management. Touraine’s “programmed
society” is structured by its production methods
and economic organization. He claims that the
present social conflict is between economic and
information
political decision making, that this new society is
“technocratic” (as defined by the nature of its
ruling class), and that the working class is no
longer a unified political agent. Similarly, for
Bell, the labor shift away from goods-producing
industries and towards white-collar service and
information-producing industries moves society
towards sexual equality and communal consciousness. Bell identifies a “knowledge class” that is
composed of a dual axis of technology and knowledge as fundamental resources. While Bell takes a
more economic approach and Touraine writes
through a sociopolitical lens, both theorists see
the sociologist as having a privileged place as a
“seer” of sorts who can understand and direct the
postindustrial society. Marc Porat and Michael
Rubin in The Information Economy: Development and
Measurement (1977) also see the transition of the
labor force from manual to informational work as
the foundation of the informational society, as
does Robert B. Reich in The Work of Nations: Preparing Ourselves for 21st-Century Capitalism (1991), who
writes about jobs that involve symbol manipulation and the international trade issues that arise
from this global class.
For Bell, scientific knowledge and values will
be involved in the political process in the postindustrial society, and intellectual work will be bureaucratized. While he calls this new society
“postindustrial” rather than “knowledge-based”
or “informational,” clearly one source of power
in it is possession or ownership of knowledge.
Jacques Ellul in The Technological Society (1954
[trans. 1964]) also posits the coming society as
a technological society – not entirely based on
technology but rather using carefully planned
“techniques” to achieve its goals.
Following closely after these theorists, Porat
identifies two information sectors – the major
information goods and services producers (industries that produce, process, or distribute information) and the secondary public and private
bureaucracies (organizations that engage in research, development, record keeping, and governmental planning). Like Machlup and Bell, Porat
uses economic statistics to support his claims.
While most theorists agree in principle that
trends in social and economic organization can
be identified and assessed, they have different
opinions about the social effects of these trends.
For liberals such as Ralph Dahrendorf in The New
Liberty: Survival and Justice in a Changing World
(1975), economic growth and social change are
necessary prerequisites to social improvement
and require a free flow of information. For
295
information
Marxists, such as Herb Schiller in Information and
the Crisis Economy (1984) and Information Inequality:
The Deepening Social Crisis in America (1991), however, information is associated with advanced
capitalism in crisis. His three themes are that
market criteria and pressures are important in
information developments; that class inequalities
play a large role in the distribution of, access to,
and generation of information; and that society,
which is undergoing many changes in information and communication systems, is marked by
corporate capitalism. For libertarian and conservative advocates such as Peter Huber in Law and
Disorder in Cyberspace (1997), the information society has unbounded potential for raising standards
of living, increasing comfort, and sparking creativity, if only the hamstringing efforts of governmental entities would get out of the way and stop
seeking to impose their collectivist values on
others. Those theorists who see the information
society as radically different from past societies
are inclined to be optimistic about its possibilities,
whereas those who see the information society as
a progression from past societies tend to predict a
downward spiral.
The political-regulation-school approach to
examining the information society is similar to
the economic approach but is linked to political
processes. Regulation-school theorists, such as
Michel Aglietta in A Theory of Capitalist Regulation:
The US Experience (1979) and Alain Lipietz in Mirages
and Miracles: The Crises of Global Fordism (1987),
examine the mode of accumulation in a given
society and the relationship of accumulation to
its mode of regulation. After a period characterized by the mass production of goods by bluecollar industrial workers, the mass conception of
goods, nation-state oligopolies, and the prominent
role of planning increasing globalization brought
about a state that was denoted by Lipietz in “Fordism and Post-Fordism,” in W. Outhwaite and Tom
Bottomore, The Blackwell Dictionary of TwentiethCentury Social Thought (1993), as post-Fordist. This
post-Fordist period has witnessed the disintegration of vertical organization, a strategy of outsourcing, an international division of labor, and
an assault on organized labor as a whole, and is
marked by flexibility in production, consumption,
and employment. When mass production declines,
the individual emerges as much more individualistic and consumption-centered, and information
takes on an individualistic representation as
people find their own information and even
become information producers on their own.
296
information
There are, of course, other approaches to regulation. One of them is the regulation-analytic
school, which focuses on influences on policymakers and the values that come into play. In
this vein, Gerald Brock in Telecommunication Policy
for the Information Age: From Monopoly to Competition
(1998) examines what he calls a theory of decentralized public decision making. According to
Brock, this model generates rational outcomes
consistent with public preferences.
By contrast, neo-Marxist Dan Schiller in Digital
Capitalism: Networking the Global Market System
(1999), as well as theorists across the political
spectrum, fears the convergence of control over
all information media in a few large multinational corporations. The nature of public life,
the autonomy of consumers, and the quality of
education would be the big losers. Schiller holds
that cyberspace will be the handmaiden of this
unprecedented centralization of power, which
will advance consumerism on a transnational
scale, particularly among privileged groups in
various countries.
Other theorists see information as intrinsic to
political processes and even the nation-state as a
whole. Jürgen Habermas in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a
Category of Bourgeois Society (1962 [trans. 1992])
builds a theory that information is the center of
the public sphere, which is the hub of information
qua social knowledge in a democratic society. The
public sphere is the source discourse, it functions
to construct knowledge, especially political knowledge, out of the information input of its
members.
Information – while perhaps always a fundamental element of political processes, public
spheres, and the nation-state – is playing a larger
role in defining the political realm. Webster points
out the increasing frequency of information warfare that uses intelligence and informational
technologies on the battlefield. This is not simply
a metaphor. Rather, information, as has always
been the case, is critical to military success.
The information-explosion approach to defining
the information society looks at the amount of
scholarly literature on this topic (Price, Little Science, Big Science, 1965) and the ways that information and knowledge play roles in everyday life.
Sometimes this approach joins qualitative understandings to quantitative baselines. This was the
case with Derek deSolla Price, an early exponent
of this approach, who adopted the term “scientometrics” to describe his efforts. As such, he was
information
part of the first generation of information scientists, and is most remembered for having documented the exponential rise of scientific
publications and knowledge across the globe and
across several centuries.
On an even grander scale, Manuel Castells uses
a world-systems perspective to explore the recent
historical transition from development by capitalism to development by information. He posits a
strong link between knowledge and economic
growth, showing that the heretofore intermediate
stage of technological development is unnecessary. Instead, he holds that knowledge can perform the technological function of producing
informatization – knowledge alone may be the
basis of production in the informational society.
How is this new development to take place?
According to Castells, information is both the
raw material and the outcome of technological
change. Information-processing activities in the
industrial mode of development were fostered by
two major factors – the central organizational
capacities of the large corporation and the shift
in the sources of productivity from capital and
labor to factors such as science and technology.
Information-consumption activities were fostered
by two additional factors – the need for information-gathering and -distributing flows to connect
between buyer and seller in the mass-market environment and the state’s role in assuming collective management of goods and services. The state,
in turn, establishes information systems that set
the codes and rules that govern citizens’ lives.
Reich echoes Bell by observing what he calls
the rise in “symbolic-analytic services” as a job
category. These services trade not in concrete
things but in the manipulation of symbols and
visual representations. Workers are problem
solvers: “they simplify reality into abstract images
that can be rearranged, juggled, experimented
with, communicated to other specialists, and
then, eventually, transformed back into reality.”
Whereas “professionals” of the earlier regime
attained mastery of a particular knowledge
domain, symbolic-analysts work by using, not
learning, knowledge. They draw on established
bodies of knowledge to rearrange and analyze
information that already exists. In this way, the
symbolic-analyst is changing the nature of information from static and isolated to dynamic and
integrated. Additionally, the rise of the symbolicanalyst leads to a breakdown in traditional hierarchies of information provision. Workers rise
in the job market not because of hard work or
information
technical expertise but because of inventiveness
and creativity: “the only true competitive advantage lies in skill in solving, identifying, and brokering new problems.” For these theorists, the
widespread availability of information, and not
technology itself, has far-reaching social implications. Perhaps one of the most striking is the way
that ideas can flow easily across borders, even
while people cannot, which will impact the international economic order and spill over into the
quality of lives for millions in both the developed
and developing nations.
One common framework for interpreting the
information society is technological innovation,
especially in telecommunications. “Information
technology (IT) diffusion” can be measured by
the scope of the IT revolution and the proliferation of computer technology (Duff, Information
Society Studies). Frederick Williams remarks that
the information society “is a society where the
economy reflects growth owing to technological
advances.” Piore and Sabel use the term “flexible
specialization” to refer to independent, small
businesses that analyze and respond to markets
far more efficiently than large corporations can.
Simon Nora and Alain Minc in The Computerization of Society: A Report to the President of France (1980)
were the first to propose the term “informatization” to represent the union of computers, telecommunication systems, and social organizations
that leads to a greater informational society. Their
report presented knowledge as the “engine of
growth” and warned of the dangers of noninformational paths of development. Herbert S. Dordick and Georgette Wang in The Information
Society: A Retrospective View (1993) enlarge this interpretation to define “informatization” along
three dimensions – infrastructural, economic,
and social. Informatization therefore is measured
by the number of telephone lines, newspapers,
computers, and television sets in a society, as
well as the number of workers who are engaged
in information technology and the size of the
information sector’s contribution to a nation’s
gross domestic product.
As with the economic definition of the information society, the technological-drivers approach
treats the information society as an objective,
quantifiably measurable entity that has both positive and negative implications.
Cultural theorist Mark Poster provides a semiotic account of studying the information society:
“an adequate account of electronic communications requires a theory that is able to decode the
297
information
linguistic dimension of the new forms of social
interaction.” His term “mode of information”
(which parodies Karl Marx’s notion of the mode
of production) suggests that history can be characterized by stages marked by differing structures of
symbolic exchange and that society currently provides a fetishistic dimension to “information.” He
criticizes the approach of Bell for making the
“postindustrial” idea a model for modern society
and for treating information merely as an economic entity. Bell’s perspective thereby ignores
the ways in which electronic technology disseminates information through communication. Instead, Poster seeks to interrogate cultural forms
of information technology in their modern and
postmodern contexts and to examine the role of
communication systems in postindustrial society.
Within this stream of thought, Jean Baudrillard
views information as being produced equally by
all people and as having no singular meaning or
interpretation. Information can thus be seen as
meaningless. However, he sees that people impose
their meanings on the information, and the structure, which is created, is largely arbitrary. As yet
another meta-framing, Ron Day shows in The
Modern Invention of Information (2001) that there
have been many information ages, and that the
concept itself tends to divorce power from its historical context, thus banishing a troubled history
of winners and losers in information’s construction and application.
When cheap, digital information is combined
with networked computers, new social forms and
interaction patterns can emerge. Some predict
negative consequences for social interaction from
these changes. Sherry Turkle in Life on the Screen:
Identity in the Age of the Internet (1995) sees a wilderness of mirrors in which identity is produced
through online interactions, and is basically synthetic. As a result, senses of community and integration are lost as people flee unpleasant “realworld” social situations for a “life on the screen,”
that is, for online pretending.
James E. Katz and Ronald E. Rice in Social Consequences of Internet Use: Access, Involvement, and Interaction (2002) offer a brighter picture in their study
of the social consequences of internet use. Their
conclusions are based on surveys of both internet
users and those who do not use the internet. These
surveys include the earliest comparative publicopinion surveys about the internet as well as
cross-national comparisons between the United
States and the United Kingdom. They conclude
that the internet does not reduce social capital
but rather contributes to it and also enables novel
298
information
forms of social interaction and self-expression.
One such novel form of information and self-expression they discuss is the web log (or blog) phenomenon. Blogs are a novel blending of diary and
self-expression that erase the lines of public and
private spheres. While blogs have been decried as
a “wasteland of self-important nobodies” (Anon.,
Wall Street Journal Online, 2004), Katz and Rice hold
that they provide a valuable opportunity for
people to express themselves and create new relationships. While Katz and Rice agree that misuse
can occur with any information system, including
the internet, they conclude that the internet
fosters opportunities for satisfying individual
interests while providing collective benefits to
society.
Incisive social critic and sociologist C. Wright
Mills anticipated many of the arguments presented above. He held that “knowledge is no
longer widely felt as an ideal; it is seen as an
instrument. In a society of power and wealth,
knowledge is valued as an instrument of power
and wealth.” He went on to identify numerous
ways in which this proposition was supported,
most famously in The Power Elite (1956).
The ancient view that knowledge is power was
also picked up by Michel Foucault in Discipline and
Punish: The Birth of the Prison (1975 [trans. 1977]),
who advanced provocative ideas about information in a social context and about why information
(and resulting knowledge) is such a coveted commodity. According to him, knowledge is synonymous with power. He presents the Panopticon, a
prison in which guards can see into every cell
but prisoners see neither guards nor other prisoners. The guards therefore have the advantage of
knowledge of the prisoners’ activities. As the prisoners internalize the idea that they are constantly
under surveillance, they begin to self-regulate,
and thus the guards have attained power over
their inmates. However, if a prisoner learns that
he is not being watched, he may try to escape; the
prisoner attains power over the guard as a result
of this knowledge. For Foucault, the relationship
between power and knowledge is inseparable,
so that knowledge always grows out of power
relations and vice versa. In the context of the
information society, a reading of Foucault may
sensitize us to the inherent power relations that
underlie flows of information and the effects that
information and social knowledge can have on
social order and form.
While Foucault takes a highly theoretical approach to power and society, Bell draws a more
concrete relation between knowledge-holders and
information
the ruling class. For Bell, the codification of knowledge, especially in the technical and scientific
professions, plays an increasingly important role
in maintaining society. As a result, a highly
trained and intellectualized elite will lead further
social progress.
On the other hand, Boyle maintains that the
information society may actually lead to horizontal social progress and that the idea of information has become so fluid and pervasive that it
completely dissolves disciplinary boundaries. For
example, gene-mapping as a topic has escaped
from biological discourse to pervade discussions
of social scientists, engineers, and artists. At the
same time, information has become a value-added
dimension of commercial products that needs to
be protected. As technological materials (such as
DVD disks) become cheaper to use and own, their
informational or intellectual content makes up a
greater part of the end product’s value.
This shift is echoed by Lyotard, who believes
that knowledge is increasingly becoming an informational commodity. Because knowledge as a
commodity is vital to maintaining productive
power, nation-states may “fight for the control of
information, just as they battled in the past for
control over territory, and afterwards for control
of access to and exploitation of raw materials
and cheap labor.” The state no longer has a monopoly on the distribution of knowledge and information: as the need for transparent and clear
information begins to underpin society, economic
interests butt heads with the state, and the
state grows powerless to control information
and knowledge dissemination and must reexamine its traditional role in guiding technological
progress.
For the optimists of the information society,
notably Yoneji Masuda in The Information Society as
Post-Industrial Society (1981), information access encourages people to participate in democracy and
to improve the environment by working from
home and spending more time in creative, intellectual work. For him and other optimists, informatization can redress and prevent social
problems like the unequal distribution of wealth
and slow economic development. Melvin Kranzberg in “The Information Age: Evolution or Revolution?,” in B. R. Guild (ed.), Information Technologies
and Social Transformation (1985), likewise believes
that the increased production of knowledge in the
information society will allow people to understand their options and the consequences of their
actions better, thus preventing catastrophic wars.
Even earlier, the theorist Kenneth E. Boulding
information
in The Meaning of the Twentieth Century: The Great
Transition (1964) proposed the term “postcivilization” to describe the freedom that he expected the
information society to bring out of the Marxist
socioeconomic class revolutions of the past.
According to Boulding, as the information society
builds up the sphere of the self-conscious social
against the individual, general mental evolution
will guide further social progression.
Wireless mobile communication promises to be
the next information revolution as it changes
people’s work and study habits and their activities
in public space (Katz, “A Nation of Ghosts? Choreography of Mobile Communication in Public
Spaces,” in K. Nyiri [ed.], Mobile Democracy: Essays
on Society, Self and Politics, 2003). When mobile communication is combined with the internet, new
problems arise, but so do novel social and economic opportunities that are comparable to those
precipitated by the computer and that can enrich
the lives of vast numbers of people, from all backgrounds and all regions of the world.
For many centuries, various experts thought
that increased information would lead to better
lives, and that enhanced communication would
lead to harmonious social interaction, perhaps
even an end to strife and war. In terms of material
lives, improved technology based on better information has eased many material burdens, so that
an ordinary worker in industrial society typically
has a life of comfort (air conditioning, antibiotics,
TV) that was beyond the reach of the richest
mogul. In terms of the second contention, it
may be that the opposite is true. While faster
flow of information can lead to enhanced material
lives, it also speeds misinformation. It is possible
that a corollary obtains, namely that new information technologies, such as the mobile phone,
can give rise to anxiety: one must be in touch
and ready to react. Or that making more information available, such as is the case with internet
websites and blogs, can keep alive, and even
stimulate, the growth of dissident political movements and attacks on even the largest media
empires.
Moreover, information flows can lead to demands for transparency and accountability at
every level from institutional to micro-social. So
instead of being a fountainhead of freedom, increased information can lead to demands for increased constraints and monitoring. From a
sociological perspective, there are many ironies
in information flow.
It is worth noting too that much attention has
been paid to sociological analyses of information
299
information society
that emphasize potential monopolistic and exploitative practices among the owners of media
content. Yet the Marxist-inspired view that the
centralized control of the means of production,
in this case of information, determines material
conditions is being turned on its head due to
technological advances. This line of argument
was pioneered by Ithiel de Sola Pool, who declared
in Technologies of Freedom (1983) that technologies
of freedom aim at pluralism of expression rather
than a dissemination of prefabricated ideas. Pool’s
prescient ideas have become realized, perhaps
more profoundly than even he might have imagined. The novel and ever-increasing array of
alternative communication systems continues to
surprise and amaze social scientists. These range
from internet steganography and web-cams to
mobile phone videos, alterative reality games
and geopositional monitoring. These proliferating
and ingenious applications have severely eroded
dominant paradigms of elites and the power of
traditional monopolistic “one-to-many” technologies (such as newspaper publishing, broadcast TV,
and studio films).
Because of personal communication technology, information has lost its relevance as part of
a Marxist superstructure of production that sits
atop society. It has instead become a form of
struggle within society. Despite efforts to the contrary at the level of policymaking, information is
becoming ever more fungible as a commodity
even while its meaning and interpretation becomes more contested. More voices are raised in
every quarter, and there is an open contest over
knowledge claims. Even while more data is collected at the level of the individual social actor,
dictators around the world are confronted by information they would wish to banish.
The ultimate irony, though, may be that, while
the narrow definition of information discussed
above – that information is uncertainty reduction
– is germane at local levels, the larger-ranging
impact may be the opposite: knowledge leads
to growth in uncertainty and psychological tension. Shannon’s axioms, as it turns out, are extremely apposite to social science and public
policy: increased information also leads to increased uncertainty. It does this in the soft terms
of human lives lived, every bit as much as in the
hard terms of communication network efficiencies achieved.
JAMES E. KATZ
information society
– see information.
300
institution(s)
information superhighway
– see information.
information technology
– see information.
inner-directed character
– see David Riesman.
instinct
– see genetics.
institutional theory
– see institution(s).
institutionalization of conflict
– see social conflict.
institutionalized racism
– see race and ethnicity.
institution(s)
Émile Durkheim defined sociology as the scientific
study of institutions. In everyday language we
refer to institutions in terms of a heterogeneous
array of concrete social forms such as the family,
the church, or the monarchy. Departments of sociology traditionally had mainstream courses that
were called “social theory and social institutions”
indicating that sociology was the study of the
principal institutions that make up what we call
society. There is, however, a second and more
subtle meaning in which institutions are conceived as regular patterns of behavior that are
regulated by norms and sanctions into which individuals are socialized. Institutions are thus an
ensemble of social roles.
In mainstream sociology, it was conventional to
recognize five clusters of major institutions in
society. These are: (1) economic institutions for
the production, distribution, and consumption of
goods and services; (2) political institutions that
regulate and control access to power; (3) institutions of social stratification that regulate access to
prestige and social status; (4) kinship, marriage,
and family that control reproduction; and finally
(5) cultural institutions that are concerned with
religious, symbolic, and cultural practices.
The analysis of these clusters was a central feature of social systems theory, and it can be said
that the functionalist sociology of Talcott Parsons
was a major contribution to this branch of sociology. In The Social System (1951: 39), Parsons
institution(s)
defined an institution as “a complex of institutionalized role integrates (or status-relationships)
which is of strategic structural significance for the
social system in question.” Parsons argued that
institutions are fundamental to the overall integration of social systems.
The contemporary analysis of institutions has,
however, been decisively influenced by the sociological writings of Peter L. Berger, whose general
sociology was in turn influenced by the philosophical anthropology of the German sociologist
Arnold Gehlen. Berger did much to introduce the
work of Gehlen to English-speaking social science,
for example in his introduction to Gehlen’s Man
in the Age of Technology (1957 [trans. 1980]). In general terms, Gehlen argued, following Friedrich
Nietzsche (1844–1900), that human beings are
“not yet finished animals.” By this expression,
Gehlen meant that human beings are biologically
ill equipped to cope with the world into which
they are born and they have no finite instinctual
basis that is specific to a given natural environment, and depend upon a long period of socialization in order to acquire the knowledge and skills
to exist in the world. Gehlen claimed that, in
order to cope with life, human beings have
“world-openness,” that is human beings have to
create and maintain a cultural world to replace or
to supplement their instinctual world. It is this
incompleteness that provides the anthropological
explanation for the origins of social institutions.
Berger and Thomas Luckmann, in The Construction
of Social Reality (1967), developed this position to
argue that, since human beings are, as it were,
biologically underdeveloped, they have to construct a social canopy or religion around themselves in order to complete or supplement their
biology.
Institutions are the social bridges between
human beings and their natural environment
and it is in terms of these institutions that human
life becomes coherent and meaningful. Institutions, in filling the gap created by instinctual
deprivation, provide humans with relief from the
tensions generated by their undirected instinctual
drives. Over time, these institutions come to be
taken for granted and become part of the implicit
background of social action. The social foreground
is occupied by reflective, practical, and conscious
practices. With modernization, however, there is a
process of de-institutionalization with the result
that the taken-for-granted background becomes
less reliable, more open to negotiation, culturally
fluid, and increasingly an object of critical debate
institution(s)
and reflection. Accordingly the social foreground
expands, and the everyday world becomes risky
and precarious. The objective, sacred institutions
of tradition recede, and modern life becomes subjective, contingent, and problematic. According
to Gehlen, we live in a world of secondary or
quasi-institutions. There are profound psychological changes that are associated with these social
developments. In premodern societies, human beings had character that is a firm, coherent, and
definite psychological structure that corresponded with reliable social roles and institutions.
In modern societies, people have personalities
that are fluid and flexible, like the precarious
institutions in which they live. The existential
pressures on human beings are significant and to
some extent modern people are confronted with
the uncertainties of what Berger, B. Berger, and
H. Kellner called The Homeless Mind (1973).
This theory of institutions and their decline
presupposes a theory of secularization in which
the traditional sanctions behind institutions decline with the advent of modern, risk-ridden cultures. However, the contemporary revival of
religion suggests that this melancholic picture of
uncertainty requires some correction. Berger’s
early sociology was also influenced by the work
of Helmut Schelsky who, in an influential article,
asked the question “Can Continuous Questioning
be Institutionalized?” in Norman Birnbaum and
Gertrud Lenzer (eds.), Sociology of Religion (1957
[trans. 1969]). His conclusion was that a process
of continuous reflectivity was not humanly possible, if enduring and reliable social relationships
were to survive. While a number of sociologists,
such as Ulrich Beck and Anthony Giddens, have
argued that “de-traditionalization” and “reflexive
modernization” are the predominant trends of
late modernity, there are valid counterarguments,
both sociological and psychological, to suggest that
people in their everyday lives need stable social
structures. Where there is de-traditionalization,
there will also be countervailing movements of reinstitutionalization.
Whereas traditional sociology was the study of
institutions, the speed of social change in contemporary society and the apparent flexibility of
social arrangements have meant that sociologists
have sought to avoid treating institutions as if
they were things, and have looked more towards
social processes – that is towards processes of institutionalization, de-institutionalization, and reinstitutionalization – than towards stable clusters
of roles. Institutions should not be reified, but
301
instrumental rationality
rather treated as maps by which to read social
processes.
BRYAN S. TURNER
instrumental rationality
– see rationality.
intellectuals
Three notions are intertwined in the idea of the
intellectual: intellectuals, the intelligentsia, and
intellectual labor.
The term intellectual came into common usage
with the Dreyfus affair in France (1894–1906),
during which the novelist Émile Zola wrote a politically charged open letter in a popular periodical. In the public controversy which followed this
crossing of the boundary between culture and
politics, Zola was accused of being a mere “intellectual,” a publicity-seeking dilettante, a popularizer who degraded cultural values in seeking a
wider audience. In response, the term intellectual
became a nom de guerre for those who wished to
do public battle with the establishment, be they
cultural or political.
The intelligentsia is historically older, having its
roots in sections of the Russian and Polish elite in
the middle of the nineteenth century who identified themselves with European modernity. The intelligentsia achieved even greater social cohesion
in taking on the missionary task of bringing enlightenment to what it considered the darker
regions of eastern Europe and central Asia.
As a sociological concept, the idea that the
working population could be divided and defined
by a division between intellectual and manual
labor emerged later as part of an attempt to operationalize the concept. The idea of intellectual
labor as the defining characteristic of the intellectual has, however, been projected backward in
time by those seeking to identify a material and
objective basis for empirical investigation. It has
served as a means of distinguishing various strata
of the middle class, for example. The “intellect” is
here treated as a source of income and social
status and “intelligence” as a personal attribute,
a form of rent-bearing property: human capital.
From this perspective, one may speak of “intellectual professions,” as well as attempting to divide
intellectual from manual labor.
Common to these three notions is the attempt
to define the intellectual as a distinctive social
category and to make some judgments about its
functions and its behavior. In the 1920s, Julien
Benda (1867–1956) railed against the “treason of
the intellectuals,” because in his eyes this social
302
intelligence
group was not fulfilling its proper role as social
reformers and critics, while Antonio Gramsci distinguished “organic” and “traditional intellectuals” on the basis of their role in social change
as much as their allotted class position. Decades
later, the American sociologist Alvin Gouldner
spoke of the intellectuals as a “new class,” to
which Georgy Konrad and Ivan Szelenyi, in their
Intellectuals on the Road to Class Power (1979), developed the idea that intellectuals, expecially in
central and eastern Europe, were moving towards
class power. The opposite point of view was proposed by John Goldthorpe in “On the Service
Class” (1982) in Anthony Giddens and G. Mackenzie
(eds.), Social Class and the Division of Labour, where he
defined intellectuals as a service class with conservative rather than radical political orientations.
Another point of view is offered by Ron Eyerman in Between Culture and Politics (1994), who defines intellectuals as an assumed social role,
rather than an assigned social category or personality type. The intellectual from this point of view
mediates and reinvents ideals and traditions in
new historical contexts. Facilitating factors in
this process are often social movements, which
provide opportunities for those without formal
“intellectual” qualifications to assume the functions traditionally associated with intellectuals,
mediating culture and politics.
RON EYERMAN
intelligence
The publication of Francis Galton’s Hereditary
Genius (1869) pre-dates by several decades the
period which is normally taken to be the moment
marking the beginning of modern sociology.
Writing in the aftermath of Charles Darwin’s
Origin of Species and The Ascent of Man, Galton maintained the real objective existence both of racial
differences and of social class differences in
mental ability. Émile Durkheim’s insistence, in
Suicide (1896), that this phenomenon was to be
explained primarily by collective rather than
individual factors can be seen as a deliberate reaction against the prior tendency to suppose that
human behavior is biologically or genetically determined. The question of the “heritability of intelligence” was critical in resolving whether or
not a sociology of education might be necessary
or possible and whether it was justifiable to
expend public finance in order to expand educational provision. The acceptance in general that
human behavior is at least partly modified by
social interaction, that human character is at least
partly the product of “nurture” rather than
wholly determined by “nature”, is a sine qua non
intelligence
for sociological research, and the debate about
intelligence has provided a case study for this
larger issue at significant moments in western
social history since 1869.
In 1953, Brian Simon wrote a small book entitled
Intelligence Testing and the Comprehensive School. In
the Preface to the text, a teacher asked: “Have we
achieved ‘secondary education for all,’ the reform
that was the keystone of the Education Act, 1944?
If not, why not? What are the fundamental misconceptions and practices that stand in our way?”
What was at stake was the widening of opportunity within the British educational system that was
projected immediately at the end of World War II.
The teacher believed that Simon had exposed
the obstacle to progress towards egalitarianism:
“He shows how the practice of intelligence testing
is used to justify the curtailment of opportunity
from the junior school onwards; he shows also
how theories based on intelligence testing uphold
a form of school organization, and forms of teaching, which make secondary education for all impossible.” The book was reproduced in entirety
in Simon’s Intelligence, Psychology and Education. A
Marxist Critique (1971) and he asked in a new introduction why a publisher should want to reprint
the earlier text, since the reorganization of secondary education on comprehensive lines was
“now well under way.” He indicated, however,
that victory was far from secured in the United
States. He suggested that “attempts to reanimate
the ideology of ‘intelligence’ testing in the United
States, as a barrier to the declared policy of desegregating schools, indicate that there are powerful
social and political forces in favor of reinstating
the doctrine that intelligence is innate and impervious to educational influences, to the detriment
of social and educational advance.” He was especially referring to the article by Arthur Jensen
which appeared in the Harvard Educational Review
in 1969 with the title: “How Much Can We Boost
IQ and Scholastic Achievement?” This article
relied on data on identical and fraternal twins
reared apart which had been accumulated by Cyril
Burt from the 1920s and presented in his Factors of
the Mind (1940). Simon’s text of 1971 criticized
Burt’s work but, in the second edition of 1978,
he was able to quote L. J. Kamin’s The Science and
Politics of I.Q. (1977) to suggest that Burt’s research
had “fudged” the evidence.
Nevertheless, the debate continued and still
continues. Robert B. Joynson’s The Burt Affair
(1989) questioned Kamin’s criticisms, and a new
statement of the heritability thesis appeared in
1994, occasioning much comment and political
intentionality
dispute. In The Bell Curve (1994), Charles Murray
and Richard Herrnstein asserted, on the basis of
statistics derived from the National Longitudinal
Survey of Youth in the United States, that intelligence is largely inherited and that genes play a
part in the fact that African Americans score
lower than whites on intelligence tests. The
debate about intelligence has always had important implications for developments in social and
educational policy (see social policy). Michael
Young’s satire of 1958 entitled The Rise of the Meritocracy, 1870–2033 was sub-titled “An Essay on Education and Inequality.” The book coined the word
meritocracy which then became part of the language of subsequent thinking about education
and society, linking with the assumption of credentialism that occupational and social advancement are the consequence of individual merit.
Young proposed the formula that IQ + Effort =
Merit and expressed skepticism that social engineering might be achieved without reference to
class assumptions or prejudices. The implications
of the debate now seem more serious as rapid
developments occur as a result of research in genetics, cognitive neuroscience, and molecular biology. After some discussion in the late 1920s of
Charles Spearman’s postulate that there must be
a general factor of intelligence, labeled “g,” that is
the underlying cause of an individual’s performance in varied tests, Francis Fukuyama commented in his Our Posthuman Future. Consequences
of the Biotechnology Revolution (2003) that scientific
advances will soon generate a more refined understanding of this phenomenon, and that there is a
possibility that the consequences of such good
knowledge will be beneficial. He suggests that
brain imaging techniques can chart blood flow
and neuron firings and that it may then become
possible to correlate these with different kinds of
mental activities so as to determine with some
finality whether “g is one thing or many things.”
Bad science has been used for bad ends in the past
but, as Fukuyama optimistically concludes his discussion of the sciences of the brain and the heritability of intelligence, this should not rule out the
possibility that good science may serve us well in
the future.
DEREK ROBBINS
intelligence task
– see intelligence.
intentionality
This is a subject with philosophical origins and
identifiable roots, according to some authorities,
as far back as Parmenides in the fifth century BCE,
303
interaction
and certainly of importance in classical and medieval writings before the contemporary interest,
which is usually dated to the work of the phenomenologist Franz Brentano (1838–1917). Mental
states are said to be intentional insofar as they
have a content. Beliefs, attitudes, desires, purposes, and the like, that are about something –
for example, I believe that extraterrestrials are among
us, I am in favor of government by extraterrestrials, and
I plan to vote for extraterrestrials in the next election –
are thus distinguished from other kinds of mental
state – for example, affective states such as I am
depressed – which do not require a specified content for them to be coherent or intelligible. This
particular technical use is to be distinguished
from a related use in ordinary language and legal
judgments, where the focus of interest is the
intended effect of an action. The former became
a subject of philosophical and sociological inquiry
through John L. Austin’s (1911–60) work on
“speech acts,” and the latter have been the subject
of work by many jurists including Austin himself.
Brentano’s focus on what he termed intentional
inexistence – which is to say mental content that
is not tied to any known existing state of affairs as
in the case of the extraterrestrials above – raises
interesting conceptual challenges. For him, the
argument from the observation that mental states
do not depend on existing cases or experiences
and the claim that mental states are qualitatively
different to physical states led to a conclusion in
favor of dualism, but left open the problem of how
a mental state thus defined can become a physical
cause.
Others, while not subscribing to an overtly dualist position in seeking to avoid this problem have
argued that intentionality inheres in computational states of the brain which are themselves
physical. However, this account is vulnerable to
the problem that there is no necessary correspondence between physical state and belief state,
nor between the belief states of two physically
matched entities as Hilary Putnam (1926– ) argued
with his Twin Earth thought experiment.
One response to the problems raised by intentionality has been the proposal that it is an
epiphenomenon and plays no role in the determination of individual action. Another, which
derives from both certain behavioral and hermeneutical positions, has been to argue that intentional talk effectively attributes intentional
states to individuals, by themselves or by other
individuals, and is part of the public calculus on
which we base the prediction of our own and each
other’s behavior. Fundamental to what some refer
304
interaction
to as the intentional stance (Donald Davidson
[1917–2003] and Daniel Dennett [1942– ]) is the
mutual recognition that individual actors have
of each other’s interpretations of their actions as
intentional. In this view, the analyst’s focus on
intentionality is drawn away from unobservable
internal psychological states to public events and
the external environment.
DAVID GOOD
interaction
In general, the term interaction is associated with
micro-sociological studies of social processes involving face-to-face encounters, and of contexts
in which people act in relation to one another.
But the term also has a broader sociostructural
import, involving a macro-sociological orientation, in that many sociologists view social systems
as built upon systems of interaction. Such systems
arise out of the production of both face-to-face
interaction and interaction with others who
are physically absent; they thus stretch away in
time and space in terms of their wider implications for analysis of the social field.
The micro-sociological analysis of interaction
derives its central impetus from Max Weber’s
concept of Verstehen (understanding), by which
Weber sought to underscore the basic role of subjective interpretation in human doing and human
action. To understand what a social agent is doing
in any particular social context, according to
Weber, demands some minimal consideration of
how that agent subjectively grasps the meaning
of their own behavior. Applying this insight to
the normative character of social action, Talcott
Parsons wrote of the “double contingency” that
shapes interaction. For Parsons, the reactions of
the other(s) always frame the acts of the social
actor, because the nature of contingent responses
is such that it serves as a potential sanction in the
broader context of power relations.
The micro-sociological study of interaction has
taken different forms. One of the most influential has issued from ethnomethodology and
analysis of “turn-taking” in conversational interaction. When we engage in conversational talk,
for example, much of what we do is based on our
recognition that only one person usually speaks at
a time (termed the seriality of participants) in
order to constitute interaction as meaningful.
Another tradition which focuses upon the conventions whereby the communication of meaning
in interaction is achieved is that of critical theory,
specifically the work of Jürgen Habermas. The
reproduction of social life unfolds, according to
Habermas, not only through technological modes
intergenerational mobility
of action but also through “symbolic interaction.”
In this sociological communicative framework,
interaction is contextualized in terms of the symbolic structuring of communication, with reflection upon human action arising in and through
reflexive linguistic interaction.
Other sociologists have been critical of the
micro-sociological neglect of the role of temporality and social reproduction in grasping how interaction, the social field, and history are closely
intertwined. Other sociologists suggest that the
micro- versus macro-sociological distinction fails
to grasp the radical extension of human interaction in space and in time as a consequence of
the overall development of modernity. In this respect, Anthony Giddens has argued that, rather
than contrast small-group interaction with larger forms of communal interaction, sociologists
should focus on the more profound difference in
interaction between face-to-face encounters and
interpersonal communication with others at a distance. The development of writing, according to
Giddens, radically extends the scope of “distanciated interaction” whereby agents can access
the past through interaction with texts. Writing
and its technologies also fundamentally alter the
nature of the social interactions that can be
carried out: the temporal gap between agents engaged in dialogical interaction is obviously much
less in the case of someone sending a fax to someone on the other side of the world than would be
the case in an exchange of letters.
A persistent theme in contemporary sociology
is that globalization is reconstituting interaction
in complex and uneven ways, principally as a
result of radical transmutations in structures of
signification. This extension of interaction in time
and space concerns not only the new information
technologies that people deploy in their day-to-day
lives, but also the mediated representations we
have of others distant in time and in space. Here
the focus is on individuals or groups of people we
do not interact with on a daily basis, but with
whom, through mediated interaction, we come
to forge some sense of cognitive and emotional
connection – however minimal. A N T H O N Y E L L I O T T
intergenerational mobility
– see social mobility.
intergenerational processes
– see generation(s).
internal colonialism
– see colonialism.
internet society
internet society
The term internet society has two general meanings. The first is a physical society that has a
large proportion of its populace online and active
in consuming, communicating, or producing information via the internet. The second refers to
the activities of people online, and the extent to
which such activities may be perceived as reproducing, imitating, or extending in a virtual sense
the activities that are carried on in a physically
real society. This second sense is a new layer on an
older discussion of the “information society.”
In terms of the first sense – a society whose
members spend a great deal of time using the
internet – two visions are usually offered: optimistic and pessimistic. The optimistic or even utopian
vision is that internet technology will enable societies to overcome the digital divide and increase
social, political, and economic participation. Use of
traditional, often stigmatizing, categories will disappear because users become unable to use such
categories and instead will deal with each other on
an unbiased basis. The other vision is pessimistic,
or even dystopian. It foresees a loss of privacy
and other civil rights, “cyber-ghettoes,” exacerbation of inequality, and dominance of modes of
communication by malevolent corporations or
governments.
Clearly, there are some important changes
taking place as more activities are transplanted
from real-world social settings to online ones. For
instance, dating and match-making have a long
tradition. These arrangements were carried out
via each new communication technology, including the mail, newspapers, telephones, and computers. With the internet, millions of people are
now involved in seeking new personal relationships. The combination of the power of the computer with networks means that one can search
the world over for a relationship candidate. The
seeker is offered unprecedented choices. There are
important ramifications for the establishment,
maintenance, and termination of real-life relationships. It has been speculated that, as online
options increase, people will be less willing to
invest in the emotional tasks of real-life relationships, which will suffer as a result. So an internet
society, it seems, follows the rubric that applies to
other areas of life: when new opportunities arise,
they often entail costs to existing structures.
As to the second meaning of internet society,
theorists have examined social relationships
that have grown out of a technology based on
physically stationary computers and wire-based
305
interpellation
communication links among them. Inquiry has
focused on the nature and number of online
communities. Boundary creation and reinforcing
mechanisms, the motives for participation in virtual societies, and the relationship between these
societies and physical ones are central analytical
constructs in this endeavor.
At the same time, R. S. Ling, in The Mobile Connection (2004), makes clear that the trajectory of use is
towards mobile internet, which in turn will require a conceptual modification on the part of
scholars. The questions of the use of public space
and social relationships stemming from this
change have been little studied. One line of reasoning concerning this is that a “walled garden”
will develop, in which people become more tightly linked to their primary relationships and
exclude those outside these relationships, and
also reduce their psychological if not physical
presence in public places. Such technological
changes will also transform the use of public
space as more people physically occupy restaurants and other public venues while being mentally absorbed in the world of the distant other.
JAMES E. KATZ
interpellation
A term developed and made popular by the
French Marxist philosopher Louis Althusser, this
describes the process by which ideology addresses
the individual. The word shares the root of the
word “appellation” (name) and interpellation is a
hailing, according to Althusser. If a policeman
shouts “Hey, you there!” at least one individual
will turn around to “answer” that call. At the
moment of realization that the addressee is oneself, one becomes a subject of the ideology of law
(see law and society). This almost instantaneous
process operates not simply at the level of individual interaction, but also is the point at which the
police officer, representing an arm of the state,
weaves the subject into a web of law. For Althusser
this is generally how ideology operates: we are
always caught up in processes in which we voluntarily acknowledge the validity of the ideological
practices. Interpellation draws on the structuralist theory that the notion of an autonomous
human subject is an illusion, since human beings
are enmeshed in discursive and social structures
that shape their identity.
Film theorists in the 1970s used the concept of
interpellation to suggest that mainstream cinema
acts as an “apparatus” to position the viewers to
“misrecognize” themselves through identification
with the fictional characters on the screen. They
306
interview(s)
thus appear to possess coherent, autonomous personalities solving conflicts, moving from disunity
to unity. Ideology is understood here not in the
sense of false beliefs but as constructing the nature
of experience itself, thus creating an imaginary
relation to the real.
LARRY RAY
interpretation
– see Verstehen.
interpretive repertoires
– see discourse analysis.
interval scale
– see measurement.
interview(s)
These are widely used forms of data collection,
not only within sociology but across the social
sciences. Although intuitively an attractive and
inherently “truthful” source of data about matters of sociological interest, data derived by researchers from talking to people (or via the
analysis of research participants talking to each
other) may also be subsumed under the category
of low-inference descriptors – that is, as the sort
of data that should always be treated with circumspection. Some critiques from within feminism
have dismissed the use of interviews in principle
as necessarily reproducing relationships of patriarchal dominance, given the power differential
in the roles of interviewer and interviewee,
respectively.
Interviews are used for a variety of purposes,
and may be employed in a variety of forms. Interviews are a routinely used technique in the pilotstudy phase of larger-scale research endeavors
where they may be employed to trial alternative
questionnaire item wordings or to assist in item
generation for larger-scale research. Increasingly,
interviews are employed in their own right as a
stand-alone research tool: for example to permit
the identification of the interpretative repertoires
of particular groups regarding social issues by the
use of discourse analysis; to survey public perceptions of specific political matters; or to develop
novel theoretical understandings of issues via
the use of grounded theory.
Interview methods vary in terms of the rigidity
of the requirement for the interviewer to adhere
exactly to a pre-scripted schedule. In terms of this
requirement – inspired by a concern for quasi-statistical reliability – interviews may, broadly, be
characterized as structured, semi-structured, and
“conversational”/open-ended. Absolute fidelity to
interview(s)
pre-scripted questions is demanded by structured
interviews, a degree of flexibility – for example
paraphrasis and clarification of items – is allowable in semi-structured approaches, and under
open-ended interviewing the simple provision of a
number of probe questions permits respondents to
elaborate on issues of research interest. Interviews
may be employed as individually administered research devices or, less commonly, via the use of
carefully selected small groups of participants, as
a tool for the generation of data from a number of
respondents simultaneously. The focus group may
be distinguished from a group interview, in that
the moderator of a focus group is usually concerned to facilitate a group discussion via a series
of open-ended questions and probes, rather than
to elicit a group’s answers to a sequence of predetermined interview questions.
Data collected by interviews also varies, that is,
respondents’ answers to pre-scripted questions
may be field coded and simply recorded as a
number (see Extract 1 for an example of problematic field coding); alternatively, the interview may
be tape-recorded and transcribed either verbatim
(as, for example, are Hansard and court transcripts) or using the more finely grained conventions of conversational analysis which record
linguistic details such as prosody, inflection, and
emphasis. Whatever the purpose, administration
format, and eventual representation of the interview, for the most part the contemporary use of
the social scientific interview as research tool
depends upon, or rather implicitly accepts, a
number of usually unexamined key assumptions.
Thus it is assumed, for example, that: all interview
questions veridically represent the intent of the
designer of the interview schedule and are delivered by interviewers precisely as such; that all
interview questions have the same semantic meaning to all respondents; that all interviewer utterances are questions and all interviewee utterances
are more or less well-formed responses; and, most
crucially, that interview talk is an essentially unproblematic means of transmitting the contents of
one mind to another. This frequently unstated
belief has been termed the conduit metaphor, or,
less kindly, the telementational fallacy.
Although the empirical study of a variety of
specific settings in which interviews are used as
sense-making practices (for example in doctor–
patient encounters, psychotherapy sessions, or
news interviews) has a long history in ethnomethodology, more recently – particularly since
the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein (see Philosophical
Investigations, 1958) and the linguistic turn in the
interview(s)
Extract 1 (from M. Rapley and C. Antaki, “A
Conversation Analysis of the ‘Acquiescence’ of
People with Learning Disabilities,” 1996, Journal
of Community & Applied Social Psychology; transcription simplified):
Interviewer: D’you feel out of place out an’ about
in social situations?
Anne:
No.
Interviewer: Anne? Never?
Anne:
No.
Interviewer: Sometimes?
Anne:
No.
Interviewer: Or usually?
Anne:
Sometimes I do.
Interviewer: Yeah? OK, we’ll put a 2 down for that
one then.
social sciences – not only have interviews become
an increasingly prevalent research method but
also, through the use of conversational analysis,
a body of work has begun to examine critically
the ways that social science interviews themselves
are used as academic sense-making practices. For
example, Hanneke Houtkoop-Steenstra’s work
(Interaction and the Standardised Interview: The Living
Questionnaire, 2000) focused on the administration
of market-research questionnaires, and Rapley
and Antaki’s work (1996) has examined the delivery of psychological tests as interactional practices, rather than as neutral probes into the
attitudes, beliefs, or intentions of respondents.
This work has started to cast doubt on longcherished social-scientific notions that interviews
offer an unproblematic “window to the soul.”
Extract 2 (from Rapley and Antaki, 1996; transcription simplified):
Interviewer: Erm and I’d like you to answer some
questions to tell me how you feel
about the –
Arthur:
They’re not ’ard ones are they?
Interviewer: Not very hard
Arthur:
No
Interviewer: No and if you don’t understand them
Arthur you can just tell me
Arthur:
Yeus
Interviewer: And I’ll I’ll say them differently. . .
Interviewer: So there’s no hurry do you have any
questions to ask me?
Arthur:
Yeers
Interviewer: What would you like to ask me?
Arthur:
I like being I like being er in ’ere
Interviewer: You like: being
Arthur:
Living in ’ere like I like living in ’ere
307
intimacy
Irigaray, Luce (1932– )
Rather, from this perspective, with interviews
understood as being no different to any other
piece of talk-in-interaction, it becomes clear that
the local interactional business of “doing interviewing” and “doing being interviewed” may itself
become highly salient in its own right; see Extract
2 for an example of how the very business of
the interview and its consequences becomes a
difficult topic.
Interviews remain a staple method in the social
scientific armamentarium. However, the canonical assumptions about the precise replicability
of interview protocols across respondents – upon
which the reliability and validity of aggregate
data gathered via interviews rely – warrant critical
review. Close attention to the social organization
of interaction revealed by interview transcripts
suggests that these assumptions are simply not
borne out by the data.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
intimacy
This is a relatively new word in the sociological
lexicon and, although sociologists have long
researched the “private sphere,” or families, or
marriage, they have not seen intimacy as a proper
focus for sociological theory. This changed, initially with the rise of feminist research which
began to identify close personal, heterosexual, relationships as possible sites of oppression for
women. In some senses feminist work prized
open the black box of close personal relationships
and began to challenge the assumption that intimacy was simply personal and/or the realm of
psychoanalysis or psychology. The mainstream
sociological revolution in understanding intimacy
came, however, with Anthony Giddens, in The
Transformation of Intimacy (1992), who called to attention the ways in which the qualities of personal
relationships were changing in late modern times.
He introduced concepts of “confluent love” and
the “pure relationship.” The former refers to the
quality of a relationship in which it is the mutual
sharing of thoughts and feelings that matters
most. Confluent love is said to be based on equality,
while the more traditional idea of romantic love
is based on gender inequality. The pure relationship signifies one which will only last as long as it
is mutually fulfilling. Under such a regime it is
seen as acceptable to end a relationship which no
longer meets one’s needs and interests. In constructing these models of contemporary relationships, Giddens owes much to earlier feminist work
which criticized the power imbalances between
men and women. Indeed, he argues that it is
308
women who are demanding these “new” kinds of
relationships and who are leaving marriages if
they are not satisfied with the quality of intimacy,
that is established. Moreover, Giddens argues that
it is same-sex relationships which are in the vanguard of the new form of intimacy, because they
are not based on traditional understandings of
gender difference.
Giddens’s intimacy is, however, mainly a sexual
intimacy; his focus is on the couple, whether heterosexual or homosexual. Other sociological discussions of intimacy have broadened the concept
to include friendship, intergenerational relationships, and parent–child relationships. Thus Lynn
Jamieson in Intimacy (1998) speaks of “disclosing
intimacy” which is of a different sort to bodily or
sexual intimacy and can encompass rather different sorts of close relationships. Work on friendship is perhaps the most interesting development
because the predominant sociological emphasis
on family life and relationships has tended to
obscure the significance of intimate friendships.
Friends have been treated as being of less significance than family members, and friendships as
less enduring than marriages. Social factors such
as high rates of divorce, the growth of singleperson households, and the rise of childlessness
have combined to ignite a re-appraisal of friendship as an important sociological category. Studies
of friendship and friendship networks (often
based on the workplace) have replaced studies of
communities (based on where people live), and
contemporary friendships are now understood to
be relationships which endure notwithstanding
the fact that individuals may have relationships
based on sexual intimacy as well.
CAROL SMART
invisible religion
– see religion.
Irigaray, Luce (1932– )
Born in Belgium, Irigaray has made her home
since the 1960s in France, where she trained in
psychoanalysis with Jacques Lacan. Her first, and
most famous work, Speculum of the Other Woman
(1974 [trans. 1985]), argued that women have
been excluded from both philosophy and psychoanalytic theory. This exclusion is explained by
Irigaray in terms of the identification of women
with nature and the association of women with
motherhood (an identification which applies
whether or not women are mothers). In contrast
to this, men are identified with culture and subjectivity, a subjectivity which women support. In
this analysis, Irigaray employs that distinction
Irigaray, Luce (1932– )
between men/culture and women/nature which
has become a familiar premise of feminist theory,
and she emphasizes – as Simone de Beauvoir had
done in The Second Sex (1949 [trans. 1972]) – that
the only form of subjectivity in western culture
is male.
Irigaray’s theoretical antecedents lie in a
number of disciplines, of which psychoanalysis
and philosophy are perhaps the most dominant.
But Irigaray’s own work crosses conventional
disciplinary boundaries, in that her concerns are
less with specific institutional changes in the
social status and position of women (she is not
concerned, for example, with social rearrangements of the social role of mothers) than with a
iron law of oligarchy
rethinking of the ways in which women and men
encounter the body and their physical existence.
For Irigaray, the most important shift in the reconfiguration of gender is the recognition by
men that nature / the body do not have to be controlled and that the “imaginary body” (a concept
inherited from Lacan) is not to be identified with
that of men. Thus welcoming the possibilities that
Sigmund Freud opened up for the study of sexuality, Irigaray also wishes to counter Freud’s theories about women and their sense of loss.
MARY EVANS
iron law of oligarchy
– see Robert Michels.
309
J
James, William (1842–1910)
An American psychologist and philosopher, James
was the founder of pragmatism. Born in New York
City, unconventionally educated in America and
Europe and a qualified MD, James never practiced
medicine. He started his career at Harvard, first as
Instructor in Physiology and Anatomy, and, at
different times, Professor of Psychology and Professor of Philosophy. Of the books published in
his lifetime, the most enduring and of interest
to sociology include The Principles of Psychology
(1890), The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902),
and Pragmatism (1907). All are still in print.
James’s influence in sociology is through a
number of routes. The Principles of Psychology includes a chapter, “The Consciousness of Self,”
that is thoroughly sociological and strongly influenced both Charles Horton Cooley and George
Herbert Mead. James proposes the notion of a
social self, later elaborated by Cooley as the
looking-glass self, and also the distinction between the I and the Me, later developed by Mead.
Through his influence on Mead, James contributed to the emergence of symbolic interactionism.
But this is not the only route through which James
enters sociology. James was also a source and inspiration for Thorstein Veblen, especially in the
conception of human evolution directed by consciousness and also the characteristic Jamesian
understanding of human instinct, both of which
featured in Veblen’s evolutionary approach in economic sociology. Additionally, James’s discussion
of religion (1902) was much more important to
both Max Weber’s The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit
of Capitalism (1905 [trans. 2002]) and Émile Durkheim’s The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life
(1912 [trans. 1954]) than a mere index check could
reveal.
JACK BARBALET
Late Capitalism (1991), and his broad, innovative,
and radical cultural criticism, especially The Cultural Turn (1998). Postmodernism, according to
Jameson, represents a new mode of representation, life experience, and aesthetic sensitivity, all
of which reflect the latest stage of capitalist development. The key features of this stage, which
evolved out of market capitalism of the nineteenth century and monopoly capitalism of the
early twentieth century, are the global division
of labor, intensified consumption, especially consumption of images, a proliferation of the massmedia, and an increasing saturation of society
with information technology. Above all, late capitalism integrates aesthetic production into general
commodity production, thus intensifying mass
consumption of ever more novel goods. Jameson
identifies the features of postmodern cultural configuration, a new “mode of production” in late
capitalism, as including the blurring of distinction between popular/commercial and highbrow/
classic culture; the weakening of the historical
dimension with the emphasis on current experience (here and now), and the organization of
space (most conspicuous in contemporary architecture); the spread of electronically reproduced
images (“the simulacra” in Jean-François Lyotard’s
terms); a wide use of pastiche; and a decline in
affectivity that reduces the need for emotional
engagement in cultural consumption. In his quest
for the “cognitive mapping” of contemporary
culture in relation to late capitalist economy and
society. Jameson links postmodernity with the
popular ethos, lifestyle, and mentality of “the
yuppies,” the young segments of a professional–
managerial class, and with a new wave of American economic, cultural, and military domination.
JAN PAKULSKI
Jameson, Fredric (1934– )
justice
Professor of Comparative Literature at Duke University, cultural critic, and the key exponent of
Marxist postmodern theory and interpretation of
contemporary cultural trends, Jameson is best
known for his Postmodernism or the Cultural Logic of
The question “What is justice?” is at the center of
political philosophy but not at the center of
sociology. Famously raised by Plato in The Republic,
it is a question which sociologists deal with in an
anti-Platonic fashion. Plato analyzes justice with
310
justice
respect to the soul. His work is organized around
an analogy between the city and the soul, suggesting that a proper understanding of justice requires a philosopher to transcend the narrow
boundaries of society, portrayed as a cave, an obscure place where little can be understood: for
Plato, the truly just can be grasped only in the
light of the eternal, beyond the social here and
now. Sociologists aim to start not from beyond the
cave but, most emphatically, from within the cave
itself: when they do study the question of justice
in itself, they aim to do so by giving morally detached accounts of the notions of justice held in
particular societies. In the preface of his Injustice.
The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt (1978), Barrington Moore notes that, for a while, he thought
of calling his book “a study of moral outrage”; but
he adds that, after all, “moral outrage suggests too
strongly the agonies of intellectuals trying to interpret, judge, and change the world.” Sociologists
offer descriptions and analysis of existing ideologies rather than a normative “theory of justice,”
an analysis given in terms of values, of ideology,
of history, of context. Such accounts of justice
often depend on or express historicism and/or
relativism.
This is why, in spite of acknowledging Montesquieu’s role as a founder of sociology, Émile Durkheim criticizes him for remaining too much of a
political philosopher. Montesquieu treats despotic
or tyrannical regimes as anomalous, but Durkheim argues in Montesquieu and Rousseau, Forerunners of Sociology (1892 [trans. 1960]) that, from a
scientific point of view, every regime must be
treated as having its own perfect form. The injustice inherent in a despotic regime does not or
should not matter from the politically neutral
point of view of a sociologist. Considered as a
unified enterprise, sociology offers an alternative
to political philosophy, an analysis of the human
condition which does not start from the political
question of justice.
The main reason why sociology tends not to
address the question of justice directly goes back
to its origins. Sociology was born as a result of the
eighteenth-century separation between state and
civil society. Originally, sociology took as its
proper object civil society, aiming to treat this
justice
independently from the activities of the state; in
this sense, sociology began with a critique of the
primacy of the political. It aimed to show that
societies obey laws or belong to types that can be
described and understood without reference to
laws (see law and society) enforced by the state.
However, this very critique of the primacy of the
political has political consequences, and bears on
the understanding of the question of justice.
In this respect, Durkheim’s focus on Montesquieu’s legacy is significant. Montesquieu distinguishes law and mores (see norm[s]), developing
an account of the autonomy of mores, of the complexity of social phenomena, of a “spirit” of laws
that is required to avoid despotism and injustice.
To the extent to which Montesquieu can be
counted among the founders of sociology, he
founds it because he thinks that it will be politically useful. Sociology is the science which, in the
hands of rulers and lawyers, should foster political moderation through an understanding of the
comparative narrowness of the political category
and of the resilience and relative autonomy of
social phenomena. A ruler cannot make any law,
and become a tyrant: he needs to take into account the “spirit” of the laws – that is, the sociology of law. Besides, a proper understanding of
the autonomy of mores paves the way for a proper
account of the balance of powers, that is the balance between the state and the representatives of
civil society in dealing with the state. From this
liberal point of view, an insistence on the limits
of the political sphere helps to protect civil rights
and minimize injustice. At the other end of the
political spectrum, Karl Marx’s theory offers a
good example of sociology put in the service not
of political moderation but of revolution. Marx’s
sociology is built around a critique of the category
of the political in the name of the primacy of the
economy. The state and its laws are denounced as
instruments of the bourgeoisie, developed for the
oppression of the proletariat. Although Marx plays
on the demand for justice, on a revolt against the
fate of the poor in the context of the industrial
revolution, he remains faithful to the sociological
critique of the category of justice, which he tries
to avoid as overly ideological.
É M I L E P E R R E A U - S A U S S I N E
311
K
Keynes, John Maynard (1883–1946)
One of the leading economists of the twentieth
century, Keynes held academic positions at the
University of Cambridge and also worked from
time to time within the British civil service. His
significance lies both in his contribution to economic theory and in his influence on public policy.
Keynes’s major work is The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money (1935). Writing in the
context of global economic depression and mass
unemployment, Keynes rejected the prevailing assumption that economic recovery could be left to
market forces. In the orthodox view, markets were
seen as creating and recreating equilibria through
changes in the demand for and supply of goods
and services. Keynes argued that, under certain
conditions, the market search for equilibrium
was incapable of resolving depression and alleviating unemployment. If aggregated demand was
low, then depression would remain endemic. In
such circumstances, one should look to government action in the form of public spending,
rather than market forces, to create economic
revival.
This theoretical insight had a significant impact
on public policy from the 1930s until the 1980s.
Government demand management became a
pillar of Western economic policy, and the basis
for welfare states and national economic planning. Under the impact of Keynesian economics,
social programs to promote welfare had an economic as well as a social rationale. In addition to
this emphasis on the Keynesian welfare state and
Social Keynesianism, Keynes strongly influenced
the architecture of global economic recovery after
World War II. Institutions such as the International Monetary Fund and the World Bank originated in the Bretton Woods conference of 1944
which Keynes attended. They were designed, in
large measure, to provide an interventionist
framework at the international level, to parallel
national economic policy initiatives.
Keynesian approaches fell out of favor from the
1970s. This occurred in part through the simultaneous onset of inflation and stagnation (stagflation),
312
not anticipated in Keynes’s theoretical framework, and in part because demand management
neglected supply-side reforms of labor markets
and public-sector efficiency. Deregulation and
the rolling back of state activity were more widely
advocated as means of optimizing national competitiveness and reaping the benefits of globalization. The Washington consensus on neoliberal
economic policy rather than Keynesianism has
dominated the Bretton Woods institutions since
the mid-1980s, though this has been challenged
very recently by Joseph Stiglitz and George Soros,
who argue for a return, if not to Keynesianism,
then at least to a more interventionist approach to
market failure and instability.
BOB HOLTON
Keynesian welfare state
– see John Maynard Keynes.
Khaldun, Ibn (1332–1406)
A Muslim social philosopher who is often described as “the father of sociology,” Khaldun was
born in Tunisia into an upper-class Andalusian
family, the Banu Khaldun. He traced his ancestry
back through an Arabic-Yemeni tribe from
Hadhramaut. He lived at various times in Spain,
Tunisia, and Egypt, where he died, in Cairo,
shortly after becoming an lslamic judge or qadi.
His work concerned the social and political
determinants of the rise and fall of civilizations.
His sociological theory was presented in The
Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History (1958). This
“prolegomena” to world history was composed
around 1375 when he had withdrawn from politics. This prolegomena concerns the circulation of
elites between town and desert in North Africa.
The town elites over time grow lazy, rich, and
corrupt, while tribal elites remain disciplined
and enjoy greater social integration or solidarity.
This greater social unity allows them periodically
to replace town elites, but in turn they become
corrupt, and are replaced by fresh elites. This
Khaldunian theory of social and political change
was used to great effect by Ernest Gellner in
kinship
Muslim Society (1981) to explain different forms of
Islam (puritanical and egalitarian versus mystical
and hierarchical) in relation to political change,
for example in Morocco. The development of
modern communications technology, especially
the telegraph, telephone, and radio, eventually
gave urban elites a military advantage over the
countryside, and the ancient political oscillation
was transformed. Radical reform movements in
Islam such as the fundamentalist Wahhabi movement, which was inspired by Muhammad b. Abdal-Wahhab (died 1791), are often said to exhibit
the social changes that were originally described
by Ibn Khaldun’s sociology. Muslim intellectuals
often complain that most histories of sociology
neglect Ibn Khaldun, because they are written
within the framework of Orientalism.
BRYAN S. TURNER
kinship
Socially universal, this is probably the most basic
of institutional modalities of human organization. Anthropology has consistently treated kinship as its special theoretical preserve, and its
preoccupations with kinship have consistently
focused on three overlapping thematic issues.
One of these is typological. From Lewis Henry
Morgan’s Systems of Consanguinity and Affinity in
the Human Family (1871) onward, the field of kinship studies has preserved the distinction between
classificatory (or “merging”) kinship terminologies, which assign a general rubric to relatives of
differing genealogical distance from any given
ego, and descriptive terminologies, which in their
most expansive versions provide each relative
with a rubric of his or her own. Morgan’s efforts
have given way to the distinction among six terminological schemas, from the expansively classificatory Hawaiian to the meticulously descriptive
Sudanese.
Another thematic focus has rested on the question of the generative principle of kinship. Its star
curiosity is the taboo against incest. Claude LéviStrauss underscores the taboo’s proscription of
marriage within the elemental family group in
arguing that kinship systems are before all else
not systems of descent but of intergroup alliance.
A final focus falls on the substantive ground of
kinship. David Schneider’s Critique (1984) of the
naturalism of even the most ardently conventionalist theories of kinship has not discouraged every
psychoanalyst or sociobiologist since, but it has
inspired a new effort to establish the grounds of
kinship in strictly socio-cultural phenomena.
Leading contenders include the symbolization of
Kristeva, Julia (1941– )
fertility, the articulation of domesticity, and the
dynamics of self-formation.
JAMES D. FAUBION
Komarovsky, Mirra (1905–1986)
Born in Baku in the Caucasus, Komarovsky emigrated to the United States in 1922 and attended
Barnard College in New York where she was
taught by Franz Boas, Ruth Benedict, and William
Ogburn. She became a research assistant on the
Westchester Leisure Project (1931–3) that resulted
in George L. Lundberg, Mary M. McInerny, and
Komarovsky’s Leisure, A Suburban Study (1934).
From 1934 to 1936 she was a research associate
at the International Institute for Social Research,
directed by Paul Lazarsfeld, and on the basis of
that work she published her PhD thesis in 1940 on
The Unemployed Man and his Family, with an introduction by Lazarsfeld. Komarovsky became an associate professor (1948–53) and later full professor
(1954–70). She was influential in the development
of the sociology of gender, through articles such
as “Cultural Contradictions and Sex Roles,” in the
American Journal of Sociology (1946), and “Functional
Analysis of Sex Roles,” in the American Sociological
Review (1950). Her books, such as Dilemmas of Masculinity (1976) and Blue-Collar Marriage (1964), were
highly influential. Her works on social class criticized American sociologists for neglecting the
working class and for applying generalizations
from the middle class to blue-collar families. The
principal theoretical focus of her empirical work –
inconsistencies in social roles – was influenced by
Robert Merton’s role theory and William Ogburn’s
concept of social lag. She had three scientific objectives, namely to understand the functional significance of sex roles, to locate their cultural
contradictions, and to assess the possibilities of
social change. Her monograph on unemployed
men has also been recognized for its methodological contribution to the use of personal documents. She made important contributions to
feminist theory in Women in the Modern World
(1953) and Women in College (1985). She was the
second female President of the American Sociological Association (1972–3); her presidential address that year was, suitably, on “Some Problems
in Role Analysis.”
BRYAN S. TURNER
Kristeva, Julia (1941– )
Born in Bulgaria, Kristeva has spent her life in
France since 1965. She is best known for the distinction that she makes between what she calls
the “semiotic” and the “symbolic,” and for her
assertion of the centrality of the mother (see
313
Kuhn, Thomas Samuel (1922–1996)
motherhood/mothers) in human biography and
the social world. Kristeva defines the “semiotic”
in terms of the drives and rhythms of the human
body, and in particular the maternal body. The
“symbolic,” on the other hand, is the frame of
reference that we use to make sense of our experience. The “symbolic” and the “semiotic” combine
to produce signification, and it is Kristeva’s contention that the structure of signification comes
from what she describes as maternal regulation.
In emphasizing the place of the mother in both
the individual and the social world, Kristeva
follows Melanie Klein (1882–1960). She takes the
centrality of the mother forward in her texts
Powers of Horror (1980) and Black Sun (1987) to
argue that, within patriarchal cultures, the
mother, and maternity, are subject to what she
describes as “abjection,” a form of subjectivity in
which women become depressed and develop a
depressed sexuality. In order to change the
degradation of the feminine, Kristeva does not
propose ideas of universal equality, nor the
development of a specific female language and
culture. Kristeva validates what she sees as multiple possible sexualities and a recognition within
cultures that there is a need to heal what she
describes as wounded narcissism. One of the characteristics of Kristeva’s work is the links she
makes between psychoanalysis and the social
world: for example, Strangers to Ourselves (1992)
considers some of the reasons for racism and the
fear of other cultures.
MARY EVANS
Kuhn, Thomas Samuel (1922–1996)
An American historian and philosopher of science,
Thomas Kuhn was an undergraduate and graduate student in physics at Harvard, where he came
under the influence of the university’s powerful
president, James B. Conant, who was himself a
physical chemist as well as a member of a small
group of politically important scientists. Conant
had a strong concern for undergraduate science
education. His new strategy was based on the
popular Harvard method of the case study that
focused on historical cases of far-reaching conceptual changes in scientific disciplines. Kuhn began
teaching this course and was asked to develop
his own historical research. After a few years at
Harvard, he took up a teaching position at Berkeley where he turned this study into his first book,
The Copernican Revolution (1957), and worked on The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), a summary
314
Kymlicka, Will (dates not known)
and overview of far-reaching conceptual changes
in science.
The book proved difficult to publish but was
eventually accepted in the logical positivist International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (1955). It was
also published as a separate volume and became
one of the best-selling scholarly books of all time
and was the most frequently cited book in the late
twentieth century. Kuhn’s key term paradigm
passed into common usage. Kuhn did not develop
the implications of his argument for the social
sciences and was shocked by some of the sociological interpretations of the text. He spent much
of the rest of his life responding to issues concerning incommensurability and meaning-change in
science.
STEPHEN P. TURNER
Kymlicka, Will (dates not known)
Professor of Philosophy at Queens University,
Ontario, Canada, and recurrent Visiting Professor
in the Nationalism Studies program at the Central
European University in Budapest, Kymlicka has
contributed extensively to the analysis of citizenship, ethnic minorities, and cultural rights in liberal democracies. His most influential publication
in this field was Multicultural Citizenship (1995). His
principal argument is that modern democracies
have sought to accommodate national and ethnic
differences under the broad umbrella of multiculturalism through the creation of “group-differentiated rights.” He identified three forms of these
rights. First, self-government rights recognize
some degree of self-determination, for example
through federalism. Secondly, polyethnic rights
recognize the entitlement of minorities to practice their own customs, religion, and language,
such as the in-principle right of Muslim girls to
wear the headscarf in secular schools. Finally,
there are special representation rights, which
would give representation to minorities, for
example by allocating a certain number of seats
to them in representative chambers (of parliament). Kymlicka’s arguments are controversial because he claims that these group rights are
perfectly compatible with the individualistic
rights of liberalism. His other publications include
Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism and Citizenship (2001), and Contemporary Political
Philosophy (2002). He has co-edited Kymlicka and
Wayne Norman (eds.), Citizenship in Diverse Societies
(2000) and Kymlicka and Magda Opalski (eds.), Can
Liberal Pluralism be Exported? (2001).
BRYAN S. TURNER
L
labeling theory
Labeling represents not a single sociological
theory, but a number of different ideas relating
to the notion that no behavior is deviant or criminal unless so labeled. Labeling thus refers to
the process by which behaviors come to be categorized as deviant or criminal. Each society
makes rules whose breach will constitute deviance
or criminality.
Labeling is a derivative of the widely used sociological idea of symbolic interactionism. Interactionist theory analyzes the way in which individual
actors develop conceptions of themselves on the
basis of their interactions with others. This gives
meaning to the behavior of individuals and places
their actions and behavior in the context of their
understanding of the world. Culture, sex, age, and
other elements of identity all shape self-conception,
of course, but the interactionists give particular
emphasis to the meanings which the individual
places on various occurrences and interactions.
Labeling theory is drawn from this, but focuses on
the impact of being labeled in a particular way on
behavior.
Early 1930s work on juvenile gangs led sociological writers to recognize that the official label
of “deviant” had potentially negative effects on
the young people concerned. In the 1950s, Edwin
Lemert in Social Pathology (1951) refined the thinking by distinguishing between primary and secondary deviation. While primary deviance might
be a temporary aberration, secondary deviance
was created as a reaction to the reaction of others
to the initial deviance. But labeling theory is most
strongly associated with Howard S. Becker in his
Outsiders: Studies in the Sociology of Deviance (1963).
His perspective on labeling revolved around the
social reactions of a group rather than individual
reactions. In a series of studies he described the
processes of becoming a prostitute or a marijuana
smoker and so on. In each case, it was the stigma
attached to the label that was critical in shaping
future behavior. Thus the labeling processes
created “outsiders” and a self-fulfilling prophecy
ensued. The processes of criminal justice are thus
perceived to be instrumental in making matters
worse.
By focusing on definitional issues, labeling theory
has injected important critical thinking into criminological theorizing. It has revealed how the concepts of crime and deviance are not universally
agreed but socially constructed. But labeling theory
itself has attracted criticism for being ahistorical,
astructural, and atheoretical. First, it is argued that
labeling fails to explain why some behaviors are
labeled as deviant in the first place; second, it is
suggested that labeling theory gives too little attention to the concept and exercise of power; and
third, it is thought that labeling theory is hard to
test empirically. More pointedly, it is thought that
the key question of whose interests are being protected in the labeling of some people’s behavior
and actions as “deviant” has been neglected. Other
criticisms relate to the neglect of the victim in the
analysis.
Despite criticisms, labeling theory has had far-reaching effects in sociological thinking that go
well beyond the sociology of deviance; for instance,
labeling theory has been applied to witchcraft and
LORAINE GELSTHORPE
mental health.
labor
This concept has several standard referents in
sociology, covering specific forms of paid employment (such as manual labor); generic features of
such employment, often conceived as one pole of
a relationship between labor and capital; the differentiation and relationships between the whole
range of different sorts of paid work (representing
the division of labor); and the collective organization of workers in a labor movement or party. All
these concepts were formulated in the specific
context of the development of capitalism and its
associated forms of waged employment, and analyses using these concepts are particularly associated with theoretical traditions (both Marxist and
non-Marxist) that have addressed the character
and dynamics of social class relations in industrial
capitalism.
315
labor
However, analyses of labor have moved beyond
these core debates about capitalist industrialism in several ways. First, “free” wage labor has
been compared with forms of unfree labor (such
as slavery and bonded labor), both outside and
within capitalism, as in R. Miles’s Capitalism and
Unfree Labour (1987). Second, analyses of the social
division of labor and specific forms of labor have
been extended beyond the formal sphere of paid
work to include work in the household (that is,
domestic labor), and voluntary and informal economies, as in C. Tilly and C. Tilly’s Work Under
Capitalism (1998). Finally, there has been attention
to expanding forms of paid work in postindustrial
societies, such as knowledge work, insecure employment, and emotional labor, and the extent
to which they can be analyzed within a labor
paradigm.
First, then, labor usually refers both to paid
work and to those who do that work, as one side
of the relationship between labor and capital or
employees and employers. This relationship is central to arguments about the fundamental features
of waged employment (see work and employment)
and hence the organization of work and industrial
relations in capitalist societies. Such features are
addressed in different conceptualizations of the
labor market, the labor contract, and the labor
process in such societies, and link directly with
debates about changing social class structures and
forms of class mobilization. The growth of labor
markets, in which workers become available for
hire to work for specified periods for a wage, sets
capitalism apart from earlier societies. However,
the implications of this development for relations
between employers and workers are contentious:
some economic accounts treat such markets as
the guarantors of equivalent choices and reciprocity between employers and workers, while
most sociological accounts emphasize that inequalities of power are intrinsic to the labor
market and to social relations between employees
and employers within the capitalist labor process.
At the nexus of the relationship between the
labor market and the labor process is the labor
contract, which in formal legal terms summarizes
the exchange between employer and employee,
specifying such matters as job title, hours, and
payment. Different and changing legal frameworks have defined the form, scope, and detail of
such contracts in very varied ways. But a fundamental argument of many sociological analyses of
labor is that any such summary is necessarily
incomplete, with important implications for the
character of employment relations. Sometimes
316
labor
this argument rests on the claim that all market
exchanges depend upon more than the stipulated
terms and conditions of exchange, because they
rely on wider institutional and normative frameworks which are often taken for granted and
would be impossible to specify completely. This
theme relates to Émile Durkheim’s notion of the
“noncontractual elements in contract” in which
informal assumptions and agreements are seen to
be a necessary precondition of formal contracts
and agreements.
More crucially, however, it rests on the claim
that the labor contract is quite distinctive in ways
that set it apart from the purchase and sale of
other commodities, for two related reasons. First,
workers do not sell their labor and depart, but
have to perform their work through their working
hours; thus what they sell is their own capacity to
labor, what Karl Marx termed the purchase and
sale of their labor power. Second, the demands
that employers make of their workers are not
fixed, but flow from the changing circumstances
of their business, as they exercise “management
prerogatives” to reconfigure the duties workers
perform while at work.
This conception of the open-endedness of the
labor contract is central to Marxist accounts of
the relationship between labor and capital, setting the scene for an analysis of the changes and
conflicts that arise as capitalists seek to impose
the requirements of capital accumulation upon
workers, and workers experience and oppose the
damage this inflicts upon them. However, it has a
more general relevance across a spectrum of social
science analyses of employment and industrial relations. It excludes those economists who argue that
the equivalence of the labor market transaction
persistently guarantees reciprocity between employers and workers, and those sociologists who
abstract from the labor contract and employment
relations in their study of other aspects of work and
occupations. But it defines common ground between many other Marxist and non-Marxist materialist and institutionalist approaches, all of
which attend to the power relations and social
processes implicated in filling out the labor contract, as P. K. Edwards shows in Conflict at Work
(1986). Where these positions differ markedly is in
their specification of the character and extent of
the uncertainties and conflicts that arise around
the performance of paid work, and in their analyses of the ways in which, and the extent to which,
such uncertainties and conflicts are successfully
managed or negotiated. Indeed, some of these approaches (such as industrial relations pluralism)
labor
devote relatively little attention to analyzing
underlying sources of uncertainty and conflict,
but concentrate on the processes through which
empirically identified contention in the workplace
is managed.
One way in which these disagreements can be
illuminated is by considering the ways in which
work processes within capitalist firms are structured and restructured over time, through analyses of management’s organization of the labor
process and labor discipline within the workplace.
One example is Marx’s analysis of the effective
subordination of workers and work processes to
the requirements of surplus extraction and capital accumulation. However, during the twentieth
century, other sociological traditions – such as
those which focus on the institutionalization of
formal rationality in bureaucracies or those that
see organizational arrangements as heavily influenced by the technology required for particular
work processes – have provided alternative bases
for analyzing the imperatives governing the organization of the labor process in capitalist (and
sometimes noncapitalist) societies. In turn this
has prompted extensive debate on the changing
character of management strategies and worker
responses in the organization of the labor process.
These debates have important implications for
analyses of the division of labor. From Adam
Smith (1723–90) onward, commentaries have distinguished between the social division of labor in
the economy as a whole and the technical (or, to
avoid implicit technical determinism, the organizational) division of labor in the enterprise and
workplace. The former is portrayed as directly
subject to the vagaries of market relations, with
the growth and decline of demand for different
types of product and associated occupations. The
latter is seen as only indirectly subject to market
relations but directly subject to management
prerogatives and strategies.
Labor process debates have focused primarily
upon analyses of the organizational division of
labor. In particular, they have debated the extent
to which management strategies have forged relatively homogeneous or heterogeneous workforces
in terms of skills, autonomies, and job security.
There has also been substantial disagreement
about how any heterogeneity is to be conceptualized, in terms of stable hierarchies, or patterns of
polarization, or as a shifting kaleidoscope of forms
of labor. For example, it has been argued that
an important feature of the capitalist transformation of the labor process has been an increasing
separation of manual and mental labor, in which
labor
mental labor conceptualizes and plans work tasks
while manual labor performs those tasks. However,
it has also been recognized that the extent of such
separation, how far it might constitute a basis for
hierarchy or polarization in the organizational division of labor, and its implications for wider processes of class formation and conflict, have been
varied rather than uniform, while explanations of
these outcomes remain controversial.
Indeed, some accounts of emergent forms of employment have suggested that networked, rather
than hierarchical, relations within organizations
and the growth of high-discretion knowledge work
have so changed work and employment relations
that all analyses using the conceptual apparatus
outlined above have lost their relevance. However,
the extent and character of these transformations
have been strongly contested by commentators
who have sought to demonstrate the continuing
salience of these analytical approaches for contemporary forms of work and employment, as in
the work of H. Beynon and his colleagues on Managing Employment Change (2002). Such controversies
relate not only to explanations of key features of
the division of labor but also to diagnoses of the
possibilities and conditions for ameliorating,
transforming, or abolishing those features.
Sometimes accounts of the organizational division of labor within enterprises have been set
in a wider context, of the changing relations between enterprises and sectors, to address the social
processes that constitute the wider social division
of labor, as in A. Sayer and R. Walker’s The New Social
Economy (1992). This involves analyses of: (1) the
ways in which management strategies in recruiting
and organizing labor in different enterprises contribute to the structuring of wider labor markets,
at a variety of spatial scales from localities to national economies and beyond; (2) the implications
of major sectoral shifts, from agriculture to manufacturing to service employment, and also between
small-firm, large-firm, and state employment; (3)
the changing relationships between enterprises
and workplaces, mediated not only through competitive market relations but also through alliances, networks, and production chains. All these
aspects of the analysis of the social division of labor
can be seen, for example, in debates over the new
international division of labor, the proposition that
leading enterprises in advanced capitalist societies
have sought to relocate labor-intensive production
processes to developing societies characterized by
low labor costs and poorly organized workers,
while retaining knowledge-intensive activities at
home. The ensuing debate, outlined in R. Munck’s
317
labor
Globalisation and Labour (2002), explored different ways in which such changes were organized,
sometimes coordinated within transnational corporations but also mediated through production
chains involving hierarchies of enterprises. It also
emphasized that corporate policies were often contradictory, and that the outcome was usually more
complex than a stable polarization of production
activities and forms of employment between advanced and developing capitalisms.
Such analyses of the dynamics of the social division of labor have primarily been developed in
interdisciplinary research, though with significant
contributions from economic sociology. More specifically, sociological commentary has focused on
the consequences of the organizational and social
division of labor for patterns of social consciousness, solidarity, and conflict. Here intellectual influences range from neo-Marxist and neo-Weberian
explorations of the scope and limits of the formation of wider class solidarities from the varied experiences of wage labor, to symbolic interactionist
and social constructionist analyses of the negotiation of occupational identities, boundaries, solidarities, and rivalries. However, there has been
little recent reference to the more ambitious but
problematical Durkheimian program which explored the occupational bases and limitations of
modern forms of social solidarity.
Meanwhile, one major sociological critique of
conventional analyses of the social division of labor
grew out of feminist analyses of the sexual division
of labor. These analyses problematized biological
accounts of the gendered division between male
workers in paid employment in the public sphere
and women engaged in unwaged household and
caring work. At the same time, they emphasized
the significance of the latter forms of work in
terms of time, tasks, and consequences for societal
reproduction. This was conceptualized in terms of
domestic labor to emphasize the parallels and linkages between work in paid employment and
unpaid work in the household, but also involved
discussion of the distinctiveness of the power relations and patterns of work characteristic of gender
relations in households and families, often conceptualized in terms of patriarchy. In turn, and in the
context of a major change in women’s involvement
in paid employment, this has prompted analyses of
the ways in which gender, and in related ways
ethnicity, have been constitutive features in the
restructuring and hierarchization of both paid
labor and unpaid work. To address these features,
M. Glucksmann has developed the concept of the
total social organization of labor, in “Why ‘Work?’”
318
labor markets
(1995) in Gender, Work and Organisation, to analyze
the varied and changing patterns of articulation
and dislocation between different forms of paid,
unpaid, voluntary, and forced labor over time and
across different social scales.
TONY ELGER
labor, social division of
– see labor.
labor aristocracy
– see social class.
labor-market segmentation
– see labor market.
labor markets
These involve the purchase and sale of a peculiar
commodity, as what is bought and sold is actually
the capacity of a worker to perform paid work, and
the exercise of that capacity is not separated from
workers but depends on their conduct at work. The
supply of such capacities is influenced by wider
institutional arrangements (for example welfare
policies, family structures, or professional associations). Similarly, demand is influenced by employment relations within workplaces (for example
strategies for securing worker compliance, training
arrangements, and negotiations with workers).
From this vantage point, labor markets represent an appropriate focus for sociological research.
Often, however, they are seen as the specialist preserve of economists, while sociologists focus on
social relations within the workplace and treat
labor markets as exogenous variables. This leaves
unchallenged the dominant economic treatment
of the labor market as a competitive arena in
which employers and workers freely exercise choices according to their talents and preferences.
This neoclassical model views the labor market
as a mechanism which, unimpeded, will generate
both reciprocity between buyers and sellers of
labor and an efficient allocation of labor to different activities. Thus social institutions that influence the supply of or demand for labor are
treated as exogenous givens or as distortions that
should be removed to allow the market to perform
its proper role. In response, some sociological approaches to labor market analysis seek to marry
sociological analyses of values and institutions to
existing economic models, but others challenge
such economic models more directly.
Historical sociologists have analyzed the historical conditions in which extensive labor markets
were formed, while also insisting that labor market
labor markets
mechanisms necessarily remain embedded in and
conditioned by wider forms of social regulation.
However, more specific challenges to neoclassical
economic models of labor markets were developed
from the late 1960s, initially by institutionalist and
neo-Marxist economists critical of the mainstream
but then taken up by other social scientists. J. Peck,
in Work-Place: The Social Regulation of Labor Markets
(1996), identifies several phases in the development
of this alternative analysis. The first phase, concerned especially with the experience of advantaged
workers, developed a dual labor market model.
The primary labor market involved internal job
ladders, usually within large organizations, with
access to many jobs governed by internal administrative rules and bargains. The secondary labor
market remained outside the firm, offering access
to insecure jobs with little scope for progression.
This model emphasized the role of management
in structuring the demand for labor: technical
imperatives encouraged managers to retain those
workers trained within the firm, who might be
tempted to move elsewhere, while those who were
deemed unsuitable for training were consigned to
the insecure periphery.
The next development also addressed the institutional logic of the demand for labor, but within
a wider historical framework. This suggested that
multiple labor market segments arose from the
efforts of capitalist managers to divide and rule
the workforce, as recruitment was structured in
terms of occupational, gender, and ethnic divisions.
Such accounts sought to integrate segmented labor
market models into a historical analysis of changing
“social structures of accumulation.” This represented a more radical repudiation of orthodox economics, but left considerable scope for arguments
about the coherence and consequences of such
segmentation.
These early analyses were primarily attempts
by American scholars to explain and critique entrenched ethnic and gender inequalities. The next
phase was primarily European and particularly influenced by feminist accounts of gender inequalities in employment. This drew upon the earlier
work on the social organization of the demand
for labor by management, but noted that organized workers could also influence this process.
More distinctively, it was emphasized that such
accounts must be complemented by analyses of
the social organization of the supply of labor. Labor
supply was influenced by existing institutionalized
patterns of labor demand, but also by developments in state policies (involving training, welfare,
or industrial relations) and relatively autonomous
labor markets
features of the social organization of gender relations and households. These arguments prompted
particular attention to the ways in which labor
market segmentation took distinctive forms within specific local and national contexts, linking
to wider debates on varieties of capitalism and
changing structures of opportunity and inequality
across societies, as in J. Rubery and D. Grimshaw’s
The Organization of Employment (2003).
Early segmented labor market models were primarily designed to understand enduring divisions
and inequalities in the labor market. However,
recent analyses have also addressed changing
forms of labor market segmentation, especially
as employers and state policymakers embraced
policies of deregulation and flexibilization of
labor markets, but also as “equal opportunity”
policies opened possibilities to widen access to
internal job ladders. In the late 1980s, the “flexible
firm” model provided one influential account of
the dynamics of such labor market change. It recommended the strategic construction of a dual
labor market: employers would gain labor flexibility by constructing multifunctional teams (rather
than job ladders) for “core workers” and extending
various forms of disposability (such as part-time,
temporary, or agency work) among “peripheral
workers.”
However, this prescriptive model faced powerful theoretical and empirical critiques, especially
from A. Pollert in “The ‘Flexible Firm’: Fixation
or Fact?” (1988) in Work, Employment and Society.
First, there were important continuities in the
institutional structuring of labor market inequalities, while management policies often remained
reactive rather than strategic. Second, contemporary developments were poorly captured by the
contrast between secure “core” and insecure “peripheral” workforces. Some core workers were becoming increasingly insecure, while the periphery
included employees with very different labor
market prospects (from well-paid, self-employed
“consultants” to day laborers in the shadow economy). Current segmented labor market analyses
of the growth of different forms of “nonstandard”
employment have built on these criticisms. In
these accounts, the boundaries and internal composition of existing labor market segments may be
reconstructed by new state and management policies, but such policies remain characterized by
unresolved tensions, while the outcomes are also
influenced by wider institutional arrangements
and social settlements, as shown in A. Felstead
and N. Jewson (eds.), Global Trends in Flexible Labour
(1999).
TONY ELGER
319
labor movement
labor movement
This refers to a major type of social movement,
traditionally addressing socioeconomic inequality
by means of its members’ engagement in collective action to improve the living and working
conditions of its constituency. Historically, the
phenomenon emerged with western industrialization (see industrial society), but its structure,
functions, and ideologies have changed with the
arrival of postindustrial society. Aside from the
United States, most advanced industrial countries
have well-institutionalized national union federations, and labor or socialist parties. Industrialization, however, is not a sufficient condition for
the emergence of labor movements, as the national histories of developing and export-intensive
economies in the twentieth century show.
Before the rise of the labor movement, workers’
actions and industrial conflict mostly took the
form of disputes about pay and working-conditions,
with contenders asking fellow workers from other
craft shops to join, while awaiting the outcome
of negotiations between strike leaders and trade
masters. Nowadays, the labor movement manifests
itself in its bargaining agents’ negotiations,
through formal organizations, with employer,
and often state, representatives. The labor movement has long been studied as a central force of
welfare state expansion; post-World War II economic growth is interpreted as conditional upon
deals between business, government, and labor.
Social policy programs decrease the economic vulnerability of the workforce and stimulate a sense
of social responsibility and solidarity among
workers. Generous welfare states raise wage floors
and increase labor costs, which, in the era of economic globalization, together with complex labor
regulation, has been taken by capitalists as a prime
argument to relocate production to low-wage and
low-regulation economies. Welfare state policies
have also brought about new organized constituencies, often autonomous from the labor movement and thus having the perverse effect of
weakening the labor movement.
Trade unions represent the traditional core of
the labor movement, with collective bargaining as
their most routinized function, and strikes (see
industrial relations) and demonstrations as their
preeminent political tactics. First emerging in
England in the early nineteenth century, their
efforts to create alliances across trades soon
became part of a greater political landscape. The
national and international labor movement came
to involve participation from political parties as
320
labor process
well as voluntary associations concerned with
workers’ rights, and these became integral, and
often respectable, elements in the industrial relations systems of the nation-states where they
emerged.
De-unionization is often used as a shorthand for
the erosion or disappearance of the labor movement as a consequence of the shrinking of the
working class (both in terms of new recruitment
and retention) and of changes in identity, class consciousness, and ideology. Recent studies of specific
industries, for example by Beverly Silver in Forces
of Labor (2003), show that patterns of labor unrest
shift together with geographic changes in production locations around the globe, and thus collective labor interest reemerges in relocated as well
as wholly new industries. Labor movements in
some parts of the world have become part of antiglobalization movements, and their international
strength much depends on how they navigate the
North–South divide, particularly as to their role
in industrial protectionism, and the extent to
which labor interest can form coalitions with other
interest-group-based movements.
ANN VOGEL
labor process
This process occurs when labor power is expended
to produce goods and services. Many scholars investigate the labor process mainly in terms of its
technical dimensions but explicit concern with its
organization in different sites and at different
scales is largely associated with studies inspired
by Marxism. There is also significant feminist
work on the gendered dimensions of the labor
process and more general work on its broader
social and cultural dimensions.
The labor process involves both a technical
division of labor (see labor) and a social division
of labor. A complete account should consider the
articulation of both aspects in specific contexts.
The technical division of labor concerns the relation among direct laborers (those who are directly
engaged in appropriating and transforming
nature), the instruments of production (such as
tools and machines), and the matter (raw materials or intermediate products) on which they
work – all considered from the viewpoint of specific embodied skills and specific products. It can
be studied at particular sites (for example individual plants, offices, shops, or universities) or for particular commodity chains (the entire labor process
for a given product from the initial appropriation of
nature through to its final consumption). The production of services (for example live performances,
labor process
sexual services, pedagogy, emotional labor) also has
a technical division of labor, even if there is no
enduring material product. The social division of
labor concerns control over the allocation of labor
power within the labor process, over the organization of the labor process, over decisions about what
to produce, and over the allocation of any surplus
production beyond what is required to renew labor
power, instruments of production, and inputs. This
raises issues of social domination, class exploitation, and aspects of the labor process that are
not directly or primarily grounded in technical
aspects of production.
Analyses of the labor process in the modern
world are often restricted to commodity production in a profit-oriented, market-mediated process
of economic organization. But there are also important studies of substantive provisioning outside
the cash nexus, such as self-provisioning, unpaid
domestic labor, or activities in the informal economy; and of the labor process in the state sector or
precapitalist societies. Some argue that only free
market competition ensures an efficient technical
division of labor and rational allocation of scarce
resources to competing ends. Others dispute this.
There are also major debates on the normative
dimensions of production.
Karl Marx analyzed the articulation of the technical and social divisions of labor and argued that
this impelled the continual reorganization of the
labor process. He shows how capital, driven to
incessant innovation as the condition for its own
existence in competitive markets, transforms
technology and the technical division of labor.
Marx’s key innovation here is the distinction
between labor and labor power. Labor occurs
when the laborer expends energy in production;
labor power is the laborer’s capacity to labor. Marx
argues that capitalists purchase labor power and
must then mobilize this potential to ensure that
value is added in production. In doing so they
are subject to the pressures of capitalist competition. Marx distinguished analytically between two
forms of such mobilization: (1) extending working
hours and/or increasing the physical intensity of
labor – this increases output based on “absolute
surplus value”; and (2) enhancing labor power’s
productivity by reorganizing the labor process so
that less time is needed for a given commodity –
resulting in relative surplus value. Capitalists
compete to reduce the socially necessary labor
time involved in commodity production and
thereby gain extra profits relative to their rivals
– but, as new ways of organizing the labor process
labor process
become generalized, these extra profits are competed away. This creates permanent pressure to
reorganize the labor process, putting capitalists
and workers alike on an apparently unstoppable
treadmill. Whereas the younger Marx studied the
capitalist labor process in terms of alienation and
dehumanization, the later Marx did so in terms of
exploitation and capitalist laws of motion. One
feature of the labor process relevant to both approaches is the separation between manual and
mental labor that occurs in capitalism, especially during the phase of machinofacture. Marx’s
analyses also provide a basis for studying class
struggle, trade union organization, capitalist competition, and attempts to control the innovation
process.
In addition to work on the generic features of
the capitalist labor process, there are many studies
on its different stages. These include the transition
from manufacture based on the use of tools in
simple or complex forms of cooperation (for
example pin manufacture), through machinofacture (where the worker becomes an appendage to
the machine), to new forms of knowledge-based (or
postindustrial) production. There is also continuing interest in various labor-process paradigms
(for example craft production, mass production,
continuous flow production, diversified quality
production, flexible specialization).
Marx rarely discusses what occurs once workers
enter the workplace, apart from allusions to their
subordination to the machine, “barrack-like discipline,” and “factory codes.” But industrial sociologists have made many studies of the labor
process in fields such as mining, fishing, agriculture, automobile production, offices, schools, and
so forth; they have also examined unskilled, semiskilled, skilled, supervisory, nonmanual, professional, and managerial labor. Recent work has
also drawn on Michel Foucault’s analyses of disciplinary power: organizing individuals in space, organizing movement in time, and the training of
aptitudes, for example in Richard Marsden, The
Nature of Capital: Marx After Foucault (1999). There
are a few studies on the labor process and the (de)
formation of the body.
Marx also compared the labor process in class
societies with the potentialities of work under Communism. Work would be freely undertaken rather
than dictated by demands of nature (essential
needs) or the logic of the market (profitability);
skills would be acquired as a chosen prowess rather
than tied to an assigned function in a rationalized
division of labor oriented to a stipulated output;
321
labor process approach
and work groups would form voluntarily, based on
intrinsic pleasure and solidarity rather than an
external goal. Thus Marx argues in Volume I of
Capital (1867) that, while Communism cannot abolish the need for humans’ interaction with nature,
it can bring that process under the community’s
conscious control and deprive it of its independent,
coercive force.
BOB JESSOP
labor process approach
– see labor process.
labor theory of value
– see Karl Marx.
Lacan, Jacques (1901–1981)
An influential interpreter of Sigmund Freud,
Lacan had a major impact upon modern European thought and social theory. A highly unconventional psychoanalyst, he delivered a famed
seminar at the École Normale Supérieure (formerly attended by philosophers such as Michel
Foucault, Roland Barthes, and Jacques Derrida),
as well as founding his own psychoanalytic organization, the École Freudienne de Paris. In
addition to his work as a practicing psychoanalyst, Lacan wrote many papers on a range of
theoretical issues.
He made two major contributions to the analysis of human subjectivity: first, in “The Mirror
Stage as Formative of the Function of the I”, which
was published in Écrits. A Selection (1949 [trans.
1977]), he proposed the thesis of the self-deception
of the ego by considering the infant identifying
with a mirror image of a complete unified body.
Following closely Freud’s proposition that the ego
is fundamentally narcissistic in character, Lacan
focused on the notion of a “mirror stage” which,
he argued, provided the subject with relief from
the experience of fragmentation, by granting an
illusory sense of bodily unity through its reflecting surface. Second, in “The Agency of the Letter
in the Unconscious, or Reason Since Freud” (1957),
published in Écrits, he argued, drawing upon
structural linguistics, that the construction of
the unconscious, and hence by implication culture
and society, is dominated by the primacy of
language. The signifier represents the subject for
Lacan; the primacy of the signifier in the constitution of the subject indicates the rooting of the
unconscious in language. In Lacan’s infamous
slogan, “The unconscious is structured like a
language.”
322
language
Along with Écrits, his principal works included
The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis (1973
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
[trans. 1994]).
language
There are at present about, 6,000 languages in the
world, 4,000 of which have been recorded or documented. Present estimates suggest that 96 percent
of these languages are spoken by a mere 4 percent of
the world’s population, and that half of them will
become extinct within the next century. Underlying
causes for these accelerating extinctions include
ecological collapse, military conflict, and political,
social, and economic hegemonic influence, whether
deliberately wielded or not.
Despite the obvious significance of language as a
basis of social identity and culture, the topic has not
received much attention from sociologists. Karl
Marx in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts
(1844 [trans. 1964]) observed that language was a
form of what he termed “practical consciousness.”
Fifty years later, Émile Durkheim declared it to be
an exemplary instance of what he called “social
facts” and took an interest in its role in systems of
social classification. Subsequently, George Herbert
Mead identified language as the crucial means by
which persons can “take the role of the other” and
thereby become objects to themselves, an insight
which was foundational for symbolic interactionism. Finally, the notion of habitus popularized by
Pierre Bourdieu serves as a valuable conceptualization of the ingrained skills and practices associated
with language use and identity and their resistance to change. These contributions notwithstanding, the theoretical invocation of language within
sociology has tended to be holistic and underspecified, and, perhaps because the sociologists of the
early twentieth century stressed the significance
of acculturation and assimilation, while the anthropologists of the same period celebrated linguistic, cultural, and ethnic diversity, interest in
language has comparatively shallow roots within
the discipline.
The sociological study of language has thus
remained somewhat sequestered from mainstream sociology. In keeping with the perspective
sponsored by Durkheim, it focuses on the ways in
which language serves as a bridge between individual identities and the social group(s) to which
persons belong. Its primary interests have cenetred, at the macro-level, on the relationship between language and identity in the context of race
and ethnicity and the nation-state, and, at the
middle-range level, on the ways in which social
language
class, community, and gender function as causes
and consequences of sociolinguistic variation.
At the most macro-level are studies of language
shift and maintenance. A number of conditions
have been identified as creating the potential
for language shift. An essential precondition is
bilingualism. A monolingual society will remain
monolingual (though its language may evolve
over time), until the arrival of an additional language that can influence the economic or power
balance among language users. Migration, industrialization, urbanization, government sponsorship of particular languages in schools and
elsewhere, and the relative prestige of different
languages are all factors that impact language
maintenance and shift. Perhaps the most important factor promoting language maintenance is
linguistic nationalism, defined by Joshua Fishman,
for example, in the Handbook of Language and Ethnic
Identity (1999) as the values, attitudes, and behavior of societies acting on behalf of their explicitly stated ethnocultural self interest. Linguistic
nationalism involves political organization, language policies that promote chosen vernacular
languages, and language codification (the creation, where necessary, of a written form of the
language).
At the meso-level, sociolinguistics studies the
relationship between language use and a wide
variety of sociological variables. Emerging out
of the study of dialect variation, contemporary
sociolinguistics was born with William Labov’s The
Social Stratification of English in New York City (1967)
which used random sampling of informants, taperecorded data, and quantitative measurements of
linguistic data to build a complex but orderly picture of language use. Subsequent research has
shown the significance of geography, ethnicity,
social networks, class, gender, and age in language
variation. The reliability of linguistic markers of
group membership means that, for other individuals, sociolinguistic variation can be a sensitive
measure of the person’s place in social space,
and for sociologists it can be a subtle unobtrusive
measure of a variety of social indicators.
In the end, sociolinguistics as a field is underwritten by the fact that people speak the way they
do because the people they identify with also speak
that way. Practices of thinking, acting, and speaking using a particular language constitute a linguistic habitus for each person, and cannot easily
be changed. Nonetheless, they are subject to maintenance or change through interpersonal processes. Social psychological research by Howard
Giles and others suggests that persons adapt their
language
use of fundamental components of dialect –
vocabulary, grammatical choices, and pronunciation – so as to converge or diverge from their
interlocutors. Convergence in any or all of these
may occur when a speaker is conversing with a
person of higher social status, or from the same
geographical area, or simply a person who is
likable. Conversely, a speaker may accentuate dialectal divergences when speaking with a social
inferior, or with a stranger, or with someone towards whom they entertain feelings of hostility.
Accumulations of convergences and divergences
can result in a change in habitus at the individual
level, and language change at the societal: the
recent shift in the direction of so-called estuary
English as a dominant dialect of the English
spoken in the United Kingdom is a case in point.
Languages are not only methods of communication, but systems of classification and conceptualization. While the notion that language influences
thought is an old one, it is most associated today
with the anthropological linguists Edward Sapir
(1884–1939) and Benjamin Lee Whorf (1897–1941).
Their thesis, which was based on anthropological
studies of the conceptualization of space, time,
and matter among Hopi Indians, asserted that
language determines our perceptions of the world.
Different languages produce different conceptual maps of reality. The original formulations of
the Sapir–Whorf hypothesis were dogged by circularity and by a lack of evidence for the cognitive side of the claim. Subsequent work during
the 1960s on subjects’ ability to discriminate
colors and shapes gave modest but questionable
support to their ideas. However, work by Stephen
Levinson and others in the 1990s that examined
the representation of space in language and
cognition appears to give solid support to claims
that, in the 1980s, were viewed as far-fetched and
tendentious.
The most important sociological contribution to
the study of language may yet turn out to come
from new trends in conversational analysis and
discourse analysis. These analytic streams insist
on the idea that speaking is a form of social action
and that it is subject to the normative constraints
that shape and drive action. Since it is within
interaction that language choices are made and
modified, family-resemblance-based classificatory
decisions are indexically attuned, linguistic and
conceptual habitus are adjusted, and social solidarity is sustained or undermined, social action and
interaction are surely the engine room of language
maintenance and change. Moreover, this conceptualization of language as action may contribute to
323
language games
releasing studies of language from their traditional
written language bias and open the way for a rapprochement between linguistics and the social
sciences which is long overdue.
JOHN HERITAGE
language games
Developed by Ludwig Wittgenstein in his Philosophical Investigations (1953) to focus attention on language use and its social context, the concept was a
useful means with which to repudiate the exclusive focus on the representational functions of
language which dominated his early philosophy.
In place of this focus, the language game concept
invited attention to the immense variety of uses to
which language is put: for example giving and
obeying orders; describing the appearance of an
object; reporting an event; telling a story or a joke;
asking questions; greeting someone; praying, and
so on. In his discussion of these uses of language,
Wittgenstein stressed both that language games
are interwoven with ordinary aspects of everyday
life, and that understanding the meaning of utterances involves knowing the nature of the activity
in which the utterances play a role. He also observed that language games are malleable: new
language games are invented and others become
obsolete. Part of this malleability arises because
the meanings of words, symbols, sentences, and
utterances are lodged, through use, in networks of
similarity and dissimilarity which lack an essence.
Although the notion of language game is not
much employed today, it has been a fecund influence on contemporary linguistic semantics and
pragmatics, and has important implications for
computational models of language. Within sociology, the concept had a potent influence on Harold
Garfinkel’s ethnomethodology and continues to influence a wide range of sociological and cultural
analyses of language use.
JOHN HERITAGE
language rights
– see rights.
Laslett, Peter (1915–2001)
A historian and sociologist, who also worked in
political philosophy and on the history of social
and political thought, Laslett was elected in 1948
to a fellowship at Cambridge and began his pathbreaking research on the social and political upheavals of seventeenth-century England. He went
on to edit and provide a new critical commentary
on the work of Robert Filmer (1588–1653) and
John Locke (1632–1704).
324
Latino/a studies
As a result of his engagement with Locke’s
writings on the nature of power within the family,
he moved towards demographic historiography
and during the 1960s cofounded the Cambridge
Group for the History of Population and Social
Structure with E. A. Wrigley. His work questioned
assumptions concerning the nature of the family
and household in early modern western Europe. In
The World We Have Lost (1965), basing his evidence
on local historical documents, he argued against
the widely held view that three-generation stem
families predominated in preindustrial England,
and that the small nuclear family was a product
of industrialization. For Laslett, preindustrial families were also predominantly nuclear, and were in
addition highly mobile; resident unmarried servants were the only non-nuclear element within
them.
In the 1980s he became interested in the aging
process, which he discussed in A Fresh Map of Life
(1989). As well as his work on social and political
demographic history and political philosophy, he
was interested in opening up academic life to a
wider audience, and with Michael Young he
cofounded the Open University.
STEVEN LOYAL
Latino/a studies
Despite their long presence in the United States,
and being the nation’s second largest minority
group in the 1960s, relatively little was known
about Latinos at that time. In many ways, Latinos
were strangers in the United States. However,
social movements of the civil rights era (1954–68)
called attention to the plight of Latinos in the
United States, particularly that of Chicanos and
Puerto Ricans, the largest Latino subgroups, both
of which were incorporated into the United States
through conquest. During the 1960s and early
1970s, these social movements would be instrumental in the development of academic programs
and advocacy organizations within the Chicano
and Puerto Rican communities. The roots of Latino/
a studies can be traced to this period.
This entry provides an overview of the development of Latino/a studies with particular attention
to the institutional arrangements, curriculum, research, professional associations, and publication
outlets related to the study of Latinos. To understand the development of Latino/a studies, we
turn to a historical discussion of its beginnings.
During the period surrounding the civil rights
era, Chicanos and Puerto Ricans protested against
discrimination and racism, and demanded equality and dignity. Because Latinos lacked easy entrance to higher education, affirmative action
Latino/a studies
programs helped them gain a modest degree of
access to colleges and universities. On their respective campuses, Latino students found few
Latinos as students and, especially, as faculty. Further, they often found academic climates devoid
of attention to the social and intellectual needs of
Latinos. In a number of campuses in the southwest and northeast, Latino students pressed for
the recruitment of Latino students and faculty
and for the creation of Chicano studies and Puertoriqueño/Boricua studies, respectively. The formation of these programs represents the roots of
Latino/a studies.
Latino sociologists played an important role in
the establishment of institutions that focus on
issues central to the Latino/a population within
and outside academia. We highlight here two key
sociologists who trained Latino/a students and
developed organizations that advocated for the
Latino/a population. Julian Samora, who received
his PhD in 1953 from Washington University, is
recognized as the first Chicano to earn a doctoral
degree in sociology and anthropology, as noted
in The Julian Samora Virtual Collection maintained
by the Julian Samora Research Institute (2005).
Samora, who died in 1996, mentored approximately fifty-five Chicano graduate students at
the University of Notre Dame before he retired in
1985. He also had a major impact in the development of important Latino organizations outside
academia. For example, he was one of the three cofounders of the National Council of La Raza (NCLR)
and was instrumental in the formation of the
Mexican American Legal Defense and Educational
Fund (MALDEF).
While Samora is a pioneer in the Chicano community, his colleague, Frank Bonilla, played an
equally important role in the training of Puerto
Ricans and in building advocacy groups to promote the Puerto Rican cause. A detailed account
of Bonilla can be found in an article entitled
“From the ‘Bulge’ to the Halls of Academia: Frank
Bonilla’s Hunger for Education Opened His Eyes to
the World,” published in Narratives (2004). Bonilla
received his PhD in sociology from Harvard University in 1959. He was instrumental in the formation of the Puerto Rican Hispanic Leadership
Forum which would eventually become Aspira,
an organization focusing on the educational
needs of Puerto Rican youth. After stints as a researcher in Latin America and a professor in the
United States, Bonilla took a faculty position
in 1973 at the City University of New York
(CUNY) where he became the Director of CUNY’s
Center for Puerto Rican studies. The scholarship
Latino/a studies
and activism of Samora and Bonilla embody
the mission of the Latino/a studies programs that
emerged in the late 1960s and 1970s and serve as a
legacy for many Latino scholars today.
The early Chicano studies and Puertoriqueño/
Boricua studies programs originating in the late
1960s and early 1970s had broad missions that
were student- and community-oriented. For example, these programs emphasized the institutionalization of courses and a curriculum for
students interested in Latino/a studies. Additionally, the programs helped in the recruitment and
retention of Latino students through both their
outreach efforts and the provision of social, academic, and cultural services, which emphasized
social change and the betterment of local Latino
communities. Finally, a distinct feature of Latino/a
studies programs continues to be their interdisciplinary focus. Faculty members participating in
such programs tend to be drawn from a broad
array of social and behavioral sciences, and arts
and humanities disciplines.
As the Latino population experienced greater
diversity associated with immigration from the
Caribbean, Central America, and South America,
some programs have maintained their focus on
the Chicano and Puerto Rican populations. However, many others have broadened their focus to
encompass the greater Latino variation with the
establishment of pan-ethnic Latino/a studies programs. The latter emphasize the linkages between
Latinos in the United States and Latin Americans
more generally, and they recognize the transnational and diaspora experience of Latinos and
Latin Americans.
There are also variations in the academic focus of
Latino/a studies programs (note that, for the sake
of simplicity, we use the term “Latino/a studies” to
encompass the diverse types of specific programs
just outlined). One set of programs has continued
to serve the primary mission of teaching and is
located institutionally as independent academic
departments or as programs within academic departments or colleges. In other cases, Latino
centers and institutes have the primary mission
of generating research on the Latino population.
Finally, teaching and research related to Latinos
takes place beyond the confines of Latino/a studies
programs and Latino research centers and institutes, as courses are taught within sociology and
related departments, and research on Latinos is
conducted by researchers without affiliations to
Latino research centers and institutes.
Themes such as “border” or “border-crossing”
often emerge within course content of Latino/a
325
Latino/a studies
studies. These themes are important reminders of
the global and transnational, as well as the transformative, nature of Latino communities in the
United States, Latin America, and the Caribbean.
Further, these metaphors permit an analysis of
the historical and contemporary relationship of
Latino communities to the economic, political,
and social structures of inequality in the United
States. These structures are rooted in the social
construction of race and ethnicity, gender, and
sexuality and these constructs often serve as catalysts for social change.
The ability to understand race/ethnicity as a
social construct is evoked in the introduction of
the syllabi. Many Latino/a studies instructors recognize that while the term Latino/a connotes themes
of similarity and shared interest across groups
falling within this socially constructed label, these
courses highlight differences that exist within and
across demographic, historical, social, economic,
and political domains. The diversity within, and
multiple experiences of, the Latino community
allow for a departure from strict disciplinary
boundaries into interdisciplinary and multidisciplinary lenses, allowing the discussion of topics,
such as culture or assimilation, to take place
beyond the confines of a single discipline. This
permits students to view “the Latino/a experience”
as one that is diverse, complex, and dynamic,
versus one that is narrow, monolithic, and static.
The American Sociological Association (ASA) has
teaching and instructional materials geared to
assisting faculty members who teach Latino courses.
In its fifth edition, Chicano/a and Latino/a Studies in
Sociology: Syllabi and Instructional Materials, by José
Calderon and Gilda Ochoa (2003), is an important
source for engaging faculty and students in the
understanding of Latino/a studies. A sampling of
topics covered in the syllabi comprising the sourcebook include “Introduction and Overview of Latino
Population,” “Mexicans: Immigration, Conquest,
and Work,” “Caribbean: Immigration, Colonialism,
and Work,” “Gender, Sexuality and Women’s Studies,” “Queer Identities in Contemporary Cultures,”
and “Institutions and Political Activism.” As suggested by these topics, Latino/a studies courses
expose students to sociological theories and analytical frameworks to understand the production, reproduction, and perpetuation of social inequalities
that shape the life chances of Latinos.
Consistent with the social change theme of
Latino studies, courses related to Latinos frequently require students to get involved in their
local communities. For example, students in such
courses tend to be involved in service learning,
326
Latino/a studies
internships, and volunteer work. Such teaching
approaches emphasize the intersection between
theory and practice and attempt to enhance the
academic experience by providing students with
experiential training.
The major absence of Latino scholars prior to the
1970s is responsible for the dearth of research about
Latinos before this time. Rogelio Saenz and Edward
Murguia, in their article “The Latino Experience:
Introduction, Context, and Overview” in Sociological
Focus (2004), observe a steady increase in the
amount of sociological research produced about
Latinos from the early 1970s to the present. In their
general assessment of research on Latinos, Saenz
and Murguia highlight four areas that have generated a significant amount of research: gender,
immigration, education, and labor markets.
One major source for the production of research
on Latinos is the Inter-University Program for
Latino Research (2005), or IUPLR, a consortium of
eighteen Latino research centers based in major
universities across the United States. Through our
examination of research projects that are being
conducted through these partnerships, based on
information from the various websites, we find
evidence of up to fifty research projects. This list
is by no means an all-inclusive summary of research projects that are connected with the various research centers. Rather it is a brief overview
from various sites, which allows us to assess
the most common research areas focusing on
Latinos.
We broadly classify the fifty research projects
into the following categories: community development; cultural and literary studies; demographic
trends; economic issues; education; ethnic relations; evaluation research; health and delivery
services; history and political economy; identity
politics; and immigration. Of these categories,
education receives the most attention, constituting 20 percent of the total research projects, with
health and delivery issues accounting for 18 percent, and art and cultural studies also receiving substantial attention. Many of these research
projects evaluate current policy initiatives or programs but also encourage other scholars to generate more research. Much of the attention in the
area of education is geared towards creating a
new generation of educated Latinos. For example,
one project assists students with college applications and another assists educators who work
with Latino parents and their children. The most
common research topics demonstrate the interdisciplinary and action-oriented nature of Latino
studies.
Latour, Bruno (1947– )
law and society
The development of Latino/a studies has also
assisted in the establishment of professional associations that have helped further develop this
branch of inquiry. The oldest of these organizations is the National Association for Chicana and
Chicano Studies (NACCS), originally established in
1972. Two decades later, the Puerto Rican Studies
Association (PRSA) was established to focus on
academic concerns related to Puerto Ricans. Moreover, Latino caucuses / special interest groups
have been formed within larger disciplinary associations. For example, the Section on Latino Sociology within the ASA was formed in the early
1990s. More recently, in the mid-1990s, the Latino
Studies Section of the Latin American Studies Association (LASA) was formed, illustrating the
transnational and diaspora links between Latinos
and Latin America.
While there have been various academic journals that originated in the late 1960s and early
1970s to disseminate research results on Latinos,
currently there are a few journals that specialize
in the reporting of evidence from sociological research investigations relating to Latino communities. These include Aztlan, Hispanic Journal of
Behavioral Sciences, and Journal of Latino and Latin
American Studies. Among the mainstream social
science outlets, Social Science Quarterly is the undisputed leader in publishing research on Latinos. Of
particular significance are the three special issues
that the journal produced in 1973, 1984, and 2000.
More recently, Southern Rural Sociology produced a
special issue on “Latinos in the South” (2003) and
Sociological Focus published a special issue on “The
Latino Experience” (2004). This article traced the
emergence of Latino/a studies during the late
1960s and 1970s.
Pioneering Latino scholars and students forged
the development of institutional arrangements,
curricula, research, professional associations, and
publication outlets. Their efforts, combined with
the growth of the Latino population, have contributed to the evolution and continued expansion of
Latino/a studies and its contribution to sociology
and wider social science disciplines.
ROGELIO SAENZ, MERCEDES RUBIO, AND
JANIE FILOTEO
Latour, Bruno (1947– )
Educated in philosophy and anthropology, Latour,
Professor at the École des Mines in Paris, has been
one of the most active contributors to the field
of science and technology studies, which emerged
in the 1970s as an alternative to more traditional approaches to the theory and philosophy
of science. Latour has combined a playful, polemical tone with conceptual and methodological innovations, as he has sought to disclose the hidden
realities of science in his Laboratory Life (1979),
with Steve Woolgar.
Latour made seminal contributions to the social
and cultural study both of science in The Pasteurization of France (1984 [trans. 1988]), most especially
through his book Science in Action (1987) and
of technology (among other places in his book
Aramis, 1992). He is also well known for his critique of modernism in his We have Never been
Modern (1993). Latour has characterized the contemporary world in terms of the “proliferation of
hybrids” and has argued that nonhumans – both
living and nonliving things – should be considered
“actors” and be attributed agency by social scientists. His work is associated with actor network
theory.
His writings have often been attacked by the
defenders of traditional approaches to science,
and he was one of the central protagonists in
what came to be called the “science wars” of the
1990s, when the kind of science studies that
Latour promoted were criticized by writers such
as Paul Gross and Norman Levitt (in Higher Superstition, 1994).
ANDREW JAMISON
law and society
This phrase refers to an association of scholars,
a journal of academic research, and a collection
of empirical approaches to understanding how law
works. As a multi-disciplinary paradigm within
twentieth-century scholarship, law and society
focuses on what legal institutions do rather than
what they ought to do. In place of the normative
and policy orientations of most jurisprudence, the
law and society approach claims that law can be
understood best empirically, as a social institution embedded within and connected to all other
social institutions. Using what are believed to be
the more reliable research practices of empirical
social scientific inquiry, law and society scholarship moved beyond purely subjective interpretations and the doctrinal argumentation of
traditional legal scholarship by systematically collecting data and developing empirically grounded
theory; at the same time law-and-society scholarship offers critical judgment about legal practices
because it is independent of the authority and
interests of the legal profession.
In 1964, a group of sociologists, political scientists, psychologists, anthropologists, historians,
and law professors formed the Law and Society
Association; in 1967, they began publishing a
327
law and society
research journal, the Law and Society Review; and
following two national meetings in the 1970s,
since 1979 they have been holding annual conferences for scholarly exchange and debate. In the
early years, the association and the journal, as
well as four research centers located on the
campuses of the University of California at Berkeley, the University of Denver, Northwestern University, and the University of Wisconsin, were
supported by generous grants from the Russell
Sage Foundation, whose interest in social policy
and change found a happy target in this nascent
intellectual movement. Recognizing law as the central governing mechanism and language of the
modern state, the foundation sought to explore
ways in which the legal profession might, or might
not, provide leadership for progressive social
change. Drawing upon diverse historical sources,
and the pioneering work of contemporaries such
as Philip Selznick at Berkeley, Harry Kalven, Hans
Zeisel, and Rita Simon at Chicago, and Willard
Hurst at Wisconsin, the birth of the law-and-society
group as a formal membership association signaled
an organized, long-term commitment to interdisciplinary empirical work that would transcend the
boundaries of distinct disciplinary fields and traditional legal scholarship. The Russell Sage Foundation, the Law and Society Association, and the Law
and Society Review created a field in which “social
science disciplines could be brought to bear on . . .
law and legal institutions in a systematic manner.”
The Foundation was, as expressed by Christopher
Tomlins in Framing the Field of Law’s Disciplinary
Encounter (2000), “both responding to and contributing to [a] moment of striking change” as epitomized by the civil rights, anti-war, and emergent
women’s and gay rights movements.
Because law is a system of both symbols and
action, structured reason and regulated force,
this social scientific study of law draws from diverse traditions that attend to both normative
aspirations and social organization. Attention to
the relationship between law and society, the role
of reason, ideas of justice, and the regulation of
force can be found in ancient and medieval works
of philosophy from Plato (427–347 BC), through
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) and John Locke
(1632–1704), to Baron Charles de Montesquieu’s
canonical work, The Spirit of the Laws (1748). These
classical works display European philosophy’s preoccupation with knowledge as a synthesis of universal, timeless truths. The cultural, social, and
variable dimensions of law became more prominent in the nineteenth century, when jurisprudential thinkers, such as Friedrich Karl von Savigny
328
law and society
(1814–75), in Germany in 1831, described law as
the slow, organic distillation of the spirit of a
particular people, and when historians, such as
Henry Maine (1822–88), in Britain in 1861, described the development of social relations over
the millennia as a movement from status to
contract.
At the beginning of the twentieth century, legal
scholars in major North American and European
institutions were devoting increasing attention to
the sociological aspects of law. The Austrian scholar
Eugen Ehrlich (1862–1922) in 1913 described what
he called “the living law,” the complex system of
norms and rules by which the members of organizations, communities, and societies actually live.
Formal law emanating from the state is dependent
in large part, he argued, on its informal concordance with the living law. Judge and jurist Oliver
Wendell Holmes, Jr. (1841–1935) perfectly expressed the movement towards a social understanding of law when he described the law as a
grand anthropological document, writing in The
Common Law (1881) that the life of the law is not
logic but experience, a word he used for culture.
Roscoe Pound (1870–1964), Dean of the Harvard
Law School, pushed the sociological perspective
yet further when, in 1910, he named the informal
practices of legal institutions the “law-in-action,”
contrasting them with the “law-in-the-books,” legal
doctrines formally enacted and ideally in force.
American legal realists, a collection of law professors and philosophers writing in the 1920s and
1930s, made the exploration of this gap between
the formal law and the law-in-action the central
focus of their research. Alongside their efforts to
expose the illogic of ostensibly logical arguments,
the legal realists began the work, taken up by the
law and society movement three decades later, to
describe the law-in-action.
By the end of World War II, the social sciences
had developed empirical tools for data collection
and analysis (for example surveys of legal use and
need, statistical analysis of court records, interviews with jurors and judges) that moved the study
of the law-in-action forward with energy and effectiveness. The social sciences had become a respectable third wing of higher education, finally
standing abreast the historically more prestigious
humanities and the more recently institutionalized sciences. From some perspectives, the social
sciences, in adopting methods from the physical
sciences, especially experimental techniques and
quantitative methods of data analysis (see quantitative data analysis), had begun to pull ahead of the
humanities as sources of reliable social knowledge.
law and society
Turning their gaze to legal processes and institutions, social scientists could also draw upon
their own disciplinary traditions to authorize
their research. The most important social theorists
writing in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries had already recognized law as a central
means of rationalized coordination and regulation
in modern societies no longer governed as tightly
by custom and religion. Post-World War II social
scientists were encouraged to look closely at how
law accomplished this role as the general societal
manager. In this work, they drew upon Émile Durkheim’s models of the different functions of law in
societies with lesser or greater divisions of labor
and sought evidence of varying degrees of repressive law or restitutive law in more or less industrialized societies. Following Max Weber, others
described patterns of litigation and legal doctrine
associated with different types of economic and
cultural development.
In its more than thirty-five years of history, this
interdisciplinary movement has produced a body
of reliable knowledge about how the law works.
Law-and-society research has discovered the role of
law everywhere, not only in courtrooms, prisons,
and law offices but also in hospitals, bedrooms,
schoolrooms, in theatres, films, and novels, and
certainly on the streets and in police stations and
paddy wagons. At times, socio-legal scholarship,
another term for law-and-society research, has
also mapped the places where law ought to be
but is not. In historical studies of litigation, policing, the legal profession and delivery of legal
services, court cultures and judicial biographies,
the effectiveness of legal regulation of workplace
and business transactions; in reports on access to
law and the structure of both professional and
popular legal consciousness; and in histories of
how particular legal doctrines and offices developed, law-and-society research demonstrates
how organization, social networks, and local cultures shape law. This research has also demonstrated how law is recursively implicated in the
construction of social worlds – of organizations,
social networks, and local cultures – and thus
contributes to both the distribution of social resources and the understandings of the world so
constituted.
These accounts describe how in doing legal
work, legal actors and officials respond to particular situations and demands for service rather than
to general prescriptions or recipes provided by
legal doctrine. Although law claims to operate
through logic and formal rationality, it is no different from most other work and, thus, rather
law and society
than following invariant general principles, proceeds on a case-by-case basis. This is evident in
the production of law through litigation and in the
creation of precedent through decisions in individual cases; it is true of law enforcement as well.
Most participants, professional and lay, operate
through reactive, situationally specific rationality.
And even in instances of organized campaigns by
civil rights organizations, trade union, or the
women’s movement for pay equity, legal strategies rely on the ability to aggregate the outcomes
of individual cases. While they may not produce
specifically material outcomes, they often achieve
cultural, conceptual transformations as described
in M. McCann’s Rights at Work (1994).
Because legal action is not rule-bound but situationally responsive, it involves extralegal decisions and action; thus, all legal actors operate
with discretion. Documenting the constraints and
capacities of legal discretion has occupied these
several generations of law-and-society scholars,
whose research provides evidence about how discretion is invoked, confined, and yet ever-elastic.
In exercising this inevitable discretion, legal
actors respond to situations and cases on the
basis of typifications developed not from criteria
of law or policy alone but from the normal and
recurrent features of social interactions. These
folk categories are used to typify variations in
social experiences in an office, agency, or professional workload and to channel appropriate or
useful responses. These typifications function as
conceptual efficiency devices.
By relying on ordinary logics, local cultural categories, and norms, legal action both reflects and
reproduces other features and institutions of
social life. On the one hand, as a tool for handling
situations and solving problems, law is available at
a cost, a cost distributed differentially according to
social class, social status, and organizational position and capacity. On the other hand, law is not
merely a resource or tool but a set of conceptual
categories and schema that produce parts of the
language and concepts people use for both constructing and interpreting social interactions and
relationships. These ideological or interpretive
aspects of law are also differentially distributed.
The most well-cited piece of law and society
research summarizes much of these findings by
creating a model of the variable capacity of legal
actors based on their status as one-time or repeat
players in the legal system, concluding that despite ambitions for equality under law, “the ‘haves’
come out ahead,” according to Marc Galanter in
his “Why the ‘Haves’ Come Out Ahead” (Law and
329
Lazarsfeld, Paul (1901–1976)
Society Review, 1974). This observation does not
undermine legality but has become part of the
common understanding that helps to sustain the
power and durability of law, just as the common
knowledge of the limitations of legality serves to
protect the law from more sustained critique.
In addition to developing a growing body of
empirical knowledge about how law works, law
and society has also been successful in institutionalizing its field of scholarship. Although the
sociology of law in Europe remains a predominantly theoretical and normative enterprise, it is,
nonetheless, a required subject for the education
and training of European lawyers. In the United
States, the original centers of law-and-society research in the law schools of Berkeley, Wisconsin,
Denver, and Northwestern remain strong, with
additional concentrations of law and society at
the University of California at Los Angeles, at
Irvine, and at Santa Barbara, the State University
of New York at Buffalo, the University of Michigan,
and New York University.
The influence of law-and-society research on
legal agencies is probably much more significant.
Most courts, agencies, and legal organizations collect data about their activities. Most recognize the
role of non-legal factors in shaping their work and
use social variables, among other indicators, to
analyze and explain legal work. Law and society
scholars regularly serve as expert witnesses in
litigations on capital punishment, witness reliability, and gender and racial discrimination,
among other topics. Newspapers also report the
results of socio-legal research. Thus, alongside a
picture of the law as a system of words and documents, law and society has succeeded in painting
a picture of law as a social system, an understanding that has been documented in popular and
professional consciousness.
SUSAN SILBEY
Lazarsfeld, Paul (1901–1976)
Born in Vienna, Paul Lazarsfeld received his PhD at
the university there in 1925. He emigrated to the
United States in 1933, became Director of the
Bureau of Applied Research at Columbia University
in 1940, and became a member of the Columbia
faculty from 1949 to 1969. Lazarsfeld is best known
for his contributions to methodology, political
sociology, and mass communications research.
Lazarsfeld was a pioneer in the development
of quantitative sociology, first through survey
research and later through such sophisticated
mathematical techniques as latent structure analysis. He helped change sociological research
from the qualitative study of communities to the
330
Le Bon, Gustave (1841–1931)
systematic, quantitative explanation of individual
characteristics and outcomes. Surveys and other
research techniques demonstrated that measurable variables could be causally linked with one
another and explain the social influences on
individual attitudes.
He utilized surveys in studies of voting behavior and audience research. In The People’s Choice
(1944), with Bernard Berelson and Hazel Gaudet,
and Personal Influence (1955), with Elihu Katz, he
developed the idea of the two step flow of communication. Though Lazarsfeld recognized that mass
media were increasingly powerful in the modern
world, he found that many people’s choices, especially regarding voting, were influenced by
the viewpoints of powerful individuals in their
communities.
Through his directorship of the Bureau of Applied Research, Lazarsfeld helped to inaugurate
university based large-scale sociological studies.
His association with Robert Merton at Columbia
contributed to a theoretically sophisticated, quantitative sociology that moved into the mainstream
of the discipline.
KENNETH H. TUCKER
Le Bon, Gustave (1841–1931)
A physician and polymath whose writings ranged
from studies of Arab and Indian civilization to treatises on photography and theoretical physics, Le
Bon is best known today as the author of The
Crowd (1895 [trans. 1896]) and as the founder of a
school of social psychology that became linked to
twentieth-century practices of propaganda and
public relations. Born in Rogent-Le-Routrou, Le
Bon studied medicine at the University of Paris
and traveled in Europe, North Africa, and India
before becoming Director of the French military
ambulance division. Influenced by Charles Darwin,
Auguste Comte, and Herbert Spencer, as well as by
Johannson Herder and nineteenth-century race
theory, Le Bon became interested in the part
played by collective psychology in the character
and development of different civilizations. For Le
Bon, what united and distinguished a nation
or “race” was not biological (since “today there
are no pure races”) but a shared depository of
beliefs and sentiments, which he conceived as a
pre-rational collective unconscious. Changes in
ideas – “the only true revolutions” – involved ferment at that level. Hence, as he explained in
The Crowd, the historical importance of crowds
and crowd psychology. Le Bon had already laid
the grounds for this analysis in L’Homme et les
sociétés (1881) and Les Lois psychologiques de l’évolution
des peuples (1884); he further developed it in Les
Le Play, Pierre Guilliaume Frédéric (1806–1882)
Opinions and les croyances (1910), Psychologie politique
(1910), and La Révolution Francaise et la psychologie
des révolutions (1912). Both with regard to peoples
and crowds, a category that extended from street
riots to legislative assemblies to the rising cultural weight of urban masses, Le Bon parallels
Émile Durkheim in his stress on the emergent
and irreducible properties of groups. He differed,
however, in his insistence on the non-rational
and unconscious elements of collective consciousness, and also in his recognition, which anticipated mass society theorists, that industrial
modernity was an “era of crowds.”
ANDREW WERNICK
Le Play, Pierre Guilliaume Frédéric
(1806–1882)
The son of a customs officer from Normandy, Le
Play was the founder of an influential school of
empirical sociology. He had a multifaceted career
and rose to become one of the most prominent
figures in the France of Louis Napoléon (1808–73).
Besides his voluminous sociological writings (many
of which were field reports in connection with
administrative assignments), he was a Professor
of Metallurgy at the École des Mines from 1844
to 1856, a member of the 1848 provisional government, and in the Second Empire was appointed a
Senator and Grand Commissioner of Expositions.
Influenced by Claude Henri de Rouvroy, Comte
de Saint-Simon, Auguste Comte, Charles Fourier
(1772–1837) and Louis Gabriel de Bonald (1754–
1840), and horrified by the violence of the 1830
revolution, Le Play campaigned for a social-sciencebased reform program that would promote social
peace in a new class-divided and individualistic industrial society. The focus of much of his
research was on the economic and social conditions of the working class family, particularly as
affected by technological, economic, and geographic determinants. His method combined fieldwork, survey research, classification systems, and
multi-sided studies of representative cases. To further his scientific work, in 1856 he established the
Société d’Économie et de Science Sociale, and in
1871, to promote his schemes for inter-class solidarity, the journal La Réforme. Among his chief
works were Les Ouvriers européens (1855), La Réforme
sociale en France (1864), L’Organisation de la famille
(1871), and La Méthode de la Science Sociale (1875).
ANDREW WERNICK
leadership
The notion of “leadership” arises as a necessary
part of a relationship. The only bodies of thought
leadership
that can deny the necessity of leadership are those
that deny that individuals need to develop
through relationships with one another.
The notion of leadership is taken for granted by
preliberal thought since hierarchy is seen as natural and people are differentiated according to
the roles they play. Rulers lead the ruled; men
lead women; lords lead their serfs; citizens lead
slaves; and so forth. The exercise of leadership is
linked to factors that cannot be changed. Leadership is permanent and static – it is preordained.
Leaders and followers cannot change places.
Indeed, the very designation of the leadership
role implies that it is irreversible. It sounds absurd
to speak of slaves leading citizens since the very
notion of a “slave” implies someone who follows.
Once a leader, always a leader.
It is therefore historically valuable that these
notions are challenged by liberalism. In the place
of hierarchical relationships, there is abstract
equality. Thus the liberal theory of representation
argues that, when one person acts as the representative of another, he or she is acting on their
behalf. The representative is authorized by those
they represent, and therefore the relationship is
not one of difference, but of sameness. The individual is re-presented at a “higher” level. No hierarchy is involved.
Hence liberalism places individuals outside relationships. Abstract individualism makes the notion
of “leadership” theoretically impossible, and it is
this abstract individualism that leads anarchists to
argue that individuals can spontaneously govern
themselves without organization or hierarchy. In
fact, since people can identify themselves as individuals only through their relationships with
others, real individuals are always in hierarchical
attachments to others.
Postliberal or relational argument accepts leadership as inevitable, since what makes a relationship
possible is that on a particular issue one person leads
and the other follows. For this reason, relationships
are necessarily hierarchical – two people can
relate to one another only because they are both
the same and different – and this difference must
generate deference of some kind. But although
postliberalism stresses the relational character of
human activity, it differs from preliberal thought
in that the notion of leadership as natural is tied
to a concept of nature that is developmental and
not static. It is natural for a parent to “lead” a
three-year-old across a busy street; it would not be
natural for a parent to lead a thirteen-year-old.
Moreover, leaders and followers continually
change places. The doctor who “leads” a motor
331
legal-rational authority
mechanic on medical matters follows such a
person when he or she wants a vehicle repaired.
Leadership, conceived of in a postliberal manner,
is always provisional and specific: a leader who is
developmental in one area becomes oppressive
when he or she seeks to guide in every issue.
Leaders in a democracy dedicate themselves to
enhancing and not diminishing the capacity of
people to govern their own lives. J O H N H O F F M A N
legal-rational authority
– see authority.
legitimacy
The authority of an institution, person, or practice
to command obedience can derive from a sense of
its rightfulness or legitimacy. People often go
along with the commands of others, rules of law
or organization, or taken-for-granted norms because of a sense of obligation or moral necessity
rather than any immediate or general threat of
coercion or promise of reward. Legitimacy,
according to Max Weber, can derive from age-old
norms (or tradition), from consciously enacted
rules (such as law), or from a sense of devotion to
an exceptional sanctity, heroism, or magical characteristic of an individual person (charisma). At
their core, all forms of legitimacy provide an explanation for the social world as it is, or as it is
hoped to be. This explanation or reason provides
the meanings that ground social action, for the
fortunate and unfortunate alike. According to
Weber, human beings are prepared to tolerate
extraordinary deprivation, suffering, and torment. What is unacceptable, however, to the unfortunate, is the meaninglessness of suffering,
and to the fortunate the meaninglessness of life
itself. “Legitimating explanations seek to justify
the distribution of fortunes by showing that it
conforms to a coherent normative conception of
some sort, a conception which not only makes the
differences in human fates intelligible but justifies them in an ethical sense as well” (Anthony
Kronman, Max Weber, 1983). Thus, legitimations,
whether from history, reason, or mysticism, offer
accounts of social arrangements and events that
make life meaningful and therefore tolerable.
Legitimacy attaches not merely to individual
actions and relationships but to institutionalized systems of power and domination. If power
consists of the probability that one actor within
a social relationship will be in a position to
achieve intended and foreseen effects (Dennis
Hume Wrong, Power, 1969), authority rests on the
belief in the rightfulness or legitimacy of that
332
leisure
action. Although authority is only one form
of power, it is the most stable and enduring
according to Weber, because it requires fewer physical or economic resources to sustain. Obedience
and deference to authority are secured by its legitimacy, deeply sedimented in social relations and
beliefs, through the “internalization of symbolically represented structures of expectation” (Jürgen
Habermas, The Legitimation Crisis, 1973 [trans.
1976]). In this sense, legitimacy is a questionbegging avoidance technique that works only to
the extent that it is unquestioned and unnoticed,
that is, it constitutes a hegemony. Once questioned, the ability of legitimacy to secure obedience is threatened because the belief in a person,
organization, or institution as legitimate derives
from its being unquestionably right. Once the subject of ideological contest, however, a social order
can experience a legitimation crisis, the revelation
of a disjuncture between the claims of legitimacy
and the validity or actual empirical facts of that
order. Embedded in legitimacy claims, therefore,
is a truth claim, which, once challenged, undermines the deference legitimacy otherwise secures.
In his analysis of types of social orders and
legitimations, Weber described a historical development from traditional to increasingly rational
systems, punctuated by charismatic eruptions.
The systemic rationalization of advanced capitalism and loss of tradition and magic would lead,
he suggested, to pervasive disenchantment.
Rationality would undermine its own legitimating
capacity by its unceasing inquiry, continually
eroding the grounds of social construction and
thus eroding the possibilities of legitimating narratives capable of commanding unquestioned deference and obedience.
SUSAN SILBEY
legitimation crisis
– see legitimacy.
leisure
The term derives from the Latin word licere,
meaning “to be allowed.” The concept was undertheorized in classical sociology, yet, arguably, it
constituted a meta-theme in much progressive
and revisionist thought of the time. For example,
the Enlightenment looked forward to the leisure
society in which individuals would have the freedom at their disposal to explore and cultivate
their diverse interests. Karl Marx regarded leisure
under capitalism to be constrained by class exploitation, commodification, and alienation. His
theory of communist society envisaged the expansion of leisure and the development of social
leisure
capital. Max Weber’s sociology implied that leisure
was subject to the rationalization process and the
bureaucratization of society. Ferdinand Tönnies’s
distinction between Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft
carried with it a critique of work-centered existence and, in as much as this is true, connoted
leisure with social well-being. However, most
classical sociologists followed Émile Durkheim in
regarding leisure as belonging to “the less serious
side of life.”
The exception was Thorstein Veblen, whose Theory
of the Leisure Class (1899) is of axial importance in
the emergence of the sociology of leisure. Veblen
defined leisure as “the non-productive consumption of time.” He argued that leisure in industrial
society is bound up with the allocation of social
distinction, which, in turn, reflects social hierarchy.
Industrial society is dominated by a leisure class of
propertied citizens, who devote themselves to nonpecuniary labor. By engaging in the equestrian arts,
cultivating etiquette, learning dead languages such
as Latin or Greek, and other non-pecuniary work,
the leisure class articulate their exemption from
the need to engage in wage-labor. Distinction in
leisure forms and practice is further expressed
through “conspicuous consumption,” that is, lavish
expenditure on fashion, entertaining, and other
forms of social display. Veblen predicted that the
development of industrial society would intensify
conspicuous consumption and erode the work
ethic.
Sociological interest in leisure expanded in the
postwar period. It was first organized around industrial sociology in the 1950s which held that the a
priori of leisure was held to be wage-labor. A variety
of studies examined the work–leisure relationship
and developed compartmentalized/segregated and
spillover/extension models of leisure. They also produced a meliorist strain in the study of leisure that
essentialized leisure as holding the characteristics
of freedom, choice, and self-determination, and related leisure practice narrowly with life fulfillment
and social integration.
By the 1960s, the coming of the leisure society
was a central element in postindustrial society
theory. It was assumed that science and technology were on the verge of solving the problems
of want and the requirement to spend a large
percentage of adult life in paid employment. Leisure Society was presented as a pluralist democracy
in which the requirement to work would be
minimized and a corresponding efflorescence of
the arts, sport, and social capital would ensue.
This approach is now regarded as unrealistic and
inadequate in its treatment of power and justice.
leisure
Questions relating to the relationships between
leisure and identity and between leisure and citizenship were peculiarly neglected until the 1970s.
Interactionist approaches developed a perspective
that stressed the situated character of leisure
action and explored choice in relation to a variety
of social, economic, and cultural constraints. However, the main units of analysis were the individual and the group, and this led to criticisms that
the approach could not deal satisfactorily with
structural influences of social class, gender, and
race and ethnicity.
The Marxist tradition revitalized the Frankfurt
School perspective that proposed that leisure is a
fundamental means of social control. The distribution of free time was directly related to class,
and the proposition that leisure is free time for
the expression of individual choice was challenged by emphasizing the preeminence of commodification and corporate domination in consumer
culture. Leisure forms and practice were analyzed
in relation to their ideological functions. The
contribution of the Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies led to leisure being
directly related to hegemony. Leisure forms and
practice were studied as contested social processes.
At the same time, feminism castigated “malestream” dominance in the allocation of leisure
time and the organization of leisure studies. Feminists related leisure to patriarchy and the tendency of commodity culture to fetishize the
female body.
All of these positions challenged meliorist overtones in the sociology of leisure by emphasizing
structural inequalities in access to leisure time
and space and by positioning myth and ideology
in relation to leisure experience.
Recent work in the field has concentrated on
questions of embodiment, classification, and globalization. Juliet Schor’s “overwork thesis” raised
the profile of the relationship of leisure to embodiment through a critique of the culture of
overwork and its consequences for physical and
mental health and mortality, such as in her The
Overworked American (1991). Overwork was analyzed as a consequence of the general addiction
to the acquisitive values of consumer culture. The
creation of a revised work–leisure balance is portrayed as the solution to overwork and the ills
of the consumer society.
Robert Stebbins’s distinction, in Amateurs, Professionals and Serious Leisure (1992), between “serious” and “casual” leisure revitalized the interest
in classifying leisure forms and practice. Serious
leisure refers to a trajectory of activity based in
333
leisure class
Leninism
the concept of a career and the progressive improvement of skills. Casual leisure refers to desultory, opportunistic practice which is associated
with low attention spans and multi-tasking.
Globalization was recognized as a foundational
issue in the development of leisure studies in the
São Paulo Declaration issued by the World Leisure
and Recreation Association in 1998. Citing Article
24 of the United Nations Universal Declaration of
Human Rights which articulated the right to leisure
for every member of the world’s community,
the Declaration pointed to the need to study the
global dimensions of inequality and injustice in
leisure forms and practice. One urgent research
issue here is the dynamics of sourcing leisure
commodities for retail by western leisure multinationals from low-wage developing economies.
CHRIS ROJEK
leisure class
– see leisure.
leisure society
– see leisure.
Lemert, Edwin M. (1912– )
An American sociologist, Lemert has been influential in the development of a social-psychological
level of analysis in relation to the onset of delinquency and crime. His particular contribution
has been to refine labeling theory. According to
Lemert, in order to describe the process of labeling,
it is important to distinguish between primary
deviation and secondary deviation.
Primary deviation refers to the initial deviant
action or behavior. Lemert acknowledged the very
wide range of reasons for this: social, cultural,
and psychological reasons. More particularly,
he acknowledged that many people do engage
in deviant or delinquent behaviors (underage
drinking, smoking cannabis or petty shoplifting)
and that for the most part engagement in activities does not lead to a psychological reorientation
in terms of self-identity (that is, individuals do not
immediately see themselves as a drunk, a pothead,
or a thief). There is no fundamental change in
identity.
Secondary deviation relates to the official or
social reaction to the primary deviant behavior
which involves the labeling of the individual (as
a “young offender” or as a “criminal,” for instance). Lemert’s thesis was that individuals so
labeled would begin to engage in deviant behavior
334
based upon the new social status of “young offender” or “criminal” conferred on them by the
criminal justice system. Through formal namecalling, stereotyping, and labeling, a deviant identity is confirmed. Lemert’s subsequent assertion
that social control causes deviance not only provided impetus for the development of a radical
and critical criminology that has flourished since
the 1960s, but fueled the abolitionist movement.
The “naming and shaming” tactics so favored by
politicians in the United Kingdom may thus have
unintended adverse consequences.
LORAINE GELSTHORPE
Lenin, Vladimir Ilich (1870–1924)
Famous for his leadership of the Russian Revolution, and for his theory of the party and imperialism, Lenin was born in Simbirsk, Russia. He was
expelled from the University of Kazan in 1887
for political involvement, and, after being sentenced to three years of internal exile, he wrote
The Development of Capitalism in Russia (1899).
In 1900 he became involved with Iskra, the
official paper of the Social Democratic Labor
Party, and two years later Lenin presented the
case for a party of professional revolutionaries in
What Is To Be Done? (1902). He returned to Russia
during the abortive 1905 revolution. In 1917 (in
Switzerland), he published Imperialism: The Highest
Stage of Capitalism.
When the tsar abdicated in March, 1917, Lenin
argued the case for a socialist revolution in his
April Theses. This was successfully engineered in
October. Lenin became head of the Soviet Council
of Peoples’ Commissars, and land was distributed to peasants, banks were nationalized, and
workers’ control of factory production introduced.
An assembly, elected to draw up a new constitution, had a socialist but not Bolshevik majority. It
was closed down and other political parties were
banned, and, although the Bolsheviks won
the civil war, they were faced with an uprising
at Kronstadt. Lenin then introduced the New
Economic Policy that allowed some market
trading and denationalization.
His health declined after an attempt was made on
his life. Three days after dictating a “will and testament,” in which he called for the removal of
Joseph Stalin (1879–1953) from the post of General
Secretary of the Communist Party, he died in 1924.
JOHN HOFFMAN
Leninism
– see Vladimir Ilich Lenin.
Lenski, Gerhard (1924– )
Lenski, Gerhard (1924– )
An American sociologist, Lenski contributed significantly to the study of inequality, social change,
and religion. In The Religious Factor (1981) he made
an importart contribution to the development of
the sociology of religion in the United States.
He is best known for his attempt at synthesizing
the functional and conflict explanations of
social hierarchy through broad historical comparisons, and for his contribution to the theory of
status crystallization (see social status). In Power
and Privilege (1966) and Human Societies (1982)
Lenski outlined an ecological–evolutionary social
theory. All desirable resources, including food,
money, prestige, and power, are scarce, and
therefore obtained through competitive struggles
by the best-endowed individuals and groups. This
competitive struggle is reduced owing to routinization of unequal distribution systems. Such
systems, legitimized by custom and tradition, reflect the operation of two parallel “laws.” The “law
of needs” reflects largely the functional needs of
society, such as survival and maintenance of the
productive efficiencies of all social groups, including the lower strata. The “law of power” applies
mainly to the distribution of “surpluses,” that is
resources exceeding basic functional needs. The
surpluses are distributed proportionately to differential power, and therefore are concentrated in
elites and privileged classes. The implication of
this argument is that the less technologically advanced societies have more egalitarian–functional
distribution systems, and that social hierarchies become steeper with the advancement of
technology and surplus production. This regularity, argues Lenski, does not apply to modern industrial societies owing to enhanced productivity,
increasing legal regulation, and democratic ideology. The rule of law changes the power balances in
modern societies to the advantage of the lower
strata by increasing their bargaining power and
widening their access to welfare. Therefore social
stratification in advanced societies is multidimensional and complex, and power hierarchies are
JAN PAKULSKI
open.
lesbian feminism
In the early 1970s, in the period of feminism
usually described as “second-wave feminism,” a
number of feminists argued that the only way to
end the oppression of women was for women
to identify themselves as lesbians. Any other
form of sexual identity was, for many writers,
merely a way of prolonging sexual inequality and
abandoning the possibilities of female autonomy
Lesbian Studies
and emancipation. Prominent among the writers
who suggested this was Jill Johnston, who published two collections of essays (Marmalade Me,
1971, and Lesbian Nation, 1973). In both collections
(drawn from essays which Johnston had written
for New York’s The Village Voice) liberal feminism,
or any feminism which accepted heterosexuality,
was seen as merely an extension of patriarchy by
other means. Johnston’s vivid prose was very influential at the time and her work contributed considerably to the ideas of her contemporaries Kate
Millett, Andrea Dworkin, and Adrienne Rich.
All these writers were to follow Johnston in her
analysis of heterosexuality as “compulsory” (as it
was to be described by Adrienne Rich) or inherently based on male violence towards women (as
Dworkin was to argue).
The influence of these writers has been considerable, but two other forms of lesbian feminism
have been equally important. The first is the integration of the idea of the strength of relationships
between women (sexually active or not) into academic literature: Terry Castle in The Apparitional
Lesbian (1993) and Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick in Epistemology of the Closet (1991) are two examples of
writers who have pointed out the hidden tradition
of relationships between women in literature. The
second is the considerable strength of the tradition of lesbian feminism which has been influential in campaigns about violence against women
and legislation about marriage. In both cases lesbian feminists have pointed out – as have some
French feminists – the importance of women,
rather than men, defining female sexuality.
MARY EVANS
Lesbian Studies
Like gay studies, this is a product of the identity
politics of the 1960s and is closely associated with
lesbian feminism, which argued that women could
still be marginalized and silenced even within
the women’s movement. Radical lesbian activists
argued that the interests of women were not best
served without the rejection of female heterosexuality, and hence lesbian studies is not identical
with women’s studies.
In the United States the National Organization of
Women adopted a resolution in 1971 that supported lesbians. In 1991 the Center for Lesbian and
Gay Studies was founded in the Graduate Center of
the City University of New York. A non-profit organization, the Lesbian Studies Institute was formed in
1995. The first National Lesbian Conference in the
United Kingdom took place in Canterbury in 1974
and a Coordinating Committee was established in
335
Lesbian Studies
1975. In the 1970s therefore lesbian communities
sprang up and were influenced by “second-wave
feminism” viewing lesbianism as an expression of
alternative values such as co-operation, a caring
ethic, and egalitarianism. Lesbianism rejected the
competitive and aggressive culture associated with
masculinity and patriarchy. Lesbians came to reject
the heterosexuality of traditional female social
roles embracing androgynous styles such as Tshirts and blue jeans, and rejecting bras, lipstick,
and jewelry.
In Sex and Sensibility (1997) Arlene Stein has
examined how lesbian identities were constructed
in the 1970s, but by the 1990s a narrow lesbian
identity had become much more diverse, fragmented, and complex. Many black women felt
excluded by the primarily middle-class, white lesbianism of the 1970s. There was also a tendency to
reject lesbianism as a political category in order to
explore sexual desire within a lesbian framework.
Lillian Faderman in Odd Girls and Twilight Lovers
(1991) describes the diverse subcultures of the lesbian movement, such as “lipstick lesbians,” “punk
lesbians” and “s&m lesbians.” The lesbian community is also fragmented around generational differences. Older lesbian women, like older gay
men, face special difficulties since they have spent
much of their lives hiding their sexuality prior to
the lesbian social movements of the 1970s.
Several academic journals now publish research
on lesbian life and culture. The Journal of Lesbian
Studies examines the cultural, historical, and interpersonal impact of the lesbian experience on society. Another journal is GLQ – a journal of lesbian and
gay studies (launched in 1994). Hypatia and Lesbian
Ethics deal with philosophical and ethical issues.
Handbook of Lesbian & Gay Studies (2002), edited by
Diane Richardson and Steven Seidman, provides a
rich guide to this diverse field of social science
research. Research related to lesbianism is organized and promoted by the National Consortium of
Directors of Lesbian Gay Bisexual and Transsexual
Resources in Higher Education in the United
States.
Lesbian Studies faces the same dilemma as gay
studies. There is a need to criticize mainstream
social science literature for its neglect of gay and
lesbian cultures, but there is also the problem of the
academic co-option of lesbian politics and identity.
Despite the proliferation of books about lesbian
and gay studies, relatively little is known empirically about how gay and lesbian people organize
their daily lives, including their sexual practices.
While the sociology of sex is underdeveloped,
historical, philosophical, and literary studies of
336
Lévi-Strauss, Claude (1908– )
sexuality experienced a vigorous growth in the
late twentieth century.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Lévi-Strauss, Claude (1908– )
The leading French anthropologist of the second
half of the twentieth century, Lévi-Strauss has had
a discernible impact on thinkers as diverse as
Simone de Beauvoir, Fernand Braudel (1902–85),
Mary Douglas, and Jacques Derrida (1930–2004). In
the first of some dozen major works, The Elementary Structures of Kinship (1949 [trans. 1969]), he
demonstrates that unilineal kinship systems
prescribing the marriage of cousins are logically
equivalent to systems of reciprocal exchange.
Against the consensus at the time, he argues that
the incest prohibition is not merely the first of
all cultural rules but also a prescription in negative form to marry outside the family; hence, kinship systems generally should be understood
first as systems of alliance and only derivatively
as systems of descent.
He is most widely known as part-founder, and the
leading exponent, of structuralism. For Lévi-Strauss,
function rarely if ever exhaustively determines
structure. Structure properly speaking is the property of logical models of a finite number of elements, each of which stands in a fully determinate
relationship to every other. Those of proper interest
to the anthropologist are generative of meaning.
None is more instructive than the linguistic model
of the phonemic system, a matrix of binarily opposed phonic qualities specific to each language
that in their several permutations yield the minimal functional building blocks of words and
sentences. In The Savage Mind (1962 [trans. 1966]),
Lévi-Strauss accordingly offers a portrait of the
primitive bricoleur or “tinkerer” whose habits of
mind tend spontaneously towards the ordering
of the finite data of sensory experience into a
closed, atemporal totality of analogical pairings of
the elements of two fundamental, binarily opposed
series, one natural and the other cultural. In the
four magisterial volumes of The Mythologiques (1964
[trans. 1969], 1966 [trans. 1971], 1968 [trans. 1978],
1971 [trans. 1981]), he presumes that the same
habits of mind and the same binary opposition
between nature and culture underlie the genesis
of myth. He replaces the model of the source-text
and its diffusion with that of the version and its
permutations; he rejects psychoanalytic, cosmogonic, and all substantialist interpretations of
mythological symbolism and defends instead the
thesis that mythology is a recoding of ordinary
language, the meaning of whose elements is determined exclusively by the relations they bear to
liberalism
other elements of the same recoding. Because
myths resolve and so mask at the symbolic level
metaphysical and social problems that cannot be
resolved in fact, they function “ideologically” in
the Marxist sense of that term. Lévi-Strauss indeed
pronounces his anthropology a contribution both
to the science of superstructures and to theoretical
psychology. Critics such as Pierre Bourdieu thus
object to his relative neglect of human interaction.
Others object to his formalistic and speculative
excesses. Still other criticisms such as poststructuralism reject in principle his attempt to accord theoretical primacy to structure over history and the
event.
JAMES D. FAUBION
liberalism
Liberalism is essentially a modern outlook, although aspects of liberalism can be found among
the Sophists of ancient Greece with their argument
that the state is not natural, but conventional.
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) was one of the
earliest liberals in Britain, and what makes
Hobbes a liberal is the abstract individual premises underpinning his argument for a strong sovereign state. Classical liberalism, until the late
eighteenth century, subscribed to a state-of-nature
thesis, in which humans were seen as naturally
equal, living outside both state and society, and
consenting to form the latter through a social
contract. It is the universality of this freedom
and equality that makes liberalism so subversive
historically. All individuals are in theory free and
equal, so that liberalism refuses to accept that
repressive hierarchies are natural. Hobbes is
quintessentially liberal in his argument that
people, by nature, seek to govern themselves:
they have inalienable rights. Although Hobbes
supported the conservative side during the English Civil War, it was the liberal premises of his
argument that accounted for the reservations felt
towards him by the royalists.
Much more conventionally liberal is the work of
John Locke (1632–1704). Locke makes the case for a
constitutionally governed state. Whereas both he
and Hobbes saw the state as authorized through
consent and contract, Locke limits the prerogatives of the state to a defense of private property
and allows radically dissatisfied citizens the right
to overthrow an oppressive state.
While the classical liberals argued that the state is
conventional and artificial, they all take the view
that the state is necessary, because, for one reason
or another, a state of nature cannot be sustained.
Even Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78), who argues
that the individual is reconstituted by the social
liberalism
contract, states that individuals have a freedom
that is natural and inalienable. For this reason, he
too is a liberal, even though his critics fear that a
“legitimate” state, governed by the general will,
might exercise extensive powers in making people
“free.”
Towards the end of the eighteenth century, liberals came to reject the notion of the state
of nature. They accepted that individuals have
always lived in a society, and the idea that the
state is the creation of a social contract was seen
as implausible. Nevertheless, liberals continued to
operate with a notion of the individual that abstracts him or her (it is usually a him) from social
relationships. Rousseau is unashamedly patriarchal in his assumption that the citizen must be
a man (and much else besides), and this led Mary
Wollstonecraft (1759–97) to complain bitterly that
Rousseau’s support for autonomy and freedom
did not apply to women. While the utilitarians
may have rejected the notion of “natural rights,”
they too accepted that individuals should be conceived as separate, atomistic beings whose freedom can be expressed in a purely abstract way.
Society remains external to the individual, even
when liberals speak of the social nature of
humanity.
It is the abstraction of individuals from social
relationships that make them what they are, that
accounts for the necessary tension between the
universal theory preached by liberals and the reality of their actual practice. Liberals historically
supported slavery (a property right, after all),
elitism, patriarchy, colonialism, and the political
power of the middle classes, and it is only in the
twentieth century that liberals have supported
the case for democratic rule. The key to understanding this apparent paradox is the liberal
view that the market is natural and the desire to
appropriate private property is linked to human
nature. By property is meant not simply possessions, but possessions that can generate sufficient
income to sustain people independently.
It is because individuals naturally appropriate
property privately that men are favored over
women; the family is seen as a mechanism for
transferring property from father to son; rationality is identified with appropriation; the propertyless are excluded from the franchise; “lesser”
people are colonized by the “civilized”; and,
given the conflicts that the private ownership of
property generates, liberals support the case for
the state. It is revealing that John Stuart Mill
could argue in his famous On Liberty (1859) that
not only is force necessary when individuals
337
life chances
life-course
harm society, but certain individuals (like Native
Americans, for example) are not “ready” for selfgovernment and must be ruled by others. Just how
freedom and the state are to be reconciled
remains an insoluble problem for liberals, since
freedom is (rightly) deemed the absence of force,
and yet the state, though artificial in most liberal
accounts, is seen as necessary.
Critics of liberalism argue that its notion of freedom allows for license and even self-destruction,
but we should not take abstract premises of liberal concepts at face value. They are tied to the
notion of private property, and therefore the exercise of liberal values is linked to this institution. It
is not surprising that liberalism has unwittingly
generated a whole range of ideologies that seek to
bring liberal theory into accord with social practice. Anarchists argue that the state is a barrier to
freedom; socialists, that freedom and equality
must be social as well as political and legal. Feminists protest that individuality, if it is to be universal, must apply to women as well as men, while
environmentalists and animal rights supporters
contend that egalitarian attitudes need to extend
well beyond humanity.
Modern liberals have extended the notion of
freedom into social spheres so that in Britain, for
example, the architect of the welfare state was a
liberal. Nor do modern liberals see the market as
an autonomous, self-regulating entity, but make
the case – John Maynard Keynes was another great
British liberal – for intervention by the state, and
the role of collective institutions such as trade
unions and cooperatives, to secure social justice.
Social liberals can be quite close to socialists, but
arguably social liberals seek to make a capitalist
society fair and humane, rather than transform it.
The notion of the individual seeking to realize
their freedom through the acquisition of private
property remains at the heart of the theory.
JOHN HOFFMAN
life chances
This notion refers to the access that an individual
has to valued social and economic goods such as
education, health care, or high income. For Karl
Marx, life chances were determined by social class
position, with members of the working classes
having structurally determined poorer life chances than those in the ruling class. Max Weber
agreed with Marx that the individual’s relationship to the means of production were an important determinant of life chances. However, he
argued that there were other sources of power
that could also determine them. In particular he
338
referred to the formation of status groups. Highsocial-status groups are accorded honor and esteem and have a lifestyle, based on consumption
rather than production, which gives them a privileged position in society, independently of their
economic position. While economically dominant
classes will successfully consolidate themselves as
high-status groups, Weber argued that this was
not always the case. For example, some economically successful groups, such as the nouveaux
riches, still find themselves excluded from the
higher reaches of society. Alternatively, impoverished aristocrats in European societies are accorded high social status and esteem, allowing
them to benefit from their access to the economically successful. Weber’s fundamental point in developing the concept of life chances and status
groups was to balance Marx’s economic determinism with an account of social life that emphasized
that it was the meaning individuals gave to their
life experiences that shaped their formation into
communities.
KEVIN WHITE
life-course
Although the life-cycle follows a linear biological
trajectory from birth to death, sociologists and gerontologists emphasize the role of historical, social,
and cultural context in aging and in shaping
trajectories of individual development. Indebted to
the insight of the German sociologist, Karl Mannheim, who argued in Ideology and Utopia (1936) that
different social and historical settings produce different perspectives, life-course researchers investigate how the timing of sociobiographical events,
such as graduation or marriage, at a particular age
interfaces with specific historical or generational
events and the social context in which they are
experienced (for example, G. Elder, “The Life
Course as Developmental Theory,” 1998, Child Development). They examine how variation in, among
other contextual characteristics, family structure
and background, gender, race, religion, occupation,
and social class differentially impact how aging
and life-course transitions (for example, adolescence, getting a first job, parenthood, retirement,
or chronic illness) are negotiated. Life-course researchers pay attention to how the contextual specificity of, for example, being a college-age student
rather than a preteen or the middle-aged parent of
a college-age student in the 1990s will lead to different constellations of experiences that in turn
may differentiate the subsequent demographic
and other life-course events of these different
individuals (and their age peers). The biggest challenge confronting studies of the life-course is
life-cycle
lifeworld
disentangling the discrete effects of, and interactions between, age, cohort, and historical period
on life-course patterns. Longitudinal studies that
follow the same individuals from multiple cohorts
and across time allow researchers to identify what
trajectories may be specific to a particular cohort
growing up in particular sociohistorical context
and what may be generalizable primarily to age
or to a particular life-course transition or event.
MICHELE DILLON
life-cycle
– see life-course.
life expectancy
– see age.
lifestyle
This refers to relatively distinctive patterns of
action and culture that differentiate people. In
this respect, the study of lifestyles is less concerned with individual idiosyncrasy than with expressive modes of behavior that forge collective
patterns of living. Many sociologists have utilized
lifestyle rather than other terms like subculture as
it does not necessarily imply a deviant relationship to the dominant culture. Instead the study of
lifestyle is employed to emphasize distinctions at
the level of practice within wider frameworks of
culture and power.
In particular, many sociologists following Pierre
Bourdieu in Distinction (1979 [trans. 1984]) sought
to emphasize how, in modern class-based societies, lifestyles serve to distinguish some groups
from others as well as providing the conditions for
in-group solidarity. Hence some lifestyles are able
to gain a wider social legitimacy at the expense of
other ways of life. In this sense, lifestyle is closely
connected to the unequal distribution of symbolic
resources and power in society. Further, having a
lifestyle depends upon certain cultural markers
and the ability to establish boundaries on the
basis of taste. However, the cultural codes that
serve to legitimize some lifestyle groupings are
not fixed and are the subject of intense contestation and cultural change. More recently, following the work of Anthony Giddens in Modernity
and Self-Identity (1991), there has been a trend to
view lifestyle as a reflexive product and to argue
that it has certain political connotations that are
not limited solely to the competition over social
status. Lifestyles in this understanding are still
concerned with wider questions of social legitimacy, but become increasingly focused on “how we
should live” in a global world.
NICK STEVENSON
lifeworld
This refers to the taken-for-granted world of our
experience. It is our “common sense,” our everyday
attitude about ourselves, others, and the objective
world. It is shaped by shared meanings, symbols,
and language.
The philosopher Edmund Husserl (1859–1938)
developed the idea of the lifeworld in The Crisis of
the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (1936 [trans. 1970]). He founded the philosophy of phenomenology, which investigates the
rules of consciousness which structure experience, the ways in which we organize our reality
so that it appears to us as integrated and authentic. For Husserl, the lifeworld supplies the underlying cultural harmony and the rules that govern
our beliefs about what is real and normal. The
lifeworld also provides the background for science, which extends taken-for-granted beliefs in
a systematic manner.
Yet Husserl did not explore the social and cultural dimensions of the common lifeworld experience in depth, as he was interested in formal
philosophical issues. Alfred Schutz developed a
sociology of the lifeworld and a social phenomenology. For Schutz, the lifeworld is a shared,
common world of culture. Our lifeworld beliefs
are based on typifications, the assumptions and
taken-for-granted knowledge through which people interpret and classify one another in everyday
life. Individuals draw on their life experience,
their biographies, to understand one another.
Social scientific research confronts a lifeworld
rich in meanings and interpretations. For Schutz,
the categories of science derive from the lifeworld.
The ideal types, the most general ideas about
the social world which social scientists utilize, are
based on everyday typifications. All knowledge
begins from commonsense and cannot be separated from the social context in which it emerges.
Schutz argues that a satisfactory social science
must begin with an understanding of the subjective
world of its subjects; it must study their lifeworld.
The idea of the lifeworld has influenced many
sociological perspectives. Harold Garfinkel, the
founder of ethnomethodology, explores the activities and performances by which people construct
a taken-for-granted lifeworld. Other authors have
taken the lifeworld concept in different directions.
Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann, in The Social
Construction of Reality (1967), argue that we inhabit
multiple lifeworlds. Moreover, people with social
power can impose their definition of reality on
others.
339
liminality
The contemporary German sociologist and philosopher Jürgen Habermas has also utilized the
concept of the lifeworld. Habermas distinguishes
between the “system” and the lifeworld. The
system is the economic and bureaucratic spheres
of social life, ruled by the criteria of efficiency and
calculability. The lifeworld is the arena of family
and voluntary associations outside these bureaucratic institutions. It is a realm of background,
intuitive beliefs from which people draw the
knowledge that they use to reach mutual understanding. The lifeworld is oriented towards unconstrained communication and the development of
shared values. Habermas argues that the system
has begun to “colonize” the lifeworld, as corporations increasingly shape everyday life, and
consumerism and mass media influence social
interactions. He fears that more and more aspects
of the lifeworld are controlled by the system
criteria of money and efficiency.
KENNETH H. TUCKER
liminality
– see religion.
linguistic turn
This is a description of the revolutionary movement
in twentieth-century western philosophy, popularized by the American philosopher Richard Rorty
who edited a book with the same title, and embodying the view that philosophical analysis is vitiated
by unexamined uses of ordinary language. Reformers (such as Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and the
early Ludwig Wittgenstein) aimed to construct
the basis for an ideal language whose undefined
descriptive terms would refer to objects that are
directly known, while ordinary language philosophers (John Austin, the later Wittgenstein, and
others) maintained that language requires detailed
analysis so that the ordinary connotations of linguistic expressions do not become unexamined
contaminants of philosophical investigation.
The failure of the reformers’ program, most
forcefully articulated in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (1953), opened the way to
widespread recognition of the extent to which
language and symbolic systems are intricated
in every form of social analysis. In the Anglophone
social sciences, this movement issued in the
Austin/Searle theory of speech acts which formed
the basis of Jürgen Habermas’s theory of communicative competence, and in ethnomethodology, conversational analysis, and a focus on
the significance of discourse and narrative in
social organization. In European social theory, it
340
Lockwood, David (1929– )
powered an assault on phenomenology that emerged in the structuralism of Claude Lévi-Strauss
and the poststructuralism of Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, and others. The methodological
questions raised by the linguistic turn remain
largely unresolved, though the structuring of subjectivity and social relations by linguistic and
symbol systems that are themselves open and revisable is a common theme in most forms of social
science influenced by it.
JOHN HERITAGE
Lipset, Seymour Martin (1922– )
A leading American sociologist, a past professor at
Harvard and Stanford, and former President of
both the American Sociological Association and
the American Political Science Association, Lipset
is the author and co-author of over two dozen books,
including Agrarian Socialism (1950), Union Democracy
(1956), Social Mobility in Industrial Society (1959), Political Man (1960), The First New Nation (1963), Revolution
and Counter-Revolution (1969), The Politics of Unreason
(1971), Consensus and Conflict (1985), Continental Divide
(1990), Jews in the New American Scene (1995), American
Exceptionalism (1996), It Didn’t Happen Here (2001),
and The Paradox of American Unionism (2004). These
writings cover a broad range of topics. Perhaps
best known are Lipset’s contributions to political
sociology, such as the theories of democracy
(especially industrial democracy) and authoritarianism, social stratification and mobility, revolution,
nation formation, and the trade union movement.
According to the original scheme formulated by
Lipset and Stein Rokkan in their Party Systems and
Voter Alignments (1967), the major social and political cleavages in modern societies – left versus
right, urban–industrial versus rural–agricultural,
religious versus secular, and national versus local –
were formed during a series of revolutions –
industrial, national, and political – between the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. These cleavages gave rise to stable party-ideological divisions
common to all modern western societies. Together
with other students of social mobility, Lipset also
formulated a thesis that the absolute rates of social
fluidity increase with industrial modernization,
and he helped to demolish some myths concerning
the unique social openness of the American society.
The Encyclopedia of Democracy edited by Lipset (1998)
remains the key source in political sociology.
JAN PAKULSKI
Lockwood, David (1929– )
A British sociologist best known for his contributions to sociology of social class, occupational
stratification, and social conflict, in his study The
log linear analyses
lone-parent family
Blackcoated Worker (1958) Lockwood argued that
the clerical occupational strata in Britain were
losing social status but maintaining social distinctiveness vis-à-vis skilled manual workers. This
was followed by a classic study in England, The
Affluent Worker (1969), in which Lockwood participated as a senior researcher. It confirmed an internal differentiation within the British working
class, and identified a new segment of privatized,
home- and family-centered manual workers, who
displayed an instrumental orientation towards
work and weak communal ties.
In his early work on social conflict and change,
Lockwood made an important distinction between
social and system integration. The former concerned the relationship between social collectivities (classes, strata, and ethno-racial groups); the
latter referred to the relationship between the
elements of the social system, that is institutions
and their clusters, such as the law, the family, and
the economy.
Lockwood’s latest theoretical work, especially
Solidarity and Schism (1992), focuses on the deficiencies of the Marxist theory of change, and the
Durkheimian and Parsonian integrative functionalism, especially the functionalist account of
social conflict. While Marxism needs a more explicit theory of action, the functionalist account,
argues Lockwood, needs a supplement on the
sources of the “systematic distribution and redistribution of material resources” (1992: 97). Popular images and classifications that underlie class
and status–occupational divisions have to be causally linked with the actual patterns of resource
distribution in society. Norms and perceptions
perpetuate social order but do not explain it.
JAN PAKULSKI
log linear analyses
These are a form of multivariate analysis particularly suited to categorical variables. Unlike true
measures, such as life expectancy or income,
many sociological variables are naturally categorical, such as gender, ethnic group, or economic
status (employed, unemployed, full-time carer,
student, or retired). For bivariate analyses, the
relationship between two categorical variables
can be examined by looking at a cross-tabulation
of the two variables and calculating the appropriate row or column percentages. However, for more
complex problems (for example, to examine the
different patterns of economic status in men and
women in different immigrant groups) more advanced analyses are necessary to explore the relationships and interactions between variables. Log
linear analyses are a class of statistics that can
analyze such multi-dimensional tables.
One particular type of log linear analysis, logistic regression, is used more than any other
in sociology. This can be seen as a direct equivalent of multiple regression, but with a dichotomous dependent variable, instead of a continuous
dependent variable.
Log linear analyses are a relatively new innovation in sociological statistics. Whereas other statistical techniques were developed at the start of
the twentieth century, log linear analyses have
only entered common usage since the 1980s. Although functionally similar to regression techniques, log linear analyses are based on more
advanced mathematics than correlations or linear
regressions.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
logical positivism
– see positivism.
lone-parent family
The terminology used to depict parents (typically
mothers) who have borne or who raise children
outside marriage has changed considerably since
1900. This shifting terminology reflects changing
social attitudes and is a kind of cultural barometer of the acceptance of alternative family forms
in Western societies. One longstanding term was
“the unmarried mother,” and her child might
have been referred to as a “bastard” or, more
recently, as illegitimate. This terminology did
not depict the mother and child as constituting a
family at all, because a socially acceptable family
required both a husband and a marriage certificate. From “unmarried mother” the terminology
changed to “single-parent” family. This reflected
the recognition that fathers too could raise children alone, as well as acknowledging that parents
and children living in a household together were,
in fact, a family. The subsequent shift to the terminology of “lone-parent family” was an acknowledgment that the most common route into this
form of parenthood was divorce rather than nonmarital conception. This means that the status of
lone-parent family in the United Kingdom and the
United States today is reached through marital
breakdown, rather than through contraceptive
failure; it also means that lone parents are now
much less likely to be teenage (or young) mothers
than in the 1950s or 1960s (Kiernan et al., Lone
Motherhood in Twentieth-Century Britain, 1999). To
complicate this picture further, it is now recognized that many unmarried mothers are not
really lone parents at all. They may be unmarried,
341
longitudinal study
Luckmann, Thomas (1927– )
but they are often living with a partner in a
cohabiting relationship.
This shifting terminology may reflect a
changing moral climate and a greater degree of
acceptance that families come in a variety of
shapes and sizes, but lone-parent families remain
a particular concern for social policy and governments. Lone-parent families are much more likely
to live in poverty than two-parent families, which
means, in turn, that their children are more likely
to face material hardship than children born and
raised in two-parent households (K. Glendinning
and J. Millar, Women and Poverty in Britain, 1992). So
although moral condemnation may have waned,
lone parents are often still depicted as “problem
families.” Of course this definition relates to whether the poverty that lone-parent families face
is seen as being a consequence of their “choice”
to leave marriage or never to marry (that is fecklessness) in which case they are problem families,
or whether it is seen as being a consequence of
the difficulty for mothers of going out to work
while raising children alone, combined with inadequate rates of state benefits, in which case they
are families with problems. Right-wing commentators have raised fears that an underclass is
developing, with mothers raising sons without
discipline or work ethic and daughters without
sexual morals (Karen Struening, New Family Values,
2002). Others, who are more left-leaning, point
instead to Nordic societies where lone parenthood
is much less likely to be associated with poverty
and disadvantage because of the state provision of
child-care, family-friendly work policies, and
higher rates of welfare benefits for those who
cannot work. The status and material well-being
of lone-parent families (particularly those headed
by mothers) is therefore highly dependent on state
policies and the extent to which governments wish
to discourage lone parenthood in preference for
married parenthood (J. Millar and K. Rowlingson,
Lone Parents, Employment and Social Policy: Crossnational Comparisons, 2001).
CAROL SMART
descriptors entail the use of summary descriptions
based closely on participants’ accounts, and the use
of field notes. A commonly used low-inference
descriptor is verbatim quotation.
There are, however, a number of potential problems with the use of low-inference descriptors as a
strategy for ensuring a study’s validity. Researchers are divided as to the relative merits of descriptive summary and isolated verbatim quotation
versus the use of detailed transcripts and conversational- or discourse-analytic commentary. In Discourse Analysis Means Doing Analysis (2003), Charles
Antaki et al. identify six possible analytic shortcomings for qualitative researchers working with
discursive data. These are: (1) under-analysis
through summary; (2) under-analysis through
taking sides; (3) under-analysis through overquotation or through isolated quotation; (4) the
circular identification of discourses and mental
constructs; (5) false survey; and (6) analysis that
consists of simply spotting features.
As Harvey Sacks noted, we make inferences by
a deceptively simple activity: that of giving a
description. Herein lies a potential concern for
qualitative researchers. By giving a description
of a description, one can, at best, lose vital information, through eliding the detail and conversational nuances of the original. Low-inference
descriptors, such as summary paraphrasing may,
on close inspection, themselves be replete with
(high-inference) descriptive psychological language – imputed motives, beliefs, emotions, and
so on. This may be problematic in that the interactional details of participants’ own accounts
of psychological matters may be obscured.
Further, the use of transcribed verbatim quotes,
though laudable, and a necessary precursor to
analysis, does not, in and of itself, constitute analysis as such. Indeed, the extraction of participants’ utterances from their original conversational
context may actually prohibit some variants of discourse analysis (including conversational analysis).
longitudinal study
Luckmann, Thomas (1927– )
– see panel study.
Born in Germany, Luckmann is a sociology professor at the University of Konstanz. Influenced by
Alfred Schutz, he played a significant role in
making phenomenology more accessible to sociologists through The Social Construction of Reality
(co-authored with Peter L. Berger, 1966) and Phenomenology and Sociology (1978). Luckmann sought
to bridge the increased differentiation of disciplines, itself the product of modernity and of
the secularization of social theory from the
looking-glass self
– see Charles Horton Cooley.
low-inference descriptors
These descriptors are one of a range of strategies
used to promote the validity of qualitative research.
Other strategies include triangulation, deviant case
analysis, and reflexivity. Specifically, low-inference
342
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
Luhmann, Niklas, (1927–1998)
control of religious interpretations. He was especially interested in reintegrating sociology’s philosophical foundations with the positivism of social
science. Luckmann’s various writings emphasize
the centrality of human experience in everyday
life and the lived, reflexive intersubjectivity of
everyday communication (thus influencing Jürgen
Habermas’s theory of communicative action).
Extending his modernity/secularization thesis to
religion, Luckmann argued that religion would
become deinstitutionalized and lose its functional
monopolization of social life as a result of the
increased differentiation of society. In The Invisible
Religion: The Transformation of Symbols in Industrial
Society (1963 [trans. 1967]), he described how the
religious dimensions of human experience would
be forced out of the public sphere and into the
privatized inner-directed self, thus making for a
new individualized religious consciousness. In
later work in R. Fenn, Sociology of Religion (2001),
Luckmann highlighted how the “moralizing
sermon,” that is instruction in what constitutes a
good life – assumed to be a staple in shaping worldviews in traditional Christian societies, though it
may have declined within the churches – is intrinsic to human life, and thus variants on it have
become part of the communicative stock of public
discourse in modern society.
MICHELE DILLON
Luhmann, Niklas, (1927–1998)
Making a substantial contribution to the development of social theory, Luhmann studied at Harvard
with Talcott Parsons, who influenced his work. His
other influences include general system theory,
Émile Durkheim’s evolutionary perspective, Arnold
Gehlen’s philosophical anthropology, and phenomenology. He was Professor of Sociology at the University of Bielefeld. Luhmann developed a system
theoretical approach to society, which in many
respects was at loggerheads with the critical theory
of Jürgen Habermas. This led to heated intellectual
exchanges between Luhmann and Habermas. Luhmann’s later work was heavily influenced
by Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela’s
notions of autopoiesis, and he began treating society as a self-organizing system. Especially influential among his works are Social Systems (1985 [trans.
1995]) and Essays on Self-Reference (1990).
In Luhmann’s theory, systems can range from
the physiological to the social. Systems always
operate within an environment and have to reduce
its complexity. Complexity depends on the
number of actual or possible events; the reduction
of complexity refers to the process by which relevant events are selected. In the case of social
Lukács, Gyorgy (Georg) (1885–1971)
systems, the reduction of complexity is achieved
through communication of meaning (Sinn). Central
to this process is “double contingency”: the process
by which, in interactions, individuals have to take
into account the orientation of other individuals
towards them. For Luhmann, it follows that a social
system is an autopoietic or self-referential system:
that is, a system that interprets the environment,
potentially undermining its autonomy, so that it
reinforces its autonomy. There are three components to any self-referential system: the code, the
structure or program, and the process. Codes are
binary oppositions through which information is
processed (for example, true versus false). Structure
refers to the central values, normative regulations,
and expectations, and process refers to the ongoing
interaction. In self-reproducing systems, the code
remains identical. The structure and process can
change.
Modernity implies more contingency and complexity, so more sophisticated techniques are
needed to reduce complexity: for instance, social
differentiation and self-reflexive procedures. Differentiation can be either “segmental” (the different
parts fulfil the same functions) or “non-segmental”
(the different parts fulfil different functions).
The non-segmental type can be either “hierarchical” or “functional” (with no hierarchy between
the different parts). For reducing complexity, functional differentiation is superior to hierarchical
differentiation, which in turn is better than segmental differentiation. Historically, the segmental
type comes first and functional differentiation
comes last. Examples of self-reflexive procedures
are: teaching how to teach, or studying how research is done. They allow for continuous adjustment of the social system to an increasingly
unpredictable environment.
Luhmann is critical of sociologists who describe
differentiation and the shift to modernity in negative terms. Many of them use a premodern logic to
describe modernity. Differentiation does not necessary lead to disorder and conflict; it is central to
the creation of order and cohesion in modern society. Likewise, it is problematic to talk about contemporary society in terms of alienation or mass
culture. Impersonal relations provide us with
unprecedented levels of freedom. P A T R I C K B A E R T
Lukács, Gyorgy (Georg) (1885–1971)
A Marxist philosopher and literary critic, Lukács
was born in Budapest, and between 1919 and
1929 he was one of the leaders of the Hungarian
Communist movement. He made important
contributions to social theory, the study of class
343
Lynd, Robert Staughton (1892–1970)
consciousness, and the sociological study of literature. Before World War I he was the intellectual
leader of the “Sunday Circle” that included Karl
Mannheim, Karl Polyani, Arnold Hauser, and
others. In 1918 he joined the Communist Party,
and during the Hungarian Commune he was, in
1919, Minister for Education and Culture. In this
early stage of his career, he was interested in the
historical development of various forms of literature such as the novel, and published Soul and
Form (1910 [trans. 1974]), History of the Development
of Modern Drama (1911), Aesthetic Culture (1913 [trans.
1963]), and The Theory of the Novel (1920 [trans. 1971]).
After the collapse of this revolutionary movement, Lukács spent his exile in Austria, Germany,
and Russia, becoming a friend of Georg Simmel,
Max Weber, and Ernst Bloch. In the period
1919–29, Lukács wrote several interpretations of
Marxist philosophy that had a major influence on
European sociology. His work had particular significance for the theory of class consciousness, the
sociology of knowledge, and the Frankfurt School.
In his History and Class Consciousness (1923 [trans.
1971]), he emphasized the importance of the work
of the young Karl Marx on alienation, and noted
the role of the reification of beliefs in capitalism.
His study of Marx promoted the importance of
dialectical thinking and rejected the deterministic
and mechanical theories of society promoted by
orthodox Marxism, which predicted the inevitable
collapse of capitalism through revolutionary
struggles. As a result, Lukács had an ambiguous
and unstable relationship with the Communist
Party. He was criticized by party intellectuals in
the 1940s for his views on culture and, in 1956, he
was briefly Minister of Culture in Imre Nagy’s
government in Hungary, but he was deported to
Romania when the government was suppressed.
When Lukács withdrew from political life, he
turned increasingly to the study of aesthetics
and ontology, publishing The Specific Nature of the
Aesthetic (1962) and Towards an Ontology of Social
Being (1971).
He made a major contribution to the sociology
of literature in The Historical Novel (1955 [trans.
1962]), Essays on Thomas Mann (1964), and Goethe
and his Age (1968), in which he treated the novel
as a reflection of the life of the bourgeois class.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Lynd, Robert Staughton (1892–1970), and
Helen Merrell Lynd (1896–1982)
Born in Indiana, Robert Lynd received his PhD at
Columbia University in 1931. He served on the Columbia faculty from 1931 to 1961. His wife, Helen
344
Lyotard, Jean-François (1924–1998)
Merrell Lynd, was born in Illinois, receiving her MA
from Columbia in 1922 and her PhD in 1944. She
was on the faculty of Sarah Lawrence College from
1928 to 1964. They collaborated on Middletown
(1929), and Middletown in Transition (1937), two important studies of changing American values in the
face of industrialization.
These studies of Muncie, Indiana (under the
pseudonym of Middletown), demonstrated the vast
changes sweeping the United States through the
experiences of a typical Protestant, predominantly
white middle-American town. They catalogued the
rise of a new culture based on consumerism and
competitive individualism which eclipsed more
traditional values of thrift, prudence, and public
spiritedness. The increasing importance of wealth
as a measure of social status was illustrated in
the disappearance of a shared sense of community,
and its replacement by a class-based hierarchical
social structure, in which differences between a
business class and the working class became more
pronounced.
Middletown and Middletown in Transition were the
first studies of the corporate, consumer society
based on new forms of industrial capital that
was arising in the United States in the 1920s. The
Lynds demonstrated that the Great Depression of
the 1930s only helped to consolidate this new
society. Robert Lynd criticized this new culture’s
influence on the social sciences in Knowledge for
What? (1939).
KENNETH H. TUCKER
Lyotard, Jean-François (1924–1998)
A French philosopher and social thinker, one of
the leading exponents of postmodernism in philosophy and social theory, Lyotard is best known to
sociologists for his Postmodern Condition (1979
[trans. 1984]), a critical reflection on the state of
knowledge in postindustrial society. It contains a
radical criticism of the epistemological foundations of scientific knowledge, and a sociological
account of commodified knowledge under the
impact of new technology and information. Knowledge, according to Lyotard, consists of narratives,
that is a mixture of norms, stories, popular
wisdoms, fables, and myths. The “postmodern
condition” is characterized by increasing public
realization that scientific knowledge is no exception: like all social knowledge, it is a type of discourse, a “metanarrative,” or a grand story of a
totalizing type. Claims of those who see scientific
knowledge as uniquely objective, true, and universal are greeted with incredulity or skepticism. This
incredulity extends to all metanarratives, including Marxism (a story of human emancipation) and
Lyotard, Jean-François (1924–1998)
modern social theory (a story of progress, secularization, and rationalization). Their legitimacy, and
their claims to privileged epistemological status,
are questioned; and their true nature as language
games opens the way for critical revaluation of
their substance and social function. Postmodern
skepticism permeates popular cultures in contemporary postindustrial or (computerized) societies,
Lyotard, Jean-François (1924–1998)
in which information and communication technologies undermine the capacity of state elites to
control public discourses and legitimize metanarratives. Knowledge turns into a commodity that
circulates among increasingly diverse audiences.
This increases the diversity of language games and
the accompanying pluralism, fragmentation, and
eclecticism of knowledge.
JAN PAKULSKI
345
M
MacIntyre, Alasdair (1929– )
From his early twenties onwards, MacIntyre’s
work has been dominated by criticism of moral
individualism and moral relativism. The critique of
moral individualism led him to sociology, which
he taught at the University of Essex in the 1960s.
Keen to strengthen a contextual understanding of
practical reason in the wake of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (1953), he has also
been concerned to avoid the relativism to which
such contextualism led in the work of Peter
Winch. Their debate is to be found in Bryan R.
Wilson (ed.), Rationality (1970). In After Virtue
(1981) and in Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
(1988), MacIntyre developed his own position, reconciling contextualism and moral realism on a
neo-Aristotelian basis, using an idiosyncratic
theory of tradition. MacIntyre denounces the
moral emptiness of advanced liberal societies, arguing that their individualism undermines the
social practices and communities required for
the development of a proper sense of virtue.
Turning away from sociology per se, MacIntyre
argues that rigorous sociology must engage with
moral and political philosophy.
His other works include (with Paul Ricoeur) The
Religious Significance of Atheism (1966), A Short History
of Ethics (1967), Secularization and Moral Change
(1967), Marxism and Christianity (1968), Marcuse
(1970), and Dependent Rational Animals (1999).
É M I L E P E R R E A U - S A U S S I N E
macrosociology
The sociological study of large processes and social
structures, it can be illustrated by such prototypical examples as studies of revolutions (see theory
of revolutions), the state, the economy, the social
system, and the world-system. Macrosociology is
often contrasted with microsociology, which is the
sociological study of small-scale phenomena – the
prototypical example is the study of face-to-face
interaction.
In practice the difference between macrosociology and microsociology not only lies in the size of
the unit of analysis, but also in their theoretical
346
and epistemological commitments. Macrosociology comprises diverse approaches, including
structural functionalism, Marxism, and worldsystems analysis. Nevertheless, it is with comparative-historical sociology that the label macrosociology has come to be principally associated.
Characteristic contemporary exponents are Barrington Moore, Reinhard Bendix, Charles Tilly,
and Theda Skocpol.
With regard to epistemology and methodology,
macrosociologists often rely, more or less explicitly, on two of John Stuart Mill’s canons of induction: the method of agreement and the method of
difference. Substantively, they have been more
interested in political and economic issues than
in cultural ones. In fact, Skocpol’s States and Social
Revolutions (1979) delineated the contours of the
field for nearly two decades. However, a new generation of scholars is increasingly moving away
from this paradigm in terms of both their substantive and their epistemological preferences.
In contrast, microsociology focuses on interpersonal situations and the contexts in which they
occur. Within microsociology, there are two main
theoretical orientations: rational choice theory
and social exchange theory on the one hand, and
symbolic interactionism and ethnomethodology
on the other. The former tradition – influenced
by microeconomics and the economic approach
to human behavior – places the emphasis upon
individual preferences and choices, constraints,
transactions, and costs and benefits. The latter
tradition – whose intellectual resources include
Max Weber’s Verstehen and Edmund Husserl’s
phenomenology which was channeled through
the work of Alfred Schütz – is concerned with
individuals’ subjectivity and the construction of
meaning.
The opposition between macro and micro used
to be conceived as a dispute over which one
is “more fundamental” or “ontologically prior,”
and was often similar to the contrast between collective and individual and to the debate over
agency and structure. Nevertheless, this essentialist
construal of the micro–macro “problem” is now
magic
Malthus, Thomas Robert (1766–1834)
largely rejected. The point is not to reduce one to
the other, but to search for theoretical and methodological linkages. Macrosociology stands on
microfoundations and microsociology stands on
macrofoundations. In any case, the distinction
maintains its value as a linguistic convention by
means of which types of inquiries and levels of
analysis are classified.
One set of criticisms against macrosociology
is methodological. Given the magnitude of the
objects studied under its auspices and the inclination to study processes over long periods of
time, macrosociologists’ samples are generally
small. Thus, Stanley Lieberson in “Small N’s and
Big Conclusion,” in C. Ragin and H. Becker (eds.),
What is a case? has argued that in small-N studies
Mill’s methods do not yield valid causal inferences. According to him, this strategy requires
implausible assumptions, such as that there be
no interaction effects, mono-causality, and that
sociological theories be deterministic rather
than probabilistic. A second set of criticisms calls
macrosociology to task for having conceptualized
history as a mere repository of data, thereby
failing to historicize social reality and its own
conceptual tools in a manner that is convincing.
GABRIEL ABEND AND JEFF MANZA
magic
– see religion.
Malinowski, Bronislaw (1884–1942)
A scion of the Polish aristocracy, Malinowski studied engineering before pursuing a degree in anthropology at the University of Cambridge. He was
not the first anthropologist to undertake fieldwork, but in his classic Argonauts of the western
Pacific (1916) was the first to provide it with an
articulate methodology and rationale. He urged
impartiality, attention to the “imponderabilia of
everyday life,” and rigor in investigating “the
native’s point of view.” His research among the
peoples of the Kiriwana Islands was itself
the benchmark of ethnographic excellence for
many decades and his reputation survived the
sometimes unflattering revelations of the posthumously published A Diary in the Strict Sense of the
Term (1967) largely intact.
From the social organization and collective psychology of the kula, the periodic sailing expeditions
that bound the Kiriwanans into a dynamic interisland ring of trade and alliance, Malinowski extracted the persuasive model of a reasonable, industrious, and practical economic actor who
remained “primitive” only in having less passion
for profit than for prestige. The model informs
Malinowski’s instrumentalistic treatment of magic
(see religion) and myth and, in “Group and Individual in Functional Analysis” (1939), a broader argument that each of the basic institutional
components of culture is so much technological
service for the satisfaction of a correlative psychobiological human need. The argument risks circularity and oversimplification, but is also the
manifesto of a pure functionalism resolutely opposed to the Durkheimian reification of society as
a thing having needs of its own.
Malinowski contributed significantly to the
study of religion in Magic, Science and Religion and
Other Essays (1948) and to the study of sexuality in
Sex and Repression in Savage Society (1972) and The
Sexual Life of Savages (1929).
JAMES D. FAUBION
Malthus, Thomas Robert (1766–1834)
Educated at Jesus College, Cambridge, where he
won prizes for Latin and English declamation, at
the age of twenty-two Malthus became a curate
near his family home in Surrey and later in Lincolnshire. In 1805 he was appointed a professor of
history and political economy at East India College, Haileybury, a position he occupied until his
death in 1834.
During his early tenure as a rural clergyman,
he published anonymously in 1798 the first edition of his famous book, An Essay on the Principle of
Population as it Affects the Future Improvement of
Society, with Remarks on the Speculations of Mr. Goodwin, M. Condorcet, and Other Writers. W. Petersen in
his Malthus (1979) writes that this publication
“immediately established its anonymous author
as a controversial figure.” Five years later, in
1803, this time under his name, Malthus published the second edition of the essay, with a
different subtitle, as An Essay on the Principle of
Population; or a View of Its Past and Present Effects
on Human Happiness; With an Inquiry into our Prospects Respecting the Future Removal or Mitigation of
the Evils which It Occasions. Petersen notes that this
was indeed a new book. The first edition was
mainly a “deductive book” of around 55,000
words, whereas the second edition expanded the
theory and provided a great deal of illustrative
data, resulting in around 200,000 words. Subsequent editions, the final being the seventh edition which was published posthumously in 1872,
included relatively minor changes. The best edition is the second, with revisions, contained in
two volumes and edited by Patricia James as An
Essay on the Principle of Population (with the Variora of
1806, 1807, 1817, 1826) (1989).
347
Malthus, Thomas Robert (1766–1834)
The principle of population stated that, if left
unchecked, populations would tend to grow geometrically, while food and subsistence would
grow arithmetically. But Malthus argued that
population growth was held in check by two kinds
of controls, preventive checks and positive checks.
Malthus referred to the major preventive check as
“moral restraint,” or the postponement of marriage. As a clergyman he was not able to recognize
birth control as a check. Indeed he was “opposed
to birth control on the grounds that such ‘unnatural’ experiments ran contrary to God’s design
in placing humankind under the right degree
of pressure to ensure its development” (D. Winch,
Encyclopedia of Population, 2003). The positive
checks included wars, famine, pestilence, and
other forms of misery. The positive checks kept
the death rate high, the preventive checks
kept the birth rate low.
Malthus’s essay needs to be placed and considered in historical context. It opposed two very
influential schools of thought, mercantilism and
utopianism, and cast doubt on the hope of human
perfectibility. Winch writes in the Encyclopedia of
Population that “Malthus showed that any attempt
to create an ideal society in which altruism and
common property rights prevailed would be
undermined by its inability to cope with the
resulting population pressure.”
The writings of Malthus are said to have influenced the work of Charles Darwin, Herbert Spencer, David Ricardo (1771–1823), John Maynard
Keynes, and many others. For instance, Darwin
wrote in his Autobiography (1887) that:
Fifteenth months after I had begun my systematic
enquiry, I happened to read for amusement
Malthus on population, and being well prepared
to appreciate the struggle for existence which
everywhere goes on from long-continued
observation of the habits of animals and plants, it
at once struck me that under these circumstances
favorable variations would tend to be preserved
and unfavorable ones be destroyed. The result of
this would be a new species. Here, then, I had at
last got a theory by which to work.
Scholars hold mixed views with respect to the
influence of Malthus on demography. W. Petersen
argues that in the writings of Malthus, modern
population theory was born. D. Bogue on the other
hand, in Principles of Demography (1969), states that
although the writings of Malthus “have attracted
worldwide attention and have dominated the
thinking of many students of population, his contribution to the development of demography as a
DUDLEY L. POSTON
science was rather modest.”
348
management
Malthusian theory
– see Thomas Robert Malthus.
management
Engineers have long been fascinated by work and
employment. Engineering has a natural affinity
with work in a profit-based economy, because it
is oriented to getting more output from less
input as its definition of efficiency. It was an engineer, Frederick Winslow Taylor (1865–1915),
whose Principles of Scientific Management (1911) first
defined management systematically.
Taylor proposed “four great principles of management”: (1) developing a science of work by
observing and measuring norms of output, using
a stopwatch and detailed observation of human
movements to improve effectiveness; (2) scientifically selecting and training the employee; (3) combining the sciences of work and selecting and
training of employees; and (4) management and
workers specializing and collaborating closely.
Taylor regarded science as equivalent to making
systematic measurement and observation, after
which work would be redesigned on the basis of
the data generated and inferences made about
existing procedures and how they might be improved. A famous example, which is discussed
critically by H. Braverman in Labor and Monopoly
Capitalism (1974), was the example of the Dutch
worker Schmidt, and the art of shoveling pig
iron. Taylor established that even a rather stupid
worker, with a carefully designed tool, could increase productivity significantly, as long as what
scientific management said should be done was
done. Armed with a checklist and a stopwatch,
Taylor observed and timed work, and then
redesigned it, so that tasks could be done more
efficiently. Taylor proposed designing the best way
of performing any set of tasks on the shop floor,
based on detailed observation, selection, and
training. Time was of the essence.
Taylor’s ideas had the advantage of being quite
easy to grasp and so were as easily adopted as they
were opposed. However, it is worth noting that
employers tended to adopt his ideas piecemeal:
they were keen on the efficiencies from time
measurement but not as keen on the rewards in
the form of bonuses that Taylor proposed under
his recommendations for the use of piece-rates.
Taylor and the movement for systematic management were opposed by a number of forces.
First, there were internal contractors – people
who provided and supervised labor to work within
factories owned by remote robber barons,
management
financiers, entrepreneurs, and industrialists – who
stood to lose their livelihoods if scientific managers
triumphed and replaced them with systematic
managers. Second, there were the owners of capital, particularly those with small workshops, who
were already fearful of being devoured or driven
out of business by big businessmen, such as the
“robber barons” (Andrew Carnegie and Theodore
Vanderbilt), gobbling up their assets into new
centers of financial control; they were also fearful
of the dilution of the power of ownership. Third,
the workers, increasingly organizing in trade
unions, railed against the loss of craft skills that
the project of standardization and systematization
of work entailed. Standardization became a wedge
that opened the door for a wider adoption of systematic scientific management through linking individual remuneration to individual effort in
scientifically framed tasks. Managers would be a
new breed of practical scientists managing corporations and organizations empirically, on the basis
of facts and techniques, rather than experience,
privilege, or an arbitrary position. Functions and
responsibilities would be aligned in a scientifically
proven manner by engineers trained in the management of things and the governance of people
working with and on them.
Taylorism did not die with Taylor – it became
sedimented deep inside organizations, wherein,
eventually, many people would be replaced by
robots, in which scientific management would
find far better raw material: there were no sources
of uncertainty in designing and calibrating pure
machines, as compared to the person/machine
interface. Of course, one does not have to go to a
factory to find Taylorism: check out the system for
manufacturing fast food in any burger restaurant
such as McDonald’s (see McDonaldization).
Another engineer, Henri Fayol (1841–1925), is
often regarded as the most significant European
founder of modern management, because he
provided a basis for systematic authority in the
fledgling occupation. In 1916, he published Administration industrielle et générale, in which he argued
that better management not only is concerned
with improving output and disciplining subordinates but also must address the training of the
people at the top. Although other early management theorists (such as Elton Mayo [1880–1949]
and Mary Parker Follett [1868–1933]) and many
subsequent ones (such as James March and
Karl Weick) were to take a less systematic and
mechanical view, these early foundations for
management thinking have proven remarkably
resilient – especially as the thrust towards the
managerial revolution
rationalization of the world has been carried forward by the managerial project. S T E W A R T C L E G G
managerial revolution
James Burnham wrote The Managerial Revolution in
1941. Aware that economies based on capitalism
had inherent structural flaws, he – as a former
adherent of Trotskyism – was nonetheless disenchanted by the Soviet state. The post-World War I
years had seen the decline of many of the huge
corporations that had dominated United States
economic life, particularly as effective anti-trust
legislation took shape from 1932. A concern with
the concentration of power and the dispersion of
share ownership was to become allied with the
view that a “managerial revolution” had occurred
in United States corporate life. Real power was no
longer to be found concentrated in the hands of
the robber barons. Power had shifted to the stewards of capital – the managers – and the major
concentrations of capital held by the dominant
stockholders.
With limited liability, the shareholders of a
corporation elect a board of directors who then
choose the top management officers to run the
business. Burnham suggested that, with this split
between ownership and control, a new society,
neither capitalist nor communist, would develop:
a managerial society. Burnham’s central argument was that ownership means control. Without
control there is no ownership. If ownership and
control are separated, the separated ownership
becomes purely a legal fiction and real control
will reside in the day-to-day stewards of capital,
the managers. Senior executives, however, generally hold major consolidated blocks of shares, so
potential conflicts between the interests of the
principals, the shareholders, and the interests of
the agents, the hired managers, may not be as
extreme as one might expect. Shareholders – often
professional and institutional investors – frequently have little interest in influencing the
way business is run; they use the share price as a
proxy of quality management. Managers typically
dominate boards of directors as well as being significant shareholders.
More recently, Alfred Chandler in The Visible
Hand: The Managerial Revolution in American Business
(1977) has revised the managerial revolution thesis.
He argues that modern organizations arose because administrative coordination was better than
the market at enhancing productivity and lowering
costs. Administrative coordination created a managerial hierarchy, one that became increasingly
349
Mann, Michael (1942–)
Marcuse, Herbert (1898–1979)
technical and professional, with a preference for
long-term stability and growth over short-term
gains (although the markets would sometimes favor
these). The move to a rational managerial system
encourages growing professionalization, which increasingly saw personal and family-owned enterprises replaced by professionally managed firms.
There has been a managerial revolution – but it
has not seen family firms disappear: indeed, some
of the world’s largest companies remain family
firms. However, those that do not employ professional managers are unlikely to be sustainable.
A new and significant stratum of professional
managers has been created as the custodians
of capital and the driving forces behind an
increasing rationalization and globalization.
STEWART CLEGG
Mann, Michael (1942–)
Professor of Sociology at the University of California, Los Angeles, Mann has been particularly influential in historical sociology and macrosociology.
His analytical framework is a theory of power that
is in part derived from Max Weber. Mann argues
that there are four types of power: military, political, economic, and ideological. He has examined
the historical development of these four types of
power in The Sources of Social Power, Volume I: A
History of Power from the Beginning to A.D. 1760
(1986) and The Sources of Social Power, Volume II: The
Rise of Classes and Nation-states 1760–1914 (1993).
Volume III will examine globalization. He has applied this framework to the contemporary United
States and its foreign policy in Incoherent Empire
(2003), arguing that American power cannot be
coherently exercised in these four dimensions.
His earlier research in political sociology was on
politics and ideology in the western working class
in Consciousness and Action Among the western
Working Class (1973), and he has argued that citizenship is an institution to regulate and incorporate the working class in capitalism in his article in
Sociology on “Ruling-class Strategies and Citizenship” (1987). In his Fascists (2004) Mann developed
a controversial interpretation of fascism, arguing
that, particularly in Germany, it was not supported by a specific social class, was not attractive
necessarily to downwardly mobile or marginal
men, and was not initially or overwhelmingly
characterized by anti-Semitism. B R Y A N S . T U R N E R
Mannheim, Karl (1893–1947)
Born in Hungary, Mannheim fled to Germany
in 1919 after the failure of the revolutionary
350
government in Budapest. With the emergence of
fascism, he moved to Britain in 1933, eventually
becoming a professor at the London School of
Economics. He made a major contribution to the
development of the sociology of knowledge in
Ideology and Utopia (1936), Essays on the Sociology
of Culture (1956), and Conservatism: A Contribution to
the Sociology of Knowledge (1986). He argued that
rising social classes embrace utopian systems of
knowledge, whereas declining social classes will
embrace romantic or reactionary ideologies.
Against cultural relativism, he defended the idea
that the “free-floating intelligentsia” can be relatively independent of social determination. Against
the Marxist emphasis on social class, Mannheim
developed the concept of generation as representing the life chances and experiences of age cohorts
passing through time. Members of a generation
are held together by experiencing events from
the same vantage point. This phenomenon of a
common experience he referred to as the “stratification of experience” and he conceived of this
experience as the dynamic aspect of generational
consciousness.
Mannheim also wrote extensively on education,
social reform, and social policy in Man and Society
in an Age of Reconstruction (1940), Diagnosis of Our
Time (1943), and Freedom, Power and Democratic Planning (1951). In this work, he argued that sociology
can make an important contribution to social
planning.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Marcuse, Herbert (1898–1979)
A philosopher by training who studied with
Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), Marcuse joined
the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt in
1934 and worked with Max Horkheimer, Theodor
Wiesengrund Adorno, Erich Fromm, and others in
developing a critical theory of contemporary society. During the 1960s, Marcuse ascended to the
unlikely role of guru of the New Left. His book
on Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and Karl
Marx, Reason and Revolution (1941), introduced a
younger generation to critical and dialectical
social theory, and he provided an excellent philosophical interpretation of Sigmund Freud in his
1955 Eros and Civilization.
In 1964, Marcuse published a wide-ranging critique of both advanced capitalist and communist
societies in One-Dimensional Man. This book theorized the decline of revolutionary potential in capitalist societies and the development of new forms
of social control. Marcuse argued that “advanced
industrial society” created false needs that integrated individuals into the existing system of
manual and mental labor
market(s)
production and consumption. Mass media and
culture, advertising, industrial management, and
contemporary modes of thought all reproduced
the existing system and attempted to eliminate
negativity, critique, and opposition. The result
was a “one-dimensional” universe of thought and
behavior in which the very aptitude and ability for
critical thinking and oppositional behavior were
withering away.
During the 1960s and 1970s, Marcuse had
worldwide influence on the student and anti-war
movement. Later works include his 1969 Essay on
Liberation, Counterrevolution and Revolt (1972) and
The Aesthetic Dimension (1979), while the collections
Technology, War and Fascism (1998), Toward a Critical
Theory of Society (2001), and The New Left and the 1960s
(2005) collect some of his most important work.
DOUGLAS KELLNER
manual and mental labor
– see labor.
market(s)
In classical economic theory, the market not only
establishes the price of commodities, but the economic exchanges it coordinates are also seen as
a means of social integration. Specialization
and the division of labor require the exchange
of goods and services which replaces the selfsufficiency of traditional societies with the
mutual advantage of economic interdependence.
For economic liberalism, market exchange produces the wealth of nations and simultaneously
reconciles self-interest and individualism with
social integration. In Bernard de Mandeville’s
(1670–1733) aphorism in The Fable of the Bees
(1714), “private vices” bring “public benefits,”
later more famously described by Adam Smith
(1723–90) as the mechanism of the “invisible
hand.”
Sociology developed to a large extent as the
result of a critical dialogue with this liberal economic theory, as in Talcott Parsons’s Structure
of Social Action (1937). From Auguste Comte’s
early nineteenth-century critique of the “invisible
hand” to today’s concern with the social and political consequences of globalization, sociologists
have pursued two related lines of attack. First,
the market was not a viable basis for social
order; indeed, impersonal calculative exchange relations inhibit the formation of social bonds based
on trust and cooperation, as F. Tönnies argued
in his analysis of the transition from community
(Gemeinschaft) to association (Gesellschaft). Second,
Adam Smith’s explanation of the existence of
markets as the natural outcome of a universal
and primitive predisposition to “truck, barter,
and exchange” was rejected as being inconsistent
with the wide historical and cultural variability in
the existence of markets. Karl Polanyi observed
that the allocation of goods according to norms
of either reciprocity and/or redistribution has
been more prevalent throughout human history
than allocation by the mechanism of market
price. Thus, the existence of markets as social
institutions required a historical and sociological
explanation – that is, how they came into being
and how they worked.
Until recently, however, sociology gave more
attention to the socially and politically corrosive
impact of market exchange. A classic exposition is
contained in Karl Marx’s analysis of alienation and
the “cash nexus.” Market exchange mediated by
money involves the estrangement of individuals
from their products and from the social relations
into which they enter in the process of production. Most importantly, labor becomes a commodity to be bought and sold and, consequently,
people become alienated from their essential humanity, or “species being.” Modern society is
based on the fragile “cash nexus” rather than the
more robust norms of traditional society. The
same general theme is pursued from somewhat
different perspectives in Émile Durkheim’s analysis of anomie; Polanyi’s discussion of land, labor,
and money capital as “fictitious commodities”;
and, more recently, for example, in Amitai Etzioni’s communitarian critique of the “free market.”
In The Architecture of Markets (2001), Neil Fligstein systematizes the literature on the macrosociological structure and historical development
of modern markets. Markets are social institutions comprising four kinds of rules: (1) property
rights; (2) governance structures; (3) rules of exchange; and (4) conceptions of control. (Note also
that the existence of stable money, in the form of a
stable “money of account,” is necessary to enable
the calculations that make large-scale impersonal
exchange a possibility.) First, property rights
define who has claims, or not, over the profits or
surplus of economic enterprise – that is, shareholders, patent holders, creditors, and workers.
Property rights are continuously contested in a
political process that produces different legal
forms of enterprise structure – for example,
family firm, corporation, partnership, cooperative. Second, governance structures consist of
the rules that define the cooperative and competitive relations within the market. These are
either laws, such as monopoly legislation, or
351
market(s)
informal norms that define unfair practices such
as “cutthroat competition.” Third, rules of exchange specify the transacting parties and the
conditions under which the transactions are
carried out – for example, contract law, accounting standards, product standards, and health and
safety legislation. Without such rules, exchange
will remain fragmented. For example, the harmonization of exchange rules is seen clearly in
the creation of the European Union’s single
market. The continued absence of harmonized
accountancy standards across the world inhibits
globalization. Fourth, and finally, conceptions of
control are the largely informal normative and
cognitive definitions of the situation held by
the participants in a particular market. These
shared understandings concern, for example,
competitive and cooperative tactics, the internal
structure of firms, and their status ranking.
They create a “social field” that enables firms to
reproduce themselves routinely, and a stable
market order.
Max Weber was one of the first to see that the
development of extensive markets in capitalism
required an explanation. Quite different in scale
and scope from the limited exchanges in traditional communities, large impersonal markets
became one of the axial bases of society as the
result of changes in the social and political structures of early modern western Europe. In his economic lectures (Wirtschaftgeschichte) which were
published as General Economic History (1923 [trans.
1927]), he showed that rules for establishing
markets as institutions for regularizing the exchange of particular goods, as opposed to relatively disorganized “truck and barter,” were
established through political struggle and state
power. Capitalist property rights were the result
of struggles which produced a balance of power
between multiple political elites, economic interests, and classes. With such a dispersion of power,
the various interests agreed to rules that established
routine competition that prevented any one group
from monopolizing power and economic advantage. For a similar analysis, see Douglass North, Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance
(1990). The competition that, for Weber, ensured
social and economic dynamism also applied to
economic competition between nations. So long
as these did not give way to a world empire,
capitalism would endure.
Weber also noted that traditional society’s
economic transactions contained an “ethical dualism.” On the one hand, within the communal
in-group, transactions were governed by an ethic
352
market(s)
of charity, comprising norms of fairness defined by tradition, ritual exchange, customary
consumption, and prohibition on usury. On the
other hand, outsiders were treated according to
the opposite ethic, and routinely cheated and
charged exorbitant interest and prices. Both dimensions of the ethic were inimical to large
mass markets and a commercialization of economic life in which strangers are treated with an
impersonal ethic of fairness. The breakdown of
the dualism was the unintended result of modern
bureaucratic state administration and the concomitant institution of formally equal citizenship.
Citizenship eroded the social closure of traditional status groups, with their substantive
sumptuary restrictions, and enabled the mass consumption that made mass production viable and,
in turn, made mechanization profitable (note that
this analysis reverses the conventional account
in economic history in which the sequence of
changes is driven by technological developments).
Weber’s account may be compared with Polanyi’s
analysis of the state’s role in creating markets in
land, capital, and labor.
On a micro-level, recent economic sociology has
criticized economic theory’s “perfect competition,” or “general equilibrium,” models of how
markets actually operate. In formal economic
models, originally developed in the late nineteenth century by economists such as Alfred Marshall (1842–1924, England) and Leon Walras
(1834–1910, Switzerland), the forces of supply
and demand interact to produce an equilibrium
price for a good at which all demand is satisfied
and all supply is exhausted. That is to say, the
market “clears.” In order to model this outcome,
a number of assumptions are made concerning
the structure of the market. It comprises: (1) a
myriad of rational, utility-maximizing individuals
making independent decisions on the basis of “exogenously” given preferences and tastes; (2) individuals possessing perfect information about the
quality and quantity of a uniform good; (3) there is
market equality – that is, all participants are
“price-takers,” not monopolistic “price-makers”;
and (4) there are frequent and regular exchanges.
Paradoxically, however, there is no competition
in the perfect competition model. Perfect information and foresight would render any competitive bargaining process redundant. In fact, the
model describes an end state of equilibrium, but
cannot satisfactorily explain how this comes
about as a result of the utility-maximizing decisions of independent, isolated individuals. To
solve this problem, the early proponents of the
market(s)
supply and demand model had to add further
components in order to make it function. Walras
introduced the “auctioneer” to initiate and coordinate the competitive bidding. (Note that real auctions have estimated and reserve prices to “frame”
the market interaction.) Marshall realized that
myriad uncoordinated actions of producers and
buyers with less-than-perfect information and rationality would result in price volatility. He introduced the middleman, or wholesaler, into his
example of the corn market to hold buffer stocks
in order to balance supply with demand and
thereby maintain a stable price and an orderly
market. In other words, Walras and Marshall
were giving the market a social structure that
would enable it to operate, as opposed to
the instability that they recognized in the model
of the interaction of the subjective preferences of
myriad atomized individuals.
Alternatively, “Austrian” economic theory advocates markets as the most efficient means of
economic decisionmaking and coordination on
the grounds of the contrary assumption of imperfect information. According to Ludwig von Mises
(1881–1973), for example, it was precisely because
we could never have adequate information to plan
an economy centrally that decentralized markets
were necessary. Competitive market struggle
was the best means of establishing the relative
scarcity of goods and of ensuring dynamic change.
Weber’s incorporation of these ideas into his
ideal type of capitalism as a “struggle for economic existence” and the “economic battle of
man against man” led him to reject socialism as
a viable form of economy.
Modern economics recognizes the existence of
“market failure” and “imperfect markets,” but
sees them as exceptions or corrigible deviations.
Market failure is said to occur when the existence
of a competitive market cannot establish a price
for a good that will clear the market – that is,
brings supply and demand into equilibrium.
Three types are identified: (1) “public goods” exist
when property rights cannot be established
securely enough to exclude “free-riding,” which
deters the production of the good in question –
for example, lighthouses shed light on all passersby; (2) “externalities” refer to the unintended
social costs that are “external” to the private
production or exchange of a good and that are
not included in its price – for example, pollution
and road congestion (in general, economics
considers externalities to be exceptions, whereas
the deleterious unintended effects of markets are
the focus of sociological critiques); (3) “perverse
market(s)
outcomes” such as “moral hazard” in which the
production of a good with a single price has
contradictory unintended consequences that destabilize the market – for example, single-premium
fire insurance that encourages negligence; or “adverse selection” in which a single price stimulates a
demand that perturbs the market – for example, the
single-premium health insurance that attracts
demand from the unhealthy; and a single interest
rate for bank loans can never be high enough to
balance the costs of defaults without at the same
time discouraging low-risk borrowers. Both circumstances give rise to social processes of risk assessment and, in the case of bank loans, credit-rating.
Modern economics explains the existence of
real-world imperfect markets in terms of “asymmetric information.” This problem was clearly illustrated by George Akerlof in his “The Market for
Lemons” (1970, Quarterly Journal of Economics), in
which the average buyer’s inability to distinguish
good from bad cars (“lemons” in American parlance) depresses the average price and deters the
owners of good used cars from putting them on
the market. In contrast, John Maynard Keynes’s
analysis of the failure of the labor market to
“clear” is inherently more sociological in its recognition of capitalism’s asymmetrical power relations. He argued that workers cannot create
more employment by accepting lower wages because employers may choose to take advantage of
the lower costs to reduce prices and, thereby, gain
a competitive advantage. This would result in the
same levels of ex ante production and employment. Or, with lower wage costs, monopoly producers might simply take higher profits.
All the above problems derive from the inadequate understanding of the market as a socially
and politically constructed institution, and from
the fact that different kinds of market – labor
markets, consumer markets, and production
markets – have different social structures. In an
“Interview” with Richard Swedberg in Economics
and Sociology (1990), Harrison White has gone
so far as to say that the “perfect-competition,” or
“general-equilibrium,” model is not a theory of
the market as such, but rather a theory of “pure
exchange.” This might describe the operation of a
bazaar or medieval fair where individual buyers
and sellers haggle over prices, but this theory of
pure exchange does not apply, for example,
to capitalist producers’ markets. A producers’
market cannot be understood as the result of discrete independent calculations of cost, revenue,
and profit maximization by individual isolated producers that converge to fit objective economic
353
market (s)
constraints. Rather, White argues in Identity and
Control (1992) and with Robert Eccles in “Producers’
Markets” (The New Palgrave, 1987) that producers’
markets can operate only after two “control projects” have been successfully completed. First, the
firm’s internal power struggle must be resolved.
Second, the potentially destabilizing effect of price
competition has to be dealt with; stable markets
are socially constructed by the participants’ comparisons of their similarities and differences and
their search for a segment of the market. Either
existing prices are taken as benchmark terms of
trade which individuals try to better; or they may
attempt to differentiate their product by quality in
a particular niche which is relatively immune from
competition. This can create a stable social structure, which is destabilized when participants actually behave like those modeled in the economic
theory, by either calculating marginal costs and
revenues and thereby creating “price wars” and
“cutthroat competition,” or by imitating a successful strategy and creating overcrowding, which has
the same consequence. Not all markets are successfully stabilized – for example, those for haircuts and
restaurant meals where intense price competition
leads to a large turnover of market participants. A
further implication of this approach is that oligopoly, rather than the myriad producers of the perfect competition model, is normal in production
markets in order that they can make the structureproducing comparisons. In The Architecture of
Markets, Fligstein has interpreted White’s work on
production markets in terms of Pierre Bourdieu’s
“theory of fields.” As actors can never have the
information or market power that will enable
them to determine what will maximize profits,
activity is directed towards the creation of a “field”
in which the participants attempt to produce the
social order that will maximize their chances of
survival.
This kind of approach is developed in Mitchel
Abolafia’s ethnographic study, in Making Markets
(1996), of the social construction of different levels
of competitive behavior in Wall Street money
markets. For example, as an outsider, the bond
trader, Michael Milkin, was able to make large
profits by selecting those stocks – the “fallen
angels” – that established elite investment banks
had neglected. They responded with imitation
that created destabilization and the designation
of the underpriced bonds as “junk” bonds. With
the market having been destabilized, Milkin
was accused of the malpractice that eventually
resulted in his imprisonment on accounting
354
marriage and divorce
offences. A restabilization of the market followed
his removal.
It has been noted by the French “sociology-ofconvention” school and actor network theory – for
example, Michel Callon, The Laws of the Market
(1998) – that the economic theory of perfect competition is now used to construct the “fields” that
constitute a market capable of reaching an equilibrium price. M.-F. Garcia’s study of the construction of the strawberry market in the Solonge
region of France in the early 1980s shows how
economic textbooks had a “performative” role in
bringing about the very same conditions that they
described. The product was standardized; demand
and supply organized into a competitive structure; and the transactions mechanism established
to frame a situation in which the participants
were able to calculate prices more efficiently.
Modern economic sociology has gone some way
towards explaining what are seen conventionally
in economic theory as the problems of imperfect
information and uncertainty which prevent the
achievement of market equilibrium. Information and certainty are not merely found in discoverable objectively given external conditions – for
example, costs of production, marginal productivity, consumers’ demand, and so on. Rather,
the information that produces an intelligible
and shared social world and the certainty, or
relative predictability, of the market consist in
the socially constructed fields and rules that
structure competition.
GEOFFREY INGHAM
marriage and divorce
Although finding a (sexual) partner and forming a
couple may appear to be a “natural” or even biologically driven activity, marriage is a social institution defined by laws, culture, religion, and of
course historical and social context. This means
that what marriage is (and what it might mean to
the people who marry) changes over time and can
reflect very different social contexts. At present,
in most western societies, marriage is regarded
in law as an essentially heterosexual contract,
entered into with the express purpose of raising
children and with the equally important function
of joining families together. It is a contract between individuals, but it also involves the state
and extended families. So although marriage is
popularly seen as the way in which couples can
proclaim their love and commitment to each
other exclusively, the state has a very strong interest in marriage and has operated, with varying
degrees of vigor at different times, to support and
marriage and divorce
buttress marriage as a social institution. Moreover,
extended families maintain a close interest in who
their children marry, with arranged and vetted
marriages being the norm in some cultures and
social classes. Marriage is therefore both deeply
personal and private, yet also the business of
families, relatives, legislators, politicians, judges,
policymakers, and social commentators.
Sociological interest in marriage has waxed and
waned over the last half-century. Typically, discussions of marriage have been combined with sociological work on “the family,” and the two social
institutions tended to be treated together, with
marriage being conventionally treated as little
more than the threshold to family life. Sociological interest in marriage was understated, and
was reflected more in the study of social problems
such as unmarried motherhood or divorce, which
were, at least in the 1950s and 1960s, seen as
deviant forms of behavior. Because marriage
was so taken for granted as something that everyone did (which was fairly true in England in the
1960s at least) it was not seen as worthy of specific analysis or debate. For example Ronald
Fletcher’s influential work The Family and Marriage in Britain, originally published in 1962, had
little to say about marriage, but rather more to
say about divorce. On marriage itself, Fletcher
was rather complacent in his depiction:
In the modern marriage, both partners choose each
other freely as persons. Both are of equal status and
expect to have an equal share in taking decisions
and in pursuing their sometimes mutual, sometimes
separate and diverse, tastes and interests. They live
together permanently and intimately in their own
home and in relative independence of wider groups
of kindred.
Yet there was an earlier tradition of more critical
work on marriage; although it was not strictly
sociological, it ultimately provided the basis of
later challenges to the taken-for-granted character
of marriage and the presumed equality between
spouses. These critical perspectives came from the
work of nineteenth-century radicals, feminists,
and suffragists like Cicely Hamilton, John Stuart
Mill, Harriet Taylor, Caroline Norton, and Friedrich
Engels. Cicely Hamilton wrote Marriage as a Trade
in 1909, in which she outlined the gender inequalities in society which led women to have no alternative but to “snare” a husband in order to
achieve economic security and social status in
society. Women, she argued, were part of a trade
which actually demeaned them and gave too
much power to men. Caroline Norton, in the mid
nineteenth century, pointed out that in marriage
marriage and divorce
men had absolute legal control over children and
could deprive mothers of contact with them,
while Mill, Taylor, and Engels all pointed to the
economic inequality between husbands and
wives, giving rise to tyrannical powers and absolute control over women in the private sphere.
Victorian and Edwardian marriage was depicted
variously as a form of virtual slavery, as a form of
feudalism, and inevitably as a site of inequality
and oppression.
Such depictions of marriage did not sit well
with mainstream sociology of the 1950s and
1960s. Talcott Parsons, taking a structural functional approach, did not see inequality between
the genders, rather he saw complementary social
roles in the form of the breadwinner husband and
the housewife. By this time the sociological gaze
was more firmly fixed on “the Family,” with marriage being left to the anthropologists who could
study the marriage practices of less-developed societies and different religions, while the “modern”
marriage depicted by Fletcher was treated as a
pinnacle of achievement. It took the polemical
work of Jessie Bernard in 1976 to disaggregate
the unity of husband and wife, to challenge the
presumption of equality once again, and to rediscover that, behind the unified front created in the
functionalist approach, there could be a man’s
marriage and a woman’s marriage, and that these
were two very different, uneven lived experiences,
albeit going on under one roof.
The work of Jessie Bernard was part of a new
wave of feminist writing which occurred simultaneously in the United States and the United
Kingdom, and which brought a very different perspective on marriage. As with the earlier suffragist
writings, the second-wave feminists focused on
the legal disparities that were entailed in marriage. Thus it was pointed out that only husbands
could sign mortgage documents and so were the
sole legal owners of the couple’s home; they revisited the problem of violence against wives and
stressed the fact that the law did not take domestic assault seriously; they pointed out that rape in
marriage was perfectly legal; they also pointed to
the double burden assumed by women who increasingly worked outside the home, yet were required to carry on with all the usual housework
and child-care obligations. While Engels had
depicted marriage as a form of capitalist exploitation with the husband as the capitalist and the
wife as worker, feminist sociologists depicted marriage as a form of patriarchal exploitation in
which the husband benefited not only financially
from the appropriation of his wife’s labor, but also
355
marriage and divorce
materially, physically, and psychologically from
her oppression. Intense debates between different strands of feminism ensued, with some
feminists arguing that men were the primary
beneficiaries of women’s oppression in marriage,
while others argued that capitalism benefited
because women’s unremunerated domestic labor
supported and renewed the labor power of men
in the labor market, to the benefit of capitalism.
The legal contract of marriage was seen as the
device that served primarily to lock women into
subservience and to remove many of their basic
civil rights. It was, for example, lawful for the
teaching profession to sack women on marriage
in England and Wales, and, long after this became
unlawful, the custom of leaving work on marriage
continued in many parts of the United Kingdom.
In the United States, Betty Friedan referred to “the
problem with no name” in her book The Feminine
Mystique (1963). By this she meant the problem of
the bored housewife whose horizons in the United
States of the 1950s and 1960s had shrunk to
encompass little more than finding washing detergents of an adequate power, or buying Tupperware
containers to keep food fresh. She depicted women
existing on Valium and other tranquilizers in order
to get through the meaninglessness of their days,
awaiting the return of their husbands and serving
his dinner on time.
The critical analyses that feminist sociologists
developed of marriage were closely linked to political activism in the 1970s and 1980s: for example
the Y B A WIFE? campaign in the United Kingdom
in the 1970s. The boundaries between scholarly
enterprise and political campaigning were blurred
in a way similar to the relationship between Marxism and class struggle and the trade-union movement, or studies of racism and anti-racist and/or
Black Power movements. These links were controversial. In the academy it meant that feminist
analyses were not seen as serious or scholarly,
and for a time a kind of parallel universe developed where mainstream sociology continued
to be largely indifferent to what might happen
in the “private sphere” of family life. It appeared
almost as if marriage and the family became an
issue for women academics, while the men concentrated on the public sphere and more global
issues, this division of labor ironically mirroring
the very problem in the “real” world that feminist
academics were trying to critique.
The feminist focus on marriage as an oppressive
institution, combined with the associated criticisms of romantic (heterosexual) love as ideology
and/or a form of false consciousness led ultimately
356
marriage and divorce
to a kind of intellectual cul-de-sac. This was because it became “unnecessary” to look into the
interiority of married relationships because they
were always already known to be oppressive.
Much evidence was collected on the problems of
marriage, but few were concerned to understand
its enduring popularity or what this form of intimacy might signify for couples in a positive way.
This meant that some early sociological insights
were lost, only to be rediscovered again in the
1990s when mainstream sociology became interested once again in issues of intimacy and the
private sphere. An example of what I mean is to be
found in Ronald Fletcher’s work. He wrote in 1966
of the way in which marriage had been transformed over time from a contractual alliance between families, designed primarily to produce
legitimate heirs, into a love relationship based
on choice and dependent for its continued existence upon mutual compatibility. He went on,
“It is clear, therefore, that the modern relationship between husband and wife must be an extremely intense affair and, as such, is potentially
unstable.”
This theme is central to his work and it bears a
striking similarity to the arguments put forward
by Anthony Giddens in The Transformation of Intimacy (1992) and by Ulrich Beck and E. Beck-Gernsheim in The Normal Chaos of Love (1995 [trans.
1995]). A striking difference is the fact that
Fletcher speaks only of husbands and wives
while, by the end of the twentieth century, contemporary sociologists spoke of couples or partners – in order to include unmarried couples in
their remit. Rates of cohabitation were much
lower when Fletcher wrote at the start of the
1960s, and unmarried cohabitation was then still
seen as shameful or something to be secretive
about. But the theme of intensity and intimacy
being the core of contemporary relationships,
and the commensurate instability that ensues
from this, is one that has returned to dominate
sociological thinking. The rise of the companionate marriage/relationship is identified as an inevitable outcome of greater equality between the
genders, as well as reflecting changing mentalities, but it is also seen as having major social
consequences, because the compassionate relationship is paradoxically identified as increasing
the chances of divorce or separation with all their
attendant hardships.
What Fletcher, Giddens, and Beck and BeckGernsheim also have in common is their understanding of the relationship between a particular
form of marriage and modernity. Fletcher speaks
marriage and divorce
of “modern” marriage, which is not quite the
same terminology as was deployed in the 1990s;
yet the idea that the late modern era produced
new styles of marriage based on choice and love is
common to all these authors. Unfortunately this
analysis tends to condemn other forms of marriage to a less modern form or to a more traditional mentality. Arranged and vetted marriage,
and various forms of “sponsored courtship,” are
inevitably seen as less desirable, based on a lack of
choice and freedom, and as devoid of (romantic)
love. The social evaluation of these marital arrangements is now complicated by the prevalence
of internet dating. These other forms of marriage
are depicted through a very ethnocentric lens, and
the meaning and significance of these forms for
minority ethnic or religious groups are given little
consideration. The significance of arranged marriages for transnational families who may be
highly disadvantaged in a dominantly ethnically
white community does not seem to have generated
much sociological interest, for example.
One other silence in much of the sociological
work on marriage has been the core fact that
marriage is a legal contract that can only be
entered into by a man and a woman. This issue
became central to the feminist critique in the
1980s because the privileged status of marriage
was understood to demote lesbian and gay relationships to insignificance. But the solution to
this was envisaged as a rejection of marriage per
se. Moreover, for a considerable time after the
1970s it appeared as if marriage was falling out
of favor, with the average age of marriage in the
United Kingdom rising to almost thirty years at
the start of the twenty-first century, and rates of
cohabitation rising annually. However, it is no
longer clear that these statistics indicate a rejection of marriage. Rather marriage might be postponed, or it might happen when children are
born, or it might happen much later in a cohabitation when issues of inheritance and property
begin to loom as salient. Marriage may be something that people do at a specific point in their
life-course, but it no longer has to occur as a kind
of rite of passage into adulthood, as it was in the
1950s or 1960s.
The fact that people can actively choose to reject
marriage, or elect to marry when it suits them
rather than in their early twenties, indicates that
the meaning of marriage is changing. It is no
longer “compulsory” and many of the legal and
personal disabilities that attended marriage for
women have diminished. In this context, gay
and lesbian groups have begun to challenge the
marriage and divorce
“heteronormative” assumptions that are still the
basis of marriage. Because marriage brings with it
certain privileges (such as recognition by the state
in terms of social benefits, tax and exemptions,
and residence) it is seen as a denial of human
rights for a sector of the community to be denied
the right to marry. Marriage has therefore become
the site of political activism again in both the
United States and the United Kingdom, and also
throughout Europe, Australia, and New Zealand.
Some countries, such as the Netherlands, now
recognize gay and lesbian marriage, while others
such as the United Kingdom have created a parallel legal institution called “civil partnership”
which carries all the rights and obligations of
marriage, but which is not given the title of “marriage.” In the United Kingdom and the United
States religious groups reject strongly the idea
that gay men and lesbians should be entitled to
have their relationships recognized and celebrated in the way reserved for heterosexual couples,
seeing it as contravening basic religious teaching.
Moreover, some gay and lesbian groups also reject
the idea of marriage and state recognition of relationships, because they see this as a way of being
co-opted into conventional family life when they
would prefer to subvert the normative order.
Others argue that to offer gay men and lesbians
“civil partnership” when heterosexual couples
retain the option of “marriage” merely confirms
homosexual relationships as second-rate, and they
demand absolute equality as a matter of basic civil
rights. Marriage is therefore back on the political
agenda in much the way it was in the 1970s and at
various points since the mid nineteenth century.
Sociology (along with political commentators
and the media) has had a fascination with divorce
rates and statistics since the 1950s. Divorce rates
have become the modern equivalent of É. Durkheim’s suicide rates, in as much as they are
treated as the measure of the stability of family
life and ultimately a measure of social cohesion.
This approach to divorce rates originates with
functionalist thinking in which “the family” is
treated as the foundation of other social institutions. This gave rise to the understanding
that instability in the family led to both personal
instability (through poor socialization of children) and social instability (through the knockon effects of underachieving, anti-social young
people, and personal and economic disruption).
Divorce has therefore occupied a particularly
significant place in the study of contemporary social problems not only because it has
been seen as a problem in itself, but because it
357
marriage and divorce
has been seen as giving rise to a host of other
difficulties.
The tradition of treating divorce as a social
problem (rather than a solution to a problem)
stems from sociology’s general lack of a critical
perspective on the family in the past. Because
gender relations in the private sphere were not a
matter of (much) sociological interest until
second-wave feminist scholarship forced them
onto the agenda, divorce could only be envisaged
as a threat to social cohesion. Even Fletcher, who
did write more positively about divorce in the
1960s, saw it as a route to remarriage and hence
a means of re-establishing proper family life,
rather than a potential liberation from the institution of marriage itself.
Control over the exit from marriage has been
closely regulated in western societies, and the
Catholic and Protestant Churches strove hard to
retain this control, even in increasingly secular
societies. In the Republic of Ireland, for example,
legal divorce became available only in 1996, and
in England and Wales it was only in the 1960s that
the Church of England gave up its opposition to
the introduction of divorce on the grounds of
mutual consent. Prior to this, divorce was only
available on the basis of proof of matrimonial
offense, and one spouse had to be identified as a
guilty party. Divorce courts were full of details of
spousal cruelties, adulterous relationships (sometimes faked), and minute details of incompatibilities. Divorce was a kind of public spectacle and
humiliation, with details published in the print
media, and with “innocent” and “guilty” parties
named and shamed.
Some early sociological work was critical of this
spectacle, and also of the class basis of divorce,
since the wealthy could afford to divorce, while
the poor could not. There also grew up a presecond wave feminist critique of the poverty
and hardship caused to women who were denied
divorce, yet were unsupported by their husbands
who had deserted them. In the 1960s the
apparently new problem of lone mothers (see
lone-parent family) was gradually recognized
and, although the poverty of women raising children alone was actually not new at all, it gained a
new name and a new urgency because of the increasing numbers of formerly married women in
this situation after World War II. While mothers
alone with children had formerly been divided
into the deserving poor (namely widows) and the
undeserving poor (namely unmarried mothers),
the advent of deserted mothers and then divorced
mothers created a new category of women who
358
marriage and divorce
were obliged to look to the public purse for
support.
In both the United States and the United Kingdom divorce rates climbed steeply in the 1970s
and 1980s and, although rates of increase have
declined, divorce has become a common feature
of family life and it increasingly involves children
under sixteen years of age. This of course means
that more young people reaching marriageable
age come from families where either their own
parents have divorced, or there has been a divorce
within the extended kinship network. The availability of divorce is therefore part of the context of
marriage in the twenty-first century.
It is this context that has given rise to a new
level of concern over divorce as a social problem,
namely the problem of the lack of commitment in
modern relationships. Divorce is seen to have generated a new psychology in which younger generations “fail” to recognize that they have to work at
relationships to make them last, and that much
self sacrifice is required. What pro-family commentators depict as a lack of commitment and
moral fiber, some sociologists have labeled the
individualization theory. Thus authors such as Giddens, Beck, and Beck-Gernsheim have identified a
changing mentality in which communication and
mutual support become key elements of relationships and where the lack of such components is
seen as adequate motivation for leaving one partner to find another. The debate over divorce and
commitment reflects wider debates in sociology
about the impact and significance of the decline
in personal life of external authorities to govern
behavior and whether this has led to a form of
moral anarchy, or to a new normative order which
has different modes of demonstrating responsibility and commitments. The rise in rates of divorce
and cohabitation are, for example, for some
indicators of the demise of the moral family,
while for others they merely indicate that in a
more open society, with greater equality between
the genders, people can mold new forms of commitment and mutual support. It seems unlikely
that there will be a ready resolution to this debate
because the social landscape of marriage and divorce is constantly changing and different implications and consequences of changes to personal
relationships emerge as social, cultural, and economic conditions change. Two new developments
are discussed below, the first being the changing
perception of childhood and the second being the
changing position of fathers.
Until the 1990s children were depicted in divorce literature as the “innocent victims” of
marriage and divorce
parental divorce. This victim status did not require children to speak, although the children
might be assessed in terms of their academic
achievements, their social skills, and their conformity to a series of life-course expectations. It
was of course expected that the sons of divorced
parents would become delinquent and the daughters would become unmarried, teenage mothers.
In the rush to calibrate the harms of divorce there
was little room for more qualitative or ethnographic research that would seek to understand
divorce from the standpoint(s) of children. However, such approaches have begun to emerge and
children are increasingly seen as actively engaging with the problems of family transformations and in seeking to find solutions and
coping mechanisms, often giving support to
their parents, and often critical of their parents’
behavior. The perspectives of children reveal their
powerlessness (particularly because children are
rarely consulted about their futures when parents
separate) but also their growing demands
for greater attentiveness from parents in the
evolution of post-divorce family life.
This concept of post-divorce family life, sometimes referred to as the divorce-extended family, is
a recent development. Almost all sociological
work on divorce took it for granted that divorce
meant family breakdown, indeed the terminology
was used interchangeably. It was assumed that
children’s family horizons were diminished
through the loss of a father (usually) and paternal
kindred. But the new attentiveness to children
and the possibility of divorce by mutual consent
has meant that children can, in some circumstances, retain their family links (including grandparents on both sides). Sociological research now
embraces concepts such as “parenting across
households” or “shared parenting” in order to
capture the ways in which parents continue to
be parents notwithstanding divorce and the establishment of different households. The idea that
divorce leads automatically to lone motherhood
and fatherless children, and that the best solution
is for mothers to remarry and create the re-constituted nuclear family with the introduction of a
step-father, is no longer seen as accurate. Indeed
the new morality of divorce seems increasingly to
embrace the idea that parenthood is for life, and
that this should be valued regardless of the quality of the relationships between former spouses.
These shifts in the moral ordering of divorce are
related to another important shift in the landscape of marriage and divorce: the position of
fathers. While mothers were seen as the economic
Thomas H. Marshall (1893–1982)
victims of marriage and divorce throughout the
1970s and 1980s, during the 1990s fathers started
to be redefined as the victims of the system. Having
been depicted as “deadbeat dads” who fail to pay
child support and to maintain contact with their
children, fathers are now redefined as being the
ones who lose most from divorce because of the
tendency for mothers to have the residence of children after separation. The Fathers’ Rights Movement has become one of the fastest-growing and
most politically influential single-issue campaigns
at the turn of the twenty-first century. This movement requires that, on divorce or separation,
fathers should be allocated 50 percent of their
children’s time to ensure equality between
parents, and also that children maintain their relationships with their fathers. This movement is a
complex one. At one extreme it may be seen as a
reassertion of paternal authority in which fathers
insist on their genetically based rights to a child,
quite independent of the quality of any relationship that they may have with the mother of the
child. At the other extreme it may be seen as a
positive reflection of the new fatherhood in which
men seek to share both the burdens and the joys
of raising children. In the former model, fatherhood is imposed regardless of the views of
mothers and/or children, in the latter, fatherhood
arises from relationships of equality and mutual
support with both mothers and children. While
the impact of this movement is still unknown, it
has already reshaped the debates that currently
surround the issue of divorce.
CAROL SMART
Thomas H. Marshall (1893–1982)
Fellow of Trinity College Cambridge and subsequently Professor of Sociology at the London
School of Economics, Marshall is famous for his
analysis of citizenship in Citizenship and Social Class
and Other Essays (1950), in which he showed how in
Britain social rights had evolved through three
stages, namely civil, political, and social rights.
These rights had been recognized in such institutions as the jury system, parliament, and the
welfare state. He argued that citizenship modified
the class system by some redistribution of entitlements to resources, primarily through the welfare
state. In his Social Policy in the Twentieth Century
(1965), he analyzed the growth of social rights
through policy development between 1890 and
1945. In The Right to Welfare and Other Essays
(1981), he argued that modern societies are ‘hyphenated’ because there is a permanent contradiction between liberal democracy and the capitalist
system. His theory of citizenship was essentially a
359
Martin, David (1929– )
description of the postwar reconstruction of Britain in terms of the tension between social class
and citizenship. He has subsequently been criticized for neglecting such issues as gender and
race and ethnicity. Marshall was not a prolific
sociologist, but his framework has been the foundation of the sociology of citizenship in both the
United States and the United Kingdom.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Martin, David (1929– )
An Emeritus Professor of Sociology at the London
School of Economics, and Honorary Professor in
the Department of Religious Studies at Lancaster
University, Martin was in 1948 a conscientious
objector and did his national service in the “noncombatant corps”. This experience influenced his
early contribution to the sociological analysis of
Pacifism (1965) and to the understanding of the
Christian challenge to violence, but his major research has been in the sociology of religion, in
which he has been a leading critic of the contention that industrial societies are characterized by
an inevitable process of secularization. In A Sociology of English Religion (1967), The Religious and the
Secular (1969), and A General Theory of Secularization
(1978), he showed that the evidence on belief
and practice does not support a theory of uniform
secularization in modern societies. He challenged
the implicit historical and sociological assumptions behind this analysis of secular society.
In Tongues of Fire (1990) and Pentecostalism: The
World Their Parish (2002), he explored the global
development of charismatic Christianity, drawing
a productive comparison between the growth of
evangelical Methodism in the early nineteenth
century and the expansion of Pentecostalism in
Latin America in the twentieth century. Martin
argues that there is an important consonance between Pentecostalism and the spread of global
liberal capitalism and “the expressive revolution”
(see Talcott Parsons). Pentecostalism, which is devolved, voluntary, local, and fissiparous, works
within a religious market that offers spiritual
uplift, social success, and emotional gratification.
While Methodism supplied the work ethic of early
capitalism, Pentecostalism is relevant to the work
skills and personal attributes of the postindustrial
service economy, especially in terms of self-monitoring and a refusal to accept failure. He has
throughout his career been concerned with the
relationship between sociology and theology, as
illustrated in his Reflections on Sociology and Theology
BRYAN S. TURNER
(1997).
360
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
The most influential of the socialist thinkers, Marx
changed dramatically the way we view society and
the world. Although he dedicated his life to writing
a critique of political economy, he also pioneered a
theory of society and history, and a view of the
world that were truly revolutionary. It is impossible to think of a criticism of capitalist society
that does not refer centrally to his work.
He was born in Trier, Germany. Although often
referred to as a Jew – he came from a long line of
rabbis – Marx was technically a Protestant. He grew
up in a professional middle-class home, and his
father, a lawyer, supported the Enlightenment. His
uncle, the Baron von Westphalen (whose daughter
Marx married), was enthusiastic about the socialism of the French writer, G. H. Saint-Simon.
After schooling in Trier (1830–5) – a schoolboy
essay showed him committed to the development
of humanity – Marx entered the University of
Bonn to study law. At university he spent much
of his time socializing and running up large debts.
His father insisted that he move to the more
sedate University of Berlin. Here he came under
the influence of one of his lecturers, Bruno Bauer
(1809–82), who introduced Marx to the writings of
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, who had been the
Professor of Philosophy at Berlin until his death in
1831.
In 1838 Marx decided to become a university
lecturer. After completing his doctoral thesis on
ancient Greek philosophy at the University of
Jena, Marx hoped that Bauer would help find
him a teaching post. However, in 1842 Bauer was
dismissed as a result of his outspoken atheism and
was unable to help.
Marx’s notion of philosophy was practical and
down-to-earth, and he distanced himself from the
empty radicalism of many of the Young Hegelians.
From Berlin he moved to Cologne where the city’s
liberal opposition movement was fairly strong. In
1842, Marx was appointed editor of the newspaper
Die Rheinische Zeitung, and interestingly he denied
at this stage any sympathy with Communism. The
newspaper was committed to liberalism, and Marx
certainly demonstrated a deep concern with social
questions, as in his defense of peasants’ right to
collect wood, or his concern about the poverty of
the Mosel wine growers. In 1843, the paper was
banned by the Prussian authorities.
Warned that he might be arrested, Marx moved
to Paris and in the spring and summer of 1843 he
wrote a detailed critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right (1821 [trans. 1942]) in which he not only
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
identified himself as a democrat, but saw a tension between democracy and the state. He now
talked about the need to dissolve civil society –
society based upon private property, the market,
and the state.
He was greatly influenced by the materialism
of Ludwig Feuerbach (1804–72) in his Essence of
Christianity (1841 [trans. 1957]), although he felt
that Feuerbach had placed too much stress upon
nature and not enough on politics. In a letter to
Arnold Ruge (1802–80) in 1843, Marx emphasized
the need to work with social and political realities as they were actually constituted. He became
the editor of Franco-German Yearbook, and it was
here he published On the Jewish Question (1844
[trans. 1932]), in which he argued that emancipation must not merely be political: it must be
social. This text is crucial because it establishes
Marx’s concern with transcending the state
(which is linked with religion), the market, and
commerce, and contains his celebrated attack on
liberal notions of citizenship as abstract and
limited. His second piece in the Yearbook proclaims the need for the principles of radical philosophy to be realized by the proletariat: for the
first time Marx identified the agent that will
move humanity beyond civil society and the
state. The proletariat is the social class with radical chains, and his piece – an introduction to the
critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right – contains
the famous characterization of religion as the
“opium of the people.”
Mixing with members of the working class for
the first time, he now described himself as a communist. He championed the revolt of the Silesian
weavers in Germany, because it emphasized the
importance of a social, and not merely political,
solution to their problems. In 1844 Marx wrote
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts (first published
in English in 1932), which consisted of a critical
assessment of the work of economists like James
Mill (1773–1836) and Jean-Baptiste Say (1776–1832),
and a critique of Hegel’s dialectic. The work is
famous for its characterization of exploitation as
a process of alienation, and the argument that religion, the family, state, law, morality, and science
are (in their conventional forms) expressions of this
alienation. Humans are enslaved by their own creation, and communism is seen as the riddle of
history solved. While in Paris, he became a close
friend of Friedrich Engels, whose essay on political
economy greatly impressed him, and they decided
to work together, writing a fierce critique of Bruno
Bauer (and his brothers) in a work entitled The Holy
Family (1845 [trans. 1932]).
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
In 1845 Marx was deported from France and
went to Brussels, where he (with Engels) wrote
The German Ideology (1845 [trans. 1965]), a work not
published in his lifetime. Before writing this
work, Marx drafted his Theses on Feuerbach (1845
[trans. 1970]) where he argued that Feuerbach
saw abstract theoretical solutions to practical
problems. The famous eleventh thesis refers to
the fact that, whereas the philosophers have interpreted the world, the point is to change it. The
German Ideology elaborates the criticisms of Feuerbach, and deals at great length with the latest
manifestations of Young Hegelian idealism, including Stirner’s anarchist theory of egoism.
Marx explicitly identifies his position as one of
“new materialism,” and the work contains general arguments for a conception of history, society, politics, and culture rooted in the relations of
production. While writing this volume, Marx and
Engels established a Communist Corresponding
Committee (the embryo of subsequent Communist Internationals). One of the socialists he was
anxious to recruit was Pierre Joseph Proudhon
(1809–65), but by 1847 he had written a fierce
critique of Proudhon’s ideas (which he denounced as abstract and doctrinaire) in The Poverty of Philosophy.
In November 1847 Marx attended a meeting of
the Communist League’s Central Committee in
London (it had originally been the League of the
Just), and this was the organization that commissioned The Communist Manifesto (1848 [trans. 1968]).
Although Engels had written some earlier drafts,
the Manifesto in its published form was written
primarily by Marx and is the most famous of
Marx’s works. With extraordinary brevity and
poetic intensity, the work contains a hymn of
praise to capitalism as a dynamic productive
system, and establishes the argument that communism must arise on the basis of capitalism as a
system that becomes increasingly crisis-ridden as
it progresses. The Manifesto refers to the way in
which more and more sections of society are “proletarianized,” although in Marx’s more specific
writings (like the political analyses on France)
the uneven nature of this process receives more
stress. The work also contains highly suggestive
comments on the need for communists to organize as a “party” (although the meaning of this is
far from clear), and it contains a denunciation of
other forms of socialism and a radical ten-point
program, as well as a famous argument that the
liberal (“bourgeois”) revolution in Germany must
be supported, as a prelude to “the immediately
following” proletarian revolution.
361
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
News of the revolution in Paris reached Brussels
in February 1848. Marx briefly decamped to Paris
but moved to Cologne where he founded the Neue
Rheinische Zeitung which published reports of revolutionary activity all over Europe. The program of
the paper was a united democratic Germany (democracy interpreted in a left-liberal fashion) and a
war with tsarist Russia. But the revolutions
were all defeated and the Neue Rheinische Zeitung
closed down. In 1849 Marx settled in Britain. He
was initially convinced that the defeats were only
a temporary setback, and Marx rejoined the Communist League. In his March circular to the
League, Marx espouses the strategy of “permanent
revolution” – a strategy of continuing an antifeudal revolution until capital itself is overthrown. This rather “optimistic” perspective was
continued in the June circular, although Marx was
to warn in 1850 that up to fifty years might have
to pass before a revolution could succeed. After a
split within the League, Marx moved “his” wing of
the Communist League to Cologne and had it
wound up in 1852.
Often depending on the money that Engels
could raise, the Marx family lived in poverty. The
Neue Rheinische Zeitung Revue, produced in 1850,
contained among other things Marx’s analysis of
French political developments. These essays were
subsequently edited by Engels and published in
Germany as The Class Struggles in France (1895
[trans. 1964]) and The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis
Napoleon (1852 [trans. 1934]), often considered his
most brilliant political pamphlet. In these works
Marx showed the importance of producing a concrete analysis of the nuances of political struggle
and the way in which a ruling bloc of different
class fractions has to be stitched together to make
up state power in a particular instance. After completing his book on the Communist Cologne Trial,
Marx turned to his economic studies and during
the 1850s he published the first two chapters of
what was to be Capital. Despite decades of midVictorian prosperity passed in Britain, Marx
made an attempt to get to grips with class structure there in a review he wrote of the pamphlet of
1850 (Pourquoi la révolution d’Angleterre a-t-elle réussi?)
by François Guizot (1787–1874).
Between 1852 and 1862 Marx published – although in many instances the actual articles
were written by Engels – for the New York Daily
Tribune as their London correspondent. He tackled
the questions of India, the Crimean War, and upheavals in China. Marx wrote an “Introduction to
the Critique of Political Economy” in 1861. In this
introduction or outline, which was not published
362
Marx, Karl (1818–1883)
until 1941 as the Grundrisse, he dealt with the
questions of money and capital, with important
asides about, for example, alienation and the division of labor in a capitalist society. In 1859, he
published A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy, which contains the famous “guiding
thread” that outlines what came to be called his
“materialist conception of history.” He identifies
the “Asiatic, ancient, feudal and capitalist modes
of production” so that a mode of production embraces both the forces and relations of production
of a given system. Critics argue that this analysis
“fits” capitalism far more easily than it does precapitalist modes of production.
Much of the argument here was rewritten in
Capital, but before his magnum opus could be
tackled, Marx spent eighteen months attacking
Karl Vogt (1817–95) who had been a leader in the
Frankfurt parliament. In November, 1866, Marx
personally took the manuscript of Volume I of
Capital over to his publisher in Germany. The first
section deals with the nature of commodities and
money; the second, the transformation of money
into capital; the third, with the nature of surplus
value. Marx argues that what makes it possible
for commodities to exchange is that they are the
product of labor, but this theory of value is seen
by many commentators (including Marxists) to
be rather archaic and implausible. This was
followed by Marx’s far more readable history of
capitalism and the effect of machinery on the
worker, and culminated in his assessment of
capital accumulation.
The other two volumes of Capital have none of
the polish of the first. Volume III deals with the
relationship of values and prices.
By the 1860s, working-class activity was reviving. In September 1864, the First International
was formed with Marx as its president. The first
years of the International were taken up with
arguments against the followers of Proudhon,
who were opposed to strikes and political involvement. One of the affiliates to the First International was the newly constituted German
Social Democratic Workers Party. Marx supported the causes of Polish and Irish independence. After the defeat of France by Prussia, the
Paris Commune was proclaimed. Marx saw this as
a heroic if doomed attempt to storm heaven,
presenting the commune (which was brutally
crushed after seventy-two days in office) in The
Civil War in France as a “working-class government,” a state ceasing to be a state. However,
after 1870 Marx became increasingly preoccupied
with a struggle against the Russian anarchist,
Marxism
Mikhail Bakunin (1814–76), and the International
was transferred to New York where it died a natural death.
Capital was translated into Russian in 1872, and
Marx learnt Russian in order to read original
sources. He became familiar with Russian socialists and declared in the 1882 Preface to the Russian translation of the Communist Manifesto that a
revolution in Russia could avoid capitalism and
spark a revolution in the West. In 1875 he wrote a
critique of the German socialist party program,
accusing the latter of liberal formulas and abstractions. But his health continued to deteriorate, and
he died in 1883.
JOHN HOFFMAN
Marxism
Karl Marx famously declared that he was not a
Marxist, and it is arguable that there is an inherent tension between his ideas and the movements that arose in his name.
Marx never saw a Marxist movement seize power
during his lifetime. The relationship between
Marx’s theory and the Russian Revolution of 1917
is highly contentious. There is evidence to suggest
that Marx thought that socialist revolutions could
emancipate humanity only if they took place
in developed capitalist countries, and western
Marxists have held to this view, although without
practical results.
Soviet Marxism used Marx’s ideas to establish a
highly authoritarian form of socialism that replicated itself after World War II in the Communist
Party states of eastern Europe. Chinese Marxism
emphasized the importance of national independence, the centrality of will-power, and economic
self-sufficiency, and Cuban Marxism arose out of
the unwillingness of the United States to tolerate
radical nationalism. It is certainly true that Marxism has been much more successful where it has
been able to integrate itself with anti-colonial and
anti-imperialist struggles in the so-called Third
World, but only in South Africa has Marxism expressed itself through an independent Communist Party; and even here it is closely integrated into
a movement of national liberation.
Marxism as a political movement has usually
been anti-liberal, except in western Europe where
the ideas of the Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci
led to a Marxism that emphasized the importance
of winning popular consent and infusing Marxism
JOHN HOFFMAN
with liberal values.
Marxist sociology
Marxism is a theory of society as well as a theory of
economics. In its classical form, Marxist sociology
Marxist sociology
argues that people enter into social relationships
independent of their will. This does not mean
that they lack agency, but rather that what people
wish to do can never be the same as what they
actually do. This is why a Marxist sociology is
materialist in that it assumes that even though
people act consciously, their consciousness is
not a reliable guide to the course of action they
pursue.
In order to survive, people must produce goods
and services, and this fact has particular significance for Marxist sociology. Production is possible
only if people have technology – what are referred
to as the forces of production – and they cooperate
with one another in particular ways – what are
called relations of production. The forces and relations of production collectively constitute the
basis of society: they have primary significance in
accounting for events.
Marxist sociology assumes that there is always a
tension between the forces and relations of production. Hence relationships must continually change,
since the technology people employ is itself always
changing. This tension occurs in all societies,
so that it would be wrong to assume that social
development can ever cease.
On the other hand, this tension becomes an
“antagonism” when society is divided into social
classes. Classes arise where those who produce are
not the same people as those who benefit from
production. Classical Marxism assumes that there
is a relationship of exploitation between classes.
This makes it impossible for changes in the forces
of production to be reflected relatively smoothly
in changes in the relations of production, since a
particular class has a vested interest in a given set
of productive relations. In class-divided societies,
the collision between the forces and relations of
production creates the necessity for revolution.
Marx and his supporters are well aware that
production cannot occur on its own. Its organization requires a culture, a legal and political framework, a set of values, and a family structure; these
are seen as constituting a “superstructure” not
because they are irrelevant, but because they
cannot be understood on their own terms. Hence
Marxist sociology is not a theory of “economic reductionism” since this would imply that, whereas
the base molds the superstructure, the superstructure does not impact on the base.
In class-divided societies, the “superstructure”
works to entrench a particular set of productive
relations, giving the latter religious, political, and
ethical legitimacy. This is why class is political
and cultural as well as economic, even though
363
masculinity/masculinities
masculinity/masculinities
the roots of class lie in the way society produces.
While certain elements of the superstructure
(such as religion and the state) are particular to
class-divided societies, others (such as culture, political and social organization, family structure)
exist in all societies. They are in tension with the
base but this tension can be resolved without
the need for revolution (see theory of revolution),
since no one has an entrenched interest in a
particular set of productive relations.
JOHN HOFFMAN
masculinity/masculinities
At a general level masculinity is understood as
the ways of being and becoming a man. As with
many of the key terms in sociology, masculinity
and femininity were developed against the background of biological definitions that suggest that
these concepts are based in nature. Recently, sociobiological and evolutionary psychology theorists
have gained increasing popular appeal with their
focus on the power of nature over culture in determining gender differences between men and
women. Since the mid-1980s, particularly, as a
result of feminist, gay, and lesbian writing, and
AIDS activism, the changing nature of men’s lives
and their experiences have been much debated
within a range of literatures, drawing upon sex
roles, gender identity, psychoanalysis, and gender
and power relations.
Sex-role theory, which developed alongside theories of socialization, has been highly influential
in the social sciences. Through socialization, sexrole theorists argue, males and females are conditioned into appropriate social roles and behavior.
Norms and expectations that are polarized between the genders are central to the definition
of masculinity. Sex-role theory assumes that these
ahistorical gender essences are quantifiable and
measurable. Consequently, attitude tests can
be used to measure levels of socialization by the
amounts of masculinity that males possess.
Within this perspective, masculinity is subject to
objective measurement through an index of
gender norms. For example, strength, power, and
sexual competence are expected of boys in western societies. Hence a wide range of individual
men and male groups, such as effeminate boys
and gays, are seen as not having enough masculinity, which is explained in terms of deficient levels
of testosterone, inadequate role models, or overpowering mothers. In contrast, black boys and
working-class boys are seen as having too much
masculinity. Second-wave feminism challenged
the conceptual and political implications of
364
the commonsense view that biology is destiny. In
response, a distinction was made between biologically based sex (females and males) and culturally based gender (femininity and masculinity).
Such work opened up masculinity to critical
scrutiny, understanding masculinity as situated
within a structure of gendered hierarchies,
in which particular social practices are used to
reproduce social divisions and inequality.
Earlier theories of patriarchy (male dominance)
used a unitary notion (one style) of masculinity.
Later feminist theorists emphasized that gender
relations are multidimensional and differentially
experienced, and are responded to within specific
historical contexts and social locations. In other
words, differentiated forms of male power can be
explained only by an analysis that takes into consideration the specific conditions that give rise to
these situations. Sociological perspectives have
been used to explore the social organization of
masculinity and the active cultural production
of masculinities within institutional sites. One of
the most influential theorists, R. W. Connell,
building on feminist analysis, suggests that men
occupying a hegemonic masculinity are asserting
a position of superiority. They do this by winning
the consent of other males and females, in order
to secure their (hegemonic) legitimacy. Men are
able to position other men by way of their subordinated, complicit, or marginalized relationships.
This suggests a move away from talking about a
single masculinity to that of a plurality of masculinities. In Masculinities (1995), Connell acknowledges the social and cultural variations in being
and becoming male. Multiple masculinities is
a term used to convey the diversity of ways of
enacting masculinity, individually and/or collectively. For example, emerging male gay identities/
subjectivities provide concrete evidence that masculinity is not something one is born with or an
inherent possession, but rather an active process
of achievement, performance, and enactment.
Furthermore, the development of a wide range of
gay male styles makes clear that the meaning of
the living out of fractured masculinities involves a
diverse range of men’s investments, anxieties, fantasy identifications, and contradictory emotions.
More recently, poststructuralists and psychoanalysts have produced texts that address the perceived limitations of sociology around issues of
the self, subjectivity, the body, and gender and
sexual identity formations. For example, J. Butler’s
contemporary theorizing on gender as performative, in Gender Trouble (1990), in which she rejects
stable categories, has opened up ways of
mass media and communications
understanding notions of femininity and masculinity. This emphasis on gender as performative
has problematized the cultural formation of sex
and the interconnections between sex and gender.
For example, it provides a framework within
which to focus on uncoupling masculinity from
male bodies, that is, uncoupling what men do from
what men are. Masculinity and femininity in this
way can be understood as something that cannot
simply be equated with biological sex. The implication of this is that, at particular historical
moments, female bodies are able to take on and
live out particular masculinities. In particular,
this highlights the inadequacy of contemporary
theories of gender in accommodating female masculinities. Anthropologists are also critical of the
conceptual development of masculinity in the
context of western academia, which they argue
tends to construct a set of insular concepts and
reified types that inadequately describe gender
relations in other cultures. This cross-cultural analysis illustrates the limitations of generalizing
about what it means to be a man from a western
model of masculinity. Work on masculinities has
tended to concentrate on the localized production
of men’s meanings and experiences. However,
recent anthropological studies suggest the need to
understand masculinities within a broader social
and cultural framework that includes such issues
as international politics, intranational economic
relations, and globalized desires.
Presently, across western societies, the main
representation of men and masculinity is that
of crisis. For example, masculinity is intimately
linked to wider social and cultural transformations within the British nation-state, and the
assumed crisis of masculinity can be read as an
effect of the wider crisis of late modernity. It is
suggested that socio-cultural change is marked
by the disintegration of older social collectivities
– such as social class – and increased fluidity of
social relationships, with an accompanying interest in identity and subjectivity. This is part of a
more general trend whereby the ascendant social
category in established binaries (for example,
men, heterosexuals, and whites) are becoming
the new objects of critical appraisal.
MAIRTIN MAC-AN-GHAILL AND CHRIS HAYWOOD
mass media and communications
During the Enlightenment and the period of eighteenth-century revolutions, the press was perceived
as a progressive source of information, debate, and
political transformation. The nineteenth century,
mass media and communications
however, saw the rise of a commercial press and
sensationalistic pandering to the masses that
evoked critique of emergent mass media and communication. With the rise of mass entertainment,
broadcasting, and a proliferation of new media in
the twentieth century, there were a series of critiques of mass culture and communication, from
the right and left. Mass media and communications were linked to the rise of what critics saw as
individualism and mass society, which were in turn
interpreted as threats to democracy, freedom, and
other positive values.
Critiques of mass culture and the press began
emerging during the late eighteenth century. Leo
Lowenthal in Literature, Popular Culture, and Society
(1961: 20) cites the comment of J. W. Goethe (1749–
1832) that the press constitutes a squandering of
time wherein the reader “wastes the days and lives
from hand to mouth, without creating anything.”
Anticipating Søren Kierkegaard (1815–55), he criticized the ways that modern entertainment and
the press promoted passivity and conformity,
noting in a ditty how the press is eager to provide
its readers with almost anything except dissenting
ideas:
Come let us print it all
And be busy everywhere;
But no one should stir
Who does not think like we.
Others had more optimistic appraisals of the
impact of mass media, and particularly the press.
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, famously, compared reading the daily newspaper with morning
prayer. Karl Marx in Collected Works (1975, vol. I:
165), had an especially high opinion of the press in
the promotion of democracy and civil liberties,
writing in 1842 that:
The free press is the ubiquitous vigilant eye of a
people’s soul, the embodiment of a people’s faith in
itself, the eloquent link that connects the individual
with the state and the world, the embodied culture
that transforms material struggles into intellectual
struggles and idealizes their crude material form. It
is a people’s frank confession to itself, and the
redeeming power of confession is well known. It is
the spiritual mirror in which a people can see itself,
and self-examination is the first condition of
wisdom. It is the spirit of the state, which can be
delivered into every cottage, cheaper than coal gas. It
is all-sided, ubiquitous, omniscient. It is the ideal
world which always wells up out of the real world
and flows back into it with every greater spiritual
riches and renews its soul.
By the 1840s, the press was thus a contested terrain with fervent defenders and critics. Some saw
365
mass media and communications
it as an instrument of progress and enlightenment,
while others saw it as an instrument of distraction
and banality. Different political groupings were developing their own distinct presses and attempting
to shape public opinion in various ways. While
Goethe and others made some critical remarks
concerning the press of the day, one of the first
systematic and sustained attacks on the press is
evident in Danish philosopher/theologian Kierkegaard’s polemic The Present Age (1846 [trans. 1982]),
with the satirical Danish review The Corsair, which
published articles making fun of him in late 1845,
inciting him into a literary duel with the journal.
Kierkegaard’s efforts constitute one of the first critiques of print media as an instrument for the
creation of mass audience and political manipulation, producing an early assault against the media
and foreshadowing later critical theories of mass
media and society.
Anticipating later Marxist and conservative critiques of the media, Kierkegaard argues that when
“passion and commercial interest determine the
issue,” when “the rattle of money in the cashbox”
is at stake, the propensity for corruption increases
(1982: 172). Kierkegaard reveals insight here into the
economic roots of the features of the press that he
finds scandalous, arguing that “immoral slander” is
“of no benefit whatsoever” and “does great harm
because it seduces the unstable, the irresponsible,
the sensate, those who are lost in earthly passions,
seduces them by means of ambiguity, lack of character and the concealment of brash contempt under
the pursuit of the comic” (1982: 179–80).
Interestingly, Kierkegaard’s privileged metaphor for the press is that it is a vicious attack
dog. He does not theorize the press as a guardian
of the public’s interests, as it was initially conceived to be in democratic theory, but rather as a
predator that goes after individuals in a contemptible way. The press, he argued, is fundamentally irresponsible because its writers were
anonymous and did not assume responsibility for
what they wrote. In addition to undertaking an
ethical critique of the press, Kierkegaard was one
of the first to see that the press is a mass medium
which addresses its audience as members of a
crowd and that itself helps to create a mass society. The press plays a fundamental role, Kierkegaard suggests, in producing a public, a crowd
devoid of individuality and independent judgment, their thought determined by the authority
of printed words and editorial fiat. The average
man in the street, Kierkegaard suggests, “believes
that what appears in the newspapers is public
366
mass media and communications
opinion, the voice of the people and of truth”
(1982: 186).
Kierkegaard thus points to the ways that the
press simulates authority and objectivity and can
thus make a lie appear as truth, or an opinion as
fact. Inverting the liberal theory of public opinion
(which is supposed to protect the interests of
the public against corrupt authority), Kierkegaard
claims that the press creates a phantom public
devoid of character and individuality. Consequently, Kierkegaard, like later postmodern
theory, ascribes to communications media a tremendous role in producing a mass society without
distinction, individuality, or conviction. Devoid of
individuality, the masses themselves are an abstraction and the main effect of modern society
is a leveling of the population into a mass.
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) believed that
modern society had become so chaotic, fragmented, and devoid of “creative force” that it
had lost the resources to create a vital culture,
and that ultimately it greatly advanced the decline of the human species that had already begun
early in western history. In Nietzsche’s view, two
complementary trends were evident that were
producing contradictory processes of “massification” and fragmentation -- the extreme consequences of which would be a central theme of
some postmodern theory. On one hand, for
Nietzsche, modern society was fragmenting into
warring groups, factions, and individuals, without any overriding purpose or shared goals. On
the other hand, it was leveling individuals into a
herd, bereft of individuality, spontaneity, passion,
and creativity. Both trends were harmful to the
development of the sort of free, creative, and
strong individuality championed by Nietzsche,
and thus he was sharply critical of each.
In their groundbreaking work Dialectic of Enlightenment (1948 [trans. 1972]), Max Horkheimer and
Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno coined the term culture industry to signify the process of the industrialization (see industrial society) of mass-produced
culture and the commercial imperatives that constructed it. The critical theorists analyzed all massmediated cultural artifacts within the context of
industrial production, in which the commodities
of the culture industries exhibited the same features as other products of mass production: commodification, standardization, and massification.
The culture industries had the specific function,
however, of providing ideological legitimation of
the existing capitalist society and of integrating
individuals into its way of life.
mass media and communications
For the Frankfurt School, mass culture and communications therefore stand in the center of leisure activity, are important agents of socialization,
mediators of political reality, and should thus be
seen as major institutions of contemporary societies with a variety of economic, political, cultural,
and social effects. Furthermore, the critical theorists investigated the cultural industries politically
as a form of the integration of the working class
into capitalist societies. The Frankfurt School theorists were among the first neo-Marxian groups to
examine the effects of mass culture and the rise of
the consumer society on the working classes that
were to be the instrument of revolution in the
classical Marxian scenario. They also analyzed the
ways that the culture industries and consumer
society were stabilizing contemporary capitalism
and accordingly sought new strategies for political
change, agencies of political transformation, and
models for political emancipation that could serve
as norms of social critique and goals for political
struggle.
The positions of Adorno, Horkheimer, Lowenthal,
and other members of the inner circle of the Institute for Social Research were contested by Walter
Benjamin, an idiosyncratic theorist loosely affiliated with the Institute. Benjamin, writing in Paris
during the 1930s, discerned progressive aspects in
new technologies of cultural production such as
photography, film, and radio. In “The Work of Art
in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction” (1934
[trans. 1968]), Benjamin noted how new mass
media were supplanting older forms of culture. In
this context, the mass reproduction of photography, film, recordings, and publications replaced
the emphasis on the originality and “aura” of the
work of art in an earlier era. Freed from the mystification of high culture, Benjamin believed that
mass culture could cultivate more critical individuals able to judge and analyze their culture, just as
sports fans could dissect and evaluate athletic activities. In addition, Benjamin asserted that processing the rush of images of cinema helped to
create subjectivities better able to parry the flux
and turbulence of experience in industrialized,
urbanized societies.
Collaborating with the prolific German artist
Bertolt Brecht (1898–1956), Benjamin worked on
films, created radio plays, and attempted to utilize the media as organs of social progress. In the
lecture in 1934 on “The Author as Producer”
(1966 [trans. 1978]), Benjamin argued that radical
cultural creators should “refunction” the apparatus of cultural production, turning theatre
and film, for instance, into a forum of political
mass media and communications
enlightenment and discussion rather than a medium of “culinary” audience pleasure. Both Brecht
and Benjamin wrote radio plays and were interested in film as an instrument of progressive
social change. In an essay on radio theory, Brecht
anticipated the internet in his call for reconstructing the apparatus of broadcasting from one-way
transmission to a more interactive form of twoway, or multiple, communication -- a form first
realized in CB radio and then electronically
mediated computer communication.
Moreover, Benjamin wished to promote a radical
cultural and media politics concerned with the creation of alternative oppositional cultures. Yet he
recognized that media such as film could have conservative effects. While he thought it was progressive that mass-produced works were losing their
“aura,” their magical force, and were opening cultural artifacts to more critical and political discussion, Benjamin recognized that film could create a
new kind of ideological magic through the cult of
celebrity and techniques like the close-up that fetishized certain film stars or images via the technology of the cinema. Benjamin was thus one of the
first radical cultural critics to look carefully at the
form and technology of media culture in appraising
its complex nature and effects.
Horkheimer and Adorno answered Benjamin’s
optimism concerning the mass media in Dialectic
of Enlightenment. They argued that the system of
cultural production dominated by film, radio
broadcasting, newspapers, and magazines was
controlled by advertising and commercial imperatives, and served to create subservience to the
system of consumer capitalism. While later critics
pronounced their approach too manipulative, reductive, and elitist, it provides an important corrective to more populist approaches to media culture
that downplay the way the media industries exert
power over audiences and help produce thought
and behavior that conforms to the existing society.
Jürgen Habermas, a student of Adorno and Horkheimer, provided useful historical perspectives on
the transition from traditional culture and the
democratic public sphere to a mass-produced
media and consumer society. In The Structural
Transformation of the Public Sphere (1962 [trans.
1989]), Habermas historicized Adorno and Horkheimer’s analysis of the culture industry. Providing historical background to the triumph of the
culture industry, Habermas discussed how bourgeois society in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries was distinguished by the rise of
a public sphere that stood between civil society
and the state and which mediated between public
367
mass media and communications
and private interests. For the first time in history,
individuals and groups could shape public opinion, giving direct expression to their needs and
interests while influencing political practice. The
bourgeois public sphere made it possible to form a
realm of public opinion that opposed state power
and the powerful interests that were coming to
shape bourgeois society.
Habermas analyzed a transition from the liberal
public sphere that originated in the Enlightenment and the American and French Revolutions
to a media-dominated public sphere in the current
stage of what he calls “welfare state capitalism and
mass democracy.” This historical transformation is
grounded in Horkheimer and Adorno’s theory of
the culture industry, in which giant corporations
have taken over the public sphere and transformed
it from a site of rational debate into one of manipulative consumption and passivity. In this transformation, “public opinion” shifts from rational
consensus emerging from debate, discussion, and
reflection, to the manufactured opinion of polls
or media experts. For Habermas, the interconnection between the sphere of public debate and individual participation has thus been fractured and
transmuted into that of a realm of political
manipulation and spectacle, in which citizen-consumers ingest and passively absorb entertainment
and information. “Citizens” thus become spectators of media presentations and discourse which
arbitrate public discussion and reduce its audiences to objects of news, information, and public
affairs.
As communication studies began emerging in
the 1930s and 1940s, and as theorists noted the
power of propaganda in World War II, a wide
range of texts began appearing on the social
effects of the media, promoting debate over the
media and social problems, and the media as a
social problem. Some of the first empirical studies
of the effects of film, for instance, criticized the
cinema for promoting immorality, juvenile delinquency, and violence. The Motion Picture Research
Council funded the Payne Foundation to undertake detailed empirical studies of the impact of
films on everyday life and social behavior. Ten
volumes were eventually published and a book,
Our Movie-Made Children (1933), sensationalized
the Payne findings, triggering debates about the
media and how they inflamed social problems like
crime, youth problems, sexual promiscuity, and
what was perceived as undesirable social behavior.
The first models of mass communication built
on studies of propaganda, film influence, advertising, and other media studies, assumed a direct
368
mass media and communications
and powerful influence of media on the audience.
This model became known as the “bullet,” or
“hypodermic,” theory, asserting that the media
directly shape thought and behavior and thus
induce social problems like crime and violence,
rebellious social behavior, mindless consumption,
or mass political behavior. Based on research by
Harold Lasswell, in Propaganda Technique in the
Modern World (1927), there were a number of
studies in the 1930s and 1940s of the propaganda
role of the media in World Wars I and II, reflecting concern about the roles of film, advertising,
and other media in intensifying a number of
social problems ranging from crime to growing
numbers of teenage pregnancies.
This model of powerful and direct media effects
was questioned in The People’s Choice (1944) by Paul
Lazarsfeld and his colleagues Bernard Berelson
and Hazel Gaulet who, in a study of the influence
of the media on voters, determined that it was
“opinion leaders” who were the primary influence
in voting behavior, while the media exerted a
“secondary” influence. Lazersfeld and Elihu Katz
expanded this model in Personal Influence: The Part
Played by People in the Flow of Mass Communication
(1955). Their “two-step flow” model claimed that
opinion leaders are the primary influence in determining consumer and political choice, as well
as attitudes and values. This model holds that the
media do not have direct influence on behavior,
but are mediated by primary groups and personal
influence, thus in effect denying that the media
themselves are a social problem because they
merely report on issues and reinforce behavior
already dominant in a society.
Yet both conservatives and left-liberal media
critics argued that the media had harmful social
effects and promoted social problems. Growing
juvenile delinquency in the 1950s was blamed on
comic books, such as Fredric Wertham’s Seduction
of the Innocent (1954), and rock and roll was broadly
attacked for having a wide range of subversive
effects. In the 1960s, many different studies of
the media and violence appeared throughout the
world in response to growing violence in society
and more permissive public media that increased
representations of implicit sex and violence in
film, television, and other media.
In addition to seeing the media as a social problem because of growing media and societal violence, from the 1960s to the present, left-liberal
and conservative media critics coalesced in arguing that mainstream media promote excessive
consumerism and commodification. This view is
argued in sociological terms in the work of Daniel
mass media and communications
Bell, who asserted in The Cultural Contradictions of
Capitalism (1978) that a sensate–hedonistic culture
exhibited in popular media and promoted by
capitalist corporations was undermining core
traditional values and producing an increasingly
amoral society. Bell called for a return to tradition
and religion to counter this social trend and saw
media culture as undermining morality, the work
ethic, and traditional values.
In Amusing Ourselves to Death (1985), Neil Postman
argued that popular media culture has become a
major force of socialization and was subverting
traditional literacy skills, thus undermining education. Postman criticized the negative social effects
of the media and called for educators and citizens
to intensify their criticisms of it. Extolling the
virtues of book culture and literacy, Postman called
for educational reform to counter the nefarious
effects of media and consumer culture.
Mass culture and communication was of great
interest in the United Kingdom and Europe, as
well as the United States. While the Frankfurt
School arguably articulates cultural conditions in
the stage of state monopoly capitalism or Fordism
that produced a regime of mass production and
consumption, British cultural studies emerged in
the 1960s when, first, there was widespread global
resistance to consumer capitalism and an upsurge
of revolutionary movements, and then emergence
of a new stage of capital, described as postFordism, postmodernity, or other terminology
that attempted to describe a more variegated and
contested social and cultural formation. Moreover,
the forms of society and culture described by the
earliest phase of British cultural studies in the
1950s and early 1960s articulated conditions in an
era in which there were still significant tensions in
Britain and much of Europe between an older
working-class-based culture and the newer massproduced culture whose models and exemplars
came from American culture industries.
The initial project of cultural studies developed
by Richard Hoggart, Raymond Williams, and E. P.
Thompson attempted to preserve working-class
culture against onslaughts of mass culture and
communication from the culture industries.
Thompson’s inquiries into the history of British
working-class institutions and struggles, the defenses of working-class culture by Hoggart and
Williams, and their attacks on mass culture were
part of a socialist and working-class-oriented project that assumed that the industrial working
class was a force for progressive social change
and that it could be mobilized and organized to
struggle against the inequalities of the existing
mass media and communications
capitalist societies and for a more egalitarian
socialist one. Williams and Hoggart were deeply
involved in projects of working-class education
and oriented towards socialist working-class politics, seeing their form of cultural studies as a progressive instrument for change.
The early critiques in the first wave of British
cultural studies of Americanism and media culture in Hoggart, Williams, and others, during the
late 1950s and early 1960s, thus paralleled to some
extent the earlier critique of the Frankfurt School,
yet valorized a working class that the Frankfurt
School saw as defeated in Germany and much of
Europe during the era of fascism, and which they
never saw as a strong resource for emancipatory
social change. The 1960s work of the Birmingham
Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies was continuous with the radicalism of the first wave of
British cultural studies (the Hoggart–Thompson–
Williams “culture and society” tradition) as well
as, in important ways, with the Frankfurt School.
Yet the Birmingham project also eventually paved
the way for a postmodern populist turn in
cultural studies.
During this period, the Centre developed a variety of critical approaches for the analysis, interpretation, and criticism of cultural artifacts.
Through a set of internal debates, and responding
to social struggles and movements of the 1960s
and the 1970s, the Birmingham group came to
focus on the interplay of representations and
ideologies of social class, gender, race and ethnicity, and nationality in mass culture and communication. The Birmingham scholars were among
the first to study the effects of newspapers, radio,
television, film, and other popular cultural forms
on audiences. They also focused on how various
audiences interpreted and used media culture in
different ways and contexts, analyzing the factors
that made audiences respond in contrasting ways
to media texts.
Like the Frankfurt School, British cultural studies observed the integration of the working class
and the decline of its revolutionary consciousness,
and studied the conditions of this catastrophe for
the Marxian project of revolution. Like the Frankfurt School, British cultural studies concluded
that mass culture was playing an important role
in integrating the working class into existing capitalist societies and that emergent consumer and
media culture was forming a new mode of capitalist hegemony. But John Fiske in Understanding
Popular Culture (1989) and other writings attacked
the concepts of mass society and mass culture
which were said to be overly homogenized and
369
mass media and communications
monolithic, neutralizing cultural contradictions
and dissolving oppositional groups and practices
into a neutral concept of “the masses” which
many in the British cultural studies tradition
found overly contemptuous and elitist.
Both traditions, though, see culture as a form of
resistance to capitalist society, and both the earlier
forerunners of British cultural studies, especially
Williams, and the theorists of the Frankfurt School
see high culture as forces of resistance to capitalist
modernity. Later, British cultural studies would valorize resistant moments in media culture, and
audience interpretations and use of media artifacts, while the Frankfurt School tended, with
some exceptions, to see mass culture as a homogeneous and potent form of ideological domination -a difference that would seriously divide the two
traditions.
Negative depictions of the media and consumerism, youth hedonism, excessive materialism, and
growing violence were contested by British cultural studies which claimed that the media were
being scapegoated for a wide range of social problems. In Policing the Crisis (Hall et al., 1978), Stuart
Hall and colleagues at the Birmingham Centre
analyzed what they took to be a media-induced
moral panic about mugging and youth violence.
The Birmingham group argued for an active audience that was able to dissect critically and make
use of media material, arguing against the media
manipulation perspective. Rooted in a classic article by Hallen titled “Encoding/Decoding” (1980),
British cultural studies began studying how different groups read television news, magazines, engaged in consumption, and made use of a broad
range of media. In Everyday Television: Nationwide,
Charlotte Brunsdon and David Morley (1978) studied how different audiences consumed TV news,
and Fiske wrote a series of books celebrating the
active audience and consumer in a wide range of
domains throughout the world.
Yet critics working within British cultural studies, individuals in a wide range of social movements, and academics from a variety of fields and
positions began criticizing the media from the
1960s to the present for promoting sexism, racism,
homophobia, and other oppressive social phenomena. There was intense focus on the politics of
representation, discriminating between negative
and positive representations of major social groups
and harmful and beneficial media effects, debates
that coalesced under the rubric of the politics of
representation.
The groundbreaking work of critical media theorists like the Frankfurt School, British cultural
370
mass media and communications
studies, and French structuralism and poststructuralism revealed that media culture is a social
construct, intrinsically linked to the vicissitudes
of the social and historically specific milieu in
which it is conceived and that gender, race, class,
sexuality, and other dimensions of social life are
socially constructed in media representations.
Media and cultural studies engaged in critical
interrogations of the politics of representation,
which drew upon feminist approaches and multicultural theories to analyze fully the functions of
gender, class, race, ethnicity, nationality, sexual
preference, and so on in the media. The social
dimensions of media constructions are perceived
by cultural studies as being vitally constitutive of
audiences who appropriate and use texts.
While earlier British cultural studies engaged
the progressive and oppositional potential of
working-class and then youth culture, under the
pressure of the social movements of the 1960s and
1970s many adopted a feminist dimension, paid
greater attention to race, ethnicity, and nationality, and concentrated on sexuality. During this
period, assorted discourses of race, gender, sex,
nationality, and so on circulated in response to
social struggles and movements and were taken
up in cultural studies to engage critically the politics of representation. An increasingly complex,
culturally hybrid, and diasporic global culture
and networked society calls for sophisticated
understandings of the interplay of representations, politics, and the forms of media, and theorizing global culture has been a major focus of the
contemporary era.
Many critics emphasized the importance of connecting representations of gender, race, class, sexuality, and other subject positions to disclose how
the media present socially derogatory representations of subordinate groups. bell hooks, in Black
Looks: Race and Representation (1992) and other
writings, has been among the first and most prolific African-American feminist scholars to call
attention to the interlockings of race, class, gender,
and additional markers of identity in the constitution of subjectivity. Early in her career she
challenged feminists to recognize and confront
the ways in which race and class inscribe women’s
(and men’s) experiences. In “Eating the Other”
(1992), hooks explores cultural constructions of
the other as an object of desire, tying such positioning to consumerism and commodification as well
as to issues of racial domination and subordination. Cautioning against the seductiveness of celebrating “otherness,” hooks uses various media
cultural artifacts -- clothing catalogs, films, rap
mass media and communications
music -- to debate issues of cultural appropriation
versus cultural appreciation, and to uncover the
personal and political crosscurrents at work in
mass media representation.
Since the 1960s, a broad range of theories and
methods to analyze the production of media texts,
their polysemic meanings, and their complex uses
and effects have been developed. Critical theories
were developed within feminism, critical race
theory, gay and lesbian theory, and other groupings associated with new political movements,
making critical theory part of political struggle
inside and outside the university. Feminists, for
instance, demonstrated how gender bias infected
disciplines from philosophy to literary studies
and was embedded in texts ranging from classics
of the canon to the mundane artifacts of popular
culture. In similar ways, critical race theorists
demonstrated how racial bias permeated cultural
artifacts, while gay and lesbian theorists demonstrated sexual bias.
These critical theories also stressed giving voice
to groups and individuals marginalized in the
dominant forms of western and then global culture. Critical theory began going global in the
post-1960s disseminations of critical discourses.
Postcolonial theory in various parts of the world
developed particular critical theories as a response to colonial oppression and to the hopes of
national liberation. Franz Fanon in Algeria, Wole
Soyinka in Nigeria, Gabriel Marquez in Latin
America, Arrundi Roy in India, and others all
gave voice to specific experiences and articulated
critical theories that expanded their global and
multicultural reach.
Focus on the politics of representation thus
calls attention to the fact that culture is produced
within relationships of domination and subordination and tends to reproduce or resist existing
structures of power. Such a perspective also provides tools for cultural studies whereby the critic
can denounce aspects of media forms and artifacts
that reproduce class, gender, racial, and diverse
modes of domination, and positively valorize
aspects that subvert existing types of domination,
or depict resistance and movements against them.
Issues of the politics of representation and violence and the media intersect in the impassioned
debates over pornography. For a school of feminism and cultural conservatives, pornography and
violence against women are among the most problematic aspects of media culture. Anti-porn feminists argue that pornography objectifies women,
that the industry dangerously exploits them, and
that pornography promotes violence against
mass society
women and debased sexuality. Pro-sex feminists
and defenders of pornography, by contrast, argue
that pornography exhibits a tabooed array of
sexuality, provokes fantasy and awakens desire,
and can be used by consumers in gratifying ways.
Hence, while there is widespread agreement
that the media has multiple effects and that its
representations are an important part of the
social world, there is heated debate over whether
the media have positive or negative social effects.
Many critics argue that one-sided pro or con positions tend to be simplistic and reductive and that
contextual analysis needs to be made on specific
media effects of certain technologies or artifacts
on specific audiences. This position also asserts
that, in general, media have contradictory effects
and that in many cases it is impossible to discern
accurately or distinguish positive or negative features that are often interconnected. Contemporary debates thus reflect the bifurcated positions
on the media and mass communications first debated in the early nineteenth century.
DOUGLAS KELLNER
mass society
A type of society based on social conformity, political complacence, the decline of community, mass
production and mass communication, this concept was most influential in the 1940s and 1950s
when it was related to theories of social order and
manipulation. Following in the footsteps of
Matthew Arnold, T. S. Eliot, in Notes Towards the
Definition of Culture (1948), refined the distinction
between elite and mass culture. Eliot argued that
it is the duty of the elite to protect the values of
high culture from the onslaught of mass culture,
which he associated with pandering to the lowest
common denominator.
C. Wright Mills argued in The Power Elite (1956)
and The Sociological Imagination (1959) that the
pluralism upon which democracy depended was
being replaced by the standardization of opinion,
values, and behavior. Individual freedom was
being replaced by programmatic behavior orchestrated by the centralized state and the business
corporation. In the popular sociology of Vance
Packard in The Hidden Persuaders (1957), ordinary
men and women were subject to the “hidden
persuaders” who controlled advertising and operated the levers of public opinion formation. The
argument paralleled key themes in the Frankfurt
School critique of society, especially the proposition that mass culture had become one-dimensional in Herbert Marcuse’s One-Dimensional Man
(1964). But it was given a fillip in these years by
371
materialism
the Cold War and the increasing knowledge about
the centralized regulation and orthodox value
systems that operated in the Soviet command state.
David Riesman, in The Lonely Crowd (1950), argued
that a new general personality type was emerging
in mass society. The first settler communities and
the generations that succeeded them up to the
1940s were characterized by “inner-directed” personality types based in self-reliance, personally
defined convictions, and a strong sense of place.
Under mass society they were being replaced by
“other-directed” types who assimilated opinions
and values from the mass media, were susceptible
to advertising, marketing, and other forms of
public opinion manipulation, and who expressed
a weak sense of belonging and community.
Mass society theory came increasingly under
fire after the 1960s. It was held to sponsor a dominant ideology thesis that exaggerated the manipulative power of ruling formations and failed
to grasp social and cultural diversity. Critical
thought shifted to questions of social class,
gender, and race, all of which destabilized the
proposition of a homogeneous mass of citizens,
producers, and consumers. The rise of interest in
multiculturalism projected issues of hybridity,
diaspora, postmodernism, and postcolonial identity to the forefront of sociological theory. The
effect was to expose the over-simplification and
inflexibility of mass society theory.
Covertly, mass society theory underwent a massive revival in the 1990s in the guise of George
Ritzer’s thesis in McDonaldization of Society (1993).
Taking over and modernizing Max Weber’s rationalization thesis, Ritzer argued that social life was
succumbing to penetrating standards of efficiency, calculability, predictability, and control.
The argument invoked again the notions of standardized social practice and mass conformity.
Following the train of classical mass society
theory, Ritzer concludes that the prospects for
resistance are dim. The fate of advanced industrial
society is to subject citizens to various processes
of standardization of emotions and practice in the
CHRIS ROJEK
conduct of everyday life.
materialism
This concept can be understood in two rather
different ways. In everyday language, it is used as
a moral judgment of a person or philosophy,
ascribing to them an excessive devotion to possessions or sensory pleasures. In a more technical
vocabulary, it means any secular philosophy or
system which accepts only explanations grounded
372
maternal deprivation thesis
in material reality. The most widespread materialist
system is that of western science, which seeks an
account of the physical world without recourse to
spiritual or supernatural forces. Anglo-Saxon social
sciences and French sciences humaines derive their
inspiration from scientific materialism. Typically
such approaches emphasize observable behaviors,
notably language, rather than intangible elements
such as psychological motivations. Equally significant is the scientific socialism of Karl Marx. Marx
sought a scientific basis for understanding human
history and social formations, and found it in the
economic activities of societies. Marx’s dialectical
variant of materialism identified the contradictions arising within economic orders as the motor
of history. Moreover, in his earlier writings, Marx
claimed that the cultural products and symbolic
and political systems of a society were products of
its economic organization. Later materialists, often
inspired by phenomenology’s interest in embodiment, inquired into the material force of communication, power, sexuality, and other factors. One
core challenge for materialism is to avoid the
mechanical determinism common in Indian and
classical materialism and some versions of Newtonian scientific reasoning. Marx’s dialectical materialism, the phenomenological emphasis on lived
experience, and developments in contemporary science, especially in cybernetics, have lessened the
more extreme determinist aspects of early materialism. A second challenge, to describe structure
and change without recourse to abstract ideas,
which are difficult to use without ascribing agency
SEAN CUBITT
to them, still proves elusive.
maternal deprivation thesis
This thesis originally arose in Britain from the
work of John Bowlby, a child psychologist and psychoanalyst, in the 1940s and 1950s, most notably
from Child Care and the Growth of Love (1953). The
idea of maternal deprivation has been much used
and abused since he developed his thesis, and so it
is important to contextualize his work. As a clinician Bowlby worked with disturbed children and
he began to relate the delinquent behavior he
witnessed to the quality of parenting, particularly
mothering, that children received. These ideas developed in a more focused way when he observed
the treatment of children in hospitals and residential institutions and, also, of those who were separated from their mothers by wartime evacuation.
Hospital practices at that time entailed a complete
separation of mother and child, and, while in
the institution, the infant was neither cuddled,
matriarchy
comforted, nor played with. Bowlby observed that
this resulted in an inability of the child to attach
to other human beings. The idea of maternal deprivation was therefore an important component
of Attachment Theory. He argued that if the child
did not learn to respond to other key individuals,
most particularly the mother or mother substitute, s/he could not learn to trust or interact in
a normal way. To achieve attachment, Bowlby
argued that mothers must form affective bonds
with their children and that these bonds should
not be disrupted by long absences, or by the introduction of multiple carers. His work was part of a
trajectory of work which sought to protect children and to improve their life chances.
However, the maternal deprivation thesis
became popularized through the growth of social
work and health visiting in the 1950s and 1960s,
and Bowlby’s originally humane ideas became
sedimented into virtual rules for how mothers
should raise their children. Mothers were criticized for going out to work, especially if their
children were under five, and the idea that
mothers were solely responsible for the delinquency or disturbed behavior of their children
also became an idée fixe. Feminist work in the
1970s became very critical of the maternal deprivation thesis because it was seen as responsible for
closing nurseries in the postwar era and condemning mothers to long, lonely hours of virtual imprisonment with their infants. The thesis was used
to deny employment to women with children, and
alternative care was also frowned upon. Fathers
too became insignificant in this process, with all
the attention being on the quality of the mother–
child bond and the father being seen solely as the
economic support to allow the mother to be a fulltime carer. However, Denise Riley, in The War in the
Nursery (1983), has argued that much of the criticism against Bowlby was misplaced because, from
a sociological perspective, it is essential to distinguish between the original ideas taken in context
(such as the importance of bonding) and the ways
in which these ideas were popularized and utilized by others who might have had different purposes. In other words, she suggests that the thesis
was treated instrumentally to keep mothers at
home, whereas the original aim was to recognize
the importance of the mother–child bond and to
improve the treatment of children. C A R O L S M A R T
matriarchy
An anthropological term which describes a society
in which descent and lineage are traced through
Mauss, Marcel (1872–1951)
the mother rather than the father; an example of
matriarchal descent patterns is that of Judaism, in
which it is the mother who confers the status of
Jew on her children. It is, however, not the case
that matriarchy can be read as the opposite to
patriarchy, since many matriarchal systems do
not confer on women the same authority, nor
access to property, as patriarchal systems do on
men. It is also the case that matriarchy can exist
in certain contexts within patriarchal societies;
the most obvious and well-known example would
be the matriarchal household, in which women
dominate the social and personal arrangements
of the domestic space, but in which power outside the household belongs exclusively to men. As
is the case with the term patriarchy, matriarchy
is often used in a more general sense to denote a
pattern of female control and authority.
MARY EVANS
Mauss, Marcel (1872–1951)
Mauss was born in Epinal, also the birthplace of
Émile Durkheim, who was his uncle and became
his teacher and mentor. Mauss led, so to speak,
the anthropological wing of the Durkheim school,
at any rate after the death in World War I of other
anthropologists (or ethnographers, as they generally called themselves) associated with it. His numerous and significant contributions derived
their data chiefly from the study of pre-literate
society but on Durkheim’s death he took over
the editorship of the Année Sociologique, and in
1931 he was called to a chair in sociology at the
Collège de France. With his uncle he wrote a seminal essay on Primitive Classification (1903 [trans.
1963]); with H. Hubert, a “Sketch of a General
Theory of Magic”; with H. Beuchat, a very successful “Essay on Seasonal Variations within Eskimo
Societies.” The latter two essays were published as
Sociologie et anthropologie (1906). Some of Mauss’s
other writings addressed classical anthropological
themes, such as sacrifice, myth, and ritual. Others,
however, owed their impact to the novelty of their
themes, such as laughter and tears, the “techniques of the body,” and, most especially, the
gift. Mauss addressed the latter phenomenon, in
The Gift (1924 [trans. 1954]), as a major instance
of what he called “a total social phenomenon,”
that is one comprising at the same time juridical,
economic, religious, and aesthetical aspects,
none of which should be studied in isolation
from the others. His sophisticated handling of all
these topics constituted a major inspiration for
the development of structuralism, especially in
373
McDonaldization
McLuhan, Marshall (1911–1980)
anthropology as practiced and theorized chiefly
by Claude Lévi-Strauss after Mauss’s own death.
GIANFRANCO POGGI
McDonaldization
This term was successfully deployed by George Ritzer in his book The McDonaldization of Society, first
published in 1993, and promoted in several other
volumes by the same author. He defines McDonaldization as “the process by which the principles of
the fast-food restaurant are coming to dominate
more and more sectors of American society as well
as of the rest of the world.” He continues by maintaining that this process affects “not only the restaurant business, but also education, work, health
care, travel, leisure, dieting, politics, the family,
and virtually every other aspect of society.” The
practices of the McDonalds restaurant chain are
thus used metaphorically to describe and illustrate more general societal tendencies. According
to Ritzer, McDonalds operates in accordance with
four basic principles: efficiency, calculation, predictability, and control. These principles, being
applied to workers and work organization and to
customers, account for the company’s success.
Their single-minded pursuit in a business organization have had some detrimental consequences for
personnel, work, and their products. Work is
boring, and their goods are uniform just as they
were in factories engaged in the industrial production of standardized commodities. Applied to other
domains of existence, like education or personal
care, the principles often have irrational effects,
damaging to the social relationships between
providers and recipients. The concept is primarily
a rhetorical device for redescribing processes
which in earlier sociological literature would be
described as rationalization.
ALAN WARDE
McLuhan, Marshall (1911–1980)
In the 1960s and 1970s, McLuhan was read as one
of the most influential media theorists of our time
and is once again becoming widely discussed and
debated in the computer era. His 1964 work Understanding Media dramatized the importance of
television and electronic broadcasting and entertainment media on contemporary society. The
eventual decline of influence of McLuhan’s work
perhaps resulted in part from his exaggeration of
the role of television and electronic culture in
effecting a break from the print era and producing a new electronic age. Yet, in retrospect,
McLuhan anticipated the rise and importance
of computer culture and the dramatic emergence
and effects of personal computers and the
374
internet that provide even more substance to
McLuhan’s claim that contemporary society is
undergoing a fundamental rupture with the past.
Indeed, McLuhan can be read in the light of
classical social theory as a major theorist of modernity, with an original and penetrating analysis
of the origins, nature, and trajectory of the
modern world. Furthermore, he can be read in
retrospect as a major anticipator of theories of a
postmodern break, of a rupture with modernity,
of leaving behind the previous print–industrial–
urban-mechanical era and entering a new postmodern society with novel forms of culture and
society. McLuhan’s work proposes that a major
new medium of communication changes the ratio
of the senses, the patterns of everyday life, modes
of social interaction and communication, and
many other aspects of social and individual life
that are often not perceived. “Understanding
media,” thus, for McLuhan, requires understanding the form of the media and its structural
effects on the psyche, culture, and social life.
McLuhan’s analyses of book and print technology,
newspapers, roads, modern industry and mechanization, war, radio and television, computers, and
other modern technologies and phenomena all illuminate the constitution of the modern world
and provide new insights into modernity and the
emergence of a postmodern era. His description of
specific technologies and how they produced the
modern era and anticipation of how new emergent
electronic technologies are fashioning a new postmodern era are often highly illuminating. McLuhan, like Jean Baudrillard, Fredric Jameson, and
other theorists of the postmodern, presents an
ideal-type analysis in which modernity is marked
by linearity, differentiation, explosion, centralization, homogenization, hierarchy, fragmentation,
and individualism. Postmodernity, by contrast, is
marked by implosion or dedifferentiation, decentralization, tribalism, synaesthesia, and a new
media and computer culture that would be called
cyberspace which would be theorized by Baudrillard and other postmodern theorists.
As with Karl Marx and certain versions of postmodern theory, there have been criticisms of
McLuhan’s notion of stages of history and his
ideal-type delineation of premodern, modern,
and postmodern societies. His depiction of premodern societies as “primitive” and “savage” is
highly objectionable from the standpoint of contemporary critical theory. Unlike more dialectical
theorists, McLuhan does not mediate between
the economy and technology in the construction
of contemporary media industries, although he
Mead, George Herbert (1863–1931)
provides unique insights into media form and
the powerful effects of specific media. McLuhan
thus remains important for social theory and
cultural studies as we enter a new millennium.
DOUGLAS KELLNER
Mead, George Herbert (1863–1931)
Best known in sociology as the progenitor of the
symbolic interactionist school, which builds upon
his ideas on the social nature of the act and its
relation to the human self and society, he
was actually one of the most original thinkers in
twentieth-century American philosophy. In addition, he dedicated much thought and effort to
movements for progressive social reform.
As David Miller observes in George Herbert Mead:
Self, Language and the World (1973), Mead’s pivotal
philosophical concept of sociality, which he explicitly articulated only late in his life, refers to
processes of interaction among and between phenomena of all kinds throughout the natural universe. Mead developed this idea by referring to
such disparate intellectual developments as,
among others, Einstein’s special theory of relativity or Charles Darwin’s evolutionary principles.
That Mead’s thought is only partially understood
by most sociologists is due, at least in part, to his
well-known writer’s block. Most of his influential
works, including Mind, Self, and Society (1934), were
not composed for publication, but rather were
compiled from course notes taken by dedicated
students. This group included Herbert Blumer,
who transmitted edited statements of Mead’s
ideas into sociological circles. But there may be
other problems as well. It is unclear if Mead modeled his philosophical notion of sociality on his
social psychology of human interaction, or vice
versa. In addition, Mead never worked out an epistemological position adequate to understanding
interactions between phenomena with different
properties. Indeed, the absence of an epistemological position in Mead’s thought is reflected in
the absence of a unifying method in symbolic
interactionism today. Not only are there two methodologically distinct schools of symbolic interactionism, the Chicago and Iowa Schools, but the
Chicago School often relies on methods much
richer in elegant ethnographic description than
in generalized sociological analysis.
Mead’s thought has experienced a renaissance in
recent years led by Hans Joas, Gary Cook, and Dmitri Shalin. Jürgen Habermas, more ambitiously,
has reframed and reconstructed sociological elements of Mead’s thought and incorporated them
Mead, Margaret (1901–1978)
into his theory of communicative action. Habermas emphasizes Mead’s focus on the coordination
of interaction via significant symbols. Mead, in
turn, was inspired, with regard to the significance
of communication, by C. S. Peirce (1839–1914), one
of the founders of the philosophy of pragmatism.
Mead was born in 1863, the son of a Congregational minister father and a mother who
became President of Mount Holyoke College after
her husband’s death. Mead graduated from Oberlin College in 1883 and enrolled at Harvard University in 1887. Though he studied with William
James, he had a higher regard for Josiah Royce
(1855–1916). The strongest influences on Mead’s
thought were Charles Horton Cooley and John
Dewey (1859–1952), both of whom Mead met at
the University of Michigan, where he took a position in 1891. Three years later he joined Dewey,
who accepted a chair in philosophy, as a member
of the Department of Philosophy at the University
of Chicago, where he spent the rest of his career.
IRA COHEN
Mead, Margaret (1901–1978)
A student of Franz Boas (1858–1942) and protégée of
Ruth Benedict (1887–1948), Mead was an anthropologist of unrivaled international celebrity
during her long and multifaceted career. She opposed cultures to races (see race and ethnicity) and
pointed to the diversity of practices of enculturation as the key to any adequate account of the
behavioral diversity of different human populations. Yet she shared with Benedict a relativism
tempered by a humanist psychology which licensed the rebuke and even the pathologization
of the culture that failed to accommodate the
whole array of putatively natural psychosexual
human needs and temperamental inclinations of
its members. The part-relativist, part-humanist
thrust of her critical pedagogy is already at work
in Coming of Age in Samoa (1928). It is a motif in
more than forty books and hundreds of essays that
she would subsequently publish. Mead’s terrains of
investigation were many and far-flung; her critical
attention consistently returned to the intolerance
and the Puritanism of her native United States.
Quiet but sustained discomfort with the quality
of much of Mead’s ethnographic research erupted
into controversy after her death with Derek Freeman’s Margaret Mead and Samoa: The Making of a
Myth (1984). Her enduring stature owes more to
her long curatorial career at the American
Museum of Natural History, her early and persistent advocacy of the use of multiple media of
375
mean
ethnographic documentation and multiple genres
of ethnographic writing, her leadership as a public
scientist and intellectual, and her great success
in rendering anthropology accessible to a mass
audience.
JAMES D. FAUBION
mean
– see distribution.
measurement
In the social sciences, measurement consists in
the application of numbers to persons, social
objects, or events. An identical number may have
a radically different meaning, depending on the
predetermined rules for its application in a particular measurement context. There are three
qualitatively different ways that numbers can be
applied to effect such measurement: nominal
scales are used to name things, people, or events;
ordinal scales are used to rank things, people, or
events; and cardinal (interval and ratio) scales are
used to represent quantity. First, nominal scales
may be used to name, or label, things, people, or
events. Scores assigned according to a nominal
scale could just as easily be letters, or words. The
numbers employed in a nominal scale operate to
distinguish between observations – but have no
cardinal, or real, value. Examples of the use of a
nominal scale include the assignment of a “1” for
females and a “2” for males, in a dataset. A student
number or social security number is also an
example of a nominal scale. The assignment of
numbers according to a nominal scale does not
permit the sophisticated statistical interpretation
of collections of such scores. For instance, it does
not make sense to infer that males are twice as
valuable as females, according to the scores
accorded to each (for it would be equally sensible
to accord a “2” to females and a “1” to males).
Similarly it would be nonsensical to compute the
average social security number. For this reason,
variables that are measured according to a nominal scale are termed qualitative variables.
Second, numbers assigned according to ordinal
scales provide the researcher with more information than do numbers assigned according to nominal scales. In addition to performing the basic
function of categorization, such numbers also
provide a sense of the relative position of a
number in relation to other numbers. In this
sense, ordinal scales are quantitative, in that
they give a rough indication of the quantity of
the entity in question, relative to other entities.
A common instance of an ordinal scale is the
activity of ranking persons, events, or objects.
376
measurement
Thus, it may be stated that X is more popular
than Y, and that Y is more popular than Z; however, an ordinal scale can tell us nothing about the
intervals between X, Y, and Z. That is, the consistency of the intervals between adjacent ranks
cannot be assumed, according to an ordinal scale.
There are two kinds of cardinal scales: interval
scales and ratio scales. Interval scales provide a
third level of measurement. Interval scales, like
nominal and ordinal scales, may be used to categorize things, events, or people. In addition, like
ordinal scales, scores reflect the property of quantity. That is, different numbers reflect more or less
of a particular variable. However, interval scales
differ from ordinal scales in that they have the
property that numerical distances on the scale
represent equal distances on the dimension argued
to underlie each scale. Temperature (whether
measured by Fahrenheit or Celsius) is an example
of an interval scale. The distance between 5 and 10
degrees is identical to the distance between 20
and 25 degrees. Similarly, a log-interval scale of
measurement is one in which numbers are
assigned so that the ratios between values
reflect ratios in the attribute being measured.
In log-interval ratio scales, the logarithms of
the scale scores form an interval scale, as the ratio
a/b ¼ log a log b. Common examples of logratios are density (mass divided by volume) and
fuel efficiency in kilometers per liter. The application of interval scales within the social and behavioral sciences is more contentious than within the
natural and physical sciences. Many statistical
tests rely upon the assumption that the data represent an underlying dimension of equal intervals. As early as 1946, Clyde Coombs in his “A
Theory of Psychological Scaling,” urged social scientists to stick with lower levels of measurement,
rather than “quantifying by fiat.” The process of
transforming data into higher levels of measurement is known as “scaling” or “quantification.”
Critics have argued that quantification or scaling
can, if applied without consideration, impose nonsensical numerical values on non-numerical dimensions. In turn, the ubiquity of this practice
raises questions about the transferability of
scaling, as a concept, from the physical sciences
to social phenomena, with the risk of otherwise
information-rich qualitative data being subjected
to the imposition of a single, linear, underlying
dimension.
Ratio scales are argued to provide the most sophisticated level of measurement. In addition to
possessing all of the properties of an interval
scale, a ratio scale also possesses an absolute zero
measurement
point. Time and length are instances of ratio
scales. Temperature is not, as “0” does not equal
the complete absence of heat.
A discontinuous or discrete variable, or dimension, of interest is one that usually increases by
increments of one whole number. Pregnancy and
number of children are discrete variables. That is,
while it may be true that the average number of
children per Australian couple is 2.21, and that
the average number of live births per single
mother per year is 0.18, these expressions do not
reflect any particular real-world pregnancy or
child. One cannot be a little bit pregnant; just as
one cannot raise 0.21 of a child. In the interpretation of averages based on discontinuous variables, one should identify the closest sensible
denominator. For instance, in the above example,
we should expect to find 221 children per 100
Australian couples.
A continuous variable, or dimension, in contrast, can in theory have an infinite number of
increments between each whole number. Height
and weight are common examples of continuous
variables. When measuring continuous variables,
it is always possible to achieve a more precise
measurement – and any measurement taken is
always an approximation. In consequence, the
measurement of continuous variables typically involves the specification of a particular unit of
measurement, which specifies the desired level
of precision. This specification will result in all
measurements taken that fall within a particular
interval being recorded as an instance of that
interval. The upper and lower real limits of a
number are typically one half of the specified
unit of measurement. Thus, if one were recording
height in centimeters, the real limits for the
figure 164 would be 163.5 cm (lower limit) and
164.5 cm (upper limit). If the unit of measurement
were tenths of a centimeter, then the real limits
for the figure 164 would be 163.95 cm (lower limit)
and 164.05 cm (upper limit).
Measurement gives rise to consideration of the
issues of reliability and validity. Reliability refers
to the ability to repeat the results of a measurement accurately (common forms include interrater reliability; test–retest reliability; and measures of internal consistency, including split-half
and coefficient alpha). Validity refers to the degree
of fit between the measurement taken and the
underlying analytic construct (construct validity);
or to the resemblance between the measurements
taken and their “real-life” equivalent (ecological
validity). The measurement scale employed may
have consequences for both these issues. Particular
measurement
caution may be necessary when combining extremely qualitative, or “subjective” social issues,
such as racism, or homophobia, with higher-order
measurement approaches.
Measurement raises a number of issues for sociologists. It engenders at least two basic challenges:
the question of finding an appropriate fit between
indicators and analytic concepts, and the search
for sufficiently accurate data. Sociological forms
of measurement are more diverse than those
found within other social sciences, including
psychology, where the variables of interest are
often articulated at an individual, rather than a
societal, level. In consequence, sociological researchers encounter issues of measurement in
the context of the collection and organization of
both primary and secondary sources of data.
Census-based data, including Severe Acute Respiratory Syndrome (SARs), offer sociologists a
rich resource for the measurement of a range of
social variables, such as socioeconomic status and
poverty, quality of life, and well-being, and other
social indicators.
The measurement of socioeconomic status is a
central activity for sociologists and policymakers
alike. However, the precise methods by which
socioeconomic status are measured is, at the
outset, a reflection of a particular theoretical approach to understanding socioeconomic status
and social class. Divergent methods of measuring
socioeconomic status tend to be, in turn, based on
divergent theoretical approaches. For instance,
Marxist and Weberian approaches tend to produce, respectively, categorical and categorial/continuous variables. That is, the very qualities of the
underlying dimension may alter, according to the
theoretical approach taken. Measures developed
using a Weberian framework, which emphasizes
a three-fold definition of socioeconomic status
(ownership of wealth-producing enterprises and
materials; skills, credentials, or qualifications;
and social prestige) tend to conceptualize this
dimension as either a categorical (discrete) or a
continuous variable. In contrast, measures
constructed using a Marxist or neo-Marxist approach produce, without exception, categorical, or
discrete, variables. This is a product of the centrality of the criterion of ownership or non-ownership
of the means of production. Marxist and neoMarxist measures accordingly take the form of at
least three distinct class groups: large employers;
the self-employed; and workers.
Thus socioeconomic status may, in practice, be
calculated from either a single measure or from
several closely related variables. Single measures
377
measurement
tend to be based upon the classification of occupational status. Multiple measures may be drawn
from a range of sources, including educational
attainment, father’s (and increasingly) mother’s
occupation, income, possessions, and home ownership. Multiple measures are often treated as
more reliable measures of socioeconomic status
than single measures, as these correlate more
strongly with such closely related variables as
school achievement.
However, even single measures based on occupation may be refined. Some systems of measurement (for example the 501 categories of the
United States Census Occupational Classification)
are capable of classifying occupations into hundreds of categories. These categories, when hierarchically ranked according to criteria such as the
prestige, income, entry-level qualifications, and
typical workplace injury rates associated with
each occupation, may be transformed into instances of a continuous variable, which in turn
enables a greater range of statistical operations
to be conducted on such data.
Within sociology, measurement has long been a
topic of critical reflection. In Method and Measurement in Sociology (1964), Aaron Cicourel developed a
critique of the unacknowledged reliance of the
sociologist as a coder – responsible for assigning
numerical values to social phenomena – on
“common sense knowledge”:
if we must rely on human judges, then we should
know as much as possible . . . about how the “human
computer” goes about encoding and decoding
messages . . . Instead it is often assumed that such
meanings are self-evident, that native-speakers of a
language are more or less interchangeable, that the
manifest content is sufficient for study, or that
judges are interchangeable. The structure of
common-sense knowledge remains a barely
recognizable problem for sociological investigation.
Further, the order created by the use of formal
instruments is, according to critics, often created
by the very administration of such scales and the
comparability between units of measurement that
they produce. Thus, scales measuring a certain
social variable may correlate with other measures
of related variables (thus demonstrating construct, or convergent validity) but may bear little
resemblance to the lived orderliness of respondents’ lives (thus lacking ecological validity).
More recently, Michael Lynch, in his “Method,”
in G. Button (ed.), Ethnomethodology and the Human
Sciences (1991), studied ordinary and scientific measurement as ethnomethodological phenomena.
Lynch has examined the practical accomplishment
378
medical dominance
of categorization and classification. He argued
that an ethnomethodological approach to the practice of measurement, following Harold Garfinkel
and Harvey Sacks’s formulation of “ethnomethodological indifference,” would operate to place
matters of methodology back into the everyday
settings they emerge from, as “ethnomethodological indifference turns away from the foundationalist approach to methodology and that gives
rise to principled discussions of validity, reliability,
rules of evidence, and decision criteria.” However,
as he notes, many sociologists may find the upshot
of these debates unsettling.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
measurement levels
– see measurement.
media
– see mass media and communications.
median
– see distribution.
mediascape
– see mass media and communications.
medical dominance
Defined as the enormous social, financial, and
political power medicine has over the organization and practice of health care, medical dominance is a concept that has been used to explain
why doctors asymmetrically have more power
than patients in their interactions, but also why
doctors have more power than allied health-care
professionals such as nurses, social workers, and
therapists who use alternative or complementary
medicine.
Medicine gains much of its power through its
exclusive knowledge about the operation of certain mechanisms of the body. The emphasis
placed on specialist medical knowledge, as opposed to the subjective opinions of an untrained
lay person, is central to medical dominance. The
notion that medical diagnoses are scientific, objectively verifiable, and replicable, and the way
health care is hierarchically organized, reinforce
medical dominance.
The professional nature of a career in medicine
profoundly affects the interactions between
doctors and patients and may reinforce medical
medical model
dominance. For instance, the professional can control the amount of time spent with a patient, can
interrupt the patient’s conversation, or can control the flow of information to a patient in a way
which exacerbates inequalities in their relationship. The power to label a patient is also a fundamental source of medical power. As well, doctors
have significant power over patients because of
their position as gate-keepers of entitlement to
certain welfare benefits and ability to influence
medical costs and insurance payments.
Some authors, such as Paul Starr in The Social
Transformation of American Medicine (1982), suggest
that changes in the organization of the healthcare industry, including the corporatization of
medicine and the rise of managerialism, may
result in a decline in medical dominance, because
doctors’ clinical decisions are influenced by corporate goals of profitability and efficiency.
MARK SHERRY AND GARY L. ALBRECHT
medical model
– see medicalization.
medicalization
Defined as the way in which the scientific knowledge of medical science is applied to behaviors or
conditions which are not necessarily biological,
this concept was developed (originally in the
United States) in the early 1970s, associated with
the view of medicine as an instrument of social
control.
Critics of the medical model, particularly in the
last decades of the twentieth century, suggested
that this model was increasingly being applied in
situations where it was not appropriate. Historically, it is common for the medical model of the
culture and period to find application in wide
areas of life beyond the body and its diseases.
Nevertheless it is true that the twentieth century
saw the increasing attachment of medical labels
to behaviors then regarded as morally or socially
undesirable (alcoholism, delinquency, and homosexuality) as well as to many normal stages of life
(such as pregnancy and old age).
Ivan Illich (1926–2002) in his Medical Nemesis
(1976) promulgated the idea that society was becoming increasingly medicalized. Doctors were
becoming the new priesthood, and modern medicine was creating overdependence on technical
fixes. Irving Zola in his article “Medicine as
an Institution of Social Control” in The Sociological Review (1972) analyzed the increasing pervasiveness of medicine in terms of: (1) expansion
into more and more areas of life; (2) absolute
medicalization
control over techniques; (3) access to intimate
areas of life; and (4) medical involvement in
ethical issues.
For instance, the medicalization of behavior
extends the concept of addiction to include a variety of activities such as shopping, gambling, and
promiscuous sexual activity. Alcoholism offers a
particularly clear example of the effects of this,
with some divergence of attitude between experts
about behavioral models of the condition and the
addiction model, which sees it in physiological or
psychological terms.
The medicalization thesis has been particularly
important to feminist sociologists, who have seen
expansionist tendencies in medicine applied
to women’s bodies and women’s lives, defining
natural processes such as pregnancy and childbirth, menstruation and menopause, as illness
conditions. Recognition of the major part which
medical technology has had in reducing maternal
and infant mortality has gone hand in hand
with longstanding dissatisfaction with maternity
services. Feminist criticisms, such as the British
sociologist Ann Oakley in her book The Captured
Womb (1984), have accused a medicalized system
of ignoring women’s own preferences and experiences. In other contexts, women are similarly seen
as the object of patriarchal medical control, for
instance over drugs (especially the prescription of
tranquillizers) and surgery, and in general the
treatment of women within the medical system
is accused of serving to enforce passivity and
dependence.
The labeling of problems as “disease” may have
the positive consequence that the individual is
absolved of moral responsibility, and offers the
prospect of treatment or help. Sociologists point
out, however, that the labels do carry moral evaluation with them, defining behaviors which may
be normal in particular circumstances as things
which should be cured.
The French social philosopher Michel Foucault
saw medicalization not as the simple exercise
of personal power by a profession intent on
extending its boundaries, but as a historical process deriving from the power of clinical knowledge and the redefinition of medicine to include
psychological, economic, and social “health.” Although the development of holistic medicine is
generally welcomed, all aspects of life become
medicalized, in need of continual monitoring,
self-examination, and education. The British
sociologist David Armstrong, in Political Anatomy
of the Body (1983), described this as a shift from
the biological anatomy of disease to the political
379
men’s health
anatomy of disease in which medicine focuses on
social life.
In late modern society, it is now generally
agreed that a degree of demedicalization is taking
place, whereby lay knowledge and experience are
being given a more important place, and lay
people’s knowledge about the body allowed more
legitimation.
MILDRED BLAXTER
men’s health
– see health.
mental health
– see health.
meritocracy
– see credentialism.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1908–1961)
A French philosopher who held professorships at
the University of Lyon and the Sorbonne, MerleauPonty was the editor of the journal Les Temps modernes which had been founded by Jean-Paul Sartre
(1905–80). He broke with Sartre and the Communist Party after the Korean War, becoming increasingly detached from politics.
He developed the phenomenology of the everyday world, and was concerned to understand
human consciousness, perception, and intentionality. His work was original in applying the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) to
intentional consciousness but from the perspective of corporeal existence. He wanted to describe
the lived world without using the conventional
dualism between subject and object. Hence,
Merleau-Ponty was critical of the dualism between
mind and body. He developed the idea of the
“body-subject” that is always situated in a social
reality. He sought to develop an epistemology that
would avoid the dualism between realism and
social constructionism. He also rejected behavioral and mechanistic approaches to the human
body, and worked towards the development of a
phenomenology of the body as a lived experience
of the everyday world. He attempted to show that
identity and consciousness of self cannot be divorced from our embodiment. For sociologists,
his most influential work was Phenomenology of
Perception (1945 [trans. 1962]), which has been important for contemporary approaches to the sociology of the body, and therefore his approach is
often contrasted with Michel Foucault’s treatment
of the body in his concept of governmentality.
BRYAN S. TURNER
380
Merton, Robert K. (1910–2003)
Merton, Robert K. (1910–2003)
Born in Philadelphia, Meyer Schkolnick changed
his name to Robert Merlin in adolescence when he
was already a gifted magician in need of a stage
name. Robert King Merton came later, but his
youthful talents for plying the line between the
apparent and the real were a promise of things to
come. After education in the public schools and
libraries of South Philadelphia, Merton attended
Temple University where he discovered sociology
(BA, 1931). His graduate studies were at Harvard
(PhD, 1936), where he distinguished himself both
in sociology and the history of science. As a graduate student he published eight articles in the
leading journals in academic sociology and science studies, which were the groundwork for his
first major book, Science, Technology and Society in
Seventeenth-Century England (1938), and his most important scholarly article, “Social Structure and
Anomie” (1938).
Merton’s place in the history of twentieth-century science and culture is assured by four among
his many accomplishments: (1) the founding of
the sociology of science; (2) his leadership (with
Paul Lazarsfeld) of one of academic sociology’s
most important centers of training and research
at Columbia University; (3) the introduction of
theoretical ideas, always empirically grounded,
that simultaneously turned American sociology
into a mature social science and renewed its appreciation of the European traditions; and (4) by
writing the English language with such clarity
and elegance that concepts of his invention (such
as “self-fulfilling prophecy,” “focus group” and
“role model”) entered the vernacular. Merton’s
genius is most simply described as a devotion to
empirical social science conveyed without sacrifice of his formidable learning in literature,
history, and philosophy.
If there was a single handbook for sociological
theory and research in sociology in the middle of
the twentieth century, it was Merton’s Social Theory
and Social Structure (1949), in which he developed
concepts like manifest and latent functions,
anomie as a structural effect, theories of the
middle range, the self-fulfilling prophecy, and reference group theory, among others, including the
key ideas upon which the sociology of science was
established. Though he is thought of as aligned
with Talcott Parsons as a structural functionalist,
Merton’s thinking was first and foremost structuralist: for example, in “Social Structure and
Anomie,” he revised Émile Durkheim’s theory of
anomie to demonstrate how structures can invent
Methodenstreit
methodology
new, if deviant, forms of social behavior when
society fails to provide the normal institutional
means. He was, thus, the master of discerning the
hidden behind the apparent.
Merton published some thirty books between
1938 and the year of his death in 2003, the last
of which, The Travels and Adventures of Serendipity
(2003), stands with On the Shoulders of Giants: A
Shandean Postscript (1965) as a work that will long
be read by literary and cultural critics as well as by
sociologists. Among his many distinctions were
twenty-nine honorary degrees, a MacArthur Prize
Fellowship (1983–8), a presidency of the American
Sociological Association (1957), and the National
Medal of Science (1994). Merton was a man of
consummate generosity who helped countless
people with their work and lives.
CHARLES LEMERT
Methodenstreit
This was a controversy over the method and epistemology of economics in the late 1880s to 1890s
between supporters of the Austrian School led by
Carl Menger (1840–1921) and the German Historical School of Gustav von Schmoller (1838–1917).
The Historical School argued that economists
could develop social laws from the collection and
study of statistics and historical materials, and
distrusted theories not derived from historical
experience.
The Austrian School believed that economics
was the work of philosophical logic and could
only ever develop by deriving abstract, universally
valid rules of conduct from first principles.
Human motives and other causes for concrete
interaction were far too complex to be amenable
to statistical analysis. At a general level the Methodenstreit was a question of whether there could
be a science, apart from history, which could explain the dynamics of human action. The dispute
began in 1884 with Schmoller’s critical review of
Menger’s Principle of Economics (1871) and Menger’s
reply, The Errors of Historicism in the German Political
Economy (1884). It subsequently involved thinkers
such as Lujo Brentano (1844–1931), Max Weber,
and Werner Sombart for the Historical School,
and Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk (1881–1914), Friedrich Wieser (1851–1926), and Ludwig von Mises
(1881–1973) for the Austrian School. Politically
there were overtones of a conflict between the
classical liberalism of the Austrian School and
the advocacy of welfare state provisions by the
Historical School. In sociology the issues were central to Weber’s approach, which attempted to
steer a pragmatic course between the pursuit of
generalizations and historically grounded and
specific analysis.
LARRY RAY
methodological individualism
This concept was introduced by the philosopher of
science Karl Popper in his influential work The
Poverty of Historicism (1957), one of the two most
influential books in the twentieth-century history
of the philosophy of the social sciences. The main
thesis of this book, developed in the 1930s, was an
attack on the notions of the forces of history and
ideas of historical inevitability in fascism and
Communism, but also in the thinking of academic
scholars such as Karl Mannheim and, before him,
Ernst Troeltsch, who employed similar “holist” or
supra-individual concepts and argued that they
referred to concrete realities of a special kind.
The use of these concepts was typically associated with the philosophical claim that understanding these concrete phenomena required a special
kind of knowledge or methodology beyond that of
science. Popper’s point was that such things as
society were theoretical constructions, of a kind
familiar from science, which were abstract concepts used to interpret our experience, but that
the experience which they construct can be adequately captured in the terms that apply to individuals, such as attitudes, expectations, decisions,
and relations. This did not imply, however, methodological psychologism, the claim that sociology
could be reduced to the laws of psychology.
Max Weber is the most prominent and consistent methodological individualist in the history of
sociology. In recent years the term has been associated with rational choice theorists who have
argued that many social processes formerly explained in terms of society could be better understood as the product of individual choices or
decisions which produce collective results
through the processes of an “invisible hand.”
STEPHEN P. TURNER
methodology
This term refers to the specialist study of procedures of empirical investigation. Traditionally, in
sociology as in other sciences, it is the reliability
of the research method which is thought to assure
the validity of the research data and the generalizability of the research findings: it is methodology
that differentiates sociology from mere anecdotage. A distinction is regularly made between quantitative and qualitative methods. Quantitative
methods are primarily those of censuses and
381
methodology
methodology
surveys, both structured interviews and postal representations of method serve to advance
questionnaires, but other examples are content claims to scientific status.
analysis in studies of documents and mark-recapture methods of population estimation. Qualitative
methods are primarily those of in-depth interviews,
ethnography, focus groups, and discourse analysis,
but other examples are life histories, group interviews, and rapid assessment techniques.
The growth in popularity of qualitative methods
in the 1960s and 1970s – and the concomitant
dissatisfaction with quantitative methods – was
part of a revolt against positivism, a concern that
sociology was studying what could be measured,
rather than developing measures for social reality.
However, the distinction between quantitative
and qualitative methods has been overdrawn.
Thus, qualitative methods of data collection have
often been subjected to realist/positivist methods
of analysis (see, for example, Rory Williams’s use
of “logical analysis” in A Protestant Legacy, 1990,
his ethnography of the health beliefs of elderly
Aberdonians). And best practice in large-scale
quantitative surveys has long embraced the need
for complementary qualitative work. This is
seen most obviously in pilot studies, such as focus
groups used to develop and refine measures
and to test the comprehensibility of research instruments, but the best examples of such complementarity are found in the multi-disciplinary,
community-based, randomized controlled trials
of health services research, where qualitative
methods are typically deployed to generate
the “process evaluation” component of the study,
that is, to explain why the service being
evaluated appears to be more effective in some
service-delivery settings – or with some subgroups
of clients – than others.
The criticisms of a preoccupation with research
method have continued to multiply. Critics have
suggested that such preoccupations lead to a disabling scientism and political quietism, manifested in a failure to engage with oppressions
such as racism. Or they have suggested that the
claim to scientific status based on methodological
expertise is a political claim to the privileges and
rewards associated with professional autonomy;
or that the same claim of expertise serves to distance the sociologist from his/her research subjects who lose the right to influence the research
findings and collaborate in the scientific representation of their social world; or that the claim
that one can accurately analyze the social phenomena of late modernity by carefully following
rules of scientific practice, is simply a claim: a
postmodern analysis would seek to examine how
382
Yet sociological research flourishes despite
these buffets from activists and action research,
from Science and Technology Studies, from discourse analysis, and from postmodernism. It
flourishes under two dispensations, that of counter-reformatory realism, and that of a reformed
methodology which incorporates reflexive awareness of its own limitations. The counter-reformatory position draws on the philosophy of Karl
Popper to argue that, by following rigorous
methodological procedures, sociologists can be
led to reject a pre-existing theoretical assumption or hypothesis as negated by the research
evidence and therefore false: research methods
assure us of the scientific basis of the investigation because they provide for the possibility of
the falsification of a hypothesis. The reformist
position recognizes that the unthinking application of rules of methodology cannot of itself
guarantee scientific reliability, that no rule can
specify all the occasions of its use, and that the
everyday application of scientific methods is a
matter for pragmatic interpretation by researchers in the situation of action. Instead, the reformist position commits the researcher to the skillful
use of certain practices to ensure outcomes such
as relatively complete descriptions of the setting/
activity, “saturation” of the analytical categories
derived, and the demonstrable credibility of the
provisional findings for collectivity members
and/or other fellow sociologists. In effect, the
reliability of the findings depends on the practical accomplishment of a reflexive researcher,
keenly aware of the pitfalls and the limitations
inherent in the research process: research
methods (including the analysis and write-up)
are craft skills practiced with varying degrees
of success. The reformist position has been
defended from a philosophy-of-science perspective, most notably by Roy Bhaskar’s “critical realism” in Reclaiming Reality (1989) and by Martin
Hammersley’s “subtle realism” in What’s Wrong
with Ethnography? (1992). Of course, much sociological research takes place owing nothing to
Popper on the one hand or Bhaskar and Hammersley on the other, but strictly speaking such
research employs the methods, not of sociology
but of cultural studies, the methods of textual
deconstruction.
The study of research methods has progressively
broadened from a preoccupation with procedures
of research design, data collection, and analysis.
Good ethical practice has become a matter for
metropolitan fringe
external regulation and professional self-regulation
as well as academic writing. Methodological writing
now also embraces topics such as the negotiation of
research access, fieldwork relationships, leaving the
field, researcher safety, and public participation in
the research process. Much recent writing has been
concerned with the authorial voice and the processes of sociological representation, so that reflexive awareness of research practice now extends to
the writing of research itself.
MICK BLOOR AND FIONA WOOD
metropolitan fringe
This concept describes a region between 16 and 64
km outside major urban centers where traditional
rural industries are giving way to residential, commercial, and industrial development. This new
development is mainly located along highways
and in the countryside rather than in established
settlements. It is often unclear where suburbs end
and the fringe begins. One criterion is to register
changes in the size of parcels of land through the
use of a GIS map in order to identify transformations of relatively small plots to larger parcels of
four or more hectares. Many people who live in
the fringe have suburban lifestyles, commuting
long distances to jobs in the suburbs, edge cities,
and the central city. The fringe is attractive because it offers open space, potentially cleaner air
and water than a city or suburb, less congestion
and noise, and less crime. In the information economy these features give the fringe significant economic development potential. Firms are more
mobile than previously, and workers prefer to
live in a pleasant environment with access to cultural amenities. The fringe combines environmental advantages with proximity to suburban
and urban activities. Since the 1980s developed
societies have seen population movement from
the suburbs (the predominant growth area of the
mid twentieth century) to the fringe, sometimes
called “exurbia.” There is a debate about whether
this new growth is substantively different from
what preceded it and some dispute claims that
counter-urbanization in developed societies
represents a dramatic break from previous growth
patterns. Rather, the development on the metropolitan fringe may be simply the latest incarnation
of continued suburbanization.
LARRY RAY
Michels, Robert (1856–1936)
A cosmopolitan political theorist, Michels made
an enduring contribution to sociology in his
micro–macro theory
“iron law” of oligarchy as developed in his book
Political Parties (1911 [trans. 1966]). His argument,
which is neither a law nor as unyielding as the
word iron implies, nonetheless offers acute insights into the general relation between bureaucracy and democracy. Using an empirical case
study of the German Social Democratic Party
(and associated organizations) to illustrate his
general point, Michels observes that bureaucracies, which are organized solely for their effectiveness, can be effective only by relying on a small
group of officials with specialized knowledge and
skills. These upper-level bureaucrats ultimately
become indispensable to administrative operations, especially when bureaucracies are under
competitive or political pressures to achieve goals.
Even organizations founded on democratic ideals
ultimately cede day-to-day authority to these bureaucratic oligarchies. Though the idea is now ubiquitously known as the “iron law of oligarchy,” it
was anticipated in many other works, beginning
with the arguments regarding democracy made
by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78) in On the Social
Contract (1792 [trans. 1913]), and including Moisei
Ostrogorski (1854–1919) in his brilliant comparative study Democracy and the Organization of Political
Parties (1902 [trans. 1964]), and Max Weber’s analysis of bureaucracy. Union Democracy (1956) by
Seymour Martin Lipset, M. Trow, and James S.
Coleman demonstrated the (uncommon) structural conditions for the persistence of democracy
in a bureaucratized trade union. Alvin Gouldner
went so far as to coin a counter concept of the
“iron law of democracy,” which maintains that
oligarchy always generates opposition from the
dominated (see “Metaphysical Pathos and the
Theory of Bureaucracy,” American Political Science
Review, 1955).
Because of its stress on the unassailability of
elites, Michels’s thought is often associated with
a broad theoretical tendency, the so-called theory
of elites.
IRA COHEN
microsociology
– see macrosociology.
micro–macro theory
For several decades, sociological theorists have
been concerned with how to link conceptualizations of face-to-face interpersonal processes to theories about more meso- and macro-level processes.
This concern is often seen as a micro–macro
theory “gap” because no theory in sociology fully
integrates various levels of social organization. If
383
micro–macro theory
we visualize the social world as unfolding at three
basic levels — the micro-level of face-to-face interaction in encounters, the meso-level of structures
revealing a division of labor (groups, communities, organization) and social categories (social
class, ethnicity, gender, age, and the like), and the
macro-level of institutional systems, societies, and
inter-societal relations — theories tend to focus on
one of the three levels. Despite sociology’s concern
about the lack of theoretical integration across
levels of social reality, the problem is not unique
to sociology; all sciences, including the most advanced theoretical science of all, physics, have
been unable to develop a unified theory that explains the operative dynamics at all levels in their
respective universes.
Within sociology, there are several basic strategies for trying to close the micro–macro conceptual gap. At opposite extremes are micro- and
macro-chauvinists who posit the primacy of one
level of social organization. Micro chauvinists view
meso- and macro-reality as ultimately constructed
from microsocial processes, such as symbolic interaction or interaction rituals, aggregated over time
and across space, whereas macro-chauvinists argue
that all micro-processes are constrained by macrosocio-cultural systems. Between these extremes are
a variety of alternative strategies.
One approach involves building “a conceptual
staircase” from conceptions of elementary actions
and micro-level units to conceptualizations of
ever-more-macro processes and structures, and
vice versa. A related approach employs simulation
techniques to posit an elementary dynamic at
both the micro- and macro-levels that, through
iterations, generates, respectively micro- and
macro-outcomes. Still another approach comes
from formal sociology and revolves around conceptualizing common processes that are isomorphic across levels of reality, ignoring the
nature of the unit and, instead, focusing on the
form of social relations among all micro-, meso-,
and macro-units. Still another mediating approach tries to use the logic of deductive theory
to cut across levels of reality by positing axioms
about the behavior of individuals from which all
propositions about meso- and macro-structures
and processes can be deduced. Yet another approach is to invoke the ceteris paribus clause to
bracket out, for purposes of analysis, other levels
of reality in order to focus on the dynamics of one
level, with the presumption that what is
bracketed out can be incorporated later into a
more robust theory. Another approach is to emphasize the embeddedness of social phenomena
384
migration
whereby micro-units are embedded in meso-level
units that, in turn, are embedded in macro-level
units, with the emphasis on how the more inclusive unit constrains the operation of the forces
driving the formation and operation of embedded
units and processes.
All of these approaches have produced interesting theory, but none has fully integrated at a
theoretical level the dynamics operating at the
micro-, meso-, and macro-levels of social organization. Perhaps the most important strategy is to
recognize that social reality unfolds at all three
levels and, while there are isomorphic processes
across all three levels, there are also dynamics
unique to each level. The goal should be, first of
all, to theorize the dynamics of each level and,
then, to see how the values of the variables in
propositions and models explaining one level are
influenced by the values of variables in propositions and models of the other two levels. In this
way, bridging propositions are created that can,
on the one hand, recognize what is unique to
each level of social organization while, on the
other, making the theoretical connections
among levels. In this way, the micro–macro
“gap” can be closed or, at least, reduced.
JONATHAN TURNER
middle class
– see social class.
middle-range theory
– see sociological theory.
migration
A change in permanent residence, often of a year
or more in duration, migration involves a geographical move that crosses a political boundary.
It is common to distinguish two basic forms by
whether the move involves the crossing of an
international boundary from one country to another, that is international migration, or whether
the geographical move involves the crossing of a
political boundary, usually a county, within a
country, that is internal migration.
Several migration concepts require attention:
in-migration (or out-migration) refers to the
number of internal migrants moving to an area
of destination (or from an area of origin); the
analogous concepts for international migration
are immigration and emigration. Return migration is the number of internal migrants who
return to the area of origin; at the international
level the analogous concept is remigration. Net
migration refers to the migration balance of an
migration
area, consisting of the number of in-migrants (or
immigrants) minus the number of out-migrants
(or emigrants); the net balance may be positive
(representing a net population gain to the area) or
negative (representing a net loss) or, conceivably,
zero. Gross migration is the sum total of migration
for an area and comprises the in-migration into the
area and the out-migration from the area. Rates of
migration are developed by dividing the above by
the number of persons in the area at the beginning
of the migration time interval. Migration efficiency
is an area’s net migration divided by its gross migration. A migration stream is a body of migrants
departing from a common area of origin and arriving at a common area of destination during a
specified time interval. A migration counter stream
is the migration stream, smaller in size, going in
the opposite direction during the same interval.
This entry now focuses on internal migration, and
next on international migration.
With respect to internal movement, if the permanent change of residence does not involve
crossing a county boundary, it is referred to as
spatial mobility but not as internal migration.
Thus all migrations are instances of spatial mobility, but not all instances of spatial mobility are
migrations. In the United States during the oneyear period between March 1, 2001, and March 1,
2002, 14.8 percent of the population aged one year
or older changed residences, that is, they were
spatially mobile. Of this nearly 15 percent, fewer
than half – 6.3 percent of the totol population –
were migrants, that is, their changes in residence
involved the crossing of a state boundary. The
reason for making such a distinction is that a
migration is meant to involve a change in one’s
community of residence.
Migration from one area to another has the
effect of decreasing the size of the population in
the area of origin and increasing it in the area of
destination. A migrant is at the same time both an
out-migrant from the area of origin and an inmigrant to the area of destination. With regard
to the growth dynamics of human communities,
internal migration is the single most important of
the demographic processes (fertility, mortality,
and migration). Differences in birth rates and
death rates in communities of the same country
are typically small compared to differences between the communities in migration. Migration
is thus the major method for redistributing the
population within a country.
Among the many theoretical models developed
to explain internal migration are: (1) the effects
of distance; (2) income and migration; (3) the
migration
physical costs of migration; (4) information and
migration; (5) personal characteristics and the decision to migrate; (6) individual expectations and
migration; and (7) community and kinship ties.
The distance model states that long distance
discourages migration because the costs involved
in migration are substantial and closely related
to distance. The income and migration model
argues that income (and job) opportunities provide a better explanation of in-migration than
out-migration; destination characteristics also
help determine the location to which the migrant
will move. The physical costs model suggests that
physical costs influence resource allocation and
migration by influencing the private costs of
migration. According to Michael J. Greenwood,
in “Research on Internal Migration in the United
States: A Survey” (1975, Journal of Economic Literature), the information model emphasizes that
“the availability of information concerning alternative localities plays a prominent role in the
potential migrant’s decision regarding a destination.” The personal characteristics model argues
that personal demographic characteristics (such
as age, gender, education, number of dependents, networks, and race and ethnicity) exert
important influences on the individual’s decision
to migrate. The individual expectations model
assumes that the dynamics of migration decision
making are based on individual expectations
about the advantages and disadvantages of the
home community versus possible alternative destination communities. P. N. Ritchey, in “Explanations of Migration” (1976, Annual Review of
Sociology), notes that the community and kinship
ties model points out that “the presence of relatives and friends is a valued aspect of life [that] . . .
encourages migration by increasing the individual’s potential for adjustment through the availability of aid in location at an alternative area of
residence.”
International migration is the permanent
movement of people from one country to another
for a year or longer time. According to Rainer
Münz, in “Immigration Trends in Major Destination Countries” in the Encyclopedia of Population
(2003), twentieth-century immigrants to most of
the major destination countries may be broadly
grouped into four categories: refugees and
asylum seekers; migrants from former colonies;
economic migrants; and ethnically privileged
migrants.
Refugees and asylum seekers emigrate involuntarily because of persecution, violence, or extreme
deprivation and usually move to a neighboring
385
migration
state. Postcolonial migration began in the 1950s
as a result of decolonization. Indigenous people
moved from former colonial countries to the European countries that had colonized them. Economic
migrants are voluntary migrants motivated by economic aspirations and are likely to move from less
to more developed countries. Some countries, such
as Israel, give priority to migrants with the same
ethnic and religious origins as those of the majority population.
Douglas Massey and his colleagues, in Massey
et al., “Theories of International Migration: A
Review and Appraisal” (1993, Population and Development Review) and “An Evaluation of International
Migration Theory: The North American Case”
(1994), focus on several of the most important
theories of international migration, most of which
focus on the determinants of voluntary migration.
The neoclassical economic model posits that migration results from individual cost–benefit decisions to maximize expected incomes by moving.
Workers are attracted from low-wage countries
with adequate labor, to a high-wage country with
limited labor.
The new economics-of-migration theory challenges some of the hypotheses and assumptions
of neoclassical economics. It argues that migration decisions are made not only by isolated individuals but also by larger units, such as families
and households.
The dual-labor-market theory argues that migration results from the labor demands of industrial societies. International migration is caused
not only by the push factors of the origin countries, but also by the pull factors of the destination countries. Capitalism tends to separate
labor markets into two sectors, the primary
sector that produces jobs with tenure, high pay,
and good benefits and working conditions; and
the secondary sector, with the opposite. Employers turn to immigrants to fill the jobs in the
secondary sector.
World-systems analysis argues that international migration is the natural result of the
globalization of the economy. A large number of
people are released from traditional industries,
such as farming, creating a pool of people ready
to move, both internally and internationally. The
market economy attracts human capital to a relatively small number of global cities, among them
New York, Los Angeles, and Chicago.
Migration network theory focuses on networks:
that is, the interpersonal ties that connect migrants, former migrants, potential migrants,
and nonmigrants in the origin and destination
386
millenarianism
countries. Networks increase the likelihood of
international movement by decreasing migrant
risks and costs and increasing the gains. Networks
make it easier for new migrants to find jobs in
destination countries.
The above theories and others endeavor to account for the causal process of international migration at different levels of analysis, namely, the
individual, the household, the country, and the
world. They are not necessarily incompatible.
DUDLEY L. POSTON
military
– see war.
Mill, John Stuart (1806–1873)
Born in London, Mill was educated by his father,
with the assistance of the celebrated legal and
utilitarian theorist, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832).
By the age of seventeen, he began publishing in
his father and Bentham’s Westminster Review. When
he was twenty, he suffered a nervous breakdown
and, questioning his father and Bentham’s ideas,
he turned to Romantic influences in general and
the work of Samuel Coleridge (1772–1834) in
particular.
In 1843, he published System of Logic in which he
argued that scientific method applied to social as
well as purely natural phenomena. In 1848 he
published Principles of Political Economy and he also
championed worker-owned cooperatives. His work
Utilitarianism, published in 1861, argued that the
pursuit of happiness was to be assessed not merely
by quantity but by quality.
Most influential of all, however, was On Liberty
(1859) – a book influenced by Alexis de Tocqueville’s Democracy in America (1835 and 1840 [trans.
1968]), in which he warned that freedom can be
undermined as much by a “coercive” public opinion as by arbitrary laws. In Considerations of Representative Government (1861), Mill spoke of the
“infirmities” to which universal suffrage is subject, while The Subjection of Women (1869) argued
that women’s “nature” cannot be known until
women live in a world of freedom.
He was elected as a Radical candidate to parliament in 1865, introducing an amendment to the
1867 Reform Act (which he lost) arguing for
women’s suffrage. He criticized Governor Eyre’s
brutality in Jamaica and was defeated in the
1868 general election.
JOHN HOFFMAN
millenarianism
– see religion.
Millett, Kate (1934– )
Mitchell, Juliet (1940– )
Millett, Kate (1934– )
Born in Minnesota, Millett was educated at the
University of Minnesota, Oxford University, and
Columbia University; it was at Columbia that Millett wrote her doctoral thesis, which was to be
published as Sexual Politics in 1970. The book was
an immediate bestseller and is one of the bestknown of the works that became known collectively as second-wave feminism. The thesis of the
book is that western culture (and in particular its
literature) is essentially misogynist; using the fiction of D. H. Lawrence, Henry Miller, Jean Genet,
and Norman Mailer as illustrative, Millett argues
that heterosexuality is used by men to degrade
women. This process of degradation is facilitated
by ideologies of romantic love and the patriarchal
structure of the nuclear family.
Millett’s success with Sexual Politics has been
followed by a number of other works: The Prostitution Papers (1973), Flying (1974), and Sita (1977). The
last two works were largely autobiographical and
trace the impact on Millett both of her considerable fame and of her shift in sexual identity,
from that of the wife of the Japanese sculptor
Fumio Yoshimura to the lover of the woman who
is the subject of Sita. The pressures and demands of
fame resulted in the mental breakdown which
became the subject of Millett’s The Loony Bin Trip
(1990), a searing account of time spent in institutions for the mentally ill. Millett continues to write
and speak on feminist issues and her work provides
a radical corrective to some of the more liberal
politics of feminism in the United States. Millett
has not been afraid to confront issues of gender,
poverty, and powerlessness, while her own work
contains much on the confrontational sexual politics which she has so forcefully contested.
MARY EVANS
Mills, C. Wright (1916–1962)
One of the most influential sociologists of the twentieth century, Mills is perhaps best known for his
trilogy on the changing character of political power
in the United States. In the three books, The New
Men of Power (1948) about the labor movement,
White Collar (1951) about intellectuals and the
middle classes, and The Power Elite (1956) about the
convergence of interests among the military, big
business, and the government, Mills developed one
of the most sustained critiques of what he and
others came to call mass society. In attempting to
explain the new sort of society that had emerged in
the period after World War II, Mills also provided
important sources of inspiration for the student
movement of the 1960s.
Mills was a self-proclaimed outsider, an “academic outlaw” in the postwar United States, and
throughout his life he was critical of what he saw
as the subservience of his fellow sociologists to
those in power.
Mills grew up in Texas, and wrote a doctoral
thesis in sociology on pragmatism at the University of Wisconsin. He was Professor of Sociology at
Columbia University in New York, and, in addition
to his academic work, he wrote articles for such
publications as the Nation, Dissent, and Partisan
Review. Mills was known for having a colorful personality, and took an active part in the political
debates of his times, writing popular books about
the Cold War and the arms race (The Causes of World
War Three, 1958), and the Cuban Revolution (Listen
Yankee, 1960) which he strongly supported, much
to the disapproval of his academic colleagues.
Throughout his short life – he died in 1962 at the
age of forty-six – Mills sought to combine indigenous American social theory, deriving from populism and pragmatism, with the theories of Karl
Marx and Max Weber. In addition to his own
writings, he edited anthologies on Marxism (The
Marxists, 1962) and Max Weber (From Max Weber:
Essays in Sociology, coedited with H. H. Gerth, 1946).
He presented his own approach to sociology in a
short volume, entitled The Sociological Imagination
(1959), which was based on lectures that he had
given in Europe. In that book, he outlined his
approach to sociological research, distinguishing
himself from what he termed grand theory, on
the one hand, and “abstracted empiricism,” on
the other. He associated the one style with the
work of Talcott Parsons, and the other with the
interest in quantitative methods that was becoming the dominant form of sociological research in
his day. For Mills, sociology was best seen as a kind
of “intellectual craftsmanship,” and the sociological imagination that he tried to foster was
meant to help people become conscious of their
place in history, as well as the social nature of the
problems that they faced. He wrote that such an
approach was not “ascendant” at the time, but, in
the intervening years, Mills has continued to serve
as a model for politically engaged and socially
committed sociology.
ANDREW JAMISON
minority rights
– see rights.
Mitchell, Juliet (1940– )
Born in New Zealand, Mitchell has been a widely
influential writer who is responsible for having
387
mobilization
reclaimed Sigmund Freud for feminism and for
enabling feminism to use the insights of psychoanalysis to illuminate the understanding of the
social and, more particularly, the symbolic world.
A long-time student of Marxism, Mitchell in 1971
published Woman’s Estate, which used the work
of Friedrich Engels to argue that women, across
cultures and social classes, were – as Engels had
suggested – the proletariat of the world. But it was
Psychoanalysis and Feminism (1974) which made a
lasting contribution to the study of gender; Mitchell’s subtle and nuanced reading showed the possibilities of Freud’s ideas about the instability
of gender and the dynamics of the formation of
gender identity. Contrary to previous readings
of Freud (for example, those of Kate Millett), which
had assumed that Freud took a rigid view of
gender divisions, Mitchell showed that Freud
understood the acquisition of gender identity as
a fluid and always uncertain process. Mitchell’s
work enabled later feminists to use psychoanalysis as a way of exploring literature and the arts:
Mitchell’s understanding of the term woman,
like Freud’s, was of a possible, rather than a fixed,
state.
Since the publication of Psychoanalysis and
Feminism, Mitchell has continued to work on the
politics of feminism (Women: The Longest Revolution,
1984) and on the social pressures that shape ideas
about gender (Mad Men and Medusas, 2000). In
all her work, Mitchell has maintained a recognition of the divisions of class, as much as of gender,
in the social world, and a commitment to a
politics of radical and more egalitarian social
transformation.
MARY EVANS
mobilization
– see collective behavior.
mode of production
– see Karl Marx.
modeling
In its general sense, a model is an attempt to
depict or describe in a dynamic manner a social
reality, process, or institution. At this general
level, a model is synonymous with a theory.
A good model should be essential – in that it
covers the important characteristics and/or processes of that which it is attempting to model –
and simple – the model should be less complex
and easier to comprehend than the reality itself.
What is essential will depend upon the purpose
of the model; for instance, an econometric model
that attempts to depict the workings of a nation’s
388
modeling
economy will highlight features and processes
quite different from a model of the diffusion of
popular culture fads through the same society.
The use of ideal types – the conceptualizations
of social phenomena in their abstract or pure
(hence ideal) form which then form a base against
which to compare the actual phenomena – can be
considered as a form of essentialist modeling.
Models imply heuristic prediction and it is for
this reason that their attempts to depict must be
dynamic rather than static explanations. The ultimate test of a model is not how well it describes
the present or the past, but rather how well it is
capable of providing reliable predictions of its
future as parameters change.
Regarding types, models may either be opaque
or transparent. An opaque model makes no attempt to duplicate the actual processes that occur
during the interim phases between input and
result. In effect, the true interim processes are
seen as a black box and the estimation procedures
of the model do not necessarily in any way resemble what may be occurring in actuality within the
box. All that is required for a successful opaque
model is that it produces reliable predictions (outputs) for any given change in parameters (inputs)
that accurately mimic what occurs in reality. In
contrast, transparent models do attempt to depict
internal interim phases. In this latter case, the
workings of the model itself may be of more interest than the eventual outcomes that it predicts.
Statistical or multivariate causal modeling is a
more specific instance of modeling in which
the principles of modeling are applied to quantitative data. All multivariate statistical models seek
to summarize information from a group of individual cases (typically the “cases” are individuals
responding to a large sample survey) into an equation or a set of predictive equations. Usually the
simplification is taken further by attempting to
eliminate redundant measures of characteristics
(“variables”) and redundant associations between
variables. Some statistical modeling techniques
(“measurement models”) go even further by
positing the hypothetical existence of ideal-type
variables that are essential representations of concepts rather than actual measured variables. The
success of the application of a statistical modeling
technique can be measured by the amount of
variance it explains in its solution.
Statistical models are “opaque” models since
they are using abstract mathematical formulas
to depict qualitatively different social processes.
However, there are aspects of “transparency,” in
that analysts can: observe the dynamic shifting of
modeling
coefficient estimates as variables are introduced;
evaluate conceptual constructs by the combinations of variables included in a model; discover
unanticipated complex patterns of multiple causality through identifying statistical interactions
between two or more variables; and construct
more elaborate models by stringing a number of
equations together.
An early use of multivariate techniques in sociology that explicitly claimed to be a model was the
use of path analysis by Otis Dudley Duncan and
Peter M. Blau to introduce the “status-attainment”
model of social mobility in the United States (The
American Occupational Structure, 1967). Working with
data from a large-sample survey of United States
men, Blau and Duncan put together the display of
results of a series of regression equations into a
single figure, a “path diagram.” Their basic diagram is an attempt to depict the process of intergenerational (inheritance) and intragenerational
(career) social mobility in the United States. In it,
an index of current occupational position (indexed
by a scale of status) is seen as being driven by point
of entry into the labor market (indexed by “first
job”), educational attainment (indexed by “years of
schooling”), and social origin (indexed by “father’s
job” and “father’s educational attainment”).
The original status-attainment model has
prompted four decades of subsequent work and
controversy about its validity around issues such
as its exclusion of women, the basic conceptualization of its core values, and its implicit stance on
social stratification. The salient point here, however, is that it displays the characteristics of a
multivariate causal model: a vastly complicated
process of social mobility is distilled down into a
set of essential relationships. Furthermore, the
construction of the model displays dynamic characteristics since it is possible to trace indirect
causal effects along the “paths” of coefficients in
the model (for example, education may have a
direct effect on current occupational position
but also could have an indirect effect since education can affect level of “first job,” which in turn
affects current occupation). In addition, a change
in a parameter, such as increasing the level of
education attained, would result in a change in
an “output” estimate: for example, the predicted
level of “first job” would be higher.
The number of multivariate statistical techniques is legion, including: (1) analysis of variance
techniques; (2) techniques of regression analysis
(general linear analysis of parametric data;
logistic regression techniques where the dependent variable is a quality, a nominal category;
modernity
multilevel modeling where the independent
variables exist on at least two levels of aggregation, such as individual data plus group, area, and/
or organizational data) that have in common the
prediction of the values of a dependent variable
based upon the values of one or more independent predictor variables; (3) techniques of data reduction, such as factor analysis in which the
values of a number of observed variables are assumed to reflect the presence of a smaller number
of unobserved “essential” variables; (4) “measurement models” that are a combination of prediction of regression with data reduction; and (5) loglinear analysis techniques for the multivariate
modeling of relationships between non-parametric data. Like modeling in general, all of these
multivariate techniques have simplification and
essentialism in common.
BERNADETTE HAYES AND ROBERT MILLER
model(s)
– see modeling.
modernity
Modernity is a civilizational epoch in the same
sense as Greco-Roman antiquity. Though modernity originated in western Europe and North America over two centuries ago, today it extends to
cosmopolitan centers around the globe and its
consequences affect all but the most isolated communities in every country on earth. Modernity,
like all epochs, includes distinctive forms of economic and political organization, characteristic
cultural institutions, and persistent tensions between antithetical civilizational trends. It is also
an epoch that generates a distinctive set of ambivalent reactions. A number of these tensions
and ambivalent reactions will be discussed in
itemized fashion in later sections of this entry.
Social theory as we know it today developed
when intellectuals began trying to make sense of
modernity as it matured during the nineteenth
century. However, early modern theorists disagreed on how modernity should be defined, and
many of these disagreements have continued in
subsequent generations, albeit with numerous
additions and revisions. The parameters of modernity can be grasped by noting the dynamic
forces that various early modern theorists maintained were the prime movers of the history of
modernity. For Adam Smith (1723–90) and Karl
Marx, capitalism in the form of markets (Smith)
or profit-oriented production (Marx) was the mainspring of modern social life. Henri Saint-Simon
and Auguste Comte maintained that scientific
389
modernity
knowledge and technology ultimately would
direct modernity in a rational, orderly manner.
Alexis de Tocqueville stressed the transition from
aristocratic political organizations and the cultural
values of aristocratic elites to representative democratic institutions and a culture based upon egalitarian values. Émile Durkheim stressed the modern
culture of individualism and the division of labor.
Until quite recently (see especially Michael Mann’s
The Sources of Social Power: Volume I, 1986, and Volume
II, 1996), social theorists had dealt with the intensively developed and extensively organized nationstate as a central feature of modernity only obliquely (see especially the works of Max Weber).
However, most contemporary theorists consider
the nation-state, including its military forces,
social services bureaucracies, judicial system, educational systems, and sources of revenue, as yet
another dynamic force of modernity.
Each of these dynamic forces contributes to modernity’s most obvious defining trait: namely its endless bouts of disruptive change. In fact, it can be said
without hyperbole that modernity is the most
unstable epoch that humanity has ever known.
The radical mutability of modernity is most easily
understood against the backdrop of premodern cultures and civilizations, most of which did not welcome dramatic change. Prior to modernity, most
rulers discouraged all but the most pragmatic
changes in the societies they controlled. Abrupt
change, with its unforeseeable results, might
threaten their dominion. (The conduct of wars
and the construction of empires were notable exceptions in this regard.) Rulers sought the stabilizing support of orthodox religions and they also
encouraged stable customs and traditions that
made commoners as suspicious of change as were
the rulers themselves. Only incremental changes
were quietly absorbed into everyday life.
Modernity makes the sharpest possible break
with the propensity for stasis in premodern social
epochs. Each of the dynamic forces of modernity,
capitalism, scientific technology, the nation-state,
and the culture of individualism not only pushed
through the cake of custom during the historical
transition to modernity, but also proceeded to
foster change after change so that the social circumstances of each generation differed from
those of its predecessors.
Intellectuals have been profoundly impressed
by the sharp contrast between the tradition-bound
cultures of the past and the ever-changing social
conditions of modernity. For example, Marshall
Berman entitled his influential commentary on
modern cultural ways of life All That Is Solid Melts
390
modernity
into Air (1982), echoing the powerful closing trope
of a passage from Marx and Friedrich Engels, The
Communist Manifesto (1848), that evokes the agitation and disruption caused by capitalism and, by
extension, modernity at large. Agitation and disruption were on the minds of other early modern
thinkers as well. In Democracy in America (1835
[trans. 1966], p. 298), de Tocqueville correctly foresaw that the rise of democratic political institutions would generate chronic instability in which
governmental regimes and even basic principles
of government would recurrently come and go
without relief. In his well-known essay, “The
Metropolis and Mental Life” (1903 [trans. 1971]),
Georg Simmel went so far as to propose that
human beings were incapable of taking in all of
the rapidly changing experiences they encountered in a typical urban environment. To fend off
excessive stimulation, individuals were forced to
distance themselves psychologically from many of
the people they encountered and the events they
observed.
Until the last decades of the twentieth century,
social theorists were divided on a key question
about the history of modernity: does modernity
have a historical teleology with a foreseeable destination, a terminus ad quem? The question itself is
thoroughly modern. No other epoch in any civilization has ever been as unsettled by what the
future might hold. If social thinkers knew where
modernity was headed and if they knew the mechanisms that were propelling it in this direction,
then they could recommend rational steps to
hasten the day when the best possible organization of society would finally emerge. Smith, Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Comte, Marx, Herbert
Spencer, Durkheim, and Talcott Parsons all did
their best to discern systematic trajectories in
the history of modernity. However, even in the
nineteenth century, de Tocqueville and Weber
maintained that the history of modernity rarely
runs true to a teleological course for very long. By
the late twentieth century, most social theorists
had come around to the open-ended historical
view that modernity has no ultimate destination.
The disintegration of the Soviet Union marked
a theoretical watershed in this regard, since
very few social scientists foresaw these world-historical events. But, in retrospect, no theorist of
modernity foresaw the onset or the profound consequences of two world wars, multiple instances
of genocide, the rapid collapse of colonial rule in
the Third World, and the transformative power of
information processing and global communications technologies.
modernity
No single force is responsible for the relentlessness of modern social change. Capitalism is subject to cycles of expansion and contraction in all
of its markets from investments and finance to job
markets and markets for consumer goods. Equally
important, capitalism endlessly seeks to increase
profitable operations and reduce costs, a trait that
leads to swift transitions between geographical
locales of operation, constant searches for cheaper
sources of labor, and a host of other propensities
to change as well.
Modern scientific technology is a vast engine of
unpredictable change. Members of modern societies in the nineteenth century had to adjust to
the steam engine, the industrial factory, the railroad, the telegraph, and electrical power. In the
first half of the twentieth century, people had to
adjust to the mechanized assembly line, automobiles, movies, radio, and telephones. And today
we are adjusting to computerized information
processing, global communication via satellites
and the worldwide web, and new forms of
biotechnology that have the potential in the
not-too-distant future to change the definition
of human life itself.
Modern states are engines of change as well.
From global and regional wars fought with mechanical weapons of previously unimagined power,
to more benign changes such as state-run schools
and social health and welfare institutions, the
modern state recurrently transforms the social
circumstances in which its citizens live. Even
modern culture, with its multivalent emphases
on the rights, prerogatives, and opportunities
that encourage individuals to pursue changes for
the better in their own lives, creates expectations
that the future will not be the same as the past.
Not only is it impossible to foresee where the
open-ended history of modernity will lead, it is
also impossible to say when modernity began. If
we again focus independently on each of modernity’s dynamic forces, the exception to the rule is
the modern state, which many historians believe
emerged in its distinctively modern (albeit not
very democratic) form in Otto von Bismarck’s
(1815–98) Germany after 1870. Beyond this there
is little consensus on when any of the principal
forces of modernity began. Consider modern capitalism. Some elements of capitalism, such as
long-distance trade and short-term profit-seeking
investments, were already on the scene before
1500. According to Weber in The Protestant Ethic
and the Spirit of Capitalism (1905 [trans. 2002]),
the cultural ethos of the profit-oriented entrepreneur first evolved during the seventeenth and
modernity
eighteenth centuries. However, capitalism as the
primary system for the provision of material
goods in everyday life did not fully supplant local
agrarian production until sometime after 1750,
and then only in the most advanced cosmopolitan
centers of Europe and North America.
Next, consider technology. According to Lewis
Mumford (1895–1985) in Technics and Civilization
(1934), the development of the modern machine
predates the industrial revolution of the late nineteenth century by at least 700 years. But modern
machinery entered the factories of western
Europe only during the nineteenth century, and
only during the period from 1880 to 1920 did
modern technology reach into the households
and everyday lives of modern populations at large.
The origin of the culture of modern individualism is difficult to date as well. According to Jacob
Burckhardt (1818–97) in The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy (1860 [trans. 1954]), the humanistic appreciation of the power and the beauty of
the individual began in the time of Michelangelo
(1475–1556). But the belief in the equality and
liberal rights of human beings as citizens moved
from the pages of political philosophy to the constitutions of governments only following the
American Revolution of 1776, and even today
these values are still partially ideals rather than
realities. The idea that every individual should be
entitled to realize her or his own potentials and
choose her or his own lifestyle is more recent still.
Even in the 1950s cultural critics such as David
Riesman worried about the degree to which
modern, middle-class individuals conformed too
closely to homogenizing cultural norms. It is
only in the current generation that theorists
such as Anthony Giddens and Ulrich Beck highlighted new trends towards alternative lifestyles
and self-identity that carry the culture of individualism into how citizens of modernity pursue their
personal lives.
One final point on the history of modernity.
While it is true that modernity is driven by multiple engines of social change, what makes the
history so difficult to predict is that all of these
forces interact with one another in complex ways.
For example, it is easy to see that capitalists were
already investing in potentially profitable developments in industrial technology as far back as
the late eighteenth century. But technology has
produced surprises to which capitalists have had
to adjust as well. This is no more evident than
in the transformative effects of modern information and communications technology which have
dramatically accelerated everything from the
391
modernity
intensity of economic competition, to the rapid
intensification of global markets and networks of
production, to new means of data gathering and
analysis that enable sophisticated firms to market
their wares in different forms to targeted consumer groups in every corner of the world. Equally
complicated interactions are found between capitalist industries and nation-states. On the one
hand, nation-states depend upon a prosperous
capitalist economy for their economic well-being.
Therefore they must adapt and adjust to changing
commercial and industrial conditions. However,
when states are engaged in warfare, capitalist
firms are compelled to support the war effort
even if this reduces their profitability. Nationstates also adjust their operations to new technologies as well. However, states also sponsor a
great deal of technological innovation. This is especially true with regard to the military. Indeed,
things as various as computers and global satellites were promoted and perfected to suit military
needs.
Modernity as an epoch may have no determinate starting point nor a historical destiny, nor
even a predictable historical trajectory, but if the
epoch at large lacks a teleological pattern, modernity has generated a number of less enveloping
developmental trends. Some of these trends
emerge in many institutional contexts; others
are confined to a specific institutional order. But
the most important trends almost inevitably encounter paradoxical opposition. Paradoxical opposition refers here to trends and countertrends
that are each evident in the fabric of modernity,
yet radically inconsistent with one another.
Democratic ideals such as equality, liberty, and
impartiality in the public sphere, and the right to
privacy in personal life, are modern values.
Though never fully realized, they are proclaimed
in the constitutions of most modern states and
judicial levers that social movements use for
social change. If modernity has a creed, it is
grounded in what Durkheim terms the cult of
the dignity of the individual, where human dignity is the lowest common denominator for all of
the values. But the paradox is that, though these
values apply universally as ideals, state policies
determine to whom they apply. All modern states
leave some populations unprotected. Some exclusions do minimal harm. But many render certain
groups (for example, racial and ethnic minorities,
immigrants, gays and lesbians) vulnerable to damaging discrimination and harsh stigmatization.
Even worse, states sometimes pursue barbaric policies to punish and slaughter peoples they leave
392
modernity
unprotected. Modern states have been responsible
for the worst genocides in history. Michael Mann,
in a controversial argument in his Dark Side of
Democracy (2005), argues that strong modern
states, mainly in the northern hemisphere, may
now be less inclined to genocide than weak states
south of the equator. Even if this speculation
proves true, modern states are still capable of
ruthless war, systematic torture, and callous oppression of minority groups. Paradoxically, the
only institution that can pursue democratic ideals
can sometimes cynically forsake or ignore them
with cruel, inhumane results.
Weber coined the phrase “disenchantment of
the world,” by which he meant the replacement
of belief in other-worldly forces such as the will of
God that once were held to govern the world by
impersonal scientific laws and formal rationality
that leave no room, at least in public life, for
unfathomable forces of any kind. Disenchantment
need not imply an end to religious faith in private
life, but it does signify the end of religious faith as
a basis for modern forms of jurisprudence, legitimate government, economic enterprise, and
knowledge of the natural world. The accent placed
on spirituality in public life in many premodern
societies disappears.
As demonstrated by recurrent waves of religious
fundamentalism in western societies, even a trend
as broad and seemingly ineluctable as disenchantment cannot sweep through modernity without
encountering paradoxical opposition. Such waves
are nothing new. Papalist political and cultural
movements have been a recurrent feature in reaction to the rise of modernity in Spain and France,
and waves of Protestant fundamentalism have opposed the disenchantment of public life in the
United States periodically since its origin. Fascist
ideologies (including Hitler’s Nazi ideology) stem
from passionate sacralization of secular symbols
(for example, the motherland, ethnic purity) in
opposition to the disenchantments of modernity
as well. Less inflammatory civil religions and nationalism may serve as vehicles for reactions to
disenchantment as well.
Material inequalities are not unique to modernity; however, as Karl Marx observed, material inequality takes a unique form in capitalism. The
bourgeoisie and the managerial classes are not
just rich, as were aristocracies in the past: these
classes systematically prosper, their wealth
expands. Classes in poverty lack structural possibilities to prosper. Though some individuals may
increase their wealth, the entire class cannot
escape in this way. Like all elements of capitalism,
modernity
today poverty must be understood globally. Large
populations of the desperately poor reside in every
Third World conurbation. Meanwhile, local and
global capitalist enterprises generate prosperity
for the upper classes.
In The Great Transformation (1944), Karl Polanyi
identifies a historical cycle in the relations between capitalism and the state that can be generalized as one of the great paradoxes of modernity.
Capitalism as an economic system prefers unregulated markets for wage-labor, which generally
allow capitalists to pay the lowest possible wages
and thereby increase their profitability. However,
when wages sink too far (and/or the cost of living
rises), workers mount political movements (often
in alliance with other groups) to enlist the state in
protecting them from impoverishment. States
often respond with extensive welfare services for
the economically disadvantaged. This constitutes
the first phase of Polanyi’s double movement. The
second phase develops on two fronts: on the one
hand, workers ultimately become excessively reliant on state aid and withdraw from the labor
markets. On the other hand, states reach certain
practical limits to the amount of funds they can
spend on social services to the poor. In a very
simplified sense, over time the double movement
operates like a pendulum pushing towards free
labor markets until a reaction sets in and the
pendulum moves back towards the protective policies of the state, and then a counterreaction sets
in and the pendulum begins to swing back the
other way. Though Keynesian policies of state
regulation seemed to moderate the double movement for a period after World War II, reactions set
in against the welfare state in the mid-1980s, and
the “double movement” once more asserted itself.
Consider a paradox of modern development that
was already evident 100 years ago. On the one hand,
the increasing division of labor in capitalist production and in bureaucratized organizations of all
kinds was dividing labor into a vast array of highly
specialized tasks and establishing deep divisions
between public and private life. But counterposed
to these trends towards differentiation, there were
also trends towards centralization, the most obvious being the centripetal forces that drew (and still
draw) people from the countryside into densely
populated cities and conurbations.
The same paradox is evident on a global scale.
On the one hand, capitalism, both historically and
in recent times, has established regional sectors of
global inequality based upon what Immanuel Wallerstein terms the principle of unequal exchange.
There are shifting global divisions based upon
modernity
military and diplomatic alliances as well. Moreover, as peoples come into closer contact with
one another around the globe, certain cultural
differences (for example between China and the
West) loom larger than they did in premodern
times. Yet there is no denying that modern modes
of communication and transportation, from the
telephone and the steamship to data transmission
by global satellites and transportation by jet aircraft and high-speed pipelines and ships, increase
both the velocity and intensity of global interaction that enable durable economic and political
networks to concentrate the control of many resources on a global scale.
In the early days of the modern era, technology
was often welcomed as an unalloyed good. No one
regards technology as thoroughly evil today. Very
few critics would completely eliminate industrial
production or modern medicine. But technology
now seems a two-edged sword. Pollution, the most
obvious byproduct of technology, threatens our
health. Global warming is changing our climate
with as yet unforeseeable consequences. And it is
already evident that biotechnology will change
the very meaning of life during the twenty-first
century. But there is more. Technology facilitates
unprecedented forms of total war in which the
object is to destroy civilian populations. Moreover,
though genocide is possible without technology,
the Nazis demonstrated the horror of genocide by
industrial means. Technology is simply a means to
make tools, and, as with all tools, the virtues and
vices of technology depend upon how it is used.
From Marx’s notion of the alienation of the
proletariat to Jürgen Habermas’s writings on the
excessive colonization of cultural life-worlds by
impersonal and lifeless social systems, social theorists have been sharp, sometimes hostile, critics
of the inequalities, injustices, and oppressive conditions and consequences of modernity. Modernity is certainly open to criticism on many counts,
from capitalism’s exploitation of labor to the
practice of total war, where the object is not to
defeat a rival military force but to destroy the
homeland of the enemy by lethal technological
means. Yet even the most comprehensive and
justified criticism of modernity contains a certain degree of ambivalence. Modernity, as previously said, is easily the most comfortable set of
material circumstances human beings have ever
established for themselves. Where is the Luddite
who would forfeit central heating in the winter
or air conditioning when the temperature is
high? Modernity has also spawned a portfolio of
political and cultural values such as the equality
393
modernity
and rights of individuals, and the notion of social
justice to which even the most acerbic critics of
modernity subscribe, even as they use these
values to highlight modernity’s shortcomings
and its hypocrisies.
As Durkheim observed, the moral ideals of modernity treat the rights and prerogatives of individuals as sacred. Each of us should possess these
rights to an equal extent. But these ideals are
contradicted by some very deep-seated modern
realities. Capitalism intrinsically generates vast
inequalities between the rich and the poor,
whether it is in the British slums Dickens described
in nineteenth-century England or the slums found
in every Third World conurbation today. Merely
noting the vast difference between average age of
death among modernity’s rich and poor alerts us to
how dramatic these inequalities are. But, as Pierre
Bourdieu observes, modernity also includes many
forms of cultural inequality that are insidious
insofar as people unselfconsciously reproduce
their habitus, even though in doing so they may
put themselves at a cultural disadvantage vis-à-vis
dominant groups. Some prominent inequalities
between women and men, racial and ethnic minority groups, and minority groups based upon
sexual differences can be understood in this way.
But critics of these inequalities have had a measure of success. From socialist movements a century ago to women’s movements today, periodic
rebellions against inequality are as modern as the
forms of inequality to which they object.
Social estrangement has been a recurrent
theme in social theory. Marx’s notion of alienation refers both to the loss of control over labor
by workers and to the estrangement of workers
from their material relations with fellow workers
and members of their community. In Suicide (1897
[trans. 1951]), Durkheim conceived estrangement
in two forms: anomie, which is the sense of profound confusion brought about by the social disruptions to which modernity is prone, and egoism,
an excessively selfish, utilitarian form of individualism which is the unappealing underside of the
moral individualism of which Durkheim approved.
Georg Lukács saw modernity in Kafkaesque terms
as subject to reification, that is, the sense that we
live a social world with hard realities that seem
too vast and powerful to change. Habermas’s
notion of the colonization of the life-world
speaks to estrangement in the sense that the instrumental policies of capitalism and the modern
state invade areas of public culture and private
life, suppressing meaningful ties of social integration in favor of calculations of organizational
394
modernization
advantages and efficiencies. (A good example is
the bureaucratization of universities and schools.)
Though each of these notions of estrangement
makes a specific point, all of them underscore
one of modernity’s enduring problems, the inability of modern civilization to generate groups to
replace the local communities that provided cultural meaning, moral solidarity, and spiritual assurance in premodern forms of social life. There is
no single great impediment to the maintenance
of communal ways of life in modernity. Capitalism,
the bureaucratized social policies of the state,
the impersonality of scientific technology, and
modern individualistic culture – each adds its
own share of obstacles in this regard. However,
estrangement is not an all-or-nothing matter.
Community groups, stable intimate relationships
and personal friendships, and close extended families remain a part of the modern social scene. But,
then, there is no denying that feelings of powerlessness, meaninglessness, loneliness, and insecurity are common experiences in modern social
life. And to the extent that these feelings are found,
the critics of estrangement in modernity are right.
Ironically, all of these complaints hinge on
modern values. Other epochs had different complaints.
IRA COHEN
modernization
As the United States emerged as the world’s hegemonic power after World War II, the structural–
functionalist modernization paradigm became
the dominant perspective in United States sociology and world social science. Elaborated by
Harvard’s Talcott Parsons, the lead figure in
American sociology, the modernization paradigm
saw societies as a relatively stable set of interrelated parts changing along similar lines, from
traditional agricultural to modern industrial societies, part of a global pattern. The models for this
transition from developing to developed societies
were the industrialized states of western Europe
and their settler offshoots in Australia, Canada,
New Zealand, and the United States, along with
countries such as Japan. Poor underdeveloped
traditional societies were believed to be in the
earlier phases of this transition, having yet to go
through the modernization process. Here, the
weight of traditional cultural beliefs and practices
supposedly inhibited the industrialization, differentiation, and specialization of occupational roles
necessary for success. Parsons aimed to provide a
holistic analysis of this process, discussing the
host of structural requirements necessary for
modernization
the orderly functioning of the social system, so as
to promote their diffusion worldwide.
Nils Gilman’s important book, Mandarins of the
Future: Modernization Theory in Cold War America
(2003), analyzes how United States social scientists
and policymakers converged on this model in the
context of American superpower competition
against the Soviet Union, including in the struggle
for the hearts and minds of those in the Third
World. Third World states were seen as being
held back by traditional beliefs and cultural practices, thought to be barriers inhibiting the steps
required for successful growth.
Perhaps the classic work of modernization or
development theory and its vision of elite-guided
democracy was economist Walt W. Rostow’s The
Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-Communist Manifesto
(1961). Rostow argued that all countries could
pass through these stages to achieve high mass
consumption as had the United States. Rostow, a
former Rhodes Scholar, became an important
member of a host of United States presidential
administrations, playing a significant role in planning the Vietnam War as part of the group
of men David Halberstram called The Best and the
Brightest (1993), eventually becoming President
Johnson’s National Security Council adviser. As
critics pointed out, many social scientists working
within the modernization framework, from
Rostow to Parsons to Samuel Huntington, saw
their task not just to analyze reality but to try
and shape it to the benefit of the capitalist
nation-states of which they were a part. In the
context of the Vietnam War, such dual roles raised
many questions about the objectivity of social
scientists, and became an important part of the
critique of modernization theory.
While the modernization perspective dominated United States and world social science up
until the 1960s, the tumult of this period, from
civil rights through the anti-war movement, to the
related worldwide revolts of 1968, ushered in a
sharp critique of this view and the forwarding of
radically different perspectives. Forming an influential critique here were the various brands of
international political economy, including worldsystems analysis formulated by Immanuel Wallerstein and followers, which borrowed from Third
World radicalism and a host of critical perspectives in world social science. Wallerstein and
others traced the rise of the modernization paradigm to the shift from biological to cultural
racism, not surprisingly given the horrors of the
Holocaust, the political context of the civil rights
movement, and the progress of decolonization.
modernization
Rather than simply arguing for the racial inferiority of the colonized as during the heyday of colonialism, now Third World backwardness was
seen instead as the result of cultural differences
and traditions, views critiqued most recently in
Jared Diamond’s landmark Guns, Germs and Steel
(1999). This culture of poverty argument also saw
cultural traditions as the cause of minority poverty in the advanced core states. While modernization was thus seen as an ideological formulation
designed to uphold power and inequality, Wallerstein nonetheless recognized that there were
many liberal scholars honestly concerned with
the plight of world poverty and seeking to add
knowledge that could aid in its overcoming. That
being said, it was argued, the modernization view
seriously distorted the actual history of the capitalist world-system, within which development
and underdevelopment were part of a single historical process, whereby the minority in powerful
core states benefited from the exploitation of
the great majority in the periphery, the semiperiphery and the internal peripheries of the core.
There were many critical blows to the paradigm
which represented the dominant consensus in
sociology and the social sciences. In particular,
profound criticisms of the underside of modernization came from the Frankfurt School of critical
theory – Walter Benjamin, Theodor Wiesengrund
Adorno, Max Horkheimer, and Jürgen Habermas –
and from Zygmunt Bauman’s Modernity and the
Holocaust (1989). There were also periods of revival,
expressed in the 1980s and 1990s, as in Francis
Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man
(1992). Today, modernization theory appears to
be making something of a comeback, this time
not so much by analyzing national backwardness,
but in the clash-of-civilizations discourse.
Increasingly, in the aftermath of the September
11, 2001, terrorist attacks, United States scholars
such as Bernard Lewis have sought to explain the
failure to modernize of Islamic civilizations in
ways that provided ideological support to the
Anglo-American argument that it is necessary to
bring democracy to the Islamic world, if necessary
through force, as with the United States’ and
United Kingdom’s retrospective justification of
the 2003 invasion of Iraq and subsequent military
occupation. Yet in spite of the nominal transfer
of sovereignty and elections, the revelations of
United States torture in Iraq and elsewhere have
undermined American claims of promoting freedom and modernization. Sociologists such as Paul
Lubeck criticized this new modernization approach, relating the decline of Islamic civilization
395
money
and its contemporary resurgence as a form of
ethno-national political mobilization to culture
and issues of global wealth and power. The rise
and demise of modernization theory formed a
critical part of the changing structures of knowledge in what observers have called “the American
Century,” and thus in the twenty-first century the
modernization project will likely be subject to an
increasingly fierce debate.
THOMAS REIFER
money
As a medium of exchange, money has been a pivotal social technology in the development of
human societies. With numbers and writing,
money was a basis for the world’s first large-scale
complex societies in the ancient Near East during
the third millennium BC. (Note that these societies did not possess coinage, but used an abstract
money notation – money of account – for making
budgetary calculations and expressing prices and
debts in monetary value.) Today, globalization is
driven by the electronic transfer of money across
national boundaries and by the rapid changes in
the value of money wrought in the foreign exchange markets.
According to the familiar economic textbook
list, money performs the following crucially important functions: medium of exchange, means of
unilateral payment (settlement), store of value,
and money of account (measure of value). (Note
that these functions describe, but do not explain,
the origins and existence of money.) A medium of
exchange makes possible the operation of the division of labor and the subsequent exchange of
products in markets of large-scale impersonal
multilateral exchange. Second, money is a store
of value – that is, of abstract purchasing power.
It enables decisions to be postponed, revised, reactivated, or canceled. In his An lnquiry into the
Meaning of Money, John Buchan (1997) defined it
as “frozen desire.” Third, as Max Weber and John
Maynard Keynes emphasized, money’s most important attribute, upon which the others are
based, is as a measure of value. The abstract notation of money of account (pounds and pence,
dollars and cents) enables the calculation of
prices, costs, benefits, debts and credits, profits
and losses – that is to say, the rationalization of
economic life. However, money has a dual nature.
This useful social technology expands society’s
capability, or infrastructural power; but it can be
appropriated by particular interests and used as
their despotic power. The power of money is not
simply found in the form of amassed wealth; but
also in the power to control the actual production
396
money
of money in mints and banks. Today, for example,
the interplay between central banks’ interest-rate
decisions and the money markets’ reactions to
them in their pricing of currencies and every kind
of financial asset is one of the most important
institutional axes of modern capitalism.
Two problems have beset the sociological analysis of money, which has remained relatively
underdeveloped. First, there is considerable disagreement about the nature of money between
and within the different social sciences. Second,
sociology has taken money’s existence for granted
and, rather, has focused on its social and cultural
consequences, especially as an expression of the
“disembedded” economic relations of “modernity,” as in Anthony Giddens, The Consequences of
Modernity (1990). With some exceptions – for
example, Geoffrey Ingham, The Nature of Money
(2004) – modern sociology mistakenly assumed
that economics offered an adequate explanation
of money’s existence. Two developments account
for this situation: the division of intellectual
labor in the social sciences after the Methodenstreit
during the late nineteenth and early twentieth
centuries, in which money was deemed to be
within economics’ province; and the general
influence of Karl Marx’s political economy.
During the Methodenstreit, Joseph Schumpeter observed that there were two theories of money – the
commodity theory and the claim (or credit) theory –
and that they were incompatible. Orthodox economic theories of money are based on the commodity theory in which money is seen as a thing
that functions as a medium of exchange in order
to overcome the inconveniences of barter that
arise in the absence of a double coincidence of
wants. According to this theory, barter transforms
myriad bilateral exchange ratios between goods
into a single market price for a uniform good.
Money originates as one of the commodities
in barter transactions that eventually function as
media of exchange – for example, cigarettes in
prison. As a commodity, the medium of exchange
can have an exchange ratio with other commodities. As a medium of exchange, money is a neutral
veil that has no efficacy other than to overcome the
inconveniences of barter.
In Karl Menger’s classical formulation in “On
the Origins of Money” (Economic Journal, 1892),
money is the spontaneous result of market exchange and the unintended consequence of individual economic rationality. In order to maximize
their barter options, traders hold stocks of the
most tradable commodities which, consequently,
become media of exchange – beans, iron tools,
money
cigarettes. Precious metal has additional advantageous properties – durability, divisibility, portability. By being weighed, struck into uniform pieces,
and counted, precious metal becomes money.
The progressive dematerialization of money and
eventual disappearance of precious metal coinage
broke this explanatory link between individual
rationality and system benefits. Why should the
individual, Menger asked, be ready to exchange
his goods for useless base metal disks or notes?
Modern neoclassical economics tries to resolve
the problem by showing that using (noncommodity) money reduces transaction costs for the
individual.
There are three major problems with this analysis. First, this methodology cannot distinguish
money from any other commodity – that is to
say, it does not specify the moneyness of money.
In this regard, economics misunderstands the significance of the abstract, or nominal, money of
account – that is, pounds and pence, or dollars
and cents. Medium of exchange is the key function of money and it is assumed that the others
(money of account, means of payment, store of
value) follow from it. The market spontaneously
produces a transactions-cost-efficient medium of
exchange that becomes the standard of value and
subsequently the nominal “money of account” –
as in the above example of precious metal coins.
However, there are both a-priori and empirical
grounds for reversing the sequence. In A Treatise
on Money (1930), John Maynard Keynes argued that
money of account, or the abstract measure of
value, was the “primary concept of a theory of
money.” Money of account provides the description of money, and specific forms – coins, notes,
cigarettes – “answer the description.” Similarly,
according to John Searle in The Construction of Social
Reality (1995), we know that various material
objects – coins, notes, plastic, electronic impulses,
and so forth – are forms of money because of the
monetary functions that we have “collectively
assigned” to them. In this view, money of account
is logically anterior and historically prior to
the market, but cannot be produced by it. It is
improbable that a measure of value (money of
account) could emerge from myriad bilateral
barter exchange ratios based upon discrete subjective preferences. One hundred goods could
yield 4,950 exchange rates. What transforms discrete barter exchange ratios of, say, 3 chickens ¼ 1
duck, or 6 ducks ¼ 1 chicken, and so on, into a
single unit of account? A “duck standard” cannot
emerge spontaneously, as the equilibrium price
of ducks established by supply and demand,
money
because, in the absence of a money of account,
ducks would continue to have multiple and variable exchange values. Moneys of account are authoritatively fixed abstract measures of value. In
order for a duck to be a measure of monetary
value, it is necessary that a sovereign power declares that one duck is equal to two chickens and
promises to exchange ducks and chickens at this
rate. (The gold standard was not based directly on
the market price of gold, but on the central bank’s
promise to buy gold at a fixed monetary price
per ounce.) But how did agreed measures of
value originate? Can an intersubjective scale
of value (money of account) emerge from myriad
subjective preferences? The question is at the
heart of a problem that distinguishes economics
from sociology. Is social order the result of the
individual calculations of advantaged interdependence or of supra-individual social norms?
(See Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action,
1937. For an account of the social origins of money
of account, see Ingham, 2004.)
Second, the explanation of money’s existence in
terms of transaction-costs reduction exposes the
problem with methodological individualism. It is
only advantageous for an individual to use intrinsically worthless money tokens if all other agents
do likewise. The advantages of money for the individual presuppose the existence of money as a
social institution.
Third, the model of the barter economy with its
neutral veil of money is inappropriate for the
understanding of capitalism. Financing of production with bank loans of credit-money does not take
place in the model of the barter exchange economy, where money exists only as a medium for
gaining utility through the exchange of commodities. Capitalist banks are not merely intermediaries between savers and borrowers; they create new
money by extending loans that are not directly
matched by incoming deposits. As the bank’s
debtors spend their credit, it is transformed into
money, which may then be deposited as money in
other banks. Thus, the banking system as a whole
creates a money multiplier (Ingham, 2004).
Neoclassical economics’ explanation of money’s
existence was tacitly accepted in Parsons’s early
work, which confirmed the division of intellectual
labor between economics and sociology. Later, in
Economy and Society (1956) with Neil Smelser,
he saw money as a generalized medium of communication that facilitates the integration of the
functionally differentiated parts of the social
system – in an analogous way to prices in the
economy. They followed neoclassical economics’
397
money
axiom that value is only realizable in the actual
process of exchange and that money is no more
than a symbol of “real” value. This does not acknowledge the obvious fact that money is socially
constructed as abstract value; it is, according to
Georg Simmel, “the value of things without the
things themselves” (The Philosophy of Money, 1907
[trans. 2004]: 121).
The production of money as a social institution
was also neglected by Marx, who was more concerned with money as an expression of alienation
in capitalism. He starts with the classical economic labor theory of value in which precious
metal can be a measure of value because the labor
of mining and minting can be expressed in “the
quantity of any other commodity in which the
same amount of labour-time is congealed” (Capital, vol. I, 1976: 186). However, in a critical departure from classical economic theory, Marx argued
that money is a double “veil.” As orthodox
economics maintains, it veils the real relations
between commodities; but for Marx this also
masks the underlying unequal social relations of
production that appear as monetary relations. For
example, the level of money wages appears to be
the result of an equal economic exchange between
capital and labor, but is in fact an expression of
exploitative power relations. Tearing away these
monetary veils will demystify the alienation and
capitalism will become “visible and dazzling to
our eyes” (187). This points to money’s role in the
ideological naturalization of capitalist social relations – as, for example, in modern economic theory’s concepts of the “natural” rates of interest
and unemployment. But Marx follows classical economics in not granting a relative autonomy to the
value of money; it is fundamentally a commodity
whose value cannot be separated from the material base of either its costs of production or the
embodiment of labor time.
The other side in the Methodenstreit – the German
Historical School – advanced the credit, or claim,
theory of money. Here money’s role as a final
“means of payment” for the unilateral settlement
of a debt is emphasized. A “means of payment”
denominated in money of account stores abstract
value in the form of purchasing power, which enables it to be removed temporarily from the circulation of commodities. This gives freedom and
flexibility to the modern world. As Simmel noted
in The Philosophy of Money (1907 [trans. 2004]), when a
feudal lord demanded a specific quantity of honey
or poultry from his serfs he directly determined
the nature of their labor. But as soon as a money
levy is imposed, the peasant is free to pursue any
398
money
activity that will raise the sum. But there is another
side to this capacity to store abstract value. Saving
money removes it from the process of production
and, according to Keynes’s “paradox of thrift,” may
cause unemployment.
From this perspective, money is a token credit
that is assigned a nominal value by a money of
account – pounds, shillings, dollars, cents, euros.
Money does not take its value from its substantive
commodity content, but from the existence of
goods that can be bought and, more importantly,
debts that can be discharged. This alternative
theory stems from attempts to understand early
capitalist credit instruments – private bank notes
or bills of exchange – and from works such as
Georg Knapp’s The State Theory of Money (1924
[trans. 1973]). States issue money to pay for their
purchases, which the population must accept in
order to meet their tax payments. Moneyness is
assigned by the issuers’ (banks and states) denomination of credit in abstract value (money of account) and in their promise to accept it back in
payment of a debt – the repayment of a loan or a
tax demand. The promise may be backed by
precious metal, or some other commodity; but
this is not essential – as modern dematerialized
money demonstrates. Money is constituted by the
social relation of credit–debt. As Ingham (2004)
argues, for something to be money it has to be
issued as a liability of the issuers – that is to say,
the issuer promises to accept it in payment of a
debt owed.
Weber’s analysis of money was influenced by
both sides of the Methodenstreit dispute: by von
Mises’s economic theory and also, more importantly, by Knapp’s historical “state theory.” In Economy and Society (1978), Weber notes that, as the
largest maker and receiver of payments, the
state’s role in the creation of money is inevitably
paramount. Moreover, for Weber, money is not a
“neutral” medium of exchange, but a “weapon” in
the “struggle for economic existence.” The production of money and the regulation of its “scarcity”
and the value of money are socially and politically
determined by the clash of interests. “The public
treasury does not make its payments simply by
deciding to apply the rules of the monetary
system which somehow seems to it ideal, but its
acts are determined by its own financial interests
and those of important economic groups” (172).
Money consists in abstract value (media of exchange and means of payment) which is also
its own measure (money of account). According
to Simmel, “Money is one of those normative
ideas that obey the norms that they themselves
money
represent” (The Philosophy of Money, 1907 [trans.
2004]: 122). Money is essentially a promise, denominated in the money of account, made by the
issuer that the issued tokens will be accepted
back in payment of a debt. This makes it acceptable for the discharge of any debt within the sovereign monetary space, circumscribed by the
state’s imposition of the money of account, in
which prices are posted and debts contracted.
This quality of moneyness has been made more
obvious with the disappearance of all precious
metal monies and monetary standards. States
pay for goods and services with their issue of
tokens which become sought after because they
are the only means of discharging tax liabilities.
Private issues of bank notes are also accompanied
by the promise that they will be accepted in payment of any debt owed to the bank. But, until
banks joined the giro network headed by a statesponsored public, or central, bank, their issued
money was unstable. Money is an expression of
sovereignty (Michel Aglietta and André Orléan, La
Monnaie souveraine, 1998). Weak monetary systems
are as much the result of a weakness of the state
as they are of any economic weakness – for
example, post-Soviet Russia and Argentina.
After moneyness has been established this way,
it can become a commodity whose value is determined by its exchangeability for goods (purchasing power) and other moneys in foreign exchange
markets (exchange rate). In other words, once
money has been produced, then economic analysis is applicable; but it cannot explain money’s
existence. Furthermore, the economic analysis of
the exchange value of money in relation to goods,
and other currencies, needs to be supplemented
by sociological analysis because the scarcity of
money is socially and politically determined. At
the macro-level, the supply of money is structured
by the rules and norms governing fiscal practice
(for example, sound money principles), which are
the outcome of a struggle between economic
interests in which economic theory plays a performative role. In capitalism, the major struggle
between creditors and debtors is centered on
forging a real rate of interest (nominal rate minus
inflation rate) that is politically acceptable and
economically feasible. On the one hand, too high
a real rate of interest will deter entrepreneurial
debtors and inhibit economic dynamism. On the
other hand, too low a rate or, more seriously, a
negative rate of interest (inflation rate in excess of
nominal interest rate) inhibits the advance of
money-capital loans. On the micro-level, creditrating produces a stratification of credit risk that
Montesquieu, Baron Charles de (1689–1755)
regulates the demand for money by means of differential interest rates and the refusal of loans.
This has an autonomous impact on the reproduction of inequality through “Matthew Effects”: the
rich receive low-interest credit and the financially
excluded fall prey to “loan sharks.” Other important areas that require sociological analysis are the
social and political construction of inflation expectations by central bankers and the financial
press. A sociology of inflation flourished in the
1970s in Fred Hirsch and John Goldthorpe, The
Political Economy of Inflation (1978), but waned
with the decline of its subject matter. This was
closely related to Keynesian theories of “costpush” inflation which reverses the implied causal
sequence in the quantity theory of money. Rather
than the quantity of money determining the price
level, it is the market power of economic interests,
in the Weberian “struggle for economic existence,” to bid up their prices and (especially) wages
that triggers inflation. This increased demand for
money is met in the capitalist system by the power
of banks to create money by extending loans. This
monetization of private debt is a distinctive characteristic of the capitalist system, as Ingham has
argued. This depiction of the monetary process in
capitalism is now acknowledged insofar as monetary policy does not attempt directly to control
quantities of money, but rather attempts to
dampen the demand for money by the manipulation of interest rates.
GEOFFREY INGHAM
monogamy
– see family.
Montesquieu, Baron Charles de
(1689–1755)
A political theorist, social critic, and an early precursor to sociological analysis, Montesquieu was
born into a wealthy French aristocratic family and
studied natural history, law, and physiology, before becoming a lawyer. As a result of a generous
inheritance, he traveled widely in Europe, spending considerable time in England. In 1721, he
published the Persian Letters, ostensibly a satirical
portrait of French and especially Parisian manners
as seen from the perspective of two Persian travelers, but on a deeper understanding a caustic social
critique of the church, Louis XIV, and the aristocracy. In 1734 he published his Reflections on the
Causes of the Grandeur and Declension of the Romans,
which charts the historical rise and decline of the
Roman Empire using ideal types as a methodological device. His major work, however, remains
the Spirit of the Laws (1750 [trans. 1914]), which,
399
Moore, Barrington, Jr. (1913– )
moral panics
written over twenty years, comprises thirty-one
books. Among the achievements of this great
work was to delineate the laws of society (see law
and society) as well as to classify governments
according to their underlying principles: the republic based on virtue; the monarchy based on
honor; and despotism based on fear. As a leading
Enlightenment liberal, he championed republicanism and, as a means to prevent despotism, advocated the separation of powers – that judicial,
executive, and legislative powers should remain
independent – modeling his arguments on what
he had witnessed in England.
As well as examining universal laws, he also
sought to explain the differences between societies, seen holistically, in terms of the influence
of various ecological and social factors such as
climate, religion, education, and the maxims of
government. He also made significant contributions to the study of law and demography.
STEVEN LOYAL
Moore, Barrington, Jr. (1913– )
One of the few American-born sociologists to
pursue questions of classical dimensions, Moore
was a contributor to themes as disparate as Soviet
studies, the history of privacy, and social scientific
method. Moore’s preeminent work is his historical
sociological study, Social Origins of Dictatorship and
Democracy (1966). The legacy of this book extends
into the twenty-first century on two fronts. First,
Moore’s works (in company with those by Reinhard Bendix, Jr.) renewed the Weberian tradition
of comparative historical sociology, which had
been almost brought to a halt as the Nazis came
to dominate Europe before and during World
War II. Second, in an era when Marxist theory set
the standards in left-wing sociology and normative political theory, Moore concentrated on the
semiautonomous rise of the state, in addition to
capitalism, as a key to understanding the development of modernity. Subsequent comparative historical sociological studies of political power, the
state, and social revolution, notably including
works by Michael Mann and Theda Skocpol, owe
enormous debts to Moore’s extraordinary work.
In Social Origins, Moore explains the differing
paths towards the modern nation-state taken as
the result of the political movements of lords and
peasants – independently and in relation to one
another – in premodern agrarian states. Spanning
six major cases (England, France, the United
States, Japan, China, and India), with secondary
observations on Russia and Germany, Moore
asked one simply stated question of the utmost
400
significance: under what conditions do lords or
peasants, or both, push historical developments
towards parliamentary democracies or authoritarian regimes or communist systems? In the course
of his work, he identifies three historical paths.
The first two are “top-down” paths – the bourgeois
revolutions leading to (in his terms) capitalist
democracy and the abortive bourgeois revolutions
leading to fascism. He also finds one “bottom-up”
path: the peasant revolutions leading to communist regimes. In all cases he finds that the ways in
which lords and peasants reacted to the challenge
of commercial agriculture played a leading role.
But this summary is much too schematic to do
justice to Moore’s sensitivity to the variations between historical cases. Like Max Weber’s comparative studies on economic ethics of the world
religions, Moore refuses to sacrifice the messiness
of history for the sake of analytical clarity. His
work poses challenges to readers, but it has a
stronger ring of truth as a result.
Another of Moore’s works, Injustice: The Social
Bases of Obedience and Revolt (1978), takes a different
methodological approach. Here Moore concentrates on one case, the German working class
from 1848 to 1920, to ask: why do people quietly
accept being victims of society in many instances,
yet passionately rise to take action in certain situations? In a reflective epilogue, Moore suggests as
one lesson of his book that obligations between
rulers and the dominated should be reciprocal.
Here again, the lesson of the book gains its credibility from the detail. Other books include Morality and Persecution in History (2000), Privacy: Studies in
Social and Cultural History (1984), and Political Power
and Social Theory (1958).
IRA COHEN
moral panics
A disproportionate public reaction in response to
actions deviating from established social and cultural norms; such actions range from acts of
provocation of cultural and historical sensibilities
to criminal offenses. Moral panics often arise in
relation to subcultural groups and youth culture,
addiction and religious deviations such as satanic
rituals. Further targets of moral panics have been
other marginalized or disadvantaged social
groups such as welfare recipients or refugees. A
distinct set of moral panics surrounds acts of
sexual transgression and violence.
Moral panics are based on a perceived threat
to mainstream society. Often this threat is constructed in relation to third parties, usually children and adolescents, who are seen as potential
victims of illicit practices (sexual abuse, or drug
moral statistics
morality
pushing) or deemed liable to deviant practices
themselves (for example, the panic surrounding
violence and homosexuality in American comics
sparked by Frederic Wertheim’s Seduction of the
Innocent, 1954).
While moral panics as a response have an original cause for concern and are thus to be distinguished from forms of mass hysteria or delusion,
they, as Stanley Cohen observes in Folk Devils and
Moral Panics (1972), diverge from other forms of
public reaction to a perceived moral or social malaise, such as the formation of social movements in
relation to ecological risk, gender discrimination
or poverty, in that they are based on an exaggerated threat: exaggerated either because the
actions that trigger moral panic are represented
inaccurately or because the threat itself is portrayed as more serious than it is in comparison
to other problems.
The different processes and actors that are involved in the exaggeration of perceived threats are
detailed in Cohen’s study of Mods and Rockers in
1960s Britain which first coined the phrase moral
panic. Crucial to the portrayal of subcultures as
“folk devils” are, according to Cohen, both legislative and executive sections of the state and the
mass media, both impacting on public perception.
The mass media in particular have been implicated in the formation of moral panics in subsequent studies: Stuart Hall’s Treatment of Football
Hooliganism in the Press (1979), Chas Critcher’s Moral
Panics and the Media (2003), and Sarah Thornton’s
Club Cultures (1995) all highlight the indispensable
role of mass media, and the (British tabloid) press
in particular, in creating moral panics. Thornton’s
study furthermore highlights the complex interplay between subcultures and mass media in
which subcultural credibility is derived from hostile media coverage, whereas mainstream media
approval spells the death of subcultures.
CORNEL SANDVOSS
moral statistics
– see social pathology.
morality
This is a term that refers to injunctions of what
to do, and how to behave, in particular
circumstances.
All societies require notions of morality, since
individuals cannot conduct their lives without
norms to guide them. It is tempting but erroneous
to divorce moral norms from the time and place in
which they arose: hence the institutions of slavery
or cannibalism, while repellent to modern mores,
cannot be regarded as inherently immoral, since
they seemed normal and natural in particular societies. Behavior becomes immoral when groups in
society begin to question particular lines of conduct and espouse practical alternatives.
This is not, however, a purely relativist view of
morality since underlying particular historical
examples are wider notions of autonomy and
self-government which are crucial to morality.
The point is that these absolute values emerge
and it would be wrong to think of them as having
“stopping points” as if they are to be fully realized
in one society or another. Indeed, the notion of
morality has been bedeviled by religion and the
idea that an absolute value has to be timeless in
order to be absolute. God is seen as embodying
this absolute and is conceptualized as the repository of a timeless absolute truth. There are absolute values (autonomy and self-government have
been mentioned), but these absolute values can
only express themselves in relative form, that is,
in a particular time and place. The influence of
theology on morality has been to instill a dualistic
divide between the absolute and the relative so
that the individual is to “choose” one or the other.
Contemporary public debates often polarize
around relativists who argue simply that “beauty
lies in the eye of the beholder” and “there is nothing good or bad but thinking makes it so,” and
fundamentalists who react against this relativism
by seeking to abstract values from their historical
context. The modernist belief in timeless absolutes is not adequately dealt with by simply
turning it inside out, so that morality is merely
denied. The modernist view of morality must be
transcended, moved beyond, so that morality is
seen as the combination of the absolute and the
relative, the utopian and the realistic.
The problem with expressing morality as a timeless absolute is that it inevitably becomes imbued
with a perfectionism that cannot be matched by
historical practice. A gulf between theory and
practice acts not as a stimulant to activity, but as
a paralyzing frustration – a distinction becomes a
dualism, an unbridgeable gulf that inevitably generates cynicism and despair. Of course, every
individual acts in a way that breaches morality,
and the more serious the breach, the more explicit
the articulation of the moral norm. But where
morality is expressed in a historically conscious
fashion, this gap is an incentive to develop and
improve, not a source of impotence and passivity.
Morality becomes problematic when focused
upon the state. It could be argued that it is difficult to see how the state can act morally when its
401
morality
distinctive attribute is the use of force to tackle
conflicts of interest. The “morality” of the state is
of a distinctively propagandist quality, designed
to bully and coerce people into compliance.
As long as society was seen as “naturally” divided
into citizens and slaves, Christians and atheists,
men and women, and so on, then the use of force
against the others is not problematic. However,
once all are deemed to be individuals – all equally
entitled to natural rights – then the force of the
state becomes problematic from a moral point of
view. Liberals are right to see force as antithetical
to morality since it is impossible to act autonomously and govern your own life if you are subject
to the coercive will of another. The use of force
destroys relationships since, to form a relationship
with another, one needs to be an agent and one
cannot be an agent if one is damaged, to a great or
lesser extent, by the acts of another. To use force
against another is to see them as a thing, an inanimate object, and not a fellow human being.
The use of force by the state can be “justified” as
the lesser of two evils since there are all kind of
contexts in which the failure to employ counterforce against a bully or thug makes a bad situation
worse, but it is hard to see how the use of force
itself can ever be moral. The problem with liberalism is that it seeks to justify the unjustifiable
since its postulates of freedom and equality are
themselves projected as timeless absolutes. Antisocial behavior cannot be given a historical explanation. It is “naturalized,” that is, illicitly
presented as natural in the sense of being unchangeable, so that the need for a state, an institution claiming a monopoly of legitimate force, is
presented as eternal and inevitable.
Morality is sometimes seen as norms that are
imposed from on high. This accounts for the view
by youth in liberal societies that morality is inherently hypocritical and corrupt. The word moral is
used pejoratively – a bad thing. There is something to be said for this argument since state
functionaries cannot practice what they preach,
and religious figures present a theoretical piety
which their practical behavior belies. But it is
important not to see morality through the eyes
of those who deform it through hypocrisy and
equivocation. It is better to say that those who
say one thing and do another are negating morality since neither they nor their victims can be said
to be governing their own lives or acting autonomously. When morality is imposed from above,
threats accompany it. Those who abide by norms
out of fear of the consequences cannot be said to
be acting morally. Morality cannot be treated as a
402
morality
purely subjective attribute: “I am moral because I
think I am.” Although it is true that a person must
intend to be moral in order to be so, it would be
naive to suppose that the consequences of an act
can be ignored: the use of physical chastisement
in our contemporary world by authority figures
may be intended to instill morality, but its effects
are crippling and deforming.
The same can be said about the lack of knowledge of the alternatives. Of course relativism
makes an input here, since knowledge that is
withheld must exist and be available. One can
hardly say, in a world in which research into
lung cancer and passive smoking has not taken
place, that smoking is inherently immoral; it becomes immoral when knowledge is available but
not utilized. This point is crucial in linking morality to an objective interest. An act is contrary to
objective interests if an individual would act in a
different way if he or she knew what others know.
There have to be what some call “counterfactuals,” that is, meaningful alternatives which can
be chosen.
Authoritarian deformations of morality divorce
the objective and subjective in a dualistic way. The
norm is imposed from on high – the authority
figure knows best – or, as a reaction to this explicit
authoritarianism, the norm is not advocated at all
on the grounds that each must do as they please
even if this destroys the individual concerned or
the well-being of others. This holds whether moral
norms are being developed in children or adults.
Context is crucial, and the way that a moral norm
is expressed for a three-year-old obviously differs
dramatically from the way in which it would be
expressed for a young person of thirteen. Morality
is both objective and subjective, since an individual
must believe in the rightness of an action and that
action needs to contribute to their autonomy and
capacity to govern their own lives. The “moral” injunctions associated with authoritarian rule –
whether of a personal or institutional kind – undermine rather than further morality.
The attempt to present the study of society as a
science devoid of moral or normative implications
is misguided. Science itself, whether natural
or social, has moral implications. It is true that
the natural sciences study a realm outside human
activity, and it would obviously be perverse for a
zoologist to describe a queen bee as autocratic or
dictatorial. But this does not mean that the study
of nature is value-free. Humans are part of and
interact with the wider world of nature, and therefore the study of nature cannot but affect their
lives. The discovery that the earth went around
morality
the sun was seen understandably as a threat to a
medieval outlook, and extraordinary lengths were
taken to repress those taking this view. To this
day, social Darwinism has proved controversial to
those who cling in fundamentalist fashion to what
they see as the letter of their holy text. Modern
ecology rightly poses the human–nature relationship as crucial to our well-being, even though
there is sometimes the temptation to invert
traditional attitudes so that our equality with
nature is treated as though we were the same as
the rest of nature. This leads to the inversion of
traditional humanism rather than to the development of a new and more concrete humanist
position.
The point is that the notion that factual statements must be morally neutral treats the facts
in an atomistic way. Factual statements pose
relationships. Skeptics dismiss these necessary relationships as purely metaphysical (that is, subjectively imposed) while philosophical idealists
present these relationships as evidence of a higher
spiritual power. In fact, relationships derive from
movement in the material world and it is impossible for an entity to move if it has no relationship
with its environment. All factual statements imply
relationships: sometimes these relationships are
commonplace in our culture and therefore they
are not controversial, but a lack of controversy
does not mean that there is an absence of values.
It merely means that the values are shared. The
statement that the World Trade Center in New
York was destroyed on September 11, 2001, is
agreed by terrorist and state functionary alike,
and the relationships which this statement postulates between an act and a point in time are not
particularly important (although those who argue
that the act was somehow created by the media
may inject controversy into a statement even
like this).
Values derive from the relationships which
factual statements imply. There is therefore no
qualitative difference between the statements of
natural and social scientists in this area, although
(as the example of the zoologist illustrates), the
language appropriate to actions of humans differs
significantly from that appropriate to the behavior of other natural beings and entities. At the
height of the behavioral revolution (a movement
that rejected the difference between humans
and the rest of nature), it was common to argue
in voting studies that apathy among ordinary
members of the public was functional for a democracy because it enabled politicians to take decisions with unimpeded expertise. Whatever one
mortality
thinks of this statement, it is not, as was claimed
at the time, a value-free discovery, since the
notion of functionalism smuggled in a moral judgment. If apathy was functional, it was in practice
a good thing. The relationship that the functional implies contains the values – whatever the
intention of the author.
Morality is thus inherent in society because relationships are inherent in society. This morality
is both relative and absolute. It links to our autonomy and capacity to govern our lives – a value
that we can only move towards but never absolutely realize. Morality is subverted if values are
expressed in timeless fashion. Morality cannot be
developmental unless it is integrated into human
practice so that it helps us to improve and does
not stand over the individual us an alienated set
of unattainable ideals. Morality is inherently all
statements; it is a positivist argument that scientific statements must be value-free. This position
ignores the relational character of factual statements, and the way in which values derive from
the relationships implied. This position holds
for the natural as well as the social sciences for,
although there are undoubtedly differences between the two, neither are morally neutral.
JOHN HOFFMAN
mores
– see norm(s).
mortality
The relative frequency of death in a population,
mortality is both a biological and a social phenomenon. Demographers distinguish between two
aspects of mortality, namely, the life span, that
is, the oldest age to which humans survive; and
longevity, that is, the capability to survive from
one year to the next. Longevity has both biological
and social components, whereas life span tends to
be mainly biological.
An easily understood and interpreted method
for quantifying mortality is the crude death rate
(CDR), that is, the number of deaths in a population in a given year, per 1,000 members of the
population. It may be expressed as follows:
CDR ¼
Death in the year
1,000
population at mid-year
Using data for China for 2004, the equation becomes:
CDR ¼
7; 800; 000
1; 000 ¼ 6
1; 300; 000; 000
This means that in China in 2004, there were six
deaths for every 1,000 persons in the population.
Crude death rates among the countries of the
403
mortality
world in 2004 ranged from lows of 2 in Kuwait and
the United Arab Emirates to 26 in Botswana and
29 in Sierra Leone. The range of crude death rates
is narrower than that for crude birth rates. Crude
death rates, however, must be interpreted with
caution. When crude death rate comparisons are
made between countries, differences are sometimes due to differences in age composition. Countries with high proportions of young people will
usually have lower crude death rates than countries with small proportions of young people.
When the countries of the world are categorized
into more developed and less developed and their
crude death rates examined, countries with low
death rates are found in both groups. This does
not mean that the more and less developed countries have the same mortality experiences. For
although crude death rates are low in many countries of the world, members of the populations of
the more developed countries have greater longevity, that is they live longer, than those in the
less developed countries. Age-specific death rates
and age-standardized death rates should be used
to compare the mortality experiences of countries
with known differences in age composition.
The quantification of mortality is central to
demography. A key measure of the mortality experiences of a population is the life table, and this
dates to John Graunt and his analyses of the Bills of
Mortality. The life table starts with a population (a
radix) of 100,000 at age 0; from each age to the
next, the population is decremented according to
age-specific mortality probabilities, until all
members have died; the mortality schedule is
fixed and does not change over the life of the
population. The basic life table consists of seven
columns including the probability of dying between age x and age x þ n (nqx), the number of
survivors at exact age x (lx), the number of deaths
between age x and age x þ n (ndx), years lived
between age x and age x þ n (nLx), and life expectancy after exact age x (ex0) .
Alfred J. T. Lotka (1880–1949), whom many
refer to as the person most responsible for the
development of modern demography, used life
tables in his development of the theory of stable
population. The concept of a stable population
was actually first set forth by L. Euler in “General
Research on Mortality and Multiplication,” Mémoires de l’Académie Royale des Sciences et Belles Lettres
(1760 [trans. 1970]), but its current development
stems from the work of Lotka, who first introduced the concept in a brief note in 1907. Later,
F. R. Sharpe and A. Lotka in “A Problem in Age
Distribution” (1911), proved mathematically that
404
mortality
if a population that is closed to migration experiences constant schedules of age-specific fertility
and mortality rates, it will develop a constant
age distribution and will grow at a constant rate,
irrespective of its initial age distribution. The
mathematical bases and foundation of stable
population theory are laid out and discussed in
many places, one of the better expositions being
A. J. Coale’s masterpiece, The Growth and Structure of
Human Populations (1972). A. J. Coale and P.
Demeny, in Regional Model Life Tables and Stable
Populations (1983), developed model life tables to
generalize about mortality under various different conditions.
A primary aspect of quality of life, directly derived from the life table, is life expectation. In
2004, life expectation at birth in the world was
65 for males and 69 for females. In more developed countries it was 72 and 80, and in less
developed countries, 63 and 67. The highest life
expectation at birth was in Japan, 78 for males
and 85 for females; the lowest was in Sierra Leone
(34 for males, 36 for females), Zambia (35 for both
males and females), and Botswana (35 for males
and 36 for females) (Population Reference Bureau,
2004). Maximum potential life span refers to the
theoretically highest known age. The longest
known life span is 122 years and 5 months authenticated as the age at death of Frenchwoman
Jeanne Louise Calment who died in August, 1997.
Another aspect of quality of life is the infant
mortality rate (IMR), or the number of deaths in
a year of infants under 1 year per 1,000 live births.
It is expressed as:
IMR ¼
deaths in the year to persons under age 1
1; 000
live births in the year
The infant mortality rate is a combination of the
neonatal mortality rate (NMR) – deaths to babies
of 28 days of age or less per 1,000 live births – and
the post-neonatal mortality rate (PMR) – deaths to
babies of 29 days to 1 year of age per 1,000 live
births.
A major explanation of mortality change has its
origins in demographic transition theory (DTT).
DTT proposes four stages of mortality and fertility
decline that occur in the process of societal modernization. The first is the pre-industrialization
era with high birth and death rates along with
stable population growth. With the onset of industrialization and modernization, the society transitions to lower death rates, especially lower infant
and maternal mortality, but maintains high birth
rates, with the result of rapid population growth.
The next stage is characterized by decreasing
Mosca, Gaetano (1858–1941)
population growth due to lower birth and death
rates, which lead then to the final stage of low and
stable population growth.
Epidemiological Transition Theory (ETT) focuses
on the society-wide decline of infectious disease
and the rise of chronic degenerative causes of
death. According to epidemiological transition
theory as postulated by A. R. Omran in “The Epidemiologic Transition: A Theory of the Epidemiology of Population Change” (1971), there are three
stages. The first is the age of pestilence and famine
in which the primary causes of mortality were
influenza, pneumonia, smallpox, tuberculosis,
and other related diseases, with a high infant
and childhood mortality and a life expectancy
averaging between 20 and 40 years. The second is
the age of receding pandemics in which there was
a decline in mortality due to improved sanitation,
increases in standards of living and public health,
resulting in a steady increase in life expectancy to
between the ages of 30 and 50 years. According to
R. G. Rogers and R. Hackenberg in “Extending
Epidemiologic Transition Theory: A New Stage”
(1987), the stage of receding pandemics was
around 1875–1930. The third stage is known as
the era of degenerative and man-made diseases
(heart disease, cancer, and stroke), in which mortality declines are due to medical advances in the
prevention and treatment of infectious diseases.
The life expectancy at birth rises rapidly so that
fertility becomes the primary factor in population
growth as life expectancy exceeds 70 years. About
three-quarters of deaths in this stage are the result
of degenerative diseases in the advanced years.
Rogers and Hackenberg have noted a fourth
“hybristic stage” where mortality is heavily influenced by individual behavior or lifestyle choices,
and deaths are due to social pathologies such as
accidents, alcoholism, suicide, and homicide, as
well as lifestyle issues such as smoking and diet.
The impact of mortality has been shown to vary
significantly according to social demographic
characteristics. People in higher social classes
live longer than those in the lower classes. In the
United States, Asians and whites live several years
longer than blacks and Hispanics, with blacks
having the shortest life expectancy. Married
people live longer than the single, separated, or
DUDLEY L. POSTON
divorced.
Mosca, Gaetano (1858–1941)
An Italian jurist and political theorist, Mosca was
active in politics and administration. With Vilfredo Pareto he contributed to the theory of elites.
motherhood/mothers
Mosca was the author of two works of abiding
significance, Elementi di Scienza Politica (1896)
which was translated as The Ruling Class (1939)
and Lezioni di Storia delle Istituzioni e delle Dottrine
Politiche (1933 [trans. 1972]). In his critique of parliamentary democracy, he argued that all political
regimes exhibit, or seek to hide, one fundamental
fact: the superiority/inferiority relationship between the political class or ruling class, who possesses political power, and the remainder of the
population. But the possession of power itself is
gained through a “struggle for prominence” between competing groups, and a significant aspect
of that struggle is constituted by the political
formula employed by each group to assert itself
over the others, and to justify its own tenure of
power. Democracy is one such formula, capable of
generating legitimacy, although, like all other formulas, it is at bottom irrational. However, there
are significant qualitative differences between
political regimes, and Mosca maintained his own
preference for a liberal one even when its Italian
version was destroyed by fascism.
GIANFRANCO POGGI
motherhood/mothers
By its very nature, the term motherhood is a relational category. Thus women who are defined as
mothers are primarily understood in terms of their
relationships with their children. This means that
studies of motherhood can tend to focus solely on
the dyad of mother/child relationships. However,
from a sociological perspective, analyses of motherhood have attempted to locate themselves in the
context of the social organization of much broader
themes such as (hetero)sexuality, conception, birth,
child rearing, child care, and paid work. Because
becoming a mother tends to be understood to be a
natural or biological process, it has been the task of
sociology to reveal the ways in which motherhood
changes in relation to other social transformations
and, within this, to explore how different elements
of motherhood (such as the ideologies of motherhood or the experiences of motherhood in different
class or ethnic contexts) shift and adjust over time.
Early functionalist sociology treated motherhood as a self-evident role for women in the context of the married, nuclear family, and the sole
component of this role was seen to be the proper
socialization of children. This narrow perception
was challenged by feminist research in the 1970s
and 1980s when motherhood started to be analyzed as a form of women’s oppression. This oppression was seen to encompass two forms, in line
with the influential neo-Marxist framework of the
405
motivation
time. These forms were the material conditions of
motherhood and the ideology of motherhood. The
former paid attention to the fact that motherhood
isolated women from the labor market and made
them dependent upon the male breadwinner for
their economic survival. The latter identified the
ways in which women were seduced into becoming mothers through a belief system which imposed the idea that women could not be fulfilled
without children and which insisted that it was
natural for all women to be mothers (and hence
unnatural not to be). Radical feminists coined the
term “compulsory motherhood,” used by Adrienne Rich in Of Woman Born (1977), thereby suggesting that in a heterosexist and patriarchal
culture women had little choice but to become
mothers – not least because they could not refuse
to have sex with men, but also because they did
not have control over contraception and reproduction. Alongside these structuralist approaches
to motherhood there developed an interest in
women’s experiences of being mothers, as illustrated by Ann Oakley in Becoming a Mother (1979),
and these accounts gradually shifted the concentration away from just the oppressive elements of
motherhood, towards some of the everyday benefits and problems associated with becoming a
mother, such as negotiating with the professions
who take charge of motherhood, and combining
motherhood with paid employment. Mothers
themselves were increasingly seen as agents in
the process of mothering, rather than just the
victims, and emphasis was given to the idea that
mothers’ voices should be heard, in particular by
the medical and health care professions. More
recently, research on motherhood has taken into
account the significance of new reproductive
technologies which are seen as disruptive of the
taken-for-granted genetic link between mothers
and the children to whom they give birth. The
rise of surrogacy, embryo and egg donation, and
post-menopausal childbirth is changing further
the idea that motherhood is simply a natural
CAROL SMART
phase of women’s life course.
motivation
Central to both lay and technical uses of this term
is the conception that motivation is why people do
what they do. None of the abilities or potential of
an individual will result in action without him or
her being motivated to act.
The range of meanings included in everyday talk
encompass the full range of meanings to be found
in the academic literature, and thereby foreshadow the conceptual difficulties and wrangles
406
motivation
present in analyses of motivation. Standard dictionaries refer to conscious and unconscious stimuli, which are characterized either in terms of
internal psychological desires or beliefs, or in
terms of physical or social environmental conditions leading to behavior which may be novel
or habitual, and learned or innate. While these
different elements can be used promiscuously
and speculatively in daily conversation, substantial and different theoretical consequences follow
from each of them. Careful technical use needs to
bear in mind five important distinctions.
First, does a person do something because of an
internal need or desire which must be satisfied, or
are they stimulated to action by an external event?
Second, are they pursuing specific goals, or are they
motivated by general drives? Third, is their motivation based on a cognitive calculation or judgment,
or on an emotional reaction? Fourth, is it something
of which the individual is conscious and aware, or
something of which he or she has little awareness?
Finally, is it a function of innate and inherent properties of the individual, or is it developed over time?
Many otherwise quite incompatible theories, for
example, psychoanalysis and sociobiology, have
argued that there are fundamental underlying
drives which are part of a person’s biological endowment. Individuals seek the satisfaction of these
drives through the pursuit of pleasurable stimuli
and the avoidance of noxious ones with highly
significant consequences for the character of persons, their social relations, and the social order
that follows. Necessarily, an account of a generalized drive towards, for example, sexual engagement, presumes a cognitive apparatus that can
organize one’s behavior in the light of a specific
demand or opportunity, but often these theories
are less forthcoming on this matter. In contrast,
many more cognitive accounts – for example, expectancy value theory – prioritize the cognitive
component in the individual’s pervasive motivation to maximize benefits and minimize costs
without paying much attention to how value is
determined.
Many authors have proposed that motivation
may be an important area of individual difference.
Abraham Maslow (1908–70) proposed that societies as a whole will vary as a function of a
hierarchy of human needs. In this, individuals
will first be motivated by physiological needs
such as food and water. When that need is satisfied, the motivation will be for safety, followed by
social engagement, then personal esteem, and
finally self-actualization. As a society or social
group enables the easy satisfaction of these needs,
multicultural citizenship
so the individuals will be motivated by the higher
levels in the hierarchy.
DAVID GOOD
multicultural citizenship
– see citizenship.
multiculturalism
There are two tensions within multiculturalism
that sociology inherits. First, multiculturalism
has come to define a set of state policies to
manage (neutralize, nullify, subdue, or conquer)
difference (multiculturalism as policy). Second,
it also has come to define those strategies that
mount resistances to state management policies
of difference (multiculturalism as politics). Thus,
multiculturalism has come to express both a
will to difference and a will to sameness (equity,
equality, fairness) simultaneously.
These tensions are not unique to multiculturalism. In the second half of the twentieth century,
many struggles for social justice have mobilized
identity and difference and placed new demands
on citizenship. There are two reasons for this.
First, which may be called the politics of identity,
many social movements (civil rights and women’s
and indigenous peoples’ rights being principal
examples) called into question the shortcomings
of the ideal of universal citizenship in practice,
signaling that, while being formally citizens, their
identities still excluded them from rights of citizenship. Second, which may be called the politics
of difference, many social groups articulated
rights that accrued to them on the basis of their
difference. Struggles for minority rights in language, schooling, and public appearance were
often waged on this basis. The politics of recognition (combining the politics of identity and difference) has, therefore, increasingly mobilized itself
as simultaneous and conflicting claims to sameness and difference, inclusion and exclusion, and
rights and obligations.
Multiculturalism, both as policy and politics,
inherited these tensions from other forms of politics of recognition but displayed unique characteristics (see, for example, Danielle Juteau,
“Beyond Multiculturalist Citizenship: The Challenge of Pluralism in Canada,” 1997). These tensions can be traced to the origins of the concept
itself (for example, Mark Lopez, The Origins of Multiculturalism in Australian Politics 1945–1975, 2000).
On the one hand, multiculturalism meant rights
for cultural minorities but, on the other, their
assimilation into the dominant culture. Both
these tensions can be observed in its official incarnation when, on October 8, 1971, Canadian Prime
multiculturalism
Minister Pierre Trudeau spoke in the House
of Commons to proclaim Canada’s policy of multiculturalism. He said, “There is no official [Canadian] culture, nor does any ethnic group take
precedence over any other. No citizen or group
of citizens is other than Canadian, and all
should be treated fairly.” With astonishing clarity,
what Trudeau was proclaiming was both the absence and presence of a dominant (in this case,
“Canadian”) culture.
This proclamation announced the acceptance of
the material conditions of the politics of recognition, which was brewing in North American but
also European and Australian cities. The shifting
patterns of global migration and immigration
resulted, within a few decades in the second
half of the twentieth century, in cities such as
Toronto, New York, Los Angeles, Chicago, Amsterdam, London, Sydney, and Melbourne becoming
home to large numbers of foreign-born residents
with ostensibly radically different cultural backgrounds from those of their host cities and
nations, as illustrated by Leonie Sandercock, Towards Cosmopolis: Planning for Multicultural Cities
(1998). Yet, this pattern was not so different from
the massive sea-change experienced in almost all
those cities at the turn of the twentieth century
when their populations had “welcomed” vast
numbers of foreign-born residents. It is often forgotten that, proportionally speaking, there were
more foreign-born residents in New York and Chicago at the turn of the twentieth century than at
that of the twenty-first. Yet at the turn of the
twentieth century the decisive requirement was
assimilation.
This is probably the source of the paradox of
multiculturalism. While, at the turn of the twentieth century, sociology, especially what came to
be known as the Chicago School and its urban
ecology, emerged out of a milieu that had asked
assimilation of its minorities, by the late twentieth century society could no longer do so, at least
not explicitly (for example, Bhikhu C. Parekh, Rethinking Multiculturalism: Cultural Diversity and Political Theory, 2000). If, at the turn of the twentieth
century, the service that sociology was pressed
into was the achievement of the assimilation of
these minority cultures into the dominant host
culture, by the end of the century confidence in
that possibility, for various complex reasons, was
shaken, and thus was born the policy and politics
of multiculturalism. As policy, multiculturalism
still clung to “integration,” “cohesion,” and “inclusion” as euphemisms to stand for assimilation
but, as politics, multiculturalism also increasingly
407
multilevel models
multivariate analysis
articulated demands for differentiated citizenship
as rights and obligations, as shown by Seyla Benhabib, The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in
the Global Era (2002) and Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights
(1995). The sociology of multiculturalism embodies these tensions by pressing itself, on the
one hand, in the service of integration, cohesion,
and inclusion, and, articulating, on the other, new
ways of being different yet equal in postnational
states and their cities.
Multiculturalism, either as policy or politics,
may well have exhausted its possibilities. It was
never as accepted and embraced in the United
States and Europe as it was in Canada, and it has
had a variegated history in Australia. The growing
securitization of the state and politicization and
racialization of borders, and the growing conflicts
between Muslim minorities and dominant cultures, have already shifted the discourse in the
United States and Europe from multiculturalism
to euphemisms of “integration” and “cohesion.”
Whatever the concepts deployed, the tensions of
the politics of recognition will continue to influence the research and political agendas.
ENGIN ISIN
multilevel models
– see modeling.
multilevel regression model
– see modeling.
multiple level regression
– see regression.
multivariate analysis
This is the generic term for analyses that involve
many variables, such as multiple regression, cluster analysis, or log linear analyses. Typically,
they are used to determine the relative importance of a number of independent variables on
one dependent variable. An example of this is
given in the description of regression. The most
important reason for using multivariate analyses
in sociological research is that many sociological
phenomena have multiple overlapping causes,
and it is difficult to unravel the relative importance of each of them by simply examining
the correlations between pairs of variables
(bivariate analysis). (The other type of analysis,
alongside multivariate and bivariate is univariate
analysis – looking at just one variable at a time,
such as when examining the averages of individual
variables.)
408
It is often noted that children whose parents get
divorced during their childhoods experience disadvantage later in their lives (for instance, in their
educational outcomes or the status of their jobs as
adults). But this simple correlation tells us little
about the relative importance of a number of
factors that could have brought this about. Is
being brought up by one parent inherently inferior to being raised by two parents? Or could it be
that other factors are to blame? For instance,
many single-parent families live in poverty, are
forced to live in poorer neighbourhoods where
the schooling might be of lower quality, or experience prejudice in society. Or perhaps it was living
in households with higher levels of conflict before
the separation or divorce that caused the disruptions to the children’s development?
Such a complex web of interrelated variables
would be nigh impossible to unravel with simple
bivariate analyses. But, given an appropriate dataset (for instance, a birth cohort study) and multivariate analyses, the relative importance of each
of these factors, and many more, can be understood in detail, as in, for example, B. J. Elliott and
M. P. M. Richards, “Children and Divorce: Educational Performance, and Behavior, Before and
After Parental Separation” (1991, International Journal of Law and the Family).
Another great advantage of multivariate interactions is that they permit the investigation of the
complex way in which independent variables combine to influence other variables. For instance,
there is evidence that individuals with larger
social networks cope better with stressful life
events, such as unemployment. So unemployment
or social networks might only have mild effects by
themselves, but, for those individuals with limited
social networks, unemployment might have a
greater effect on their well-being. In this case
there is an interaction between unemployment
and social support affecting well-being – a relationship that cannot be adequately described by
the bivariate relationships between social networks and wellbeing or unemployment and wellbeing.
Multivariate analyses can also be performed
where there are several dependent variables that
might be considered simultaneously. For instance,
in medical sociology, if one is interested in health
outcomes, rather than analyzing a whole raft of
health measures separately (such as blood pressure, body mass index, cholesterol levels, cortisol
levels, and self-rated depression), they could all
be analyzed simultaneously using multivariate
analysis of variance.
Mumford, Lewis (1895–1990)
Before the advent of computers, multivariate
analyses were considered an advanced technique,
only attempted by the statistically most competent social scientists. More recently, computer
packages such as the Statistical Package for Social
Scientists (SPSS) have made them more accessible
to all social scientists, and multivariate analyses
are taught in most sociology undergraduate
degrees.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
Mumford, Lewis (1895–1990)
Recognized as an architectural critic, Mumford’s
most enduring legacy may well have been as a
social and political critic, raising fundamental
questions about modernity and its drive towards
technological progress. An independent scholar,
he followed his The Story of Utopias (1921) with
imaginative and original books including Sticks
and Stones: A Study of American Architecture and
Civilization (1924), the widely acclaimed The Culture of Cities (1938), and the trenchant The City in
History: Its Origins, Its Transformations, and Its Prospects (1961). His Technics and Civilization (1934)
provided the first glimpse of his developing critical views on technology. His later The Myth of the
Machine: Technics and Human Development (1967)
and The Myth of the Machine: The Pentagon of Power
(1971) fully developed these early critical
thoughts on technology, power, and democratic
imagination.
Mumford was independent in at least two
senses. According to D. L. Miller, Lewis Mumford, a
Life (1992), he did not have an institutional employment all his life and, perhaps consequently,
developed an original and prodigious mind along
with a powerful literary style. This combination
gave him an independent voice that was as resolute as it was agile, highlighting, in equal measure, the darkest and brightest aspects of being
social throughout human history. In his The Culture of Cities (1938), he had already developed an
idea of the city both as being the institution for
fulfilling the brightest possibilities of being social
and as enacting its darkest nightmares. He did not
flinch from calling the city a war machine right
from its inception and yet believed that it could,
and indeed it did in certain periods of human
history, become the crucible of the outmost possibilities of being social. Similarly, his views on
the increasing reliance on technological progress
did not deter him from investing in human capacities for collective responsibility, whether that
meant planning urban regions or stopping
nuclear proliferation.
ENGIN ISIN
myth
Myrdal, Gunnar (1898–1987)
A Swedish economist and sociologist, Myrdal was
educated and subsequently taught at the University of Stockholm and held a Chair in Political
Economy and International Economics. He was
also active in Swedish politics and was elected to
the Senate as a member of the Social Democratic
Party in 1934, and again as Minister for Commerce
in 1945–7. In 1974 he was jointly awarded the Nobel
Prize for Economics together with F. A. Hayek.
He, together with a research team of thirty-eight
members, was commissioned by the Carnegie Corporation to study the social, economic, and lifestyle conditions of black Americans in the United
States. The result was a carefully and extensively
documented 1,500-page report which was published as The American Dilemma (1944). The report
pointed to the gap between the American democratic ideal of the equality of man, and the reality
of racial segregation and denial of civil and political rights that American blacks experienced. It
discussed the caste-like relations between blacks
and whites and the processes of cumulative causation that maintained and reinforced racism. The
work was crucial in the Supreme Court’s decision
to rule against the “separate but equal” law in the
1954 Brown versus Board of Education of Topeka case,
which outlawed racial segregation in public
schools.
His other major publications include The Political
Element in the Development of Economic Theory (1930)
and a three-volume study of South Asia, Asian
Drama: An Inquiry into the Poverty of Nations (1968).
STEVEN LOYAL
myth
From the Greek muthos (plot or story), this term
now circulates in religious studies and in anthropology largely free of the association with error,
delusion, or childish flights of imagination that it
had for many scholars of the nineteenth century
and still has in popular usage today. Bronislaw
Malinowski is transitional; myths are for him primarily functional instruments deployed in ritual
contexts to lay claim to specific properties or titles,
but their specific messages are barely interpretable
at best. From Sigmund Freud to Bruno Bettelheim
(1903–90), myths are collective displacements onto
the symbolic plane of common but illicit desires
whose literal representation would be unbearable.
For Carl Gustav Jung (1875–1961) and his still considerable following, the motifs found so widely in
mythologies throughout the world arise from a
collective – indeed, pan-human – unconscious of a
409
myth
less exclusively libidinous nature and serve less
defensive than therapeutic purposes. Both of these
psychoanalytic approaches must be distinguished
in turn from the existentialist approaches of
religionists such as Mircea Eliade (1907–86) and
Joseph Campbell (1904–87), who claim to find in
mythologies everywhere a common store of enduring human concerns and virtues. Methodologically,
psychoanalytic and existentialist interpretations of
410
myth
myth are largely substantialist; most presume that
the same symbol conveys the same meaning in
every one of its occurrences. In this respect, they
are typically at odds with Claude Lévi-Strauss’s
structuralism, which rests in a positionalist theory
of meaning and whose decryptions uncover in
myths themselves socially specific messages having
a specifically ideological function and force.
JAMES D. FAUBION
N
narcissism
Associated with the doctrines of Sigmund Freud
and psychoanalysis, the term has come to enter
sociology as an account of certain pathological
trends of modern social life. Often interpreted as
a consequence of consumer society and the West’s
obsession with surface appearances, the rise of
narcissism is said to have played a significant
role in the shrinkage of public political life, thus
promoting a defensive, painfully empty search for
self-gratification.
The sociological analysis of narcissism has been
plagued by lack of conceptual precision. It is important to distinguish between three related
issues: first, psychodynamically, narcissistic disorders have their origin in what Freud termed
“primary narcissism” – with the child remaining
stuck in a destructive omnipotence, which thus
prevents the development of healthy boundaries
between self and others. Second, in terms of
generations, narcissism is reproduced in capitalist
society through parents relating to their children
primarily as “investments.” Third, culturally, narcissistic pathology is said to arise not only from
capitalism but as a result of globalization, mass
communications (see mass media and communications), and the decline of tradition. Contemporary patterns of narcissistic identity-formation are
thus conceptualized in sociology as at once thin
and precarious, as the self is outstripped by the
dislocations and terrors of modernity.
The sociological critique of narcissism is best
known through the writings of Richard Sennett,
Christopher Lasch, and Joel Kovel.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
narrative analysis
Narrative as a topic of sociological investigation
has a long and diverse history. Interest in narrative has always been predicated on the assumption that to grasp adequately the nature of some
aspect of the social world one must analyze one’s
research subjects’ own understandings of their circumstances. However, many different approaches
to accomplishing this project have emerged over
the years. The earliest exemplars for narrative
analysis in sociology used a combination of data
sources including oral histories, biographies,
interviews, diaries, letters, and archival records
to construct life histories of research subjects.
These life histories were sometimes held up as
important sociological chronicles in their own
right, but they were usually valued for the contributions that could be made to more general sociological topics by their use. Hence, individual life
histories have been compared to more general
narratives either to enrich what is known about
the experiences of ordinary people in particular
historical periods or to evaluate critically more
general theoretical claims about those periods.
Narrative analysis has thus been used as a prominent resource in fulfilling the mandate for sociology to understand the relations between history
and biography which C. Wright Mills famously
set in his book The Sociological Imagination (1959).
More recently, theoretical and political trends
within the discipline have further invigorated narrative analysis while simultaneously shaping the
direction of its development.
During the 1960s, several theoretical movements converged to suggest language is the
medium through which personal experience is
made meaningful. This “linguistic turn” in sociological research highlighted the “storied” character of personal experience and inspired research
on the structural characteristics of both oral and
written narratives. While still flourishing, the
structural approach to narrative analysis has
been criticized for reifying narrative structures
and under-emphasizing how narratives are accomplished in the ongoing course of social interaction.
It is much more common now for analysts to
consider narratives not for their intrinsic structural characteristics but for the ways in which
these characteristics are themselves socially contingent. Most analysts now appreciate that both
oral and written narratives are best understood as
collaboratively constructed by storytellers and the
myriad audiences for whom stories are told.
Therefore, most contemporary narrative analysis
411
nation
seeks to discover how the work of storytelling
is itself responsive to the wider round of social
activities within which storytelling is embedded.
Narrative analysis has also been profoundly influenced by political developments both within
the discipline of sociology itself and in neighboring disciplines. Social scientists once prided
themselves on their professional ability to use
the information they elicited from their research
subjects to generate superior understandings of
those people and their social worlds. Without necessarily forsaking their claim to objectivity, many
researchers are now a good deal more attentive to
the fact that they do not possess a monopoly on
the capacity to describe social events objectively.
Feminist scholars, in particular, have promoted
the view that narrative analysis is not merely a
project of generating scientific accounts of the
narratives of others but of giving “voice” to those
historically denied the authority to speak for
themselves.
DARIN WEINBERG
nation
– see nationalism.
nationalism
This is an ideology that holds that the nation is
the natural basis of social life and that the best
and most natural political units are states based
on nations, that is, nation-states. Correspondingly,
it gives rise to movements in which groups which
define themselves as nations demand that they
have their own independent national state.
Thus understood, nationalism is unproblematic. The difficulties have to do mainly with the
concept of the nation, and the different understandings of nationhood. Who belongs to the
nation? In one tradition, the nation is seen largely
in political, civic, and territorial terms. This has
been the dominant understanding of nationhood
in such countries as Britain, France, Spain, the
Netherlands, the United States, and Canada. To
belong to the nation, in this view, has nothing to
do with religion, race and ethnicity, or any other
cultural marker, and everything to do with political membership of a particular, territorially defined, state. In principle, all one needs to be a
national of, say, Britain or France, is to be born on
the territory of the state or to become naturalized
as a citizen. National belonging and citizenship, in
this tradition, are more or less synonymous.
Hence the famous commentary by Ernest Renan
in his lecture “What is a Nation?” at the Sorbonne
in 1882 (published in G. Eley and R. Suny, Becoming
National, 1996) emphasized the willed, voluntary
412
nationalism
nature of civic membership (What is a Nation?,
1889).
The other tradition of nationhood puts the
stress on blood and belonging, on deep or primordial ties of race, ethnicity, religion, history, and
other cultural factors. Membership is a hereditary, involuntary, matter, especially as this concept
tends to stress an assumed common descent.
Nations, in this view, are born, not made. This is
the cultural or ethnic understanding of the
nation. It had its birth in eighteenth-century Germany, from where it spread to eastern Europe and
other parts of the world. The power of the ethnic
concept of the nation is that, though it normally
aims at statehood, it can exist without statehood.
It therefore has wide appeal to those peoples who
feel themselves to be nations but who do not have
their own states or who exist as – often subordinate – groups in states dominated by other nations.
There can in this concept be nations without
states, commonly given examples being the Catalans of Spain, the Scots of Britain, and the Québécois of Canada. Not all such nations necessarily
want states, and whether or not they actually get
their own states is largely a matter of power politics – the 20-million Kurdish nation, for instance,
has been waiting and fighting for a very long time
for statehood, but international politics have
stood in the way and are likely to do so for the
foreseeable future.
Nationalism as a doctrine arose in the late
eighteenth century in Europe, and received powerful definition in the course of the French Revolution. This was also the time when the two
principal concepts of nationhood were identified,
though the French themselves tended to promote
the civic concept – leading, by reaction, Germans
and others to stress the ethnic concept. But
whether the nation was politically or ethnically
defined, in the first half of the nineteenth century
nationalism was widely identified with the progressive currents of democracy and liberalism. Its
earliest and one of its greatest prophets, Giuseppe
Mazzini (1805–72), saw individual nations as subdivisions of a larger family of mankind, and envisaged a future world order in which nations would
live peacefully and harmoniously together. In the
later nineteenth century, nationalism, affected
partly by the Social Darwinism of the time, took
on a sharper edge. It now tended to be hijacked by
right-wing thinkers and statesmen, and to become
aggressive and intolerant (a form of nationalism
known as integrative nationalism). Nationalism in
this period was often allied with imperialism, and
sought through the acquisition of colonies the
nationalism
aggrandizement of national power at the expense
of other nations. This form of nationalism reached
a climax in the 1930s in Europe, when it was often
transformed into fascism and other totalitarian
ideologies and movements. With the defeat of
fascism, nationalism also suffered a rebuff, the
more so as liberal hostility to nationalism was also
echoed by the left-wing movements of socialism
and Communism. Socialism historically had
always been opposed to nationalism as a bourgeois, class-based, ideology with which the international proletariat should have no truck (which
did not stop most socialist parties from supporting
their nations during the two world wars).
But while nationalism was under a cloud in the
post-Second World War western world, it was the
central inspiration behind the liberation movements of the developing, non-western, Third
World as they sought to throw off colonial rule.
Even where the movement took a communist
form, as in China, Vietnam, and Cuba, its driving
force was clearly nationalist. In some cases, especially in Africa and the Middle East, the nationalism was made problematic by the fact that many
of the nations were of recent invention, usually
the creation of western powers under colonialism.
They might contain several ethnic groups of
widely differing character, though usually one
managed to achieve dominance during the independence struggle. This threw up a welter of conflicts after independence as different ethnic
groups claiming national status tried to free
themselves from “alien” rule. Examples were the
Biafrans in Nigeria, the Tamils in Sri Lanka, and
the East Timorese in Indonesia.
But it was not only in the developing world that
nationalist conflicts continued to flourish. In the
West too, after a relatively short period of quiescence, nationalism revived vigorously, with strong
movements in such places as Britain, Belgium,
Spain, and Canada. Further East, the collapse of
communist regimes after 1989, and the break-up
of the Soviet Union in 1991, were accompanied by
a powerful surge of nationalism throughout the
region – leading, for instance, to the separation of
Czechs and Slovaks and, in a bitter and bloody
conflict, to the disintegration of Yugoslavia and
the rise of five new nations in its place. Nationalism, it is clear, far from being the passing phenomenon that most nineteenth-century thinkers
assumed, remains one of the most powerful forces
in the world, overriding most other distinctions of
social class, gender, and region, and apparently
thriving even amidst the current currents of
globalization.
KRISHAN KUMAR
Nelson, Benjamin (1911–1977)
nature
– see environment.
nature/nurture debate
– see genetics.
neighborhood
In sociology, neighborhood is a largely undertheorized and commonsense term referring to
urban locales based on residential proximity. The
context for neighborhood studies in urban sociology was provided by early twentieth-century
sociologists (for example Georg Simmel, Ferdinard
Tönnies, and Louis Wirth), who emphasized the
impersonality and anonymity of the modern city.
Against this view, neighborhood studies (for
example Michael Young and Peter Willmott’s
Family and Kinship in East London, 1957) found that
neighborhoods can be the site of close kinship and
personal ties that are not a residue from the past
but, on the contrary, have been facilitated by
modern cities. Urban living enables people to
form associations based on kinship, or religious,
ethnic, political, or other interests which become
the basis of local networks and subcultures. Cities
may thus facilitate a level of diversity not found in
rural areas. In recent work the idea of neighborhood decline or regeneration has been linked to
the concept of social capital drawing on the work
of Robert Putnam and James S. Coleman. This has
focused on the neighborhood’s potential as a site
of integrative social networks and solidarity. The
level of social capital in a neighborhood is often
related to factors such as stability, integration,
trust, solidarity, and tolerance, which in turn are
used to explain such things as differential economic growth or levels of crime between regions.
Two problems should be noted. The specific influences of the local environment may now be mitigated by global factors. The argument is often
circular in that the evidence for and conditions of
social capital in neighborhoods may be the same.
LARRY RAY
Nelson, Benjamin (1911–1977)
A sociologist and historian who trained as a medieval historian at Columbia, Benjamin taught
social sciences at Chicago, Minnesota, and the
State University of New York, before becoming a
professor of history and sociology at the New
School for Social Research.
His classic work remains The Idea of Usury: From
Tribal Brotherhood to Universal Otherhood (1949),
which engages with and extends Max Weber’s
413
neoliberalism
historical and comparative work on religion and
rationalization. Nelson examined the expansion of
the moral community and the problems of conscience and moral regulation. Drawing on numerous medieval books, he elucidates the manner in
which the original dualistic injunctions against
usury, found in Deuteronomy 23:19–20, were inverted and extended by the rise of Christian universalism. An ethic of tribal brotherhood and
communalistic association, which excluded the
quest of gain and treated outsiders as enemies
and morally out of bounds, was first extended to
universal brotherhood from the twelfth century
onward, and again by John Calvin (1509–64) in the
sixteenth century, to an ethic of universal otherhood in which “all become brothers by becoming
equally others.” The breakdown of the inherited
structures of consciousness – where a triangulated
regulation of “conscience, casuistry, and the cure
of souls” existed – resulted in competition and
calculation replacing cooperation.
His later work emphasized the intracivilizational study of social action and cultural change,
and highlighted the necessary interconnection between sociology and psychoanalysis. Both of these
preoccupations are evident in his comparative
historical sociology of science which compares
the development of science in the West with
that in China, and extends his discussion of the
two great revolutions in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries, the Reformation and the
scientific revolution.
STEVEN LOYAL
neoliberalism
Referring to a broad range of economic policies
adopted since the 1970s by western capitalist
nations, this doctrine advocates measures to promote economic development, and is used to guide
the transition from planned to market economies
in former communist countries. In the United
States, neoliberalism is often referred to as “neoconservatism,” thereby creating some confusion
in social-science debates. This “new” economic
liberalism is based on the late eighteenth- and
early nineteenth-century classical political economy of Adam Smith (1723–90) and David Ricardo
(1772–1823), and on Austrian economic theory –
especially, that of Friedrich von Hayek (1889–
1992). It came to prominence in the wake of the
demise of the Keynesian macroeconomics that
had informed economic policymaking after World
War II. In a critique of the two older approaches,
Keynesian theory argued that the labor market
was not self-adjusting and that it could not
secure full employment unless the government
414
network theory
manipulated its expenditure and fiscal policy to
maintain the necessary aggregate demand in the
economy.
Following classical political economy, neoliberalism maintains that the most efficient allocation
of resources is achieved by the competitive
market. To function effectively, the market requires that property rights are clearly defined by
law and that prices are not distorted by the power
of monopolies – such as governments and powerful trade unions. Thus neoliberal policies advocate
the reduction of direct government participation
in the economy; the privatization of the supply of
goods and services; and the reduction of trade
union power and job security in order to create
labor markets that are “flexible” enough to exert a
downward pressure on wage levels if economic
conditions dictate. Rather than spending to maintain demand and employment and thereby fueling inflation through an increase in the money
supply, governments should try to maintain balanced budgets and a stable supply and, consequently, stable value of money. Direct control of
the money supply by means of “monetarism”
failed, but the anti-inflation goal is now pursued
by interest-rate policy administered by central
banks that are independent of government. These
policies of privatization, competitive markets, and
stable money are advocated by the International
Monetary Fund and World Bank as the framework
within which individuals, and not governments,
in underdeveloped economies can create wealth.
Von Hayek’s contribution to neoliberalism was in
arguing that economic planning would inevitably
fail because states could never have sufficient
knowledge. Only competing individuals could establish the real scarcity value and prices of goods.
At the international level, neoliberalism takes a
pro-globalization stance in following Ricardo’s advocacy of free trade based on “comparative advantage.” Global economic welfare will be maximized
in the long run if there is an international division
of labor in which nations produce and then trade
the goods for which they are best suited.
The neoliberal policy-set is often referred to as
the “Washington Consensus” and is frequently
criticized for ignoring, in the same way as classical political economy, the fact that economies
are characterized by a power structure in which
freely competitive markets tend to increase the
power and wealth of the powerful at the expense
of the weaker participants.
GEOFFREY INGHAM
network theory
– see networks.
networks
networks
The study of social networks first emerged within
postwar sociology and anthropology as a way of
studying multi-centered micro-level connections
between individuals. Since then the network idea
has expanded in scope and significance as a means
of characterizing macro-level qualities of social
structures, and as a means of linking micro- and
macro-levels. The controversial idea of network
society advocated by Manuel Castells in The Rise
of the Network Society (1996) and The Internet Galaxy
(2001) represents a leading contemporary example
of social network theory, linking large structures
to individual settings.
The recently expanded scope of network theory
is connected, at least in part, with new information technology and the creation of virtual
communication networks such as the internet,
e-commerce, and broader processes of globalization. While debates continue on the precise connection between electronic and interpersonal
networks, a proliferating typology of social networks has emerged, focusing on one or more areas
such as business and commerce, policy and governance, advocacy, knowledge, science and the
professions, migration and diaspora, religion,
empire, and terrorism. Despite all of this, skeptics
ask what exactly is distinctive about networks.
Are we dealing with a metaphor that simply
alludes to informal patterns of social connectivity, or does the concept carry more analytical
purchase?
In its original form as micro-level sociology,
network analysis was applied to phenomena
such as the support systems at work in rural–
urban migration, or interactions within the classroom. A major landmark was Mark Granovetter’s
“The Strength of Weak Ties” (1973, American Journal of Sociology) on how people gained information
about job opportunities in professional and technical labor markets. He found this typically occurred less through intimate associates than
through more distant acquaintances. This generated the micro-level insight that “weak ties” could
have “strong” social consequences.
A neglected application of network theory to
larger social structures was undertaken by Ira
Lapidus in “Hierarchies and Social Networks; A
Comparison of Chinese and Islamic Societies”
(1975) in F. J. Wakeman (ed.), Conflict and Control
in late Imperial China, which developed a theory of
social organization in Islamic societies by comparison with China. While he saw Chinese society
as dominated by a hierarchy of levels binding
networks
together lineage, gentry, bureaucracy, emperor,
and world order, in Islamic society, in contrast,
there was a vast mosaic of small groups with little
unity. These are better described as networks.
This distinction between hierarchies and networks anticipated a major development in social
scientific approaches to organization, systematized by, amongst others, W. W. Powell in “Neither
Market nor Hierarchy: Network Forms of Organisation” (1990) in Research in Organisational Behaviour
(12:295–333). This argument distinguished three
organizational forms: markets, hierarchies, and
networks. While markets are high on flexibility
and spatial reach they are by themselves low on
trust, and prone to opportunistic self-interest and
exit. Hierarchies are stronger on co-ordination
and formal control but often inflexible and poor
at incubating innovation. Between the two stand
networks which typically combine the flexibility
of markets with some of the co-ordinating capacity of hierarchies, albeit based on interpersonal
trust. This is the nearest network analysis has
come to a general theory.
Castells’s recent work offers an alternative perspective on network society. This proposes a new
form of global capitalism that draws on network
flexibility, enabled by information technology and
digitalization. Flows of capital, information, organizational interaction, images, sounds, and
symbols occur through the hubs and nodes of
virtual networks. For Castells, the centrality
of virtual networks extends to politics, which is
increasingly conducted through electronic media,
and to culture, where the new technology encourages networked individualism. Network society,
however, is dominated by mobile cosmopolitan
elites, and creates new forms of social exclusion
of the immobile poor.
This powerful body of work may, however, be
stronger on speculative plausibility than empirical accuracy. Critics point out that most
economic communication is not transacted electronically. Even those transactions that are
electronically enacted are not usually interactive.
Nor is activity on-line strongly networked since
much of it takes the form of mundane interpersonal emails. Even more damaging, there is no
necessary connection between information technology and globalization.
A contrasting, more historically informed approach to networks is provided by Randall Collins
in The Sociology of Philosophies (1998). Philosophical
ideas are neither engendered by heroic individuals nor do they arise spontaneously from the
415
new class theory
operation of structures or cultures. Rather they
develop within a finite number of interpersonal
networks. Particular networks link the relatively
small core of key individuals that constitute
schools, while debate and conflict between
schools is mediated through networks. Network
analysis helps explain why only a relatively small
number of philosophical schools form in any
given epoch, since ideas require articulation
and reproduction through teachers to pupils and
through wider connections between peers, in
order to be sustained in a robust and distinctive
form.
In the work of Castells and Collins, social network theory offers two contrasting approaches to
micro–macro linkages. The empirical research
programs entailed by these approaches remain
underdeveloped however.
ROBERT HOLTON
new class theory
– see social class.
New Deal
– see welfare reforms.
new institutionalism
The relationship between institutions and society,
long a central concern for sociology, was revitalized in the 1990s with the growth of interdisciplinary theories of institutions known as the
“new institutionalism.” The new institutionalism
is diverse, with different versions found in economics, international relations, political science,
and sociology (and differences within disciplines
between rational choice variants, comparativehistorical institutionalism, and organizational
institutionalism).
At the core of the new institutionalism in sociology are several key insights. At the level of organizational field, new institutionalists have argued
that organizations operate in distinctive environments which exert pressures for conformity, a
process known as institutional isomorphism (see
the influential collection of Walter Powell and
Paul DiMaggio, The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis, 1991). Over time, institutional
environments become coherent, predictable, and
ordered as organizations inexorably respond to isomorphic pressures. A second set of insights examine institutional influences on individual behavior
within organizational settings. Institutional rules
and norms have long been understood to shape
individual behavior, irrespective of the beliefs or
orientations of an individual before s/he enters
the organization.
416
new religious movements
To this traditional focus of institutional analysis, however, the new institutionalists have added
a focus on cognitive factors. In particular institutional settings, taken-for-granted understandings of acceptable behavior rule out alternative
choices. In this way, institutions exert cognitive
control over actors’ range of possible actions. Most
notable here have been the contributions of Richard Scott and his colleagues; see his Institutions and
Organizations (2001). In historical institutionalism,
the role of institutions in shaping political actors’
strategies and influencing political outcomes is
emphasized. Political institutions create certain
kinds of “path dependence” that favor some outcomes and discourage others. These institutional
constraints influence the strength of contending
groups, public opinion, and the content of specific
political or policy proposals that actors may propose, as illustrated in Sven Steinmo and K. Thelen
et al. (eds.), Structuring Politics: Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Analysis (1992). In all of these
ways, the new institutionalism has argued that
institutions have independent, autonomous
impacts on organizations, individuals, and social
and political conflicts. They are powerful carriers
of embedded social norms and rules, and modes of
acceptable behavior.
JEFF MANZA
new religious movements
The term new religious movements (NRMs) usually refers to the diverse range of religious groups
that emerged mostly in western countries in the
1960s and later. Although the presence of new
religious movements or sects (see church–sect
typology) has a much longer history, especially in
the United States, the phrase is customarily applied to movements that are seen as outside the
culturally established religious traditions. As part
of the broader critique and declining authority of
social institutions associated with the political
protest and identity movements of the 1960s,
many college-age youth in particular were drawn
towards participation in the alternative or countercultural norms articulated by NRMs and the
alternative values and lifestyles they promoted
and/or required of members (see C. Glock and
Robert N. Bellah [eds.], The New Religious Consciousness, 1976). Within Christianity, these movements
included Jesus-oriented groups such as “The Children of God” (now called “The Family”) and the
Charismatic Renewal Movement (which revolved
around Catholic prayer groups seeking a more
biblically grounded and emotional Catholicism),
as well as crossing religious traditions (such as
“Jews for Jesus”). The increasing appeal of eastern
new reproductive technologies
non-profit organizations
religious traditions was exemplified by the visibility and popularity of the Hare Krishna movement,
the Nation of Islam, and the Unificationist
movement of followers of the Korean spiritual
leader, Sun Myung Moon, popularly known as
the Moonies.
Although new religious movements represent a
small proportion of religious adherents in any
given society, their cultural exoticism relative to
the routines of institutionalized churches and to
accepted norms allows them to achieve a massmediated presence in the public sphere that bears
little relation to their numerical strength. Part of
this attention derives from the recruiting strategies (such as indoctrination and allegations of
brainwashing) and the somewhat volatile charismatic leadership associated with many of the
movements, and more generally from the disruption these movements, to a greater or lesser
extent, pose, or are seen as posing, to the moral
order (see E. Barker, The Making of a Moonie: Choice
or Brainwashing?, 1984). The communal living
and the values of communal property and interfamily parenting that characterize some NRMs challenge established definitions of private property,
marriage, and the functions of the family.
The disruptive power of new religious movements is illustrated most visibly by the violence
associated with some movements, notwithstanding the many complexities that may surround
the specific circumstances of any particular movement’s recourse to violence. Most notably, the
mass suicide of followers of Jim Jones at Jonestown in Guyana in 1978; the fire that killed the
Branch Davidian leader, David Koresh, and some
of his followers during the stand-off with federal
law-enforcement agents in Waco, Texas, in 1993;
the subway gas attacks in Tokyo in 1995 by the
Japanese movement, Aum Shinrikyo; and the Heaven’s Gate suicides in southern California in
1997 – all these insure that the typification of
violence with new religious movements becomes
imprinted in the public imagination (see J. Hall,
P. Schuyler, and S. Trinh, Apocalypse Observed: Religious Movements and Violence in North America, Europe
and Japan, 2000). Such negative associations, in
turn, attenuate efforts to shift attention to the
sociohistorical reasons why particular religious
movements emerge at the time and place and in
the form that they do, and to why they succeed,
however temporarily, in attracting followers.
MICHELE DILLON
new social movements
– see social movements.
new working class
– see social class.
Nisbet, Robert (1913–1996)
American sociologist and historian of ideas who
emphasized the importance of conservative ideas
for sociology, Nisbet attended the University of
California, Berkeley, where, under the supervision
of the cultural historian Frederick J. Teggart, he
pursued his doctorate on the thinkers of the “Reactionary Enlightenment.” The arguments and
ideas of a number of these thinkers, including E.
Burke, A. de Tocqueville, J. de Maistre, L. Bonald,
and F. R. Chateaubriand, formed the basis for
the rest of his work, which attacked rationalism,
individualism, and socialism, whose exemplary
embodiment he considered to be Jean-Jacques
Rousseau (1712–78).
In his first major work, The Quest of Community
(1953), he examined the disappearance of intermediate associations, such as the family, the
church, and the local community – which existed
as a crucial buffer between the individual and
society – as a result of the growing concentration
of power in a centralized, and potentially totalitarian, political state. The ensuing personal alienation and cultural disintegration that followed
led to a broadly based quest by individuals for
moral guidance and community. These arguments
were reworked in his classic study of The Sociological Tradition (1966), in which he examined five
“unit ideas,” all deriving from conservatism, and
which formed the nucleus of the sociological tradition: community, authority, social status, the
sacred, and alienation.
As well as examining the adverse consequences
of politicization for the university and the social
sciences in The Degradation of Academic Dogma
(1971) and The Idea of Progress (1980), he edited
two influential books, Contemporary Sociological
Problems (1961) with Robert K. Merton, and A
History of Sociological Thought (1978) with Tom
STEVEN LOYAL
Bottomore.
nominal measurement
– see measurement.
non-parametric statistics
– see statistics.
new reproductive technologies
non-profit organizations
– see reproduction.
– see voluntary associations.
417
non-response
non-response
– see sampling.
normalization
Defined as those social processes which pressure
individuals to conform to culturally desirable or
appropriate norms of behavior, the practice of
normalization produces certain ideals or standards against which the members of a society
are judged. Through this process, individuals are
socialized into believing that certain forms of behavior or self-presentation are acceptable and
valuable, while other behavior that transgresses
social expectations is not as acceptable or legitimate. Normalization is a key concept in the study of
social control. It helps sociologists understand
how societies develop rules governing conduct,
how they deal with deviance, how individuals
resist or challenge such norms, and how social
values and expectations within a society change
over time.
One way of defining norms is through simple
statistics. However, the standards which are produced and reinforced through the process of normalization are often regarded as more than
statistical averages. They are often socially valued
and presumed to be good, or even ideal. Certain
rewards (such as esteem, money, or access to resources) are often provided to those who conform
to, reinforce, or exceed, social norms. However,
those who do not conform to social norms may be
punished, socially excluded, or stigmatized. They
may be defined as “deviants” or “non-conformists”
and they may also be pathologized, and treated as
if they had a disease or disability.
Within the area of disability service provision,
the idea of normalization has a more specific
meaning. It is commonly identified with the
work of Wolf Wolfensberger whose theory of
“social role valorization” revolves around ways to
find normative social roles for disabled people.
This approach to disability makes a strong
effort to ensure that both service delivery and the
social relationships which disabled people have
reinforce their image as “normal,” socially valued
citizens.
Much of the sociological interest in the process
of normalization can be traced to the influence
of Michel Foucault, whose work suggested that
normalization is reproduced through various
institutional frameworks (including education,
medicine, the military, and the judicial system).
Foucault argued that these social institutions are
involved in various disciplinary practices which
418
norms
overlap and support one another, with the overall
effect of producing bodies that conform to certain
ideas, which he called “docile bodies.” Normalization is not only created through pressure from
social institutions though, Foucault’s later work
suggested that a major element of normalization
stems from the way people think about their own
bodies and their own behavior. An example of the
self-regulation of individuals in this manner can
be found in Susan Bordo’s discussion of the behavior of anorexics in Unbearable Weight (1993). She
suggests that anorexics are not only victims of
gendered social pressures to have slender bodies,
but are also engaged in self-regulation that
requires considerable will, and self-determination.
The behavior of anorexics can be understood,
Bordo argues, by focusing on the normalizing
pressures which lead women to have a preoccupation with fat, diet, and slenderness. In this way,
social norms about the physical body are seen to
reflect wider cultural codes around gender and
other social vulnerabilities.
The study of normalization begs the question,
“Who defines the norms?” Sociologists are therefore very interested in unpacking the power
dynamics that underpin normalization. They
study the ways individuals are encouraged, compelled, and coerced to regulate their behavior so
that it seems “normal,” but also how people resist
such pressures (both collectively and individually).
In this way, a study of normalization shows how
pressure to conform to social norms operates
within social interactions, as well as through a
person’s own desires to control their behavior or
image.
MARK SHERRY AND GARY L. ALBRECHT
norms
These are expectations shared by members of a
group or collectivity that more or less effectively
determine individual behavior. Norms typically
attach to social roles rather than human individuals, who in performance of their roles conform to
a greater or lesser extent to norms. The concept of
norm is located in various categories associated
with the development of sociology.
William Graham Sumner, for instance, in Folkways (1906), holds that collective life, necessary for
individual survival, requires the preservation of
efficacious experience, stored in and communicated as custom. Custom is the collective form of
individual habit. Folkways are produced, according to Sumner, in the frequent repetition of petty
acts. Folkways are accepted because of the conviction that they are conducive to societal welfare and
norms
can therefore be defined as systems of persisting
expedient customary behavior. Sumner says that,
within a group, folkways are uniform, universal,
imperative, and invariable; over time they become
increasingly arbitrary. Socially formed and selected inferences derived from folkways, Sumner calls
mores. Mores consist largely but not exclusively of
taboos (see sacred and profane dichotomy), things
that should not be done. A characteristic of mores,
as coercive ethical principles, is the likelihood
that they will contain an explicit rationalization
or reason for adherence to them, for example
don’t eat pork because pigs are unclean. Sumner’s
approach was related to Social Darwinism. Believing that social change is achieved through the
evolution of folkways and the development of
folkways into mores is no longer in vogue.
Talcott Parsons argues that, through social
interaction, persons are able to communicate
because signs and symbols acquire common
meaning. By virtue of a shared meaning system
there arises a mutuality of expectations and sanctions that constitutes what Parsons calls a normative order in The Social System (1951). Thus norms
operate through internalization of a standard of
group expectations and are maintained by the
reactions of others, both positive and negative.
These reactions are sanctions that reward conformity to role expectations and punish departure
nuclear family
from expectation such as deviance. For Parsons,
the institutionalization of both expectation and
sanction constitutive of norms is achieved in varying degrees. Anomie occurs in the absence of institutionalization. Norms therefore are not to be
located at the level of individual social actor
but necessarily function in the institutionalized
activity of a plurality of social actors.
While the notion of norm can adequately describe the habitual institutional patterns of a
society, explanations of societal processes in
terms of norms risks accounting for regularities
of social action in terms of expectations. In fact,
interaction in groups or societies may result from
a number of possible factors, of which norms are
only one. One alternative approach to explanation
of social process points not to the system of
norms, but to power relations and the balance of
power that is the outcome of social conflict between groups. Exponents of this approach include
Ralph Dahrendorf in Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society (1959) and John Rex in Key Problems of
Sociological Theory (1961). David Lockwood’s Solidarity and Schism (1992) developed a sophisticated
critique of the normative approach that avoids
the problems of conflict theory.
JACK BARBALET
nuclear family
– see family.
419
O
John O’Neill (1933– )
A distinguished research professor emeritus at
York University, Canada, and a Fellow of the Royal
Society of Canada, O’Neill developed a critical
interpretation of sociology in his Sociology as a
Skin Trade (1972) and Making Sense Together (1974).
His work is characterized by an attempt to bridge
the gap between the humanities and the social
sciences, which is illustrated in his Essaying
Montaigne. A Study of the Renaissance Institution of
Writing and Reading (1982). He contributed to the
development of the sociology of the body in his
Five Bodies. The Human Shape of Modern Society (1985)
and The Communicative Body (1989). He was critical
of postmodernism in his The Poverty of Postmodernism. More recently, he has made two important
contributions to the sociology of citizenship in
which he has been concerned to examine the
status of children in modern society in his The
Missing Child in Liberal Theory (1994) and Civic
Capitalism. The State of Childhood (2004). He is a
founding editor of the Journal of Classical Sociology.
BRYAN S. TURNER
Oakley, Ann (1944– )
A British sociologist who has worked on diverse
issues related to the specific condition and experience of women, Oakley’s earliest work was a study
of the politics and gender relations of housework
(The Sociology of Housework, 1972, and Housewife,
1974). Informing both those texts was a concern
with the isolation of women in the home and
what was – at the time – a refusal of the social
world to recognize the unpaid domestic work of
women (see women and work). Oakley’s later work
has been concerned with medical aspects of
women’s lives, particularly childbirth and the
transition to motherhood. In a number of studies
(Becoming a Mother, 1979, and The Captured Womb,
1984), Oakley criticized the male control and medicalization of childbirth and the loss of an autonomous female voice in questions related to women
and reproduction. Oakley’s work has been widely
influential in the management of childbirth in
the United Kingdom.
420
In recent years, Oakley has written fiction (for
example The Men’s Room, 1991) and studies of the
way in which gender informs global politics and
the universal organization of social life (Gender on
Planet Earth, 2003). Throughout her work Oakley
has argued that it is socialization that creates and
maintains the social prioritization of the male
and the masculine; her many crosscultural references demonstrate her awareness of cultural difference in the construction of gender roles and
behavior. Oakley has worked with Juliet Mitchell
on collections of essays discussing the meaning of
feminism and has maintained a consistent loyalty
to a politics which affirms the voices and concerns
of women.
MARY EVANS
objectivity
A quality of mind such that the investigator is
enabled to discern the true properties of the phenomenon being studied by remaining free from
bias or prejudice, objectivity is often considered to
be a goal of scientific investigation.
Researchers have deployed a number of strategies to aid impartial investigation. These include
attention to validity, reliability, and sampling.
Finally, because published research reports are
available for public scrutiny, and in many cases
have been peer reviewed, the authors’ claims can
be critically assessed for personal prejudices.
The distinction between scientific facts and
social (or political) values was important for both
Émile Durkheim and Max Weber. Weber argued
that scientists can only report on facts and, while
they may involve themselves in political polemics,
they may maintain objectivity through compliance with scientific protocols and proceeding
in accordance with standard rules of evidence
and proof. In Alvin Gouldner’s 1962 analysis of
Weber in Social Problems, “Anti-minotaur: The
Myth of a Value-free Sociology,” interpretation of
facts may be infused with personal values, but the
research techniques that produce those facts are
value-neutral.
The quest for objectivity has been met with
resistance on a number of points. One of the
occupational segregation
arguments against objectivity concerns the debate between realism and relativism. Relativists
argue that scientific truth may be different seen
from different perspectives, thus there can be
multiple and non-contradictory reports of the
same phenomenon.
There is also opposition to the positivistic
notion that sociologists should seek to imitate
the natural sciences. While sociology may employ
systematic methods of inquiry and evidence-based
theories, human activity and interactions may require different approaches to investigation from
objects of nature. The reality of sociological research means that access and rapport with one’s
informants is often a consequence of a personal
approach from one human being to another
rather than from scientist to subject. If sociologists are determined to maintain their objective
stance they are at risk of damaging their fieldwork
relationships. Emotional distance will in turn
affect what the subject allows the researcher to
observe or hear about their lives. Feminist research has led the main challenge to the positivist
orthodoxy that sociology should strive to be objective, arguing that it is only by a transition to
friendship and a collaborative approach to research that a more insightful account of women’s
experiences will be generated.
It has also been argued that sociological work
cannot be objective in that it is influenced by
sociologists’own experiences and values. Sociology
is by its very nature ideologically driven, thus the
notion of value-free social inquiry is unsustainable. Thus, Howard S. Becker, in his paper in
Social Problems, “Whose Side are we on?” (1967),
maintained that sociologists are constantly presenting someone’s point of view and have traditionally been unable to remain neutral in the
face of moral and political controversies. The issue
therefore focuses less on whether objectivity has
been maintained but rather whose interests are
served by the sociologists’ subjectivity. Sociologists may therefore be caught in an ethical tension between a desire to present themselves as
objective to their audiences and their commitment to principles of social justice.
MICK BLOOR AND FIONA WOOD
occupational segregation
– see occupations.
occupations
In complex societies with a high division of labor
specialized work roles develop. On the one hand,
Émile Durkheim argued in the Division of Labour in
occupations
Society (1893 [trans. 1960]) that this increased interdependence of each of us on others leads to social
integration. On the other hand, Karl Marx claimed
that such specialization leads to alienation and
the fragmentation of the self. What is clear, however, following the work of Max Weber, is that
occupational roles provide the basis for a social
hierarchy, with some being positively valued
status groups and others negatively valued. The
Registrar General in the United Kingdom explicitly recognizes this hierarchy, providing a list of
social classes based on occupation. These are:
I. professionals; II. managerial; IIIN. skilled nonmanual occupations; IIIM; skilled manual occupations; IV. partly skilled occupations; V. unskilled
occupations; and VI. the armed forces. Occupational inequalities thus provide sociologists with
a proxy measure of class differences. For example,
sociologists use this classification to examine the
impact of occupation on life-chances, and sociologists of health and illness have demonstrated that
people in socio-economic classes V and VI have
lower life expectancy and higher morbidity than
people from the non-manual classes (I, II, and IIIN).
Feminist sociologists have also demonstrated
that occupations are structured by gender, with
women pooling in the “pink-collar occupations” of
nursing, teaching, and service and secretarial
work, a phenomenon known as “occupational segregation.” Even where women participate in male
occupations, they find it difficult to rise to the
top, either because of the existence of a “glass
ceiling,” as informal sanctions are applied, or the
“mommy effect” as they break their careers to rear
a family. Women also tend to be concentrated in
the “caring occupations.” This impact of gender
on the structure of occupations is reflected in the
fact that, even when women medical practitioners
go on to specialize, they do so, for example, in
psychiatry and pediatrics, reflecting wider social
assumptions about their caring and nurturing
roles.
Occupational groups protect themselves to enhance their social status and income, a process
known as social closure, through credentialism.
That is, they set entry criteria, usually marked by
tertiary-sector qualifications, that are not necessary to the performance of the occupational role.
This closure has the effect of keeping out lower
social-status groups, and especially ethnic minorities, who do not have access to the resources
(such as time and money) to pursue these qualifications. The occupational structure of society thus
both reflects and maintains patterns of social inequality based on class, gender, and race and
421
Ogburn, William F. (1886–1959)
online communities
ethnicity. Participation in an occupation is less
likely to be structured as a career, as is the case
for the professions, to be more discontinuous,
and in postindustrial society, to be insecure and,
increasingly, part-time.
KEVIN WHITE
Ogburn, William F. (1886–1959)
A lifetime proponent of empirical positivism,
Ogburn pioneered the study of social change and
the systematic use of social indicators. Born in
Butler, Georgia, and raised in a middle-class
home, Ogburn studied under Franklin Henry
Giddings (1855–1931) at Columbia University and
received his PhD in sociology for a statistical analysis of child labor laws in 1912. He spent most of his
career at the University of Chicago (from 1927
until retiring in 1951) where, during a time of
ascendant qualitative studies, his quantitative approach attracted a number of distinguished
scholars, including Samuel Stouffer and Otis
Dudley Duncan.
While he was skeptical about the value of social
theory, Ogburn’s work Social Change (1922) had a
huge impact on the theory of social evolution.
He argued that social change is brought about
not by social action but by “inventions” – novel
combinations of existing cultural material. Social
problems, in turn, emerge from disjunctures, or
“cultural lags,” between one aspect of culture that
changes due to invention, and another aspect of
culture that must adjust accordingly.
In his 1929 presidential address to the American
Sociological Society, Ogburn predicted that
sociology would become increasingly a science of
“verification and proof.” The methodological
domains he cultivated include ambitious projects
of interdisciplinary cooperation, techniques to
measure social change, and large-scale government surveys to inform policymakers (largely
through work as Director of the President’s
Research Committee on Social Trends [1930–3]).
Through his study of secular social trends, Ogburn
came to argue that such trends usually persist
even in the face of disruptive events – so much
so that deviations from these trends are more
noticeable than the overall course of change.
DONALD N. LEVINE
oligarchy
According to the classic Aristotelian typology, oligarchy is a system of rule by a few, exercised in
their own interest. It is contrasted with monarchy,
aristocracy, tyranny, democracy, and polity. Classic
elite theorists Vilfredo Pareto, Gaetano Mosca,
and Robert Michels, who popularized the term,
422
saw oligarchies as synonymous with consolidated elites. Michels in Political Parties (1958)
coined a famous “iron law of oligarchy”: all complex bureaucracies give rise to elites. For some
social analysts, oligarchy acquires a more specific
meaning.
In The Class Structure of the Advanced Societies
(1973), Anthony Giddens analyzed effective power
in relation to elite formation (consolidated versus
diffuse power), and “issue-strength” (broad versus
issue-specific). He defined oligarchic rule as involving consolidated “strategic” elites with power over
a restricted/specialized set of issues. Such oligarchic elite power was contrasted with autocracy
(consolidated elites and broad power), hegemony
(diffused and broad), and democracy (diffused and
restricted). Traditional oligarchies consisted typically of top aristocratic families (magnates) controlling monarchs. Modern oligarchies take many
forms. Power elites involve the leaders of big
business, the top government officials, and the
top echelons of the military. Strategic elites include a number of well-integrated but sectorspecific elite groups. Ruling class (see social class)
is an oligarchy consisting of owners and controllers of corporate capital. The inner circle consists
of executives of the largest corporations. Some
students of communist elites refer to “party–
state” power oligarchies (the nomenklatura). The
term oligarchy is seldom used in contemporary
sociology of politics; it has been largely superseded by the term elite(s).
JAN PAKULSKI
online communities
Both the idea and practice of communities have
always been an essential component of sociological theorizing. Such communities were originally location-based constructs. But as studies of
them deepened, another category has developed,
namely the idea of conceptual communities. Thus,
one could for instance speak of the scientific
community. The enormous growth in online activities has led scholars to question whether communities could exist online, and what differences
might arise between traditional physically based
communities and their online counterparts.
C. Arensberg and S. Kimball in Culture and Community (1965) identify three elements to the concept of community: environment, social form, and
patterned behavior. I. Sanders in The Community
(1966) asserted there were four: a place to live, a
spatial unit, a way of life, and a social system.
Using the former, it can be argued that online
groupings that have these elements can qualify
as a community. Reliance on the physical and
ontology
spatial dimensions of the term, by, for example,
Sanders, would force one to dismiss the possibility
of online communities at all. Yet despite their lack
of physical reality, it seems plausible that, since
communities are mental constructs in the first
place, they could be virtual as well as physical in
their nature. Interestingly, the absence of the
necessity of overcoming geographical distance,
combined with computer processing power, makes
many new types of communities possible.
J. Meyrowitz in No Sense of Place (1985) has argued
that communities, both online and off, can be
viewed in a context that is both upward to institutions and downward to social roles. He analyzes
social roles and identities in terms of information
systems that comprise patterns of access to social
information, determined by the mix of physical
settings, media, and mental constructs. Regarding
mental constructs, he extends George Herbert
Mead’s notion of the generalized other to the
mediated generalized other. He describes how
people gain a sense of who they are in part by
imagining how others, both live and mediated,
view them. Additionally, he anticipated much discussion of virtual life by advancing the notion of
the generalized elsewhere, wherein one imagines
how distant others imagine one’s own location
and general environment. With considerable variation, this schema allows one to have a grasp of
the general theoretical outlines possible in attempting to pin down, then contrast, online communities to their physical counterparts.
JAMES E. KATZ
ontology
In sociology, an ontology responds to generic (that
is transhistorical and transcultural) questions
about the properties of social life. Though quite
fundamental to all disciplinary concerns, ontological issues in sociology are more modest
than ontological issues in the broadest philosophical sense. In philosophy, ontology refers to metaphysical issues concerned with the nature of
existence and the structure of reality at large, a
concern that has intellectual precedents reaching
as far back as Aristotle (384–322 BC). Whereas most
philosophical schemes are hierarchical, with some
form of human “being” or “existence” at the top,
sociological ontologies may be more loosely structured and do not concern themselves with “being”
at all. Thus, the twentieth-century ontologies
by Martin Heidegger and the early Jean-Paul
Sartre have no correlated sociological ontologies.
Examples of sociological ontologies include structuration theory, which identifies structured social
organicism
practices as the basic constituents of all aspects of
social reality. Karl Marx’s preface to Critique of
Political Economy (1849 [trans. 1859]) includes a
crude materialist ontology. The well-known first
chapter of Émile Durkheim’s Rules of Sociological
Method (1895 [trans. 1958]) makes an elementary
case for a collectivist ontology. Some commentators interpret Max Weber’s basic concepts of
social action in ontological terms, though others
disagree.
Though social theorists have always relied upon
ontologies, the term only recently entered the
lexicon in the wake of the declining influence of
positivism in the 1970s. Positivists tried to deny
that what they termed metaphysical issues had
any legitimate place in scientific thought. The
term ontology gave these issues a place to stand
in post-Kuhnian sociological theory.
IRA COHEN
Operationalization
– see Falsification.
organic anology
– see organicism.
organicism
Sociology has often linked human society to
organisms. Herbert Spencer, for example, drew
attention to the fact that low animals or the
embryos of high animals have few distinguishable
parts, their elements becoming more numerous
and differentiated during evolution or lifetime
development. Similarly, he suggested, societies
become increasingly complex and subdivided as
they grow. Émile Durkheim’s well-known distinction between “mechanical” and “organic” forms of
sociology also relies on an organic analogy, one in
which society becomes more complex as it develops. In the middle of the twentieth century,
Talcott Parsons argued for a general evolutionary
law, change again taking the form of increasing
differentiation between elements of the social
“subsystem” – the home and the factory, for
example. Forms of organicism are alive and well,
especially among German sociologists strongly influenced by Parsons. Niklas Luhmann, for example,
envisaged society as a set of distinct subsystems
with their own rules and codes, making society
very complex and difficult to manage.
Analogies between societies and organisms
were important in establishing sociology as a new
discipline. But they are highly misleading when
carried too far. Organicism can easily become
teleological, social change apparently having a
direction, purpose, and maturity, processes
423
organization man
organization theory
analogous to human growth and which all societies must inevitably experience. Another questionable implication is that of an unproblematic
“progress” being steadily made, “simple” societies
being replaced by more complex social forms.
More generally, organicism can be criticized for
implying that human societies, with all their
power relations and divisions of labor, are somehow a product of nature. Despite such criticisms,
however, organicism has had an important heuristic value, suggesting new hypotheses about
social change and social organization.
PETER DICKENS
organization man
William H. Whyte’s The Organization Man (1956)
was a famous commentary on American business
culture, but it belongs to another era: one in
which careers could be foreseen in a large organizational bureaucracy, in an era before feminism,
with its demands for a new type of man as well as
the equal participation of women, a new approach
to parenting, and a new set of commitments. It
was also an era before downsizing, rationalization,
and outsourcing threatened individual careers
and lives. The organization man of the title was
expected to be a loyal and conformist member of
the organization. Indeed, in mid-1950s America,
he was expected to be a loyal and conformist
American.
Whyte was doubly well placed to produce an
outstanding ethnography of the organization
man. First, the times were right: he wrote during
the height of the Eisenhower administration
(1953–61), when corporations appeared to provide
all the necessities of modern life – careers, consumer goods in abundance, and suburban lifestyles.
Second, as an editor of Fortune, Whyte could observe corporate America up close, and what he
saw belied what he and many others believed.
America was shifting from a land of individual
initiative to one of corporate control.
Whyte observed that the young men who
entered organizations saw their whole working
lives as being committed at that point: their interests were inexorably tied to those of the organizations that employed them. The assumption was
that they would be rewarded in their career for
the time they invested in the organization. The
Organization Man showed the white-collar employee as increasingly shaped by employer
demands: focused on advancement through the
firm, he became narrow, conformist, and unwilling to innovate. This figure’s fear of original
thought and his lifestyle (situated in rationalized
424
suburbs and marked by consumption rather than
community) stood in direct opposition to the
ideology of American competitive individualism.
As recently as the 1980s, Whyte revisited the
organization man and claimed little had changed.
Today he would have to draw different conclusions. The social contract has been broken.
Managers and professionals work harder than
ever – but more often than not for their individual
as much as organization interests. While organizations seek to align individual and organization
interests with inducements and salaries, they do
not promise lifelong careers. Project-based careers
are increasingly becoming the order of the day.
Downsizing does not produce loyalty but survivor
syndromes, where loyalty is contingent, bought
with high salaries, bonuses, and stock options,
until a better offer comes along or until the manager is dismissed. Pay is performance-related, and
managers cannot afford to slacken the intensity of
their work if they are to maximize their income.
The expectation is, increasingly, of a career in
projects and parts, rather than a commitment to
one organization, with the expectation of the pursuit of central life-interests occurring outside work
rather than through the job. Organizations have
increasingly become de-bureaucratized and more
marketized, with correlative shrinkage of organization-man opportunities. While cultural consent
may still be valued, it is increasingly bought and
specifically contingent on the risk/reward package
negotiated.
STEWART CLEGG
organization theory
The work of Max Weber was initially influential in
shaping the sociological analysis of organizations.
It offered a unifying frame – the theory of bureaucracy – within which to research organization
processes and, unlike early management theory,
did not offer prescriptive and mutually contradictory principles. Typically, researchers first started
to interpret organizations using Weber’s ideas,
which they then revised as they attended to features of reality that were not captured in his
model, producing an influential body of postwar
work (see, for example, that reviewed in S. Clegg,
M. Kornberger, and T. Pitsis, Managing and Organizations, 2005). Until the mid-1950s, the case study
was the dominant method of research and Weber a
central resource. These were based on substantive
aspects of specific cases, and thus their generalizability was low and hard to cumulate into a consistent body of interrelated theoretical knowledge.
In the 1950s, after the emergence of the journal Administrative Science Quarterly, the systems
organization theory
perspective came increasingly to dominate organization analysis. The perspective solved some problems inherent to the typological approaches.
Systems perspectives such as that of Talcott
Parsons promised a general approach to any and
every organization, conceived as a system of
inputs, transformation processes, and outputs.
General systems theory was scientifically influential and organizations became a specialist domain
of its analysis.
Emerging out of systems theory in the 1960s
was the approach known as contingency theory.
Organizations were still seen as systems but
they had to deal with specific contingencies that
shaped their structure, such as their size, technology, environment, and the national culture in
which they were embedded. While the earlier
generation of researchers used case studies, contingency research was characterized by survey
methods and larger samples, seeking to operationalize factors identified in the earlier literature,
such as Weber’s fifteen dimensions of bureaucracy.
From the 1970s onwards, a number of new
currents emerged. First, the influence of the labor
process approach, derived from H. Braverman’s
Labor and Monopoly Capitalism (1974), spawned a
renewed fascination with case studies, such as
the work of M. Burawoy on Manufacturing Consent
(1979), many of which were reported in a series of
edited volumes that represented the work of the
labor process conference, held annually from
1983. Second, from the early 1980s onwards, there
was a renewed interest in Weberian theory, as a
result of two related trends. One was the reemergence of institutional theory, after the publication
of P. DiMaggio and W. W. Powell’s seminal paper
on the “iron cage” in the American Journal of
Sociology (1984); the other was the popular success
of G. Ritzer’s Weberian-inspired analysis of organizational rationalization in The McDonaldization of
Society (1993).
Further, from a sociological perspective, one
would have to count the influence of population
ecology, an approach influenced by general ecological theory, which concentrates on populations
of organizations and changes at the population
level, typically dealing with big changes over large
datasets, across significant periods of time, often
using datasets that were not generated by the
researchers themselves but which were available
or constructed from available sets. The approach
was based more on the statistical testing of relations between constructs than upon intimate
research knowledge. It was a sociological approach
organizational culture
premised on biological models but one whose
peak of influence seems to have passed. More recently, in the 1990s and beyond, the influence of
Foucauldian-inspired genealogical analysis has
begun to make an impact on the field, perhaps
best represented in A. McKinley and K. Starkey’s
Foucault, Management and Organization Theory (1997).
Closely related, but hotly contested, are more postmodern approaches, debates about which may be
found in E. Locke’s Postmodernism in Organizational
Thought (2003).
All of the above may safely be thought of as a
part of sociological approaches to organizations.
However, with the massive growth in business and
management programs across the world in the
recent past, today the vast majority of organization theory is taught not in sociology but in business and management faculties. Typically, the
definition of what constitutes organization theory
in such places may be less sociological than the
currents identified here. For instance, a number of
economic approaches to organization theory have
developed, the most significant of which is known
as transaction-cost analysis, as seen for example in
O. E. Williamson’s The Economic Institutions of Capitalism (1985). Increasingly, organization and management theory is being taught by people with
little or no trained capacity as sociologists – a
situation quite dissimilar to the generation of
work done in the aftermath of World War II.
Nonetheless, organization theory remains one of
the more populous and significant homes of applied sociology.
STEWART CLEGG
organizational culture
T. Peters and R. Waterman’s In Search of Excellence
(1982) placed organizational culture center stage.
The message was simple: great companies have
excellent cultures. Culture was typically defined
in terms that stressed a pattern of learned and
shared basic assumptions, framing how organization members perceive, think, and feel. It was
presumed that if you forged a strong culture –
one that incorporates all organization members
in shared beliefs and commitments – then everything else – good morale, performance, and
results – should follow. Having such a widely
shared and integrative culture in organizations
became seen as a panacea for management and
an algorithm for corporate success.
Organization theorists were relative latecomers
to the consideration of culture in the pantheon of
social science but may be said to have discovered
it quite early in the development of their field.
425
organization(s)
organization(s)
F. W. Taylor sought to create a single utilitarian
culture to minimize employee resistance and
maximize productivity – and, of course, earnings.
However, it is clear that Taylor in his Principles
of Scientific Management (1911) did not have an explicit analytical focus on culture. The earliest
confirmed sighting seems to be when F. Roethlisberger and W. Dickson realized, in Management
and the Worker (1939), that the most significant
variables governing the output at the Hawthorne
Plant appeared not to be physical but social. As
N. Mouzelis pointed out in Organization and Bureaucracy, they defined the “culture of the group”
(1967: 99).
Since at least E. Mayo’s The Social Problems of an
Industrial Civilization (1975), managers have had
available the use of various types of expert knowledge (psycho-technological and managerial) for
the management of culture. Increasingly, managers have sought to regulate workers through
attending to their thoughts and emotions as
well as securing compliance for shaping workers’
attitudes and sentiments.
Recent approaches argue that organizational
culture will always be fragmentary (and contingent on identities deriving from occupational, regional, social class, ethnic, gender, and other
forms of social marker, under highly variable local
conditions). However, all approaches understand
cultures (whether fragmented or homogeneous) as
extremely important patterns that shape organizational realities. Understanding organizations
means understanding their culture.
STEWART CLEGG
organization(s)
Although the medieval monastery became the
template for rational bureaucratic organization,
the transfer of the organization form to secular
society occurred primarily through the modern state developing extensive bureaucracies, in
areas such as education. These forms were later
replicated in commerce and industry.
In industry, the central issue became the maximization of private profit. Owners of capital had
to be able to exercise regular and routine dominion and sway over the working lives of those on
whom its reproduction depended. Industrial property owners could not rely on feudal fealty to
deliver able and willing bodies, as did the lords
of old; however, it was a matter of record that they
often found religious deference and piety to be
invaluable assets. Authority that could claim it
had God on its side stood a better chance of
426
success, as Max Weber realized in The Protestant
Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1905 [trans. 2002]).
In the early days of industrialism, a combination of heavy doses of paternalism, rough discipline, and an efficient labor market buttressed less
secular sources of moral authority with sheer necessity. More traditional relations could often
overlie the wage relations that mostly bound production. In lieu of internalized religious ritual or
deference to feudal hierarchy, management control seemed best assured through the routine disciplining of those employed.
In small craft workshops, discipline was relatively easy to enact, organized around mastery of
a specific knowledge, such as how to make barrels,
fabricate metal, or weave wool. In such a structure, the master was presumed to know the craft,
which apprentices were presumed not to know
and had every motive for learning, so that they
too could become skilled workers. The master exercised power by getting the apprentice to do
things in the favored way. Authority was based
on power unified with knowledge: masters owned
the workshop as well as expert knowledge of how
to work in it. Effective oversight was by direct
control of people in the workshop. The early days
of modern management and organizations were
bootstrapped. Primitive methods of surveillance
and drill were adapted, panopticons proposed,
and elements from preindustrial craft relations
incorporated. Bootstrapped solutions worked appropriately for as long as the scale of enterprise
remained small.
There were two distinct shortcomings associated with expanding scale. To grow large meant
expending capital. The capital in circulation in
the early industrial economy was relatively small
compared to that invested in landed estates. It was
raised mostly through merchants combining
credit with rented buildings and machinery, together with cheap sources of labor. Keeping costs
low meant that, if the enterprise were to fail, the
liability and exposure of the emergent entrepreneurs would be limited.
It was the institutional innovation of limited
liability legislation, pioneered first in Britain
in 1856, but widely copied internationally, that
enabled enterprises to grow by separating the
private fortunes of entrepreneurs from their investments in business; if the latter failed, personal
fortunes were sequestered and the debtors’ prison
was avoided.
Limited liability legislation did not resolve the
problem of how to manage the vastly expanded
Orientalism
Orientalism
enterprise. How was the master to achieve effective governance over a vastly increased scale
of operations? Two resolutions to the puzzle of
how to ensure mastery were proposed: one adopted a market solution while the other copied what
had already occurred in the large-scale public
service of the day and threw in its lot with
bureaucracy.
In firms that were taken over by use of the new
financial instruments, owners of previously independent businesses were re-employed as internal
contractors to oversee the processes of labor.
One consequence of internal contracting – where
the contractor used materials, plant, and equipment supplied by the owners but managed the
labor contracted to deliver a certain quantity of
product – was that quite different methods of
internal control could flourish in different plants
in the same industry. Standards were highly variable. However, under pressure for more standardization from both financial controllers and
emergent unions, internal contracting gave way
to a bureaucratization of relations of production
in large concerns, such that, by the early twentieth century, Weber noted that bureaucracy had
become the fate of our times. Weber argued that
no special proof was required to demonstrate
that military discipline was the ideal model for
the modern capitalist factory in the early twentieth century. Since that time, standardization – as
the blueprint for designing modern organizations
– has increasingly stressed being disciplined and
being visible. Order, discipline, and authority were
to become the organizational watchwords of the
new world under construction, and have remained
at the core of much organization ever since.
STEWART CLEGG
Orientalism
The modern debate about western views of the
Orient was significantly influenced by Edward
Said’s Orientalism (1978). However, the anthropological controversy about “other cultures” can be
traced back to the European encounter with its
colonies, and hence, over an even longer period,
between Christianity and its antagonists. Said’s
controversial paradigm had the effect of establishing the notion of “Orientalism” as a specific and
pervasive ideology about Asian societies. His
critique has laid the contemporary foundation
for an extensive inquiry into the problematic relationships between power, sexual desire, religious
identity and cultural dominance.
Orientalism is a largely implicit paradigm
within which Oriental civilizations have been
understood by the West. It makes a clear distinction between the Orient and the Occident, emphasising the rationality, reflectivity, and dynamism
of the latter. In its sociological versions, Orientalism has been associated with theories of modernization, in which the Orient is regarded as
stationary and unchanging. One illustration is
the comparative sociology of Max Weber who
regarded rationalization and asceticism in Christian sects as unique characteristics of western
modernity. The general argument of Orientalism
has been that the Orient has not experienced the
revolutions that shook the West, and hence has
not experienced an independent form of modernization. Orientalists argue that, for example, Islam
is inherently incompatible with democracy. Orientalism has been criticized, for example by Andre
Guider Frank, on the grounds that the paradigm
seriously underestimates the dynamic nature of
economic and social change in India and China.
In recent sociological debates about “otherness,” Said’s criticisms of the Orientalist tradition
are typically associated with the critical social
theory of Michel Foucault. Representations of the
Orient are seen to be manifestations of an enduring ideological paradigm that constructs the
Orient as an object of scientific knowledge. Said’s
analysis of Orientalism was also influenced
by Erich Auerbach’s Mimesis (1946 [trans. 1953]).
Written in Istanbul between 1942 and 1945,
and published in German, it was a study of the
literary practices by which reality was represented through definite stylistic conventions. Said’s
Orientalism can be said to do for French literary
representations of the Orient what Mimesis attempted more generically to do for western literature as a whole. Said also relied heavily on
Raymond Schwab’s The Oriental Renaissance (1950
[trans. 1984]) that first provided the concept of
Orientalism in a study of western attitudes towards India. In short, Said’s account of Orientalism belongs to a recognizable heritage of western
self-reflection in the context of the engagement
with other cultures.
Said’s account of Orientalism has been criticized because it failed, for example, to differentiate clearly between French, British, and Spanish
views of the Orient. His work was largely focused
on the Middle East, and had little to say about
Asia. Despite the criticisms of Said, the debate
about Orientalism has produced a rich, critical
literature on the consequences of colonialism,
and the attempt to explain modernization comparatively still remains a major task of the social
sciences.
BRYAN S. TURNER
427
Ossowski, Stanislaw (1897–1963)
Ossowski, Stanislaw (1897–1963)
A Polish sociologist writing on social structure,
methodology, social psychology, aesthetics, and
art, Ossowski led the post-Stalinist revival of
Polish sociology, served as a President of the Polish
Sociological Association (1956–63), and cofounded the International Sociological Association. While his analyses cover a wide range of
topics, Ossowski is best known for his synthesis
of humanistic (interpretive) sociology with rigorous empirical analysis, and for his influential
study of Class Structure in the Social Consciousness
(1957 [trans. 1963]). He analyzed the three major
interpretations of the class structure: the functional, stressing complementarity; the gradation
(“social ladder”) highlighting hierarchy; and the
polar one (owners versus workers) emphasizing
social antagonism. He identified the social functions of these three interpretations: while functional and gradation schemes were typically
embraced by the supporters of the social order in
the upper strata, the polar schemes served as
idioms of radical social contestation. The concept
428
oversocialized conception of man
of “classlessness” was used by Ossowski in his analyses of gradation schemes popularized in the
United States and the “non-antagonistic” class
visions promoted in the then Soviet Union. In
this context, he pointed to the inadequacy of
Marxist class schemes for the analysis of social
hierarchy and division in modern industrial society. Anticipating the criticism of class orthodoxy
by the students of industrial society, he suggested
that modernization brings increasing complexity
of social divisions. The social distribution of
privilege and disadvantage reflects not only
the control of the means of production, but
also – and increasingly – the control of the means
of compulsion (authority), and the means of
consumption.
JAN PAKULSKI
other-directed character
– see David Riesman.
oversocialized conception of man
– see Dennis Hume Wrong.
P
panel study
paradigm
These studies offer researchers the opportunity to
follow the same group of research participants
over time; they differ from cross-sectional studies
(although they may represent sub-components of
some cross-sectional studies) in that they allow
researchers to track changes in the views, attitudes, and reported behaviors of a defined panel
on a longitudinal rather than “snapshot” basis.
Panel studies promise to analyze the effect of
“real-world” events on particular social groupings.
For classic examples of such studies, see the British
Household Survey or the University of Michigan –
Institute for Social Research’s Panel Study of
Income Dynamics (PSID), which has followed a
representative sample of 8,000 United States
households, or 65,000 individuals, since 1968.
Panels may be any social unit with a sufficient
degree of theoretical homogeneity to make the
study empirically compelling: thus panels may
consist in households, university graduates of
a given year (otherwise known as age-cohorts),
or other groupings with a common and datesensitive life experience such as the birth of a first
child. Panels, once constituted, are regularly
mined for data, most often using interviews or
other standardized surveys, to explore the relationships between lived experience, social factors,
and period effects.
Difficulties with panel studies are attrition (if
people are followed over months and years some
leave the area forgetting to provide a forwarding
address, emigrate, or die) a difficulty that may be
ameliorated by the adoption of a dynamic sample
panel whereby matching “replacement” panel
members are substituted for those who drop out.
Alternatively, the dynamic methodology may be
used to control for “experience bias” – that is to
say, respondents becoming practiced at providing
material that the researchers wish to hear.
The concept of paradigm, used by Thomas Samuel
Kuhn in his classic book, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions (1962), was taken from its use to describe
model “correct” sentences in Latin. Kuhn argued
that in science, scientific discourse was rooted in
exemplary achievements, such as experiments,
which served as models of the correct way to approach scientific problems. Kuhn further argued
that major conceptual changes in science, which
he called scientific revolutions, typically consisted
of changes in what constituted a paradigmatic
achievement, what constituted a scientific problem, what counted as evidence, and the meanings
of the terms themselves, which derives from their
place in practice and in the conceptual scheme.
He used psychological terms such as Gestalt and
sociological terms such as worldview to characterize paradigms, emphasizing their pervasive worldconstituting role, and emphasized the role of
scientific communities in sustaining them.
The most distinctive of the ideas making up the
concept of paradigm was also the most problematic to Kuhn, namely incommensurability, meaning non-comparability.
Kuhn’s notion of scientific revolution raised the
question of what sense could be given to the notion
of progress in science or to the notion of science
as increasingly approaching higher degrees of
STEPHEN P. TURNER
truth.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
panopticism
– see Michel Foucault.
Pareto, Vilfredo (1848–1923)
An Italian economist and sociologist, active also in
Switzerland, his contributions to sociology fall
into two components. The first consists in aspects
of his outstanding work as an economic theorist
which have a direct bearing on questions of social
policy – for instance, a notion of “optimality”
which still bears Pareto’s name, or a statement of
the narrow limits within which policies for redistributing wealth must operate. The second aspect
largely coincides with his expressly sociological
work, the massive Trattato di Sociologia (1916)
which was translated as The Mind and Society (1935).
429
Park, Robert Ezra (1864–1944)
Pareto considered sociology a science complementary to economics. The latter deals with rational conduct oriented to the maximization of
individual utility, while sociology deals with all
other forms of conduct, where non-rational motivations and reasonings prevail. The Trattato transcended this negative understanding of the near
totality of social experience by classifying the
accounts of actions generally given by actors or
observers. It distinguishes between the few fundamental, most recurrent accounts (the “residues”)
and their multiple, less significant variants (the
“derivations”).
The resulting classification is clumsy and unworkable; but the process of producing it yielded
further significant results, particularly a theory of
elites. These small groups, all distinguished from
the masses by some outstanding quality and attainment, differ according to the respective
weight in their makeup of two contrasting types
of “residue” – those leading to “combinations”
(the foxes) and those favoring “the persistence of
aggregates” (the lions). This difference leads to
competition between elites and their inevitable
“circulation.”
GIANFRANCO POGGI
Park, Robert Ezra (1864–1944)
Perhaps best known as the key figure of the Chicago
School of sociology, Park led the University of
Chicago sociology department from 1914 to 1934.
Born in Harveyville, Pennsylvania, he studied
under luminaries John Dewey (1859–1952) and,
at Berlin, Georg Simmel, whom he introduced to
American audiences. He also worked for twelve
years as a journalist, experience that shaped
his methodological penchant for scrupulously
accurate reporting.
Park held a clear view of sociology as genuinely
scientific, a view manifest in the classic text he
co-authored with Ernest W. Burgess, Introduction
to the Science of Sociology (1921). By directing his
many students towards accurate reporting of
events observed first-hand, he notably extended
the use of ethnographic methods in early American
sociology.
Park’s major theoretical contributions include
the notion of “self-conception” and how it relates
to the organization of social roles; the idea of the
“marginal man” – one who moves in plural social
worlds, where he is nowhere at home; and clarification of the concept of the public and how it
differs from the crowd.
Several areas of modern sociology owe a huge
debt to Park. He pioneered the field of race relations, owing in good part to his earlier work with
430
Parsons, Talcott (1902–1979)
Booker T. Washington (1856–1915) and his eyeopening accounts of Belgian atrocities in the
Congo. His definition of the modern American
urban setting as a natural laboratory formed a
point of departure for the sprawling field of urban
studies. Relatedly, his work on human ecology
foregrounded the understanding that humans
both compete for resources and are interdependent. Even so, he balanced a purely economistic
view of urban communities by insisting that
they are constituted by a moral as well as a spatial
order.
DONALD N. LEVINE
Parsons, Talcott (1902–1979)
A leading social theorist of the twentieth century,
Parsons’s work is much criticized. However, his
contribution to sociological thought is immense
and has seen something of a revival since the mid1990s. Parsons, while justly noted as a general
theorist of society, also made influential contributions to particular areas of sociology, including
medical sociology, the study of the self and the
human condition, economic sociology, family
and socialization, and the sociology of religion.
These contributions attain a level of concreteness
that contrasts with the high levels of analytical
abstraction found in the general theory.
Born in the United States, Parsons studied in
North America, Britain, and Germany, before
taking up a position at Harvard. Deeply influenced
by European sociology and social thought, Parsons
may also be seen as a distinctly American contributor to the evolution of social theory, providing a new set of priorities and emphases within a
tradition previously dominated by Europeans.
Parsons’s overriding ambition was to provide a
systematic general theory of the social. This meant
the establishment of boundaries between the social
and what lay beyond, as well as accounts of the
most salient features of social life, embracing culture, personality, and social structure. Reflecting
an early interest in biology, Parsons maintained
an interest in the boundaries between social life
and the biological organism, and between social
life and the metaphysical world of ultimate
values.
His first and possibly most important book, The
Structure of Social Action (1937), argued that a general theory of social life could be constructed,
taking into account the strengths of previous traditions, while remedying their weaknesses. The
task was one of reconciling positivist thinking
that saw action determined by external structures
with idealist thinking that emphasized individual
and interpersonal constructions of meaningful
Parsons, Talcott (1902–1979)
action. While the former emphasized analysis of
the means by which objectives were pursued, the
latter stressed the significance of the values or
ends that were pursued. A general theory, for
Parsons, should pursue patterned means–ends relationships, and sociology was par excellence the
discipline equipped for the task. In contrast with
current attempts of economics to colonize sociology via rational choice theory, Parsons saw economics with its utilitarian emphasis on choice of
means, as a subfield within a broader social
theory, able to analyze ends and their connection
with means. For sociology, ends were endogenous
not exogenous to social analysis.
The building of a general social theory that was
neither exclusively materialist nor idealist was
Parsons’s major intellectual task, and in this he
followed the multidimensionality of Max Weber,
whose work he helped make widely known in
the United States. Further key elements in the
development of this theory include the pattern
variables, and concepts of social differentiation
linked with the so-called four-function paradigm.
Parsons’s pattern variables offer a striking set of
conceptual dichotomies, between universalism
and particularism, achievement and ascription,
diffuseness and specificity, neutrality and affectivity, and lastly self-orientation and collectivityorientation. The first term in each pair signified
for Parsons a constitutive element in the nature of
modernity. This involves a higher level of freedom
of individual action from what went before, but
set within a normative framework founded on
generalized values, such as universalism and
achievement. Modernity is therefore very far from
a free-floating individualism, though Parsons’s ostensibly universalistic account was strongly inflected with North American versions of the
secularized individual vocation.
This pattern of modern variables was linked
with the performance of a set of social functions,
which Parsons believed were necessary for any
social system to survive and develop. There were
four of these, namely adaptation [A] (the securing
of material resources available for distribution),
which might be called the economic function;
goal-attainment [G], akin to the political allocation
of resources; integration [I], involving the development of a stable set of norms, as, for example,
embodied in law; and latent pattern-maintenance [L],
involving ordered patterns of value-commitment.
For Parsons, all social systems, whether national, supranational, or subnational, can be analyzed in terms of functional differentiation
into four subsystems corresponding to the AGIL
Parsons, Talcott (1902–1979)
paradigm. The further task is then to explain
interaction and integration between them through mechanisms of exchange such as power and
influence.
This highly abstract and much-criticized theoretical edifice, widely referred to by others as structural functionalism, was developed via both
theoretical commentary and analysis of empirical
phenomena, as exemplified in The Social System
(1951). Empirical themes included the development of the modern professions as exemplars of
modern pattern-variables, and the emergence of
the sick role as a normative regulator of sickness
and health. The sick role draws on a distinction
between feeling sick and being sick, the latter
carrying social expectations including temporary
withdrawal from normal social roles, a responsibility to work for recovery on the incumbent, and
a duty to seek out appropriate professional advice,
embodied in the neutral universalistic modern
professional. This argument made a striking contribution to the development of an autonomous
medical sociology distinct from the perspectives
of the biomedical model.
Parsons’s pattern variables and four-function
paradigm also fed into his evolutionary approach
to social change. Contrary to those who argue that
Parsons had no adequate theory of change, his two
books Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Perspectives (1966) and The System of Modern Societies (1971)
argued that certain human institutions such as
markets, democracy, and the rule of law possessed
an evolutionary advantage over alternative types
of economy, polity, and social integration, in
meeting social functions. This provided much of
the intellectual grounding for modernization
theory in the 1950s and 1960s.
Many critics of Parsons have attacked structural
functionalism for a variety of reasons. Some of
these are very wide of the mark, while some are
damaging. The most misconceived criticisms
impute to Parsons a structural determinism in
which human agency is lost, while Parsons aimed
at what he called an action-systems perspective in
which norms and values are central. Other problematic criticisms include the idea that Parsons
saw integrative values as the prime mover of
social life, to the exclusion of material issues and
conflicts of interest. While he opposed Hobbesian
and Marxist accounts of society as a war between
constellations of coercive power, he was mindful
both of the centrality of economic functions to
system survival, and of the existence of forms of
social stratification, such as racism, that inhibited
equality of opportunity.
431
participant observation
More telling criticisms may be made of his assumption that the integration of social systems
typically occurs through normative integration
(that is, if it occurs at all). More specifically, he
was criticized for making the following assumptions: that socialization processes are typically
successful in binding individuals to the social
order, that the nuclear family offered ideal solutions for women’s domestic roles within it, and
that modernization on the western model would
unambiguously enhance the welfare of Third
World populations. The advent of political and
student unrest throughout the western world in
the second half of the 1960s was but one of a
number of instances of more fundamental value
conflict that challenged Parsons’s optimistic liberal world-views, requiring revisions and additions
to his sociological position. One instance here is
the idea of the expressive revolution, whereby new
value orientations were seen as emerging around
forms of countercultural expression, beyond the
work ethic and family-centeredness.
Even so, Parsons’s system remained incapable of
providing accounts of coercive and discursive
power functional to the self-interest of economic
and social groups rather than to overall normative order. Similarly the emergence of a rich social
history of social and political contestation has
rendered Parsons’s accounts of human agency
unduly abstract and formulaic. What does remain
intact is the breadth of his synthetic program for a
unified social theory, a resource drawn on even by
other thinkers of a more radical disposition such
as Jürgen Habermas.
ROBERT HOLTON
participant observation
A technique used by adherents of interpretative
methods in sociology in which the researcher participates in the practical activities of institutions,
social groups, or communities in order to ground
observations in naturally occurring practices. The
method may vary according to the setting and the
disposition of the observer. The observer may
become a full participant in the practical action
(for example Susan Krieger in Mirror Dance: Identity
in a Woman’s Community, 1983); or he/she may be
unable to pass as a full participant (for example
Elliott Liebow, in Tally’s Corner, 1967).
The strength of the method is that participation
allows the observer to examine social events at
close hand, which can lead to additional sources
of information such as informants, members of
the group observed who are willing to disclose
their understandings of the local practices. The
weakness of the method is that the validity of
432
path analysis
the observations is limited to the setting studied,
making it difficult to generalize in precise language. This problem can be ameliorated somewhat
by triangulation, the technique of crosschecking
observations in the local setting against data acquired by more formal methods including surveys
and demography, such as in William Julius Wilson,
When Work Disappears (1996).
Participant observation is widely used by academic sociologists, though at the beginning of
the twenty-first century it became common to
call it ethnography, which had long been in use
by anthropologists. The method can also lead to a
romantic attitude whereby the observers overstate
the realism of their accounts of groups; see
Patricia Clough, The End(s) of Ethnography (1991).
CHARLES LEMERT
paternalism
This term has two important meanings: the first is
the set of informal expectations and codes of
manners held by men about how to behave towards women, and the second is the assumption
that the more powerful and the better-off in any
society have obligations towards the less powerful
and the poor. What unites these two assumptions
is the idea that it is the responsibility of the more
powerful to demonstrate concern for the less
powerful, but without disturbing existing power
relations or taking steps to ensure that those in
weaker social positions are enabled to improve
their situation. Paternalism is frequently associated with nineteenth- and twentieth-century attitudes towards the poor: paternalistic strategies
advocated acts of individual charity to alleviate
poverty while rejecting more radical attempts to
provide social assistance that did not depend on
acts of individual goodwill. In the latter part
of the twentieth century, western feminism has
identified paternalism as a masculine pattern
of conduct that maintains male power and is
essentially random and individualistic. At the
same time, other critiques of paternalism have
identified it as a set of expectations that are
always organized around the presumption of the
authority of the powerful (whatever the source of
power) over the less powerful.
MARY EVANS
path analysis
This describes a class of statistics that aim to
understand how a set of variables relate causally
to each other. The analysis typically starts by
sketching out a diagram consisting of variables
joined by arrows to represent the researcher’s
conception of a particular system. The statistical
patriarchy
analysis is then computed to evaluate the relative
importance of each of those causal links, by
assigning them a coefficient representing the
strength of the relationship.
The computations of those paths can be done by
simple multiple regression, but increasingly now
it is done through a more advanced technique
called “structural equation modeling” (SEM), that
permits a more complex analysis of the data
and the error that is inherent in the measurement
of many sociological variables. By isolating the
effects of this error, truer estimates of the size
of the relationships between variables can be
obtained.
In more conventional statistics, the focus is on
using the data to develop a model. Path analysis
reverses that order. One starts by carefully theorizing a model (or several models) that describes the
links between variables in one’s theoretical view
of the world. Only after that theorizing has been
done is the data then used to test how well it fits
the model, or which of several models best fits the
data.
Until the 1990s structural equation models
were the preserve of the most mathematical social
scientists. But more recently, the advent of userfriendly statistical software packages that perform
structural equation modeling have made them
commonplace in many areas of research.
BRENDAN J. BURCHELL
patriarchy
The concept of patriarchy is one which is widely
used across a number of disciplines in both the
social sciences and the humanities, even if the
way in which the term is used differs between
particular contexts (for example, Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels write about the “patriarchal”
family, whereas literary critics might employ the
term to indicate a bias towards the masculine).
Whatever the discipline, however, the term always
indicates the rule of men, not just over women
but also over the general structure of social relations. The term is therefore about the power of
men, a power which extends to the individual
jurisdiction of men (or a man) over a family and
its members, as well as the more general power of
“the male” over the organization of a social group
or a society.
The discussion of the term patriarchy, and its
general use within social and political theory, can
be traced to the seventeenth century. In 1680 Sir
Robert Filmer’s Patriarchia. A Defence of the Natural
Power of Kings against the Unnatural Liberty of the
People asserted the right of one man to rule the
patriarchy
many; an assertion challenged by John Locke
(1632–1704) in Two Treatises of Government. The liberal tradition, of which Locke was a crucial founder, consistently challenged the assumption of the
“natural,” patriarchal, rights of the monarch.
However, it was not until the nineteenth century
that the discussion of the term was widened to
include the context of gender relations. Engels,
writing in 1884 in The Origin of the Family, Private
Property and the State (1972) wrote of the defeat of
“mother right” but also claimed that in monogamy and individual sexualized love (coupled with
the entry of women into social production) lay the
basis for the emancipation of women. For Engels,
there were crucial relationships between the
power of men in the private realm (the family)
and in the public sphere, a connection which has
been consistently important in mary of the social
sciences. The emphasis on the loss of the power of
the mother and the appearance of the father as
the crucial authority figure in human social relations is drawn from the work of the German
writer, Jacob Bachofen, who, in 1861, wrote of
the historic struggle between the old order of
matriarchy (the social authority of mothers) and
the newer, emergent, authority of fathers in Myth,
Religion and Mother Right (1861 [trans. 1967]). The
struggle, Bachofen suggested, was articulated in
Greek tragedies, for example Aeschylus’ Eumenides
in which Orestes murders his mother, Clytemnestra, in revenge for her murder of his father,
Agamemnon. The Greeks were to be a later source
of inspiration for Sigmund Freud, who drew on
the story of Oedipus for his conjecture about the
nature of psychic competition between father
and son, a competition fueled by their mutual
wish for primary access to, and control of, the
mother. The power of the mother, as interpreted
by Freud and others, was a power to attract men,
and excite their wish to control, rather than an
autonomous power which allowed authority over
others.
The development of the social sciences in the
nineteenth and twentieth century saw an emphasis on the study of different societies, in both
historical and geographical terms. The term patriarchy became a crucial organizing concept for
social anthropologists, whose discipline placed a
particular emphasis on the study of kinship and
kinship relations. By the second half of the twentieth century, anthropologists had generally concluded that the majority of human societies were
explicitly patriarchal, in that authority, lineage,
and descent were situated in men, the social function of women (as Claude Lévi-Strauss was to
433
patriarchy
point out) being as objects of the exchange process
which cemented and continued social relations
and structures of power. Nevertheless, there were
some societies (for example in regions of West
Africa) where kinship was inherited through the
mother. These societies, undeniably matriarchal
in their patterns of inheritance, nevertheless
invested other forms of social power in the
mother’s brother, ensuring that even in apparently matriarchal societies it would be wrong to
conclude that social relations were represented
and ordered as the reverse of patriarchy.
In the second half of the twentieth century the
authority of patriarchy, and the patriarchal, has
come to be contested in a number of ways. Patriarchy was identified by second-wave feminism as
the conceptual apparatus, both symbolic and material, through which the social inferiority of
women was maintained. In this re-thinking of
the ways in which male power is both socially
and psychically reproduced, psychoanalysis, post
Freud, has questioned his emphasis on the part of
the father in the life of the infant and the child.
Although debates still continue about the meaning of the father, there is a general consensus
that his authority cannot be understood without a
more dialectical account of relations between
women and men, mothers and fathers. This discussion provides the context for work on language
and the recognition that it is saturated with assumptions about the relative power of women and
men. These exchanges (involving figures such as
Jacques Lacan and Monique Wittig) have informed
the study of literature, just as the recognition
of the almost universal authority of men has
informed studies of the law (see law and society),
work, the body and politics. For example, it was
through the recognition of patriarchy as a crucial
research term that feminist historians were able
to demonstrate the ways in which patriarchy was
a form of authority which crossed class and ethnic
boundaries: as Barbara Taylor was to write in Eve
and the New Jerusalem (1982), her study of gender
and labor relations in Britain at the beginning of
the nineteenth century, “the men are as bad as
their masters.” For many feminist historians and
social scientists this comment reflected their own
findings on the ways in which human society
worked and represented itself: in a wide range of
contexts and meanings it was the male, and the
interests of men, which were given priority over
those of women. At the same time it was also
observed that the recognition, from the eighteenth century onwards, of the detailed biological
differences of men and women made possible the
434
peace studies
emergence of social understanding which did not
understand women as, in biblical terms, “Adam’s
Rib.” Many parts of the West have now attempted
to produce “gender neutral” (and non-patriarchal)
forms of social practice and regulation, although
in other societies the patriarchal authority of
men, endorsed by religion, remains dominant.
MARY EVANS
patrimonialism
This term is used to describe relationships that
distribute power and authority within organizations. Usually referring to Max Weber’s use in
Economy and Society (1922 [trans. 1968]), patrimonialism is a system of rule that is based upon
personal–familial, rather than rational–legal relationships. Central to the notion of patrimonialism
is that the leader of the organization distributes
power and authority according to his or her
wishes. At the same time, patrimonialism also
refers to systems in which authority may be
claimed, based upon birth right, heritage, or tradition. Patrimonialism derives from the Latin patrimonium that refers to a “paternal estate” and the
model of the traditional patriarchal family, where
a man, in a system of patrilineage, is the ruler of
the household. As relationships with the patrimonial organizations are based upon personal patronage (or lack thereof), the exercise of power is
highly informal, subjective, and open to change. In
contrast, state bureaucracies in western democratic societies operate through the formal separation of public and private spheres. Such
organizations insist on the primacy of rational or
technical competency as legitimate sources of authority and social status. More recent work has
blurred the neat distinction between the two forms
of organization by suggesting a notion of neopatrimonialism. In these accounts, organizations (often
implicitly or clandestinely) combine both rational–
legal sources of authority and those of patrimonialism. An example of this might be where the
head of a privately financed company nominates
or promotes close friends or family members.
MAIRTIN MAC-AN-GHAILL AND CHRIS HAYWOOD
pattern variables
– see Talcott Parsons.
peace studies
Peace studies is an interdisciplinary academic enterprise that is the institutional outgrowth of various political and ideological programs of the
global left in the 1960s. As an intellectual field,
peace studies focuses on the development of
peasant society
nonviolent strategies for redressing interpersonal,
institutional, national, and global conflicts. As
such, peace studies represents a significant challenge to dominant perspectives in social science
and philosophy, such as realism, elite-centered
analyses of conflict, and just war theory. In contrast to such perspectives, peace studies stresses
ideas such as pacifism, mercy, reconciliation, constructive engagement, and forgiveness, and has
been primarily concerned with nuclear disarmament, the avoidance of international conflict (especially war), and redistributive efforts in the
name of social justice. The field is characterized
by a strong activist agenda: knowledge about
various types of conflicts is seen as a means towards conflict resolution at all levels of social life.
Peace studies is a utopian intellectual movement,
characterized by a historicist and teleological
view of progress defined as the absence of war,
a preference for nonviolent means of conflict
resolution, and the desire for more equitable distribution of economic resources. Much of the
discourse of peace studies focuses on the critique
of western political and cultural formations, to
the detriment of understanding other systems of
social, political, and cultural domination, such as
communist totalitarianism (see Communism) and
religious fundamentalism. While a widespread
movement with many notable practitioners, the
overtly ideological agenda of peace studies has
made it difficult for the field to gain legitimacy
as an intellectual endeavor in the contemporary
academic environment.
TOM CUSHMAN
peasant society
– see peasants.
peasants
For centuries, peasants were the internal other of
European society but also its “folk,” lingering repositories of primitive innocence but also of
superstition and dull conservatism in the midst
of a progressive and enlightened civilization. In
classical social theory, they are of central concern
first to the Marxists, who from Marx onward had
little confidence in their revolutionary potential.
Max Weber addresses them most systematically in
The Agrarian Sociology of Ancient Civilizations (1909
[trans. 1976]). They become the specific subjects of
ethnographic research only in the 1920s and not
in significant numbers until the later 1940s.
Their politico-economic condition is the key to
their typological distinctiveness. Thus, in Peasants
(1966), Eric Wolf characterizes them as “rural
cultivators whose surpluses are transferred to a
peasants
dominant group of rulers that uses the surpluses
both to underwrite its own standard of living and
to distribute the remainder to groups in society
that do not farm but must be fed for their specific
goods and services in turn” (1966: 3–4). As A. V.
Chayanov in The Theory of the Peasant Economy (1986)
was the first to underscore, the peasant economy
is further a family economy. Its labor units are
households. Its goal is not profit but securing the
survival of the household through the course of
its yearly cycle. In The Moral Economy of the Peasant
(1976), James Scott characterizes its attendant
ethic accordingly as a “subsistence ethic.” Wolf
appropriately notes that subsistence itself demands more than the provision of a nutritional
minimum over and above what must be expended
as tribute or the rental of land. It further requires
the production of a surplus sufficient to cover the
expenditures of sociality and the ceremonial life,
including those associated with such central rites
of passage as marriage and death and dying.
Peasants are indeed noted for their religious
devotion around the world, but also for a devotion
that is often at odds with the churches to which
they might belong. Their systems of belief tend to
be syncretic, relatively informal, and practically
oriented – popular heterodoxies at the fringes of
the cultivated orthodoxy of a clerical or elite tradition. Such a tendency led Robert Redfield in Peasant Society and Culture (1956: 70) and elsewhere to
press a broader distinction between the “little
tradition” of the typical peasantry and the “great
tradition” of “the philosopher, theologian, and
literary man.” The distinction is an appropriate
register of stratification not merely of a political
but also of a cultural order. Spatially, such stratification is often manifest as the distinction
between the countryside and the city, but peasantries can and do exist in societies, such as that of
early feudal Europe, having no urban centralization at all. Temporally, it is almost always manifest as what in Vasilika (1962) Ernestine Friedl
describes as “cultural lag” (see W. E. Ogburn). In
their beliefs and practices alike, peasantries reveal
the influence of the great traditions that encompass them and frequently seek to emulate their
stylistic and even intellectual standards. Distortions in the processes of cultural diffusion, however, leave them stylistically and intellectually
behind or out-of-date, even in the age of effectively
simultaneous media of transmission such as
television.
That peasants are inclined to emulate the advanced cultural fashions with which they happen
to come into contact suggests, after Norbert
435
peasants
penology
Elias’s and Pierre Bourdieu’s work, that they middle classes seem in ever greater numbers to
harbor certain values more similar to those of be joining them. The future may not thus bring
aspiring middle classes than those stereotypically
ascribed to them. There are in any event no clear
empirical grounds for declaring the destiny of
peasants in developing or developed capitalist
economies to point any less to embourgeoisement – at least the petite embourgeoisement –
than to proletarianization. The egalitarian but
sometimes proto-fascist populism of which peasants everywhere are putative carriers is similarly
ambiguous. In part, these ambiguities reflect the
often notable socioeconomic diversity of peasant
populations, whose better-off and sometimes even
rich members may find themselves in overt social
conflict with their poorer relations. In another
part, however, they inhere in what even charitable
analysts judge to be a political sensibility that
remains as personalistic and short-sighted as its
economic counterpart. Peasants can and do rebel;
as Wolf (1966: 107) and others have pointed out,
and in further contrast to their stereotypical
conservatism, they often heroize the rebel figure.
What galvanizes them when they rebel, however,
is rarely the unbroken domination and exploitation to which they are subject, but instead
the unexpected imposition of some particularly
onerous collective burden. What inspires them is
rarely an articulate program of socioeconomic
change, but instead a millenarian vision of imminent and total redemption. Norman Cohn in The
Pursuit of the Millennium (1957) and Eric Hobsbawm
in Primitive Rebels (1959) document the long
European history of peasant millenarianism (see
religion), and examples are readily available from
elsewhere. Peasants so inspired have almost never
furthered their practical interests. Most often,
they have been brutally repressed.
Yet the destiny of the peasants of the future is
probably neither redemption nor complete failure. It may rather be much the same as the destiny of the majority of the peasants of the past – to
drift towards other socioeconomic positions, of
greater or of lesser means and prestige, that only
add to the ambiguities of the position from which
they began. As Michael Kearney has argued in
Reconceptualizing the Peasantry (1996), typologization can do more to obscure than to elucidate
the frequency and the ubiquity with which peasants keep one foot in the household but another
squarely planted in the market. It can also
obscure the frequency and ubiquity with which
petits bourgeois and proletarians do the same –
and with the advent of consumption-driven and
flexible capitalism, the higher reaches of the
436
the disappearance of the peasant; it may instead
bring the peasantification of ever broader fractions of the market society as a whole.
JAMES D. FAUBION
pedagogical practices
The sociology of education took a specifically practical turn in the 1960s and 1970s in relating to the
problems of the science of pedagogy – the science
of the communication of knowledge content.
Whereas the political sociologist Harold Dwight
Lasswell (1902–78) had developed a theory of
mass communication, arguing for distinct kinds
of control, content, audience, and effect analyses,
the work of Marshall McLuhan destroyed this neat
categorization, claiming that the “medium is the
message.” The study of the transmission of knowledge raised questions about the a-priori status of
curriculum content as well as about the status of
language as a medium of transmission. These
issues related to those highlighted by poststructuralism. The work of Pierre Bourdieu at this time
focused more on the epistemological dimension of
pedagogy, while the work of Basil Bernstein was
part of the contemporary linguistic turn of analysis. These forms of sociological pedagogy defied
the attempts made to absorb it into the science
of sociolinguistics or, by Jürgen Habermas, to generate a theory of autonomous communicative
action. The most systematic attempt to produce a
sociological pedagogy was made by Bourdieu and
J.-C. Passeron in Reproduction in Education, Society
and Culture (1970 [trans.1977]). They defined pedagogic action (PA), pedagogic authority (PAu),
pedagogic work (PW), school authority (SAu), educational system (ES), and the work of schooling
(WSg), in order to present a framework within
which the functioning of pedagogical practices
can be understood, both within the confines of
institutionalized education and in relation to
more general processes of cultural communication within society.
DEREK ROBBINS
peer group
– see group(s).
penology
This term is used to refer to theories of punishment, forms of punishment, and penal conditions.
It refers to the systematic application of clinical,
social scientific, or managerial expertise to the
penology
study and evaluation of penal measures, especially
prisons.
The birth of the modern prison or penitentiary
occurred in the eighteenth century. Prior to industrialization, life was cheap, and capital and corporal punishment predominated. The modern
prison represented progress from a brutal and
barbaric system of punishment to benevolent discipline. The social role of the prison has been of
considerable interest to Marxist historians such as
George Rusche and Otto Kirchheimer in Punishment and Social Structure (1939), to historian David
Rothman in The Discovery of the Asylum: Social Order
and Disorder in the New Republic (1971), and to philosopher/historian Michel Foucault in Discipline and
Punish: The Birth of the Prison (1975 [trans. 1977])
among others. Certainly, it is thought that the
prison might have an ideological function as
well as representing progress from previous
barbaric punishments.
The inception of modern penological thinking
with questions such as “what is punishment for?”
can be partially attributed to Christian reformers
such as John Howard (1726–90) – who believed
that punishment should be about the religious
reformation of the offender and reflect humanitarian magnanimity – and utilitarian rationalist
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), who thought that
punishment should be directed more instrumentally at the refinement of techniques of behavioral
control – hence his idea of the Panopticon: a circular architectural structure in which complete
surveillance of the offender was possible. Thus,
while Howard traveled the world denouncing
poor prison conditions that would arguably militate against the reclamation of the offender’s soul,
Bentham was concerned with the formation of
discipline via prison architecture as if surveillance
would lead to order within and without prisons.
Bentham’s thinking went beyond this, however,
and he promulgated consequentialist theories of
punishment.
Consequentialist theories of punishment are essentially those that justify punishment by making
claims about the desirability of its future consequences. These theories are sometimes known as
reductivist, because they claim that the incidence
of crime will be less than it would be if no penalty
were imposed. Bentham’s “felicific calculus” is
thus that punishment of the individual is justified
if it can be shown that the good derived thereby
outweighs the pain. Such consequentialist theories include those of general deterrence, individual
deterrence and incapacitation, and rehabilitation.
Nonconsequential theories of punishment revolve
personality
around retribution and desert theory. The idea of
retribution derives historically from the Roman
concept of lex talionis, illustrated by the biblical
phrase “Wherever hurt is done, you shall give life
for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth, hand for hand,
foot for foot, burn for burn, bruise for bruise,
wound for wound” (Exodus 21: 23–5). Classical
desert theory was predicated upon the assumption that offenders are rational, autonomous individuals who, having made the decision to offend,
“deserved” punishment for their wrongdoing.
Modern desert theorists focus on notions of proportionality in sentencing according to the seriousness of the crime, and on desert theory as a
communicative device for censuring wrongful behavior in such a way that it permits the offender
to rejoin the moral consensus.
For much of the twentieth century, penological
projects focused on the monitoring of sentencing
and the manipulation of penal regimes both
within and outside custodial settings. Optimism
that penal interventions could work were at their
highest in the 1960s (the so-called rehabilitative
ideal), but this was short-lived because systematic
analysis of the effects of such interventions led to
the sobering conclusion that “nothing works.”
Since the mid-1990s there has been a resurgent
international interest in “what works?” Research
findings from meta-analytical studies have
prompted the development of a panoply of institutional and community-based programs based on
cognitive-behavioral ideas. The findings from
these studies, however, are not encouraging and
early 21st-century penological thinking indicates
moves away from such programs towards education and training for offenders.
LORAINE GELSTHORPE
personality
The study of personality builds on the everyday
recognition that people around us are different in
their social behavior, and seem to be disposed to
react in particular ways. It seeks to characterize in
a rigorous way the basis of that difference by
identifying characteristic patterns of behavior
that are distinctive and consistent across time.
Some accounts of personality try to use these
characterizations as a basis for predicting future
behavior by establishing lawlike generalizations
about factors that underpin variation in all
people. These accounts, sometimes referred to as
nomothetic statements, adhere to a scientific
model of inquiry which sees the testing of predictions, ideally in an experimental setting, as the
best way to establish a secure understanding. They
437
personality
phenomenology
are part of a tradition in psychology that focuses
on individual differences, for example intelligence. Other accounts, sometimes referred to as
idiographic accounts, focus on the individual in
depth and pursue an understanding of that individual using a variety of interpretive or phenomenological approaches.
Many nomothetic theories have antecedents in
classical descriptions, and many can ultimately be
linked to Hippocrates (470–410 BC) who defined
the four humors: yellow bile, black bile, phlegm,
and blood. This system had two dimensions (hot
and cold, and dry and wet) on which all people
could be placed, with different individuals being
characteristically hotter or colder, and wetter or
drier. These terms still exist in everyday speech
as choleric, melancholic, phlegmatic, and sanguine, but in personality theories the humors are
now referred to as “traits.” Five traits (extraversion, neuroticism, agreeableness, conscientiousness, and openness) are widely accepted as
defining the essential descriptive framework that
best captures individual variation. Idiographic
theories have often drawn on the same tradition,
but in the modern era are much more closely
associated with clinical work and individual psychotherapy. The clinic is where many of them
were first developed, and the best known is
Sigmund Freud’s work on psychoanalysis.
The personality literature is very diverse in
terms of its theoretical and methodological assumptions, and most of the critical debates from
across the social sciences are to be found here.
One important critical line that intervenes in these
debates concerns how much of the individual’s
behavior is to be understood in terms of personality. At one time, grand claims were made for the
range and types of behavior that personality theories could explain, but now personality theorists
are more circumspect, and recognize the significance of other social characteristics such as age,
gender, and race and ethnicity, or other personal
determinants of behavior, such as attitude.
Apart from the application of idiographic accounts in psychotherapy, personality theories
from the nomothetic tradition are of interest
and value to those selecting people for different
roles in organizations and teams, or advising individuals on career choices. Personality tests such as
the Myers–Briggs test, which identifies four dimensions akin to the five traits mentioned above,
is typical in this regard, and in over sixty years of
use and development it has a reasonable degree of
reliability and validity in many eyes.
DAVID GOOD
438
petite bourgeoisie
– see social class.
phenomenology
A philosophical school, which gained prominence
in the course of the twentieth century, etymologically speaking, phenomenology refers to the
study of phenomena or of how the phenomena
appear to the individual. It investigates the structure of various forms of experiences and assumes
that this analysis provides a better foundation
for philosophy than, for instance, epistemology
or metaphysics. Amongst phenomenological philosophers, Edmund Husserl (1859–1938), Martin
Heidegger (1889–1976), and Maurice MerleauPonty are particularly well known. Some hermeneutic philosophers like Hans-Georg Gadamer and
Paul Ricoeur (1913–2005) partly draw on the
phenomenological tradition. Existentialist philosophers like Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–80) and Karl
Jaspers (1883–1969) also rely on insights from
phenomenology. Phenomenology had a significant
impact on sociology, especially through the work
of Alfred Schutz. Phenomenological sociology is
a particular version of interpretative sociology.
It shows affinities with other types of interpretative sociology such as ethnomethodology (which
was strongly influenced by phenomenology),
symbolic interactionism, and hermeneutics. Phenomenology also influenced the writings of Peter
L. Berger, Harold Garfinkel, Georges Gurvitch,
Thomas Luckmann, and Maurice Natanson. Phenomenological sociology pays attention to the
ways in which people make sense of social reality
and act accordingly. It tends to oppose neo-positivist appeals for a unity of method between the
social and the natural: contrary to the natural,
the social is already “pre-interpreted,” and this
begs for an interpretative methodology. In American sociology, phenomenological sociology emerged in the 1960s in opposition to the dominant
orthodoxy of structural functionalism.
The aim of Husserl’s phenomenology was to
capture the universal structures of people’s subjective orientation towards their external environment. Schutz was a student of Husserl and very
much influenced by him. Where Husserl’s preoccupation was purely philosophical, Schutz on
the other hand explored the sociological relevance of phenomenology. Max Weber and George
Herbert Mead also impacted on Schutz’s thought.
In The Phenomenology of the Social World (1967) and
in his Collected Papers (1962–6), Schutz was particularly interested in the way in which individuals
use interpretative schemes to make sense of their
phenomenology
everyday surroundings. This “stock of knowledge”
enables them to attribute meaning to what others
say or do. People are not normally aware of the
stock of knowledge they employ; it is part of tacit
knowledge. In this context, Schutz talked about
everyday rationality as opposed to scientific rationality. Whereas scientific rationality is characterized by theoretical knowledge and systematic
doubt, everyday rationality draws on practical
knowledge and suspension of disbelief. Schutz’s
phenomenology paves the way for a sociological
inquiry into how people attribute meanings to
their surroundings. Influenced by Schutz and Sartre, Berger and Luckmann’s The Social Construction
of Reality; A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge
(1967) focused on how everyday conceptions of
reality are constructed and maintained.
Harold Garfinkel and Aaron Cicourel’s ethnomethodology drew on Schutz’s writings, but unlike
Schutz – who remained a pure theorist – their research was empirical. In Studies in Ethnomethodology
(1967) Garfinkel investigated the interpretative procedures that people employ to make sense of their
social environment. In a number of experiments,
Garfinkel and his team also studied what happened
when these encounters do not square with people’s
expectations. In those situations, they discovered
that people did not question their presuppositions. Rather, individuals drew on their presuppositions to make sense of their surroundings, and
they did so in ways that maintained or reinforced
those very presuppositions. Garfinkel called this
the “documentary method of interpretation.”
For a long time phenomenology remained on
the margins of sociology, because its premises
were in opposition to the reigning orthodoxy. Phenomenology contradicted Émile Durkheim’s guidelines in his Rules of Sociological Method (1895 [trans.
1958]), notably his dictum that social facts need
to be treated as “things.” In the 1970s sociologists became interested in phenomenology, partly
through the writings of Anthony Giddens and
Pierre Bourdieu. Ironically, this interest went
hand in hand with a growing recognition that
this philosophical tradition was one-sided. Phenomenology focused too much on how individuals
make sense of the world, and it ignored the constraining and external nature of social structures.
Sociologists became preoccupied with bridging
the gap between phenomenological approaches
and structuralism, taking insights from both. In
The Constitution of Society; Outline of the Theory of
Structuration (1984), Giddens proposed a structuration theory, which investigated how people draw
on tacit, practical knowledge in their everyday
Phillips curve
life, and, in so doing, contribute to the reproduction of society. Likewise, Pierre Bourdieu’s Outline
of a Theory of Practice (1972 [trans. 1977]) attempts to
transcend the opposition between “subjectivism”
(phenomenological approaches) and “objectivism”
(structuralist approaches). Bourdieu’s notions of
habitus and hexis rely on phenomenology. The
habitus is a set of “dispositions” that allow for the
perception and account of the world in a particular
way. The hexis points at the bodily aspects of the
habitus. In Bourdieu’s writings, however, the habitus is linked to broader structural concerns and to
the reproduction of inequality.
More recently, sociologists have been drawn to
Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology at the expense of
Schutz’s, especially Merleau-Ponty’s The Phenomenology of Perception (1945 [trans. 1962]). In this
work, Merleau-Ponty paid attention to the role of
the body in perception. His notion of the “phenomenal body” (in opposition to the “objective”
body) undermined the objectivism at the core of
the natural sciences. Although in some respects
close to Sartre, the closing chapters of The Phenomenology of Perception include strong criticisms of
Jean-Paul Sartre’s ideas. The increasing interest
in the body explains why sociologists have recently been drawn to Merleau-Ponty’s work. Bryan
Turner’s Sociology of the Body (1984) was one of the
first books to point out the relevance of MerleauPonty for sociological purposes.
PATRICK BAERT
Phillips curve
In A. W. Phillips’s famous article “The Relationship between Unemployment and the Rate of
Money Wages in the UK 1861–1957,” in Economica,
he argued that when the unemployment rate was
low, the labor market was tight and employers
had to offer higher wages to attract scarce labor.
At higher rates of unemployment, there was less
pressure to increase wages. When the economy
was expanding, firms would raise wages faster
than “normal” for a given level of unemployment;
when the economy was contracting, they would
raise wages more slowly.
Policymakers used the Phillips curve to determine economic policy. For example, if unemployment increased, the government might stimulate
the economy to lower it. Monetarist economists
challenged the theory by arguing that only real
wages mattered: the inflation-adjusted purchasing power of money wages. Thus, the more quickly
worker expectations of price inflation adapt to
changes in the actual rate of inflation, the less
successful governments will be in reducing unemployment through monetary and fiscal policy.
439
philosophy of the social sciences
There are more fundamental objections: the
meanings of both unemployment and inflation
are not constant over time. The former is measured by the definition of what being employed
constitutes: in Australia today, for instance, if employees are employed for more than one hour a
week, they are classified as “employed,” and thus
the unemployment rate can be represented as 5.3
percent. If the measures used to define unemployment twenty years ago were still used, it would be
closer to 15 percent. Similarly, inflation is constructed from an index that measures the price
of a bundle of commodities. As these items are
changed, or their weights change, then what is
being measured ceases to be constant. The measures are socially constructed.
STEWART CLEGG
philosophy of the social sciences
Philosophy of the social sciences is a metatheoretical reflection on the workings of the social
sciences. Some philosophers of social science prescribe guidelines for social researchers, for instance about how to make research scientific or
how to make it a proper critique. Some philosophers focus on other issues, for instance, the relationship between values and facts or the validity
of particular theoretical frameworks.
Initially, sociology had strong links with a positivist philosophy of social science. Positivism assumed a unity of method between the social and
natural sciences. If the social sciences employ the
method of the natural sciences, then they will
uncover scientific laws or law-like generalizations.
In addition, some positivist authors argued that
we should keep a clear separation between facts
and values (one cannot be inferred from the other)
and between theory and observation (observations
ought to be theory-independent). Since the mid
twentieth century, various schools within the philosophy of the social sciences have developed in
reaction to positivism.
Karl Popper introduced falsificationism or critical rationalism. According to this view, scientific
theories are falsifiable rather than verifiable. That
is, they can, in principle, be refuted. Various psychological and sociological theories purport to be
scientific but are not, because they are immunized against refutation. For example, Alfred
Adler (1870–1937), Sigmund Freud, and Karl Marx
present non-falsifiable theories.
Influenced by hermeneutics (see, for instance,
Charles Taylor) or Ludwig Wittgenstein (see,
for instance, Peter Winch), some anti-naturalist
authors stress the differences between the study
of the social and that of the natural. According to
440
pilot study
this view, there are no significant laws or law-like
generalizations in the social realm.
Critical realism rejects the positivist “regularity” notion of causality, according to which
the regular observation that “X is followed by
Y” is both sufficient and necessary for saying that
X causes Y. Critical realists argue that both natural
and social sciences try to uncover the underlying
structures or powers that affect the observable
level. These structures or powers are not necessarily immediately accessible to observation.
Critical theory disagrees with the view that
social research is a purely descriptive or explanatory endeavor. Critical theorists like Theodor
Wiesengrund Adorno, Max Horkheimer, or Jürgen
Habermas contend that social research should also
aim at a critical assessment, possibly leading to
self-emancipation. This calls attention to the question of what criteria or procedures can be used in
order to arrive at a judgment. Habermas believes
that the notion of an open, unconstrained debate
provides the key to answering this question.
Pragmatism argues against foundationalism
(any attempt to find atemporal foundations of
reliable knowledge) and against the spectator
theory of knowledge (any view that sees knowledge as representing the inner nature of the external world). Instead, pragmatists prefer to see
knowledge as active and tied to cognitive interests. Habermas’s critical theory relies heavily on
Charles Peirce’s pragmatism. For Habermas, different types of knowledge accomplish different
goals. Empirical-analytical knowledge aims at
prediction and control, hermeneutics is directed towards understanding, and critical theory
combines both to achieve self-emancipation.
PATRICK BAERT
pilot study
Just as naval pilots guide larger vessels safely into
port, so too are pilot studies intended to secure
the passage of research projects from a tentative
and questioning approach to the issue in question, to a secure berth as a substantive contribution to knowledge in sociology. As such, pilot
studies are often designed to act as either smallscale replicas of a much larger research project
and/or to act as a “test bed” upon which potentially problematic methodological or procedural
issues can be tried out and resolved. The size of
any pilot study will be variable, and determined
by the nature of the research methodology being
used. Some pilot studies may thus be much larger
than full-scale studies using tried and tested
instruments.
plural society
pluralism
For example, if a study in a new area of enquiry
wished to examine the relationship between, say,
religious affiliation and car-buying intentions,
questionnaires may be designed to effect the
measurement of both variables via a representative sampling of the wider population to which
inferences are to be drawn. A pilot study, using a
small (possibly even a convenience) sample, may
then be used to trial the newly minted questionnaires to ensure that items are not infelicitously
phrased, ambiguous, or incomprehensible to research respondents. Should problems be identified at this stage of the research process (via
debriefing of interviewers, for example), steps
may be taken to rewrite or otherwise disambiguate the measures in question prior to the execution of the full-scale study. It is not unknown for
second pilot studies to be required to confirm the
successful rectification of methodological, study,
and measure design difficulties.
MARK RAPLEY AND SUSAN HANSEN
plural society
This concept refers to a society that respects differences. In one sense, all societies are plural since
it is impossible for individuals to relate to one
another unless they have differences that each
respects. But a plural society is one in which
these differences are explicitly and consciously
accepted, and they are seen as a strength rather
than a weakness.
But differences generate conflict and these conflicts have to be resolved. A plural society is not
therefore a society without conflict, but a society
in which conflicts can be managed, rather than
suppressed, in which compromise and conciliation prevail over the use of force and violence.
Should conflicts be violent, then the case is likely
to be made for a strong state able to employ
counterforce, so that instead of a plural society
we have an authoritarian one in which differences
are seen as disloyal and problematic.
In an increasingly globalized world, societies
are becoming more and more obviously plural as
people from different cultures and language
groups come together in large, heterogeneous
communities. However, it would be naive to imagine that differences can be respected unless
there is toleration and accommodation. People
need to have common values if differences are to
strengthen a society, and not cause it to break
down and divide.
Living within a society has to be both a unifying
and diversifying experience. Without conscious
plurality, society becomes suffocating, but without
mechanisms for accommodation, a society ceases
to exist.
JOHN HOFFMAN
pluralism
Arguments about the virtues or otherwise of pluralism span from the works of ancient philosophers to recent times. It stands as a protest
against “monism” or one-ness, and emphasizes
that difference and multiplicity must be taken
seriously.
In its more recent social science form, pluralism
is identified with the argument that, in a liberal
democracy, interests are diverse so that, although
some groups may (say) be wealthier than others, it
is wrong to regard one factor as ultimately predominant since other groups may enjoy popularity or represent large numbers of people. This
doctrine became discredited in the late 1960s
and during the 1970s. The notion that in liberal
societies different groups “balanced” themselves
out was considered to be propagandistic and inaccurate. A pluralist view of politics and society
excluded the idea that, in the liberal form, a particular interest might prevail in the form of an
elite or ruling class.
More recently, critiques of the liberal pluralism
of the 1960s have themselves been criticized on
the grounds that an emphasis upon underlying
structures that unify society generates dogmatism, exclusivity, and authoritarianism. Feminists,
for example, argued that society consisted of two
sexes, not just one, and that liberal (and left-wing)
notions of the individual and humanity viewed
the world through the lenses of men. Some feminists (the “radicals”) turned liberalism inside out
and argued for the primacy of women and their
outlook, and argued that women need to keep
aloof from men. But why should plurality “stop”
with the acknowledgment that individuals can be
either male or female?
The postmodernist argument enshrines pluralism as its key value. People can identify themselves only through their difference from others,
so that it becomes invidious to privilege one difference over others. Postmodern feminism argues
that not only are women different from men, but
they are different from one another. An infinite
range of other factors need to be taken into account – a person’s social class, religion, language,
culture, and region. Traditional concepts like the
state and conventional religion, and thought
systems like Marxism and liberalism, are challenged since they appear to ascribe primacy to
one particular factor over all others. The search
for the Truth or the belief in Reason are dogmatic
441
pluralization
political economy
and authoritarian postures that must be challenged and rejected.
The problem with pluralism is that it can operate its own system of “privileging.” The danger
with a dogmatic pluralism is that differences
themselves are seen as more important than similarities. All forms of unity become dissolved into
differences, and these differences lack anything to
hold them together. If women differ among themselves, does this mean that feminism itself is impossible since the whole notion of “women” has
been dethroned? If individuals are plural and each
individual may have numerous identities, does
this mean that individuals no longer exist, so that
the concept of the subject becomes redundant?
Pluralism can only be sustained as an outlook
and approach if it operates alongside, and not to
the exclusion of, a monist stress upon sameness.
JOHN HOFFMAN
pluralization
This involves an ethos of deep diversity, as in, for
example William E. Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization (1995). While pluralism can be seen as either
accommodation and tolerance of differences or
distribution of power among competing interest
groups, pluralization is an ethos to deepen and
multiply differences that involves a refusal to flatten them under any kind of pretense or goal:
unity, common ground, or union. The concept of
pluralization emerged out of a discontent with
various forms of politics of recognition that either
essentialized identities (multiculturalism, integration, assimilation) or imagined their boundless
proliferation (tolerance, accommodation). By contrast, pluralization aspires to recognize the depth
and multiplicity of differences while recognizing
the necessity for crossing them, for example, Paul
A. B. Clarke, Deep Citizenship (1996). As such, it
remains as a research and activist ethos rather
than a celebrated policy or avowed politics.
ENGIN ISIN
Polanyi, Karl (1886–1964)
Born in Vienna and brought up in Budapest, as a
student Polanyi knew Georg Lukács and Karl
Mannheim and became acquainted with the works
of Karl Marx, Max Weber, and Georg Simmel.
While he did not, strictly speaking, profess sociology, these influences and those of Émile Durkheim are to be found in his major work, The
Great Transformation: The Political and Economic
Origins of Our Time (1944), which was started during
his stay in England in the 1930s and finished after
emigration to the United States.
442
He sought to explain the breakdown of
nineteenth-century liberal capitalism which led
to the turmoil of the 1920s and 1930s. In a critique
of orthodox economic theory, he argued first that
its analysis did not apply to all forms of economy,
and, second, that the market was not selfregulating. Before market capitalism, economic
exchange had been embedded in social structures
regulated by norms of either “reciprocity” and/or
“redistribution.” The determination of economic
exchange exclusively by market price destabilized
social and political order; and the fundamental
economic “factors” – land, labor, and moneycapital – were, in fact, “fictitious commodities.”
The free market in land created environmental
degradation; in labor, human misery; and in
money, inflation and financial crises. This led to
a “double movement” in capitalism between, on
the one hand, states’ creation of these socially and
politically “disembedded” markets and, on the
other, the efforts to regulate their worst effects.
Thus, by the end of the 1930s, there was a swing
towards regulation in all sectors of the economy
and the beginnings of the modern welfare state.
Polanyi’s critique of the self-regulating market has
experienced a revival following the economic liberalization and globalization of the late twentieth
century.
Other important works by Polanyi are, with
Conrad Arensberg and Harry Pearson, Trade and
Market in the Early Empires (1957), and the posthumous The Livelihood of Man (1977).
GEOFFREY INGHAM
political economy
Classical political economy emerged as a distinct
field of scholarship and policy-oriented analysis
during the eighteenth century, in rough parallel
with the development of a distinct sphere of
profit-oriented, market-mediated economic activities that was nonetheless seen as dependent on
a wider nexus of legal, political, social, and moral
conditions. In contrast with the later discipline of
neoclassical economics, which studies such activities in isolation, classical political economy was a
predisciplinary field of inquiry insofar as it tried to
put the emerging capitalist economy in its wider
social context. Adam Smith (1723–90) is exemplary
here, writing not only An Inquiry into the Nature
and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776) but also
A Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and studies
of jurisprudence, politics, logic, and language.
Other key figures in this tradition are David Malthus (1766–1834), and David Ricardo (1772–1823)
political economy
whose work On the Principles of Political Economy and
Taxation (1817) made him its leading figure.
Classical political economy is linked to the rise
of a commercial and industrial bourgeoisie that
sought to challenge the economic, political, and
ideological domination of feudalism and the absolutist state. It is part of the more general European Enlightenment. A parallel tradition in
Germany, which was an economic laggard, was
more oriented to the political dimension of the
emerging system of political economy – reflected
in the Polizeiwissenschaften (“police” or policy sciences) that were concerned with good economic,
political, and moral government on behalf of the
population of a given state.
Following the rolling back of feudalism and the
consolidation of capitalism, the rise of organized
working-class resistance, and the recurrence of
capitalist crises, classical political economy was
slowly displaced by vulgar political economy.
This downplayed the class relations between capital and labor and the origins of value in the labor
process, began to focus on the efficient allocation
of scarce factors of production to competing uses,
and sought the causes of economic crisis in factors
external to the nature and dynamic of capitalism
itself.
Although their work is often mentioned as a key
part of the tradition of political economy, Karl
Marx and Friedrich Engels developed an explicit
critique of classical and vulgar political economy
both as scholarship and as the basis of economic
policy and practice. They elaborated an alternative
account of the capitalist mode of production
based on radically different philosophical assumptions and a political commitment to the proletariat rather than the bourgeoisie. Thus a significant
part of their studies was concerned to critique the
economic categories and analyses of orthodox political economy. Two major examples are Marx’s
Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (1844 [trans.
1964]) and the three-volume Theories of Surplus
Value (1861–3 [trans. 1963]). They also built on
this critique to provide an alternative account of
the capitalist mode of production, its social foundations, its dynamic, and its crisis tendencies.
Marx’s Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy
(1859), the Grundrisse (1857 [trans. 1973]), and the
incomplete analysis in the three volumes of Capital
(1867, 1885, 1894 [trans. 1970]) are his best-known
work here. Their guiding theme is that capital is
not a thing (a simple, transhistorical factor of
production) but a social relation that is a historically specific class relation between persons,
mediated through the instrumentality of things.
political economy
Marx argued that the best starting point for
such a critique was to ask why wealth in societies
where the capitalist mode of production is dominant presents itself as an immense accumulation of
commodities. He regarded the commodity as the
“cell form” of capitalism and, on this basis,
unfolded the key contradictions of capital as a
social relation. He defined the historical specificity of capitalism in terms of the generalization of
the commodity form to labor power, arguing that
the nature and dynamic of capitalism were rooted
in the inhuman treatment of labor power as if it
were a commodity. Capitalism is the first mode of
production based on the existence of formally free
wage-labor and a labor market in which workers
sell their labor power in a formally free and equal
commercial transaction to the owners of the
means of production, who in turn need this labor
to set the labor process into motion. The resulting
goods and services belong initially to the capitalists for whom the proletariat works, who are
therefore free to sell these commodities in the
marketplace. Beneath the surface appearance of
free and equal market exchange, however, lay a
despotic world of production in which capital
sought to maximize the production of surplus
labor as the basis for economic exploitation and
the accumulation of capital.
Marxism became a crucial reference point for
the subsequent development of radical, heterodox, and more orthodox forms of evolutionary
and institutional political economy. This trend is
sometimes signified in the idea that authors such
as Max Weber, Werner Sombart, Joseph Schumpeter, and Karl Polanyi engaged in a debate with
the “ghost of Marx.” Evolutionary political economy holds that time matters: there can be no valid
transhistorical analysis of economic activities because the nature of economic institutions and
conduct, the sites and stakes of economic conflict,
and the scope for economic change depend on
their prior developmental trajectory. And institutional political economy argues that institutions
matter: there can be no pure, isolated economic
calculation and conduct because these are always
shaped by specific economic institutions and
market relations and their embedding in a complex extra-economic environment. It is on this
basis that political economy has not only studied
the development of different forms of economic
organization but has also identified a number of
more or less distinct varieties of capitalism.
Vulgar political economy was the basis for neoclassical economics. This tries to develop a universal, transhistorical analysis of economic activities
443
political parties
based on a general model of rational economic
calculation about the most efficient allocation of
scarce resources (factors of production) to competing ends. Neoclassical economics is associated
with “economics imperialism,” that is, the extension of economic analysis to social spheres that
are not dominated by profit-oriented, marketmediated economic activities but are nonetheless
marked, it is claimed, by individual utility maximization within defined rules of the game.
The extension of this model is the basis for
rational choice institutionalism, theories of constitutional design and public policy, and a new
form of political economy.
BOB JESSOP
political parties
A political party is an association of like-minded
individuals that seeks to gain power in a community (usually a state) in order to promote its
chosen social order. As a social organization, a
political party has two main functions: interest
articulation and interest formation. Interest articulation is simply the process of bringing together within a single organization all the
members of a community who share relatively
similar political views on an issue or set of issues,
and to voice this position in such a way that
existing political institutions heed it. Interest formation is the process by which a party is able to
shape and influence the political views of the
members of the community at large. This dual
function that political parties perform creates internal tensions that are solved in different ways
according to the political and organizational outlook of the parties. At the interest articulation end
of this spectrum, populist parties behave in a
demagogic way and shape their political discourse
and program of governance primarily according
to what is popular in the community at any one
time. At the interest formation end, by contrast,
authoritarian party systems claim that the party’s
primary function is to teach the population
how to behave in a politically enlightened way.
In between are competitive party systems, such
as the ones present in most contemporary electoral democracies, where this tension is resolved
through compromise.
In modern electoral systems, the legitimacy of
the government rests principally on political
parties. However, party politics acquired a bad
reputation as it came to represent the (sometimes
violent, sometimes petty) struggle between different factions vying for power. During the period of
formation of modern democracies, key thinkers
and politicians such as James Madison (1751–1836)
444
political parties
and Alexis de Tocqueville saw this factionalism as
one of the main drawbacks of the new era of
democratic politics. From outside the political establishment, Karl Marx took an equally dim view
of the (bourgeois) political parties that dominated
the scene in his days. In The Eighteenth Brumaire of
Louis Napoleon (1852 [trans. 1934]), he equated
them with propaganda tools that the ruling class
used against the proletariat to give the latter the
illusion of participation, while entrenching their
own interests. Marx’s followers on the Leninist
side would take this characterization of party
politics as the starting point for their construction
of the one-party political model that came to
symbolize socialist and communist states in the
twentieth century. In pluralist political systems,
however, political parties have become the most
common form of social mobilization for participation in politics. As Max Weber pointed out in
“Politics as Vocation” (1919 [trans. 1994]), with
the bureaucratization of the state and the growth
of mass politics, political associations had to
manage more effectively the drawbacks of electoral competition, and the professionalization of
their party machinery was an effective means of
ensuring the survival of the organization over
time. Today, therefore, the vast majority of politicians are professional politicians, paid by states
(if elected) or parties to fulfill their role.
In modern multiparty systems, the most
common distinction between parties is that between left and right. Historically, this terminology
referred to the physical location of the parliamentary groups in the French Assembly after the revolution of 1789. Those on the right side of the
assembly represented principally the interests of
the nobility, while those on the left side of the
assembly represented the bourgeoisie and the
Third Estate. The right tended therefore to be
more conservative and the left more reformist.
This left–right distinction was compounded
throughout the nineteenth century by the industrial revolution. In effect, the right came to represent principally the interests of the upper classes
(the former aristocracy) as well as those of an increasingly wealthier section of the middle classes
(the petite bourgeoisie), while the left represented
the former Third Estate, which became the
working class. Throughout most of the twentieth
century, this left–right opposition dominated
pluralist political systems, be they based on a
two-party model or a multiparty one. In the late
twentieth century, however, with the apparent
weakening of class distinctions, this left–right
configuration began to lose its sharpness. At the
politics
same time, helped by the drop in electoral participation in most advanced industrial democracies,
single-issue parties as well as new political movements (for example green parties) began to
reshape the parameters of party politics.
The level of predictability that multipartyism
gave, to electoral democracies particularly, proved
wrong many of the earlier assumptions about the
negative influence of party politics on political
stability. Although the debate about the pros and
cons of party politics is still alive in many developing countries, the arguments put forward by
Robert Dahl (1915– ) in A Preface to Democratic Theory
(1956) and in Polyarchy (1971), concerning the stabilizing influence of political parties, remain
powerful explanations of this phenomenon today.
According to Dahl, what political parties provide
is a multitude of powerful minorities that ensure
that pressure is applied to the faction in government to take into account the interests of many
different social groups in society. In order to rule
effectively, parties in government find it practical
to reach out to some of the opposition factions
and to create as wide a consensus on their policies
as possible. Besides directly entering ruling coalitions, what political parties (and the bargaining
process in which they repeatedly enter) create is a
cohesive political culture that underpins the
formal institutions of the polity and strengthens
a consensual model of political rule. This phenomenon is most obvious in mature party systems
with a strong tradition of pluralism. In developing
countries, as granting the franchise to vote to
the population at large is often a recent development, the competition between mass parties
and cadre parties (which do not rely on mass
support but simply represent a political front for
groups of powerful interests), remains a source of
instability.
FREDERIC VOLPI
politics
This term refers to the process of organizing social
power in a community. Politics takes place at various levels of social interaction, from the microlevel – the politics of friendship, family politics,
and so on – to the macro-level (international politics and global politics). Most commonly, within its
broad field of application, politics is concerned
with the activities of human beings, as Aristotle’s
(384–322 BC) description of human beings as political animals (zoon politikon) indicates. However, in
the late twentieth century, biologists and specialists in animal behavior – particularly primatologists – have argued that non-human animals
living in complex societies could also be described
politics
as having political activities. Aristotle’s The Politics
(c. 350 BC) introduced the terms politic into our
vocabulary from the word politikos meaning “of, or
pertaining to, the polis” (city-state). For Aristotle,
the object of politics was the good of the community and social order embodied in the polis. As a
practical activity, it was therefore prescriptive in
nature. And the role of the politicians, whom Aristotle likened to craftsmen, was to ensure the
good functioning of the polity in order to allow
the community to reach its normative goals. The
task of those involved in politics was, and
remains, to establish and implement laws and
rules of government that promote the good of
the community (though not necessarily or systematically that of each single individual within it).
Because politics is concerned with harnessing
the social forces of a polity into an effective organization, those models of collective action that can
achieve this feat on a large scale have traditionally
been highly valued. The highest organizational
units for politics have varied significantly over
time, from small city-states to large empires. In
the contemporary context, however, the most
complex form of institutionalized political order
is the nation-state. Today, we may be witnessing
the emergence of an international community
(for example the United Nations) and of powerful supranational regional organizations (for
example the European Union) but the ability of
these institutions to dictate the rules of the political game remains tied to the behavior of the
states that compose them. Because of the enormous power that the state can muster, its political
institutions have always received a high degree of
attention. In this respect, politics is tightly connected to the science (or art) of government. It is
this art that all the great political thinkers have
tried to describe in new and ingenious ways over
time.
Probably the foremost question that political
thinkers have traditionally been asking regarding
the politics of government is whether a rule ought
to be moral in order to be effective. Classical Greek
philosophers like Plato in The Republic (c. 360 BC) or
Aristotle in The Politics generally argued that it was
so – and so did most Roman humanists and Christian medieval thinkers in their footsteps. It is not
until the Renaissance that the notion that a political rule needs not to be just to be successful
began to take the ascendancy. At this juncture,
the works of Niccolò Machiavelli (1459–1517),
such as The Prince (1513 [trans. 1988]) and The
Discourses (1531 [trans. 1996]), were of particular
importance. From this conceptual transformation
445
politics
comes the notion of raison d’état – the idea that, for
the greater good of the political community, the
state (and its representatives) could and should
behave outside the moral framework that applies
to ordinary individuals. As theorized in works
such as Six Books of the Commonwealth (1576 [trans.
1955]) by Jean Bodin (1530–96) and, most notably,
Leviathan (1651) by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679),
this rationale for politics was increasingly put to
the service of the absolutist powers that ruled
Europe and its growing number of colonies in
the early modern period. The inadequacy of absolutist politics and of authoritarianism were highlighted by thinkers like John Locke (1632–1704) in
Two Treatises of Government (1690) and Baron
Charles de Montesquieu in The Spirit of the Laws
(1748 [trans. 1989]). However, it is only in the late
eighteenth century with the French Revolution
and the diffusion of writings such as the Social
Contract (1762 [trans. 1997]) by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78) that politics increasingly became a
matter and an activity for the people as much as
for the aristocracy.
In the nineteenth century, with the extension of
the voting rights to an increasingly larger proportion of the population (the poor, women, slaves,
and so forth) politics truly became a mass phenomenon. This transformation of the nature of
the political community had important implications for earlier notions of “government,” conceived as the greater good of the state and the
monarch. Now, the state was redefined to include
the nation and a new brand of raison d’état was
introduced, which was influenced by the philosophy of classic utilitarianism – often known as “the
greatest happiness for the greatest number.” The
notion of utilitarian politics developed from
works such as the Introduction to the Principles of
Morals and Legislation (1789) by Jeremy Bentham
(1748–1832) and John Stuart Mill’s On Liberty
(1859), but also in a different vein from those of
Karl Marx. Under various guises, utilitarianism
and the notion of the good of the people have
remained important justifications of the politics
of government throughout the twentieth century
and up to the present day. It is only towards the
end of the twentieth century, most notably under
the impulse of John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice
(1971), that the utilitarian logic that underpinned
politics slowly began to be partially superseded by
a more ontological and procedural approach to the
political good, grounded on notions of fairness and
justice for each member of the community. This
conceptual evolution, in its turn, reinforced
the articulation of identity politics by minority
446
politics
groups who were forcefully incorporated in the
nation, and who increasingly began to challenge
the political organization of the contemporary
nation-state from within.
Historically and geographically, the issues that
have been deemed political always varied enormously. In western Europe, for over a millennium,
religion was a political issue par excellence. However, with the rise of secularism in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries, particularly in western
democracies, religious preferences increasingly
became an essentially private matter, which political actors endeavored to maintain outside the
boundaries of the political debate. (But the revival
of religious politics at the beginning of the
twenty-first century illustrates clearly that any
such historical trends are always susceptible
to being reversed.) If some issues can become
de-politicized over time, other previously nonpolitical matters can also enter the political
debate. Some issues have long been recognized as
having political implications without being selfreflectively acknowledged as a political matter.
Gender is one of them. In most political systems,
political opportunities are influenced by gender
status (typically to the detriment of female participants), but it is only with the rise of women’s
movements in the nineteenth century and of
feminism in the twentieth century that gender
issues have become legitimate political concerns.
Finally, other issues acquired a political status
simply because of the realization that the requirements for the survival of a growing human population in limited spatial settings demanded that
such concerns be formulated in political terms.
The environment is one such aspect; and the rise
of environmental movements and green politics
increasingly contributes to redefining the boundaries of the political in the twenty-first century.
The boundaries of politics are always and necessarily highly contested because of the range of
issues that can potentially be considered as political – from the economy to the environment, and
from morality to sex. Drawing from the genealogy
of the term, it is generally acknowledged that
politics is an activity that concerns the polis, in
other words the public sphere. But even such a
general statement about public affairs is not easy
to sustain systematically The identification of
public goods and the distinction between the
public and the private, in particular, have been
continuously questioned by social groups arguing
for a better (more effective, fairer, and so on)
organization of wealth and power in the community. These debates and challenges underscore the
politics
fact that an element of force is always necessarily
involved in politics. From this perspective, politics
can be conceived in the terms of Harold Lasswell’s
book Politics: Who Gets What, When, How (1936) (or
encapsulated by Vladimir Ilich Lenin’s saying, Kto?
Kogo? [Who? Whom?] – who does what to whom?).
Yet, in so far as politics, as a social activity, is
distinct from the exercising of brute force, it also
consists in the art of resolving public disagreements and conflicts by engaging collectively in
dialog and bargaining. The boundary between politics as a means of resolving social conflict, and
politics as a cause of conflict, is a porous one. As
the military strategist Carl von Clausewitz
pointed out in On War (1832), in international
affairs it is often the case that war is the continuation of politics by other means – even though this
difference of means cannot be underestimated
from a social perspective. Even in domestic settings, politics, and particularly party politics for
the followers of Marx, involves an element of oppression of the masses by the ruling classes in the
ongoing struggle between the proletariat and the
bourgeoisie for the control of the means of production and the institutions of the state. Yet, in
contemporary political systems, as the discourse
on democracy has come to dominate the global
debate on politics, this activity tends to be seen as
more discursive and consensual than might otherwise be thought.
In the contemporary context, one can distinguish at least four main levels of political
interaction for analytical purposes: global/transnational, international, domestic, and local/intimate. Despite appearances, these categories cannot
be neatly located along a well-defined spectrum as
the two ends often meet – religion, for example
affects politics on a global scale, as well as intervening in this process at a very intimate level, and
so do economic issues that have both macro- and
micro-political implications. Traditionally, state
politics has been at the heart of people’s understanding of what politics stood for. State politics
has two main aspects: an internal dimension
(domestic politics), and an external one – international politics or international relations. In
domestic politics, the ordering of society by the
state is probably the most common yet intense
form of political activities in which individuals
are repeatedly involved, as well as being subjected
to. In this context, politics is simply the way in
which individuals act collectively (usually by
joining political associations) in order to mold
the political community in to the shape that
they see fit. Whether this process is in fact
Popper, Karl (1902–1994)
bottom-up or top-down depends on the type of
political system that is in place at any one time –
for example democratic on autocratic contexts. In
the field of international politics, individuals outside the ruling circles hardly have any direct involvement in the decisionmaking process, except
in the form of the proverbial public opinion. International politics, especially at its war-like end,
can, however, have a massive and direct impact
on all the members of the political community.
Local and even intimate politics, by contrast, represent the sphere of political activities in which
social interactions are the most common for most
individuals, most of the time. The networks composed by the family, friends, kin, neighbors, and
other formal or informal proximity associations
constitute a ready-made receptacle for politics,
albeit one with usually limited resources for
action. Finally, the process of globalization of politics – be it through the activities of transnational
non-state actors (for example Al-Qaeda) or supranational institutions (such as the International
Monetary Fund) – increasingly has such an impact
on every aspect of life that it is becoming the one
single set of factors that redefines the concept of
politics in the interdependent global system that
is emerging in the twenty-first century.
FREDERIC VOLPI
polyethnic rights
– see rights.
Popper, Karl (1902–1994)
Born in Vienna, Karl Popper attended the University there, and worked as a cabinet maker and
primary school teacher. He received his PhD in
1928. From 1937 to 1945 he taught at Canterbury
University College, New Zealand, and from 1945 to
1969 at the London School of Economics.
Popper is best known as a philosopher of science
and defender of open societies. In books such as
The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), Popper contends that the study of nature and society share
similar logics. Yet social scientists and philosophers often misinterpret the logic of natural science while attempting to imitate it, creating
pseudo-scientific theories that cannot be refuted.
Popper counters such claims with his theory of
critical rationalism. In Popper’s view, scientific
theories must be falsifiable. Any theory can find
evidence to support it. Only those theories that
can stand the rigors of empirical testing and
attempted refutation can claim to be scientific.
Popper devoted The Open Society and Its Enemies
(1945) and The Poverty of Historicism (1944) to the
447
popular culture
analysis of theorists such as Plato and Karl Marx,
who assert their discoveries of universal truths.
Popper criticizes such theories as unscientific
and anti-democratic. They do not promote open
discussion, tolerance of opposing views, or a pragmatic and piecemeal approach to social change,
the ingredients of a good society. For Popper, the
growth of knowledge is tied to a community of
scientists who freely and rationally criticize one
another’s viewpoints. Institutions guaranteeing
such debate and dialog are crucial for the advancement of science and an open, democratic society.
KENNETH H. TUCKER, JR.
popular culture
The early waves of studying popular culture
emerged out of Great Britain during the 1950s
and 1960s. Figures such as the literary and cultural critics Raymond Williams and Richard
Hoggart and the historian E. P. Thompson (1924–
93) sought to discover within the study of popular
culture the political contestation of values and
ways of life. If high culture was enjoyed by the
few, then most popular culture, it seemed, reproduced the dominant orientations of a capitalistdominated marketplace. However, historically the
working class and the Romantic movement had
sought to produce alternative forms of popular art
and culture that had sought to criticize the status
quo. These arguments led many in sociology, cultural studies, and history to investigate how the
people had been actively involved in making their
own culture (or cultures) from below. Such views
were at this time contrasted with the ideas of the
early Frankfurt School, that tended to reduce the
study of popular culture to that of mass culture.
Whereas mass culture captured the way in which
the production of culture was centrally organized
in terms of the needs of a culture industry (rise
of mass audiences for television, press, and consumer goods), a genuinely popular culture was
made by and for ordinary people.
From the 1970s onward, the work of Italian
Marxist Antonio Gramsci and his conception of
hegemony were to influence these debates deeply.
The idea here was that popular culture was constituted by a set of institutions, practices, and
forms that aimed to win the consent of the people.
This was more than a simple act of dominant
groups establishing their domination, but always
required the active incorporation of subordinate groups and cultures. This approach became
strongly connected with a number of writers
who associated with the Birmingham Centre for
Contemporary Cultural studies (including Stuart
448
popular culture
Hall, Angela McRobbie, and Paul Willis). The study
of youth cultures, popular magazines, sport, and
the media then were undertaken to reveal processes of containment and resistance in respect
of the dominant culture. In particular this tradition has placed intellectual emphasis upon the
various and contested meanings of popular culture and its role in disrupting or securing relations of domination. There are three main
criticisms of these arguments: the emphasis on
meaning leads to a relative neglect of changing
institutional features which organize the production and distribution of popular culture; the critical role which the avant-garde or more elite
forms of high culture have played in creating
critical consciousness historically tends to disappear from the analysis; and little of the actual
theorizing about cultural resistance pays much
attention to the need to formulate more adequate
social and political environments that would
seek a more just settlement between competing
cultures.
Since the early 1990s many have become aware
of the need to promote more global understandings of the operation of popular culture. The
new mode of popular cultural studies has sought
to understand its formation both within and in
opposition to cultural nationalism. This has further broken with the idea of homogeneous national cultures in order to investigate the ways
in which, in an increasingly global culture, different groups have been able to maintain interconnections with one another. In particular the
development of transnational forms of mobility
in respect of tourism and the media, as well as
the development of counter-publics on the basis
of race and gender, have pushed the analysis of
popular culture beyond the nation-state.
Paul Gilroy, in There Ain’t No Black in the Union Jack
(1987), argued that black popular music has been
the key cultural location for the articulation of a
sense of diasporic connection between Africa,
America, and Britain. This has operated in a
number of ways, including the borrowing of musical styles and influences, protesting about injustice, the recording of struggles, and in certain rap
songs the display of misogyny. Through the
fostering of a distinctively black aesthetic, Gilroy
argues that music has provided a uniquely connective culture in a globalized civil society. Such
features have not only proved to be important in
the study of the complexity of popular forms but
have also warned against many postmodern arguments which simply assumed that distinctions
between high and popular culture had evaporated.
population studies
However, many remain critical of these and similar studies for neglecting to analyze the continued
power of the nation-state and popular discourses
of nationhood that continue to exert a considerable amount of influence over the organization
and meaning of popular culture.
Further, many are now less concerned with the
meanings of particular popular texts and more
with how a diversity of audience members actively
constitutes the popular. John Fiske, in Reading the
Popular (1989), has gone farthest in this respect,
arguing that the art of everyday life is commonly
involved in the transformation of consumer products. All popular culture is the site of struggle
where meanings are never controlled by the producers, but are actively and pleasurably produced
by the consumers. These irreverent forms of jouissance erupt from below and are opposed to the
disciplinary techniques utilized by the power
bloc. Here there is a double pleasure involved in
the audience’s reading of popular texts. The first is
the enjoyment involved in the symbolic production of meanings that oppose those of the power
bloc, and the second concerns the actual activity
of being productive. In this scenario, the market,
by contrast with the declining high culture of the
powerful, brings certain cultural products within
the critical horizons of the people. Many have
been extremely critical of these developments,
arguing that, unlike those who first sought to
study popular culture in the 1950s and 1960s,
such views end up endorsing an uncritical culture
of consumption. If popular culture depends upon
what we do with culture rather than what it does
to us this would seemingly cancel any criticisms
we might want to make of the power of cultural
producers. Most popular culture continues to be
shaped by the practices of a dominant capitalist
culture, whatever role it might play within the
domains of everyday life.
NICK STEVENSON
population studies
– see demography.
populism
This began as a movement of small farmers in the
South and Midwest in the late nineteenth-century
United States who desired control of the federal
government, which they believed was dominated
by northern industrialists and bankers. Populism
has resurfaced as an ambiguous political concept,
designating political positions from a call for a
more equitable distribution of wealth to criticisms
of liberal beliefs regarding abortion, gun control,
affirmative action, and the like.
populism
Late nineteenth-century agrarian populism attempted to preserve a way of life against an encroaching industrial society. During this era,
technological growth was unprecedented, as railroads, the telegraph, and eventually the telephone
increased the scope and pace of business activity.
Immigrants from southern and eastern Europe
streamed into the United States, transforming
the countenance of the working class. Large corporations and an aggressive federal government
centralized economic and administrative power,
and local communities lost control over their
destinies.
As wealth flowed into railroad and manufacturing industries, the incomes of many small
farmers declined. They were driven into debt by
falling agricultural prices, increased transportation costs, and a shortage of credit. The populist movement grew as many farmers banded
together in order to pool resources and break the
monopoly on lending held by banks. Populists
developed a political and economic program,
advocating a more egalitarian economic system.
They attempted to democratically reform federal
and state governments, supporting a progressive
income tax, the direct election of United States
senators, and more reliance on popular initiatives
and referendums to change government policy.
Many of these demands were stripped of their
radical impulse and incorporated into the platform of the Democratic Party, as populism faded
in the early years of the twentieth century.
The populists called for the power of the people
versus the elites. It provided a distinctive language of American radicalism, different from the
Marxism more popular in Europe. Yet the definition of who constituted the “people” was ambiguous. Many populists harbored nativist prejudices.
Racism against African Americans sometimes
intertwined with a fear that a vast conspiracy of
moneylenders, often either Catholic or Jewish,
controlled the economy and the government.
This ambiguity continues to haunt the meaning
of populism. Many politicians embrace populism,
calling for a more egalitarian economy, and criticizing the power of large corporations. But a conservative cultural populism has arisen in the
United States in the wake of the controversial
era of the 1960s. Often tied to a fundamentalist
view of religion, contemporary cultural populism
feeds on animosity towards government taxation
and affirmative action programs, and policies
aimed at helping the (largely nonwhite) poor.
Yet it favors government action to suppress forms
of behavior considered immoral, from restricting
449
positional goods
abortions to controlling the distribution of
pornography.
Scholars such as Seymour M. Lipset in Political
Man (1960) contend that populism arose as the
United States political center broke down, and
people embraced authoritarian beliefs that gave
voice to their economic and cultural frustrations.
Progressives such as Thomas Frank in What’s the
Matter with Kansas (2004) state that American conservatives have convinced many working-class
people that their enemy is an ambiguous cultural
elite, rather than the wealthy.
KENNETH H. TUCKER, JR.
positional goods
– see consumption.
positivism
The term positivism was coined in the 1830s by
Auguste Comte as the name for his philosophy of
science. Philosophie positive, as the theory and history of the positive sciences, whose full range was
deemed to have been completed by Comte’s own
sociology, would provide the mental framework
for industrial society. In contrast with theology
and metaphysics, positive (or scientific) knowledge was based on impressions externelles, and was
oriented to the discovery of laws, understood as
regularities in phenomena, rather than ultimate
causes. Positivism thus had a relative rather than
absolute view of truth. “Positive,” at the same
time, meant affirmative and constructive, as opposed to critical and negative. The “metaphysics”
that Comtean positivism sought to expunge was
not only an obfuscatory residue of religious belief.
In the context of the grande crise that marked the
birth of industrialism, it expressed the rising up of
individual reason, which, in itself, was abstract,
anarchic, and “incapable of building.” By the same
token, positivism adopted a social, rather than
individual, viewpoint, a shift that was not only
epistemological but linked to the altruisme that
gave knowledge its ends and fixed the mind on
objects outside itself.
While positivism has continued to be associated
with Comte, his totalizing philosophy and program have long been abandoned, and the term
has come to have a more generic meaning. In
this wider sense, positivism encompasses a diverse
spectrum of positions which champion a scientific
viewpoint, and insist that knowledge claims, including in the social domain, should confine
themselves to what can be derived from observable phenomena. Such positions range from the
classical positivism of Comte and his followers, to
450
post-Fordism
the more astringent logical positivism of the
Vienna Circle, as well as, more generally, to operationalist, quantitative, and statistics-based tendencies in sociology and other human sciences.
Whether sociology itself, as Comte claimed, can
be a positive science, and in what sense, has been
hotly debated throughout its history. Besides
issues about causality and agency, and about the
constructed nature of “facts,” there are difficulties
conceiving and treating the social as an objectively knowable domain. Social reality has an interior, subjective, dimension, and sociology itself is a
social phenomenon, so that, for sociology, the
subject of knowledge is part of its object. For classical sociology, which grappled with these issues,
a science of society was not impossible, but it had
special features, and could not be modeled on
other sciences without reductionism. Karl Marx
thought that the capitalist economic base could
be analyzed with the precision of natural sciences,
but not the superstructure where “social antagonisms become conscious and are fought out.” In
Germany, sociology came to be classified among
the Geisteswissenschaften, implying an interpretative and non-quantitative approach which Max
Weber sought to imbue with a “value-neutral”
spirit through an emphasis on formal structures,
chains of cause and effect, and comparative civilizational analysis. In France, Émile Durkheim criticized Comte’s sociology as itself metaphysics, and
adopted a neo-Kantian conception of knowledge,
but still affirmed that social facts could be studied
“according to the methods of the natural sciences”
so as to establish “laws of concomitance and succession.” However, the Post-Durkheim Annales
school shifted from laws to structures and abandoned developmentalism, while philosophical
issues about positivism in the social sciences
were raised anew by phenomenology and critical
theory. These resurfaced in the 1960s with a new
round of the late nineteenth-century “positivism
debate” (Positivismusstreit) between Jürgen Habermas and Karl Popper, as well as in the controversies surrounding Louis Althusser’s intervention
“for Marx,” which resurrected Comtean themes
ANDREW WERNICK
in a Marxist form.
post-Fordism
This is an ambiguous term that describes a relatively durable form of economic organization that
happens to follow Fordism and/or resolves the
crisis tendencies of Fordism. A basic problem is
that this concept lacks any positive content – its
chronological prefix indicates only that it comes
after Fordism. This is why some theorists propose
post-Fordism
substantive alternatives such as Toyotism, Fujitsuism, Sonyism, and Gatesism or, again, informational capitalism, the knowledge-based economy,
and the network economy. However, to understand the rationale behind such terms, we must
first consider Fordism and its crisis tendencies.
Fordism is widely used to describe the system of
mass production pioneered in the early twentieth
century by the Ford Motor Company and/or the
typical postwar mode of growth in North America
and western Europe. In the latter respect, Fordism
has been analyzed, often without adequate distinction, in terms of four dimensions. First, the
Fordist industrial paradigm involves mass production of standardized goods on a moving assembly
line using dedicated machinery and semi-skilled
labor. Second, as a national accumulation regime,
it involves a virtuous cycle of mass production and
mass consumption. Third, in line with regulation
theory, it has been analyzed as a mode of regulation with five dimensions: (a) an institutionalized
compromise between organized labor and big
business such that workers accept capital’s right
to manage in return for wages indexed to productivity and inflation; (b) monopolistic competition
between large firms based on cost-plus pricing
and advertising; (c) centralized financial capital,
deficit finance, and credit-based mass consumption; (d) state intervention to secure full employment and enable all citizens to share in mass
consumption; and (e) the embedding of national
economies in a liberal international economic
order. Fourth, as a form of social life, it involves
a mass society with mass consumption, mass
media, mass transport, mass politics, and so on.
Despite (or perhaps because of) its wide use, the
notion of “Fordism” is contested. Key disputes
concern: (1) the extent and significance of mass
production for postwar advanced capitalist economies; (2) whether economies as varied as the
United States, Germany, Denmark, Italy, or Britain can all be usefully described as Fordist; (3) the
extent to which the social and political contexts in
which mass production and mass consumption
developed were similar, and, in turn, how far the
growth of mass production and mass consumption was shaped by these contexts; and (4) whether
social phenomena such as McDonaldization derive
from the Fordism industrial paradigm or from
broader social processes.
The Fordist accumulation regime and mode of
regulation allegedly became dominant in advanced capitalism during postwar reconstruction
and then facilitated the long postwar boom.
During the 1970s, however, crisis tendencies
post-Fordism
started to show in each of its four dimensions.
This is seen in the gradual exhaustion of the
growth potential of mass production and an intensified working-class resistance to its alienating
working conditions; an emerging market saturation for mass consumer durables; a declining
profit rate combined with stagflation; a growing
fiscal crisis and a declining state capacity for economic management due to internationalization;
a popular rejection of standardized, bureaucratic
treatment in the welfare state; and a weakened
international order due to declining American
economic dominance and political hegemony.
These conditions promoted various economic
and political actors to search for solutions to the
crisis of Fordism, either by restoring its typical
growth dynamics to produce a neo-Fordist regime
and/or by developing a new accumulation regime and mode of regulation. Social scientists
have adopted three main approaches to giving a
positive content to such a new, hence post-Fordist,
regime: (1) focus on the transformative role of new
technologies and practices in regard to material
and immaterial production – especially new information and communication technologies and
their facilitation of a new, more flexible, networked global economy; (2) focus on the leading
economic sectors that enable a transition from
mass industrial production to postindustrial
production; and (3) focus on how major crisis tendencies of Fordism are overcome through the consolidation of a new and stable series of economic
and extra-economic regulatory fixes corresponding discursively and materially to new and profitable growth potentials. Even thirty years after the
crisis of Fordism became apparent, debate continues over whether a stable post-Fordist order
has yet been consolidated and, indeed, whether
the stability of Fordism was an exceptional period
in an otherwise typically disorderly and crisisprone pattern of capitalist development.
Those who are committed to the assumptions of
a stable post-Fordist order regard its key features
as: (1) a flexible production process based on flexible machines or systems and an appropriately
flexible workforce; (2) a stable mode of growth
based on flexible production, growing productivity based on economies of scope, rising incomes
for polyvalent skilled workers and the service
class, increased demand for differentiated goods
and services favored by the growing discretionary
element in these incomes, increased profits based
on technological rents and the full utilization of
flexible capacity, reinvestment in more flexible
production equipment and techniques and/or
451
postcolonial theory
postcolonial theory
new sets of products, and a further boost to economies of scope; (3) a post-Fordist wage relation based
on polarization between multiskilled workers and
the unskilled and a decline in national or industrial collective bargaining; (4) the rise of flexible,
lean, and networked firms oriented to their distinctive core competences and strategic alliances;
(5) the dominance of hypermobile, rootless private
bank credit and forms of cybercash that circulate internationally, and the subordination of government finance to international money and
currency markets; (6) a shift from the primacy of
the postwar Keynesian national welfare state to
a political regime concerned with international
competitiveness and innovation, with promoting
a flexible workforce and full employability rather
than jobs for life, with coordinating economic and
social policies on local, regional, national, and
supranational scales, and with developing new
forms of economic and social governance to compensate for state as well as market failure; and (7)
the shift from international regimes that secured
the conditions for the survival of national economies and sovereign states to supranational or
even global regimes that address economic and
political problems that transcend national
boundaries.
These supposedly generic features of postFordism are very unevenly developed and, where
they exist, they assume quite different forms –
neoliberal in some contexts, statist or social democratic in others. There is also continuing debate
over the extent, significance, and durability of
these features in the face of the continuing
contradictions in global capitalism. Nonetheless,
attempts to identify the positive content of postFordism have contributed to the emerging shape
of an after-Fordist economic and political order.
BOB JESSOP
postcolonial theory
This is a field of inquiry and collection of concepts
aimed at illuminating, as well as criticizing, the
cultural, intellectual, literary, and epistemological dominance of the modern West over countries previously colonized by western imperial
powers. Postcolonial theory is not a theory in the
tradition of positivism or realism but rather a
range of premises, analytic approaches, and conceptual tools for understanding the legacies of
colonialism and imperialism in formerly colonized
societies, with a primary focus upon cultural legacies. Postcolonial theory also carries an explicit
political agenda. It examines the cultural bases
and legacies of imperialism in order to identify
452
and support resistances to them. Its main contributions include: advancing colonialism and imperialism as categories of social analysis on a par
with categories like social class, gender and race
and ethnicity; identifying the cultural processes
involved in colonialism and imperialism; and questioning the position that European knowledge and
culture has normative supremacy.
The origins of postcolonial theory are disputed,
but three sources from the humanities are typically identified. One lies in Commonwealth literary
studies, a field of study that began in the 1960s in
former British colonies among literary critics seeking to contribute their voices to an academy seen
as “Anglocentric.” Another source is Edward Said’s
Orientalism (1978), which argued that imperialism
had been facilitated by forms of knowledge and
categorical binaries. A final source is the field of
Subaltern Studies, advanced by historians of
British colonialism in India seeking to uncover
the voices and agency of peasant groups in the
making of colonial history. Further proponents of
postcolonial theory include literary critics: Homi
Bhabha and Gayatri Spivak are among the most
notable. Writers in the field of postcolonial
theory have also sought to expand the base of
its founders by turning to African intellectuals
like Franz Fanon, Ainé Césaire (1913– ), and Albert
Memmi (1920– ).
Given these diverse origins and developments,
postcolonial theory does not offer a unified theory
or a single methodology. There are, however, at
least two key theoretical claims upon which its
key concepts and lines of inquiry are based. The
first is that imperialism did not only involve the
use of coercion or economic domination but also
discourse and associated forms of knowledge and
representation. Said’s Orientalism is seen as the
foremost innovator of this thesis. Said argued
that British imperialism in the Middle East was
enabled by a “style of thought,” field of academic
study, or “discursive formation” called “Orientalism.” Orientalism constructed a fundamental
“ontological and epistemological distinction . . .
between ‘the Orient’ and ‘the Occident’” or “the
West” and “the East,” akin to the socialpsychological distinction between self and other.
It likewise portrayed westerners as “rational,
peaceful, liberal, [and] logical” while portraying
Orientals as uncivilized, irrational, inferior, and
lacking and therefore in need of control by the
West (1978: 2). According to Said, Orientalism was
critical for imperialism and colonialism because it
enabled the West “to manage . . . the Orient politically, sociologically, militarily, ideologically,
postcolonial theory
scientifically, and imaginatively” (1978: 3). Said
therefore identified a cultural or epistemological
dimension to imperial domination that worked in
conjunction with other dimensions of power. One
of his targets was Marxism, which was seen as
either overlooking the importance of Orientalism
in facilitating imperialism or reducing it to mere
ideology. Said instead drew upon Michel Foucault’s theory of power and knowledge to argue
that Orientalism did not reflect the economic
bases of imperialism but was productive of imperialism itself. Orientalism allowed for a “flexible
positional superiority, which puts the westerner
in a whole series of possible relationships with the
Orient without ever losing him the relative upper
hand” (1978: 6–7).
The other key claim of postcolonial theory is
that decolonization did not bring the dissolution
of political, social, and economic inequalities between former imperial powers and previously colonized societies. Postcolonial theory insists that
those inequalities have continued through the
postindependence period. World-systems and dependency theories make a similar argument, but
the contribution of postcolonial theory is to suggest that persistent inequalities are related to the
epistemological and cultural legacies of colonialism. The dominating discourses and knowledges
that facilitated imperialism persist into the postindependence period, contributing to a form of
cultural hegemony and rendering postcolonial
peoples without the cultural tools or critical consciousness to challenge western dominance. The
persistence of colonialism’s effects is important
for postcolonial theory because it underlies one
of its key suggestions: that the former colonial
status of societies could be seen as a category of
social analysis alongside race, class, and gender.
It also led postcolonial theorists to employ the
term “postcolonial” rather than “post-colonial.”
The latter hyphenated term posits the end of colonialism, but the unhyphenated term is meant to
signify the continuation of colonialism’s effects
despite formal decolonization.
The main lines of research and thinking in postcolonial theory have been guided by these two
main insights. The idea that colonialism and imperialism were facilitated by knowledge and discourse set the basis for colonial discourse analysis,
which seeks to examine colonial forms of representation and their relationship to power. Literary
critics, for example, examine novels and other
forms of popular representation for the ways in
which they portray colonized peoples. Historians
working from a postcolonial perspective extend
postcolonial theory
Said’s analysis by arguing that the idea of “history” itself, like Orientalism, has served to portray
postcolonial societies and peoples as inferior and
lacking. Western historical knowledge is rooted in
a Hegelian logic that encourages further binary
distinctions between the Occident and the Orient
while privileging the former as the agent of
history. Other postcolonial theorists have stressed the incoherence of colonial discourse and
representations. These theorists accuse Said of
portraying Oriental discourse as uniform and
monolithic and argue that colonial discourse was
fractured and incomplete. H. Bhabha drew from
poststructuralism and deconstruction to argue
that colonial stereotypes were contradictory and
“ambivalent” or “undecided”: they offered images
of the colonized that were presumably fixed and
natural but the images themselves were shifting
and at times contradictory. The colonial subject is
portrayed as “savage (cannibal) and yet the most
obedient and signified of servants (the bearer of
food); he is the embodiment of rampant sexuality
and yet innocent as a child; he is mystical, primitive, simple-minded and yet the most worldly and
accomplished liar” (Location of Culture, 1994: 82).
The premise that the cultural effects of colonialism persist through the postindependence
period also guides postcolonial studies. Some postcolonial theorists turned to the work of Fanon and
Memmi as a new source of inspiration. Fanon and
Memmi argued that colonialism had psychological effects that were detrimental to colonized
peoples and which continued even after decolonization, and so postcolonial theorists extend this
theme in various ways. A. Nandy’s The Intimate
Enemy (1983) argued that the superiority of the
West portrayed in Orientalism became deeply
rooted in the psyche of the colonized. While
Fanon argued racial hierarchies were internalized, Nandy argued that geographical and civilization hierarchies were also internalized. Nandy
also took up Memmi’s idea that the psychological
effects of colonialism extended to colonizer and
colonized alike.
Postcolonial theory’s key insights have also
guided its explicit political project. If imperialism
was supported by discourse, forms of representation, and knowledge, and if its cultural legacies
persist through the postcolonial period, postcolonial theory aims to construct an alternative basis
of knowledge that might challenge or resist those
effects. In Orientalism, Said raised one of the key
questions to which postcolonial theory has tried
to respond: “How can we know and respect the
other?” To meet the challenge, literary critics who
453
postcommunist societies
work with postcolonial theory look for ways in
which literary representation might subvert
Eurocentrism. Historians advancing postcolonial
theory aim to write historical narratives that
highlight the experiences, agency, and voice of
colonized subjects so as to question in turn the
authority of European experiences and perceptions. Here postcolonial theory can be seen as
having an affinity with postmodernism in that it
questions rather than presumes linear narratives
of historical progress and development. Yet its
distinct contribution is to stress that those narratives have helped to subjugate colonized peoples
in particular.
The key dilemma for postcolonial theory, as G.
Spivak pointed out, is to produce alternative
knowledges without reproducing the forms they
aim to resist. How can one write a history of colonialism and postcolonialism while “history” itself
is a form of knowledge that facilitates imperialism? To meet this challenge, some have turned
to deconstruction. Postcolonial theory cannot cast
off western knowledges and so the best it can do is
show that those knowledges are incomplete and
fractured. Bhabha expanded his analysis of colonial discourse to introduce the idea of hybridity as
a potentially resistant form. As colonial discourse
was fractured and ambivalent, colonized subjects
were able to appropriate it and use it in ways that
challenged its authority. The task of postcolonial
theory is to examine these instances. Others,
employing the genealogical method of analysis
proposed by Foucault, suggest that proper postcolonial histories should offer narratives that
“provincialize” Europe, that is, treat European
dominance as a contingent or accidental rather
than a necessary or linear outcome, thereby
challenging the West’s representation of itself.
Marxist critics, however, suggest these methods
run into difficulties because they lead to a selfreferential textualism that ignores the material
bases of domination. These debates with Marxism
constitute one of the main turning points for
postcolonial theory in establishing its research
agenda and orientation.
JULIAN GO
postcommunist societies
This concept refers to the countries of eastern
Europe and the republics of the former Soviet
Union which, during the anticommunist revolutions of 1989–91, gained full sovereignty and autonomy, and introduced comprehensive regime
change towards western models of political democracy, market economy, and open, pluralistic
culture. They include two groups of countries.
454
postcommunist societies
First, those which fell under the political, economic, and ideological domination of the USSR
after World War II as the result of the Yalta and
Potsdam agreements among the Allied powers:
Poland, Hungary, Czechoslovakia, the German
Democratic Republic (central–eastern Europe), Albania, Bulgaria, Romania, and Yugoslavia (Balkan
states). Their number has grown in the 1990s
owing to the separation of the Czech Republic
and Slovakia, as well as the breakdown of Yugoslavia in the wake of Balkan wars into Slovenia,
Croatia, Macedonia, and Bosnia-Herzegovina, only
Serbia and Montenegro retaining the label of the
Yugoslav Republic. The second group consists of
the fifteen successor states to Soviet republics: the
Russian Federation, plus Ukraine, Belarus, and
other members of the Commonwealth of Independent States (CIS), with Lithuania, Latvia, and
Estonia (the Baltic states) remaining outside the
CIS.
After World War II all these countries became
part of the Soviet Empire, and were ruled or dominated by the largest and most powerful country
of the region. The republics of the Soviet Union
constituted an internal empire, over which Russia
exercised direct rule, whereas the countries of
eastern Europe constituted an external empire,
whose countries had limited sovereignty and imposed regimes patterned on that of the Soviet
Union (they were satellite countries). The chief
commonalities of these regimes were the oneparty state and monocentric authority in the
area of politics, and central planning and state
ownership in the area of the economy. These features were combined with a controlled official
culture (marked by extensive censorship), and the
suppression and limitation of civil society. Apart
from these principal similarities, there was great
diversity in their concrete implementation. In the
Soviet Union itself there were temporal differences in the repressiveness of the regime, ranging
from the dictatorial Stalinist period on one hand,
to a relatively liberalized system under Mikhail
Gorbachev (1931– ). Among “satellite” countries
Yugoslavia under Tito (Joseph Broz) (1892–1980)
was the first to obtain political sovereignty, and
approximate a market economy, but it retained
strong ideological control. From the middle 1950s
Poland under Wladyslaw Gomulka (1905–82)
and Hungary under Janos Kadar (1912–89) became
exceptional in allowing the rudiments of an economic market and entrepreneurship, as well as
some liberalization of politics, for example the
unique phenomenon of the Polish Catholic
Church possessing considerable autonomy, or
postcommunist societies
the emergence of organized democratic opposition in Poland and Czechoslovakia as early as
the 1970s. Romania under Nicolae Ceaucescu
(1918–89) was able to conduct relatively independent foreign policy, otherwise sticking to communist orthodoxy. At the other extreme, tight political
and ideological control and direct Soviet influence
were characteristic of the GDR (East Germany –
the frontier country against the West), Albania,
Bulgaria, and – after 1968 – Czechoslovakia.
The breakdown of the communist empire
started from eastern Europe, with the revolutions
of 1989 typically originating from below and mobilizing pro-democratic and opposition movements (Poland’s Solidarity movement being the
biggest and most powerful). The concrete processes
of extrication from the communist regime differed
markedly: for example in Poland and Hungary it
was by means of round-table talks and the peaceful, gradual exit from power by communist elites;
in Czechoslovakia, by means of a bloodless “velvet
revolution” in the streets; in Romania, by means
of the bloody uprising against the communist
dictatorship; in the GDR by direct incorporation
into the political and economic system of West
Germany, through the process of unification. The
disbanding of the Soviet Union itself followed
soon after, in 1991, as the result of a process
initiated from above, by Gorbachev’s reforms of
glasnost and perestroika, and carried further in the
direction of democracy and capitalism under the
leadership of President Boris Yeltsin (1931– ).
Calling the societies which emerged in these
processes “postcommunist” draws attention to
their continuing dependence on the communist
past and their incomplete reshaping into the western model. The legacies of Communism are to be
felt in four areas. In the political domain, there
are deficiencies in the operation of the democratic
system, which are most pronounced in the countries devoid of earlier democratic traditions (for
example in Russia, some post-Soviet republics,
Bulgaria, and Albania), and relatively smaller in
the countries which had experienced periods of
democratic rule in their earlier history (for instance Poland, Hungary, and the Czech Republic).
But everywhere one observes: incompetent, illprepared, often corrupt, and nepotistic political
elites, chaotic and amorphous party systems, lack
of an independent apolitical civil service, weak
rule of law, continued influence of former communists able to convert their earlier political
capital into personal enrichment (“new nomenklatura” or “oligarchs”). In the economic domain
the consolidation of the market has been favored
postcommunist societies
by the existence of earlier capitalist traditions
(as present, for example, in the Czech Republic),
as well as where the initial economic reform was
of the radical, “shock therapy” variety, while gradual or evolutionary steps have proven less effective. But everywhere it was slowed down by the
continuing presence of inefficient large state
sectors, resistance to privatization, an overgrown
agricultural sector, as well as unresolved issues of
restitution of private property nationalized under
the communist regime. In the cultural area, the
readiness to embrace the western way of life
depends on the strength of earlier pro-western
orientations (higher, for example, in the countries
existing formerly in the orbit of the Habsburg
Empire, with a dominant Catholicism, than in
those which were in the orbit of the Ottoman
Empire and the Orthodox Church). But everywhere there are mental and value deficiencies
covered by the concept of civilizational incompetence: in particular, attitudes not adapted to
the new conditions of democracy and capitalism,
such as collectivism, egalitarianism, avoidance of
responsibility, aversion to risk, claims to social
security and welfare directed towards the state,
system-blame for personal failures, and indifference to the public good. In the area of civil society,
its suppression under Communism, and the flight
of citizens to the private sphere of the family,
friends, and “connections,” results in the persistent opposition between “us” and “them” and a
reluctance to engage in public participation and
in voluntary associational activism.
Nevertheless the process of development and
consolidation of democracy, capitalism, and free
culture proceeds consistently, and has already led
to the rebuilding of key institutional structures,
to new cultural and mental orientations and to
changes in the everyday life of postcommunist
societies. A significant role has been played in
this process of shedding of the legacies of the
communist past by the incorporation of leading
countries of the region into supranational economic and political organizations of the western
world: the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD), the World Bank,
and most significantly NATO (with Poland, Hungary, and the Czech Republic joining first, in 1999,
and Bulgaria, Estonia, Latvia, Lithuania, Romania,
Slovakia, and Slovenia invited in 2004), and the
European Union (with the accession of Poland,
Hungary, the Czech Republic, Slovakia, Slovenia,
Estonia, Lithuania, and Latvia in 2004).
In sociology the complex social changes occurring in postcommunist societies have become the
455
posthistoire
postfeminism
subject of various theoretical accounts. They
describe the process under the headings of transition, transformation, modernization, and traumatic sequence. The idea of transition assumes
that we witness the simple replacement of one
regime by another, and that by imitating western
institutions the postcommunist societies will
quickly reshape themselves in the likeness of
leading societies of the West (namely the United
States and western Europe, and westernized countries such as Japan, and so forth). The idea of
transformation sees the process as a more complex, path-dependent, and open-ended construction of a new form of society, partly patterned
on the West, but also revealing specific historical
experiences within the region. The idea of modernization focuses on the continuation and extension of the incomplete, “fake modernization”
under Communism – limited to industrialization,
urbanization, and educational emancipation –
into the political and cultural domain, as well as
on the reemergence of civil society. The idea of
traumatic sequence emphasizes the negative, unintended side-effects of the process: a certain disorientation and anomie in the domain of values,
adverse effects of reforms (for example unemployment, raised levels of crime, and impoverishment
of considerable segments of the population), and
the resulting post-traumatic moods of the people
(distrust, apathy, and nostalgia for the past). The
key process is conceived as a long-term effort to
cope with such traumas, by mobilizing entrepreneurial energies, educational aspirations, and citizens’ activism. And the fulfillment of the ultimate
promise of success is entrusted to the turnover of
generations, where young people are already
immune from communist legacies.
PIOTR SZTOMPKA
postfeminism
This has two meanings. First, it is used as a comment on what some writers see as the disappearance of feminism in the West, and, second, it can
be used as a description of societies that have
changed various social practices as a result of
what is known as the “second wave” of feminism
in the 1970s. In the first case, the term postfeminism can be interpreted as a fervent hope by some
critics of feminism that this social movement,
which they find to be profoundly disturbing, has
lost its impact and support and that feminism no
longer exists as a viable movement. Right-wing
critics of feminism have been quick to assume,
report, and state the “death” of feminism
while hailing a return to the halcyon days of
456
more traditional relationships of gender. The evidence of the demise of feminism is usually anecdotal information about women choosing to
become full-time mothers; other arguments (for
example, that the current arrangements of the
labor market are rarely supportive of parents)
are seldom part of the same discussion. Tabloid
newspapers throughout the West have played a
considerable part in the popularization of the
idea that feminism is dead and that it was only
ever a minority social movement, associated with
lesbian sexuality.
The second use of the term postfeminism recognizes the impact of feminism on the social world
(for example, the calculation of unpaid work in
the household as part of the Gross National Product, the greater equalization of the law in relation
to women and men), but tacitly assumes that the
work of feminism has been done. A “postfeminist”
society is thus one that has put into place equal
rights legislation, recognized disparities in social
power between women and men, and questioned
practices that were related to the social inferiority
of women. For many feminists, the term postfeminism has been created out of the backlash
against feminism from the political right and the
rise, most significantly in the United States, of a
religious right which has increasingly challenged
the liberalization of laws relating to reproduction
that were achieved by feminists in the 1970s.
Postfeminism can thus be read as a construct of
those social groups that were always opposed to
feminism.
MARY EVANS
posthistoire
A theorem associated with postmodernism and
notions of the end of history, posthistoire refers to
the analysis of the social beyond the horizon of
the Enlightenment self-understanding of modernity. The term was first made popular by Lutz
Niethammer in his Posthistoire Has History Come to
an End? (1989 [trans. 1992]). Often interpreted as
spelling the collapse of modernity, its analysis
has played a central role in sociological debates
about the exhaustion of ideas stemming from the
European Enlightenment.
Posthistoire has taken two key sociological forms.
Arnold Gehlen argued that, in an age of intensive
modernization, there is an uncoupling of rationality on the one side and the cultural self-understanding of modernity on the other. For Gehlen,
posthistoire means the guiding assumptions of
the Enlightenment are dead; only their consequences live on, and unpredictably so. From
this perspective, processes of modernization have
posthumanism
postindustrial society
become unhinged from any internal connection
with the conceptual horizons of western rationalism in which the project of modernity was
founded.
The idea of posthistoire also arises in sociology as
a result of the postmodern turn, but in this reading it is both society and culture that are deconstructed. In postmodern sociology, the end of
cultural modernity spells a similar eclipse of advanced modernization. In posthistoire, society is directionless, producing itself only in the fleeting
transparency of pluralistic discourses.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
posthumanism
Associated with postmodernism and poststructuralism, posthumanism is a form of postmodern
philosophy predicated on the notion that the
human species is self-limiting. Posthumanists
seek to promote a radical political agenda, pushing beyond the ideas and images from the European Enlightenment on the “natural” constraints
of the body and towards alternative utopias promoting artificial intelligence, nanotechnology,
cyber technologies, and biomachines. In this sociology beyond humanism, in which society is said to
have entered a post-Darwinian era, the political
aim is to eradicate distinctions between humans
and machines.
The historical emergence of posthumanism is
closely connected with the philosophy of Friedrich
Nietzsche (1844–1900) and his unearthing of an
imminent process of continual self-overcoming,
such that an erasure of the “subject of man” was
the theoretical premise from which the Overman
(Ubermensch) might be conceptualized. Yet whereas
Nietzsche’s analysis of evolution – human and
nonhuman – was concerned with the spontaneous growth of productive desire, posthumanists
focus on the mutations of machine intensities,
biomachine becomings, bodily transpositions.
Specifically in terms of sociological analysis, there
is an emphasis on radicalizing human forms
through the use of technological and other means.
Developments in artificial life, particularly neural
networks and biomorphs, promise a nonlinear
conceptualization of evolutionary life; so, too,
computer models and digital technologies offer
a revaluation of the fundamental sociological
concepts through which self-organization and
sociality are constituted.
These arguments advanced by posthumanists
suggest that sociology needs to embrace interdisciplinarity in order to engage critically the dynamism of configurations of nature, sociality, and
technology. In Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (1991), Donna J. Haraway noted
that human and nonhuman “actants” are mixed
in “material–semiotic entities”; these are biotech
knowledge objects, such as the database, the chip,
the neural net, the ecosystem. Haraway suggests
that, from this perspective, complex socialities can
be analyzed otherwise, from the micro-physical to
the macro-physical.
A persistent theme in posthumanism is that
social memories and socialities are multiple.
Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari argue in A Thousand Plateaus (1980 [trans. 1987]) in favor of molecular memories, of open, complex systems,
where mutant “lines of flight” initiate forms of
becoming that call into play novel forms of communication between heterogeneous phenomena.
Refiguring established epistemologies and ontologies in terms of the posthuman, some argue –
like Hans Moravec in Robot. Mere Machine to Transcendent Mind (1998) – that biotechnologies can
expand human horizons indefinitely, refiguring
our understanding of speed, vision, strength, and
intelligence. However, there are other posthumanists who caution against the more extreme
flights of utopian vision concerning the transhuman condition. Keith Ansell Pearson argues in
Viroid Life (1997) against the biotechnological
vitalism of cybergurus. While the posthuman condition involves sociology in thinking beyond the
“beyond,” as Pearson argues, the intellectual task
concerns, above all, mapping creative intelligences
and productive becomings.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
postindustrial society
This argument is that, following a period of
almost two centuries of industrialization, some
societies of the advanced industrial world have
undergone further changes which require that
we now speak of “postindustrial societies.” The
most important exponent of this view is the
American sociologist Daniel Bell, though it has
also been echoed by several European sociologists
such as Alain Touraine. According to these
thinkers, postindustrial societies are characterized by the following features: economically, a
move from a goods-producing to a service economy; occupationally, the decline of the manual
working class and the rise of a professional, managerial, and technical class; culturally, the growing importance of universities and other research
institutions, to some extent replacing the business
enterprise as the source of innovation and growth;
in politics and decision- making, the creation of a
457
postindustrial society
new “intellectual technology” involving computer-simulations, game theory, scientific forecasting, and other types of theoretical systems
that increasingly displace the deliberations of
“amateur” politicians. Overarching all this, what
Bells calls the “axial principle” of the new society,
is “the centrality of theoretical knowledge” as the
source of innovation and policy formation for society as a whole. In later writings, moved by the
rapid developments in computers and communications technology, and the links between them,
Bell has increasingly come to see postindustrial
societies as information societies. Others, such as
Peter Drucker (1909–2005), for similar reasons
have spoken of “the knowledge society,” for
example in his Post-capitalist Society (1993), while
Zbigniew Brzezinski (1929– ) writes of “the technetronic society” in his Between Two Ages (1970). In all
these accounts, central features are the emergence
of a new type of worker, the “knowledge worker,”
the significance to the economy and society as a
whole of the new information technology, and the
increasing proportion of Gross National Product
that is devoted to research and development.
The United States, western Europe, and Japan
are the countries that by common consent have
advanced farthest in the direction of postindustrialism. But east European theorists, putting a
Marxist slant on it, have also hailed the advent
of the “scientific–technological revolution” in
their region, incorporating many of the central
changes identified by Bell and others. It is seen
as heralding a new mode of production in industrial societies, whether socialist or capitalist. Certainly there is no doubt that the majority of
workers – somewhere between two-thirds and
three-quarters in most cases – in all industrial
societies are now service workers; nor that between 30 and 50 percent of the tertiary education
age cohort now goes on to some form of higher
education. At this most basic level no-one can deny
that there have been fundamental changes in industrial society, leading, for instance, to a significant decline in the power of trade unions and
forcing traditional socialist parties to modify their
programs away from an exclusive focus on the
proletariat. Many of these changes have been discussed under the heading of embourgeoisement.
The question is whether these changes add up,
as Bell and others claim, to a new principle of
society. Here there can be serious doubts. The
driving forces of the postindustrial society appear
to be much as they were in industrial society:
capital accumulation, technical innovation, and
rationalization. Neither Karl Marx nor Max Weber
458
postmodern theory
would have been much surprised at the new developments, which were indeed implicit in their
KRISHAN KUMAR
theories of industrial society.
postmodern theory
As the very prefix post- indicates, postmodern
theory reflects uncertainty as to the direction of
change and critical skepticism about the grand
narratives of modernization, including ideological
constructs of socialism, liberalism, conservatism,
and welfarism. The term refers both to a postmodern theorizing, that is a specific form of analysis
and explanation of contemporary society, and to
the theoretical accounts of postmodern understood as either a new socio-cultural configuration
(postmodernity) or a new trend in social change
(postmodernization). The former usage (postmodern theorizing) has been associated with such
thinkers as Michel Foucault and Jean-François Lyotard who analyze the discursive and narrative
foundations of knowledge (language games). This
predisposes them towards cultural criticism and
philosophical reflections that engender postmodern sensitivity to language–power relations. The
latter usage (theory of postmodernity or postmodernization) is associated with writings of such
thinkers as Fredric Jameson, Zygmunt Bauman,
and David Harvey, who analyze postmodernism
as a new configuration, and Jean Baudrillard,
Stephen Crook, Jan Pakulski, and Malcolm Waters
in Postmodernization (1992), who study postmodernization as an ongoing process and directional
trend.
Postmodernism typically refers to changes in
cultural representations, mentalities, feelings,
and lived experience. While the idea of postmodernism has been gaining currency since the 1970s
in relation to the visual arts and architecture, its
origins reach back to the second decade of the
twentieth century, when radical artistic avantgarde movements, such as Dada, attempted to
link art back to life through the use of images
drawn from popular culture and found objects,
such as the hatstands of Marcel Duchamp (1887–
1968). It has been argued that this makes Dada an
early forerunner of postmodernism. However, the
Dada avant-gardism is usually seen as a failure in
the sense of its confinement to the isolated modernist establishment. By the 1950s, modernist art
started to lose its isolation and radical edge, becoming sanitized, popularized, commercialized,
and internationalized – a step in a postmodern
direction. The Pop Art of the 1960s has also
been seen as a forerunner of postmodernism. Pop
used images from popular culture, hyperrealism,
postmodern theory
collages, jokes, and parodies (for example Soft
Toilet). Recent decades have seen a bewildering
variety of postmodern styles: a resurgence of figurative work, realism and hyperrealism, historicism, and a deliberate superficiality that rejects
the psychological depth of modernism.
Postmodern architecture, like postmodern art,
rejects the elitist and avant-garde orientation of
modernism. It is programmatically popular, immediately attractive to the eye, diverse, and eclectic. The term has been applied to decorative
designs, neo-classicism, neo-vernacular, parody,
and pastiche. These styles are united in their
double coding of modernist techniques and materials, and contain stylistic references to something
else. In one view, postmodernist architecture
and art are welcomed as popular, accessible,
and playful. In another view, they are deplored
because they become the decorative façade of contemporary niche-marketed consumerism.
While there seems to be a consensus on what
constitutes postmodernism in art, there is no
agreement about contemporary notions of social
postmodernity. Some (like Mike Featherstone) contrast the postmodern epoch with the modern era;
postmodernity implies a break with and shift
away from the organizing principles of modern
society. Others such as Jameson in Postmodernism
or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (1991) see it as
a continuation of modern trends; postmodernism
constitutes just the cultural reflection of modern
capitalism, an expression of American domination, and a lifestyle of the “yuppies.” Jean Baudrillard, in turn, sees social postmodernity as a
correlate of expanding mass media and communications and mass consumption, and as a new era
brought by the proliferation of mediated communication, symbolic consumption, and the compression of time and space. This results in a
proliferation of self-referential signs, intensified
consumption of signs (for example brands), and
the emergence of social order based on symbolic
consumption.
There are differences in the view of how widespread the postmodern features are and how advanced the postmodern trends are. Bauman and
Jameson see the advanced societies as already
postmodern. By contrast, Crook and his colleagues
analyze postmodernization as an ongoing – and
by no means even or complete – social process.
Postmodern trends include social fragmentation,
differentiation, and the increasingly ephemeral
nature of social formations; flexible specialization; progressing cultural pluralism, depthlessness, commercialization, and populism; widening
postmodernism
eclecticism and syncretism of styles; and generational libertarian shifts in values and sensitivities. Critical culturalists, such as Ronald
Inglehart, focus on changes in values and the
rise of diverse identity politics. Others, like
Lyotard and Baudrillard, highlight the decline of
ideological meta-narratives and the return to the
local and vernacular, and the ascendancy of
autonomous but empty symbols or simulacra.
For Baudrillard, the world is saturated by sounds
and images from mass media, eroding the distinction between representation and (social) reality
and producing the “end of the social.”
Postmodernization typically means the processes
that accelerate and reverse modern trends. One can
see the accounts of postmodernization as ranging
from less radical, pointing to some continuities, to
more radical, suggesting discontinuities. Jameson
and Harvey, for example, analyze postmodernization as involving continuities: a gradual commodification of culture, collapse of styles and high/low
cultural tastes, populism of standards, fragmentation of social classes, and political realignments
as reflected in the proliferation of ephemeral
movements. Crook, Pakulski, and Waters (1992)
see postmodern trends in the “reversal through
acceleration” of the key processes of modernization: commodification to hypercommodification,
social differentiation to hyper-differentiation, and
rationalization to hyper-rationalization. They identify postmodern trends in the domains of culture
and identity, the role of the state, politics, work
and production, and weakening class relations.
Hypercommodification extends market relations
to formerly non-commodified regions (for example intellectual property, and televangelism).
Hyperdifferentiation breaks up institutions into
fragments that combine in an unpredictable
manner (for instance syncretic lifestyles, multimedia, transdisciplinary science). Hyperrationalization splits off inaccessible “expert cultures,”
produces “irrational” social responses and pluralizes rationalities (for example fundamentalism
and new age cults). On this view, postmodernization involves also the blurring of the boundaries
between social, cultural, and political domains.
For Crook and his colleagues this means that flows
of social action (as in new social movements) are
no longer contained in social institutions.
JAN PAKULSKI
postmodernism
Associated with postindustrial society and poststructuralism, postmodernism arises as a consequence of advanced modernization, in particular
459
postmodernism
the fragmentation of the West’s institutionalization of unilinear history and systems of meaning.
A conception of history as having a single direction, the endeavor to develop a rational program
of collective emancipation, the grounding of all
human experience and representation in reason:
these are some of the key criteria of modernity. Yet
in our own time, paradoxically, it is precisely such
modernist aims for self-mastery and control that
fall victim to the very social processes they seek to
colonize. Recent decades have powerfully shown
that the ethos of modernity has come to haunt us.
Global risks, threats, and pandemics, from AIDS to
terrorism, have served to highlight the gross limitations of modernist perspectives, generating in
turn the emergence of new social and political
agendas.
Postmodernism confounds identity, theory, and
politics in a scandalous way, with its leveling of
hierarchies, its dislocating subversion of ideological closure, its interpretative polyvalence and
its self-reflexive pluralism. In this sense, postmodernism refers to certain currents of cultural and
critical discourse which seek to deconstruct the
ideological affinities of totalizing thought, the operations of power, the legitimating functions of
knowledge and truth, and the discursive practices
of self-constitution.
A growing appreciation of the limits of rationality, various postmodernists have argued, has led
to the abandonment of the epistemological illusions of emancipatory declarations made in the
name of freedom, truth, equality, liberty, and so
on. As the pioneering postmodern analyst JeanFrançois Lyotard put this in The Postmodern Condition (1979 [trans. 1984]), postmodernism is defined
as an “incredulity toward metanarratives.” The
grand narratives that unified and structured western science and philosophy, grounding truth and
meaning in the presumption of a universal subject and a predetermined goal of emancipation,
no longer appear convincing or even plausible.
Instead, in the anti-totalizing, postmodern perspective, knowledge is constructed, not discovered;
it is contextual, not foundational.
Social transformations are understood to be of
central importance in this erosion of the grand
narratives of the modern era. Globalization and
especially the proliferation of new information
technologies introduce a qualitative transformation in the experience of space and time, the
result of which is a dramatic acceleration in the
turmoil and flux of personal and cultural life. The
overall effect, as Jean Baudrillard argues, is an
implosion of all boundaries, an erasure of the
460
postmodernity
distinctions of high and low culture, of appearance and reality, of past and present. Postmodernity is thus inherently decentered and dispersed:
everything is of the same value, which means
that nothing much counts in terms of meaning,
distinction, hierarchy.
There are two major criticisms of postmodernism, one sympathetic, one critical. The sympathetic argument is that sociology should remain
critical of the postmodern turn by attempting to
develop a sociology of postmodernism, rather
than succumbing to a postmodern sociology.
This case has been vigorously argued by Zygmunt
Bauman. The second response within sociology
has been to reject the view that postmodernism
spells the end of modernity.
ANTHONY ELLIOTT
postmodernity
The idea of postmodernity has until recently been
the focus of a contested debate amongst intellectuals. Those seeking to defend the concept (it has
many detractors) use it as a way to imply a change
in modern social conditions and a new way of
relating to modernity. The changes in modern
social conditions usually include the development
of new technologies, the decline in the power of
tradition, the erosion of a strong version of secularism, globalization, the role of culture and communications, and the emergence of ecological
issues and of other world regions challenging
Euro-American modernities. New ways of relating
to modern times have led to an enhanced questioning of ideas of progress and a reflection upon
the limits of reason.
These arguments and others have begun to
emerge in a political and intellectual context
that has begun to debate the limits of specifically
western modernity. A growing realization that
there are other non-western civilizations and the
idea that Euro-American forms of development
have a number of negative side-effects, making
them unsuitable for universal application, have
aided thinking on these questions. In addition,
the cultural turn in sociology has led to an increasing recognition of both the complexity and
cultural plurality of modern societies. Zygmunt
Bauman has arguably gone the farthest in pressing the claim that the condition of postmodernity
is more than just changing social conditions. Postmodernity articulates a particular crisis for intellectuals who have suffered a period of relative
displacement.
First, intellectuals are unable to offer authoritative solutions to questions of truth, the normative
claims of justice, and taste. Their position of
poststructuralism
influence in modern society then can be said to be
in decline. In this respect, Bauman suggests that
they become interpreters of knowledge rather
than legislators of new social systems. Second,
the recognition of the inevitably pluralistic features of modern life disrupts universal claims
and introduces questions of relativism into the
production of knowledge. Finally, modern social
conditions have also changed, introducing the development of a society based upon consumption
rather than production. This means that the
system now requires the pleasurable consumption
of commodities rather than the deferral of gratification and thrift. Political domination is no longer
achieved through the legitimation of social values
as much as through a combination of seduction
and repression. The requirement that we recall
our unconditional responsibility towards the
other without trying to reinvent the existential
security of rules and expert systems takes us to
the heart of postmodernity. In this respect, processes of globalization and individualization offer
new opportunities for responsible political engagement beyond the now permeable walls of
the nation-state.
Many intellectuals have sharply disagreed with
these and similar ideas. They have suggested that
ideas of postmodernity signify not so much a new
social order, but a form of intellectual defeatism.
The failure of intellectuals to offer up new
blueprints for alternative social orders exhibits a
lack of social responsibility. The global triumph of
capitalism, new imperialist wars, the continuation of nationalist violence, and a planet that is
being pushed beyond its ecological limits are
reason enough to reject the label of postmodernism. Rejecting any notion of new times, many
point to both the continuation of a largely capitalist-driven modernity and the need to develop
solutions to social problems.
NICK STEVENSON
poststructuralism
This is concerned with the relations between
human beings, the world, and the process of
making and reproducing meanings (see Catherine
Belsey, Poststructuralism. A Very Short Introduction,
2002). There are at least two historical narratives
which relate to this definition, offering different
routes leading to the intellectual position which
became dominant in France in the last quarter of
the twentieth century and, by extension, globally
significant through the translations into English
of the work, in particular, of Louis Althusser,
Roland Barthes, Jean Baudrillard, Pierre Bourdieu,
Jacques Derrida (1930–2004), Michel Foucault, Julia
poststructuralism
Kristeva, and Jean-François Lyotard. One route
tends to locate poststructuralism in the context
of language and literature, whereas the other
associates it with philosophy and the social
sciences.
The first account takes the work of Ferdinand de
Saussure in linguistics as the main starting-point.
In analyzing “signs,” Saussure distinguished between the “signifier,” which is the sound or
appearance of words being deployed, and the
“signified,” which is their meaning. Linguistic
signs are arbitrary. Particular combinations of
signifiers and signifieds are arbitrary entities.
There is no natural correspondence between signifiers and what they signify (the signified). To
analyze language, one has to analyze the relations
between signs rather than the relation between
those signs and any prior reality which they might
be thought, fixedly, to represent. Language is not
a nomenclature but a relational system of signs.
But Saussure also distinguished between “langue”
and “parole,” between the systemic structure of
language and contingent speech-acts. It was his
contention that the primary purpose of linguistic
science was to understand the structure of the
non-contingent system of non-referential signs.
In this account of the origins of poststructuralism,
the work of Barthes was critical in following
Saussure’s notion of signification while rejecting
his attempt to generate a universal analysis of
signs. At the beginning of his S/Z (1970 [trans.
1975]), Barthes has commented that there are
said to be Buddhists whose ascetic discipline enables them to perceive a whole landscape within a
single bean. He asserted that the first analysts of
narratives worked on this premise, attempting
what is ultimately undesirable because the text
as a result loses its distinctiveness and difference.
Barthes’s science of signs, semiology, was poststructuralist in emphasizing “difference” rather
than structural uniformity, but for a poststructuralist social scientist like Bourdieu, Barthes persisted in operating with the fundamentally
structuralist assumption that an a-priori, systemic
“langue” regulates speech practice. Bourdieu
wanted to de-regulate “langue” as well as liberate
signs from referential constraint. The second account of the development of poststructuralism
incorporates the influence of Edmund Husserl’s
phenomenology and the ontology of Martin
Heidegger (1889–1976). These influences from
philosophy pushed the social sciences towards a
recognition of the primacy of agency, towards the
recognition of difference at the level of signifying
actions rather than at the level of objectivized
461
poverty
signs. There is a close relationship between the
development of poststructuralism and postmodernism. One could say provocatively that
postmodernism exposed the extent to which poststructuralism remained parasitic on structuralist
assumptions.
DEREK ROBBINS
poverty
This concept describes an empirical reality, both
globally and in individual societies, but the meaning of which is contested. What constitutes poverty depends on how it is defined and measured.
The main debates around definition concern the
role of material resources, in particular income,
and whether poverty should be understood in absolute or relative terms. The nature of the debates
differs according to context, in particular that of
the global South or North.
Disagreements about the role of income revolve
around a number of issues. One concerns the relative importance of income versus living standards,
which may also reflect factors such as access to
services and quality of the local environment. Another raises wider questions about the significance of nonmaterial aspects of poverty that are
often raised by people in poverty in both the
North and the South. These include disrespectful
treatment, loss of dignity, lack of voice, and of
power. With regard to nonmaterial aspects, it is
possible to resolve any disagreement by making a
distinction between the (narrower) definition and
(broader) conceptualization of poverty. The latter
is better able to embrace the relational aspects of
poverty while the former focuses on poverty as a
material condition.
The other key definitional debate has revolved
around whether poverty should be understood in
absolute or relative terms. Definitions deployed in
the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
by Charles Booth (1840–1916) and Seebohm Rowntree (1871–1954), the pioneers of modern poverty
research, were supposedly absolute in the sense
that poverty was said to be understood as lack of
sufficient money to meet basic physical needs to
subsist and survive. The alternative, relative definition was pioneered by Peter Townsend. In his
major study Poverty in the United Kingdom (1979),
he defined poverty in terms of exclusion from
the living conditions, and inability to participate
in the activities, taken for granted by the wider
society because of lack of material resources. Central to his approach was the concept of relative
deprivation, but understood as an objective condition rather than a subjective feeling as in W. G.
Runciman’s formulation.
462
poverty
In judging whether relative poverty exists, comparison is made with others living in the same
society at the same point in history. This means
that historical and global North/South comparisons are misplaced. Such a comparison also highlights any inequality of resources between groups
in a society, although relative poverty and inequality are not synonymous. The latter does not
necessarily imply the inability of some members
to participate fully in society because of lack of
material resources. A relative definition also involves a particular reading of human needs not
merely as physical but as socially and culturally
constituted. One implication of an understanding
of even the most basic physiological needs as socially conditioned is that the conventional notion
of absolute poverty falls apart. Indeed, contemporary scholarship questions the conventional
wisdom that Rowntree promulgated a definition
of poverty, in terms of subsistence, that was
absolute.
There have also been attempts to develop a
framework that treats absolute and relative as
complementary rather than competing formulations, which can be applied to both North and
South. The first was by Amartya Sen (1933– ). He
identified an absolutist core to poverty, the most
obvious manifestation of which is starvation and
malnutrition. He suggested that what one is able
to do or be (capabilities) is a question of universal
absolutes, whereas the goods (or commodities)
needed to translate this ability into actual being
or doing (functionings) takes us into the sphere of
relativities because commodities vary according
to cultural and historical context. A heated debate
with Townsend ensued in the early 1980s, which
was confused because of a failure to clarify different interpretations of absolute and relative. More
recently, Townsend and colleagues have promulgated a two-part definition of poverty – absolute
and overall – which emerged from the 1995
United Nations (UN) Copenhagen summit. This, it
is argued, can be applied to both industrialized
and poorer countries.
The capabilities approach has been developed
by Sen and Martha Nussbaum (1947– ) in numerous books and papers, most recently, Development
as Freedom, 1999. Their approach has been particularly influential in development circles, providing
the framework for the annual UN Development
Program Human Development Report. The essence of
Sen’s thesis is that what matters is not income
or living standards as such but the kind of life
that a person is able to lead (functionings) and
the choices and opportunities open to people in
poverty
leading their lives (capabilities). Money, Sen
argues, is just a means to an end and the goods
and services (commodities) it buys are simply particular ways of achieving functionings. Thus, poverty should be defined in terms of failure to
achieve minimally acceptable capabilities.
In order to identify and count those defined as
poor, measures are needed. These too generate
controversy, involving choice of indicators and
the standard, often called the poverty line, against
which indicators are assessed. Questions include
whether poverty should be measured in terms
of income, living standards / consumption, or
expenditure; increasingly the view is that a combination of approaches is needed to improve
the accuracy of measures. Official measures tend
to use income levels to establish a poverty line.
Examples are 60 percent of median national income, as used within the European Union, and the
World Bank’s (much-criticized) $1, $2, or $4 a day.
In addition to headcount measures, poverty-gap
measures have been devised to gauge the extent
to which people fall below the poverty line,
although these are used less frequently. A focus
on the numbers below the poverty line or on
the poverty gap can point to different policy
priorities.
This is one of the criticisms made by those who
query the very construction of poverty lines. At
the heart of such criticisms is the question as to
whether there exists a clear threshold which
neatly divides the poor from the nonpoor or
whether the relationship between the two is
better understood as a continuum, with gradations among both groups. The idea of a simple
dichotomy between poor and nonpoor has also
been questioned in the light of the growing use
of longitudinal datasets to measure the dynamics
of poverty. These show considerable movement in
and out of poverty (although not usually very far),
which is obscured by traditional snapshot measures. The length of time in poverty also affects the
degree of deprivation of necessities experienced.
An alternative approach to drawing a poverty
line is based on estimates of the income levels at
which people are unable to afford items specified
as essentials by either experts or the population at
large. Typically, budget standards are calculated,
based on the cost of a basket of goods and services.
In the United Kingdom, a number of poverty studies have used a list of necessities agreed by a
survey of the general population. Yet another
device is to ask a sample of the population directly
a question aimed at gauging what they think the
poverty line should be for their household.
poverty
Although poverty estimates generally refer to
individuals, they are typically based on measures
of combined household/family resources. This is
problematic where resources are not shared fairly
within households, as research indicates can be
the case. The result can be hidden poverty experienced primarily by women. It is one example of
the ways in which poverty is gendered, although
this was largely ignored prior to the intervention
of feminist scholars. Even on conventional measures, women are more likely than men to be in
poverty. They also tend to take the main responsibility for managing poverty and often go without
to protect other family members, especially children, from its full impact. The stress involved can
damage both physical and mental health.
Poverty is also racialized in terms of its incidence,
racialized stereotyping, and the effects of discrimination and racism. This dimension is most marked
in the United States where race and ethnicity
and urban segregation figure prominently in the
sociological poverty literature. Segregation is one
aspect of the geography of poverty, which is a
manifestation of wider spatial inequalities.
Explanations of poverty can broadly be understood as behavioral or structural. Behavior-based
explanations attribute poverty to the values, attitudes, and behavior of the poor. An example is
Charles Murray’s writings on the underclass (including The Emerging British Underclass, 1990). In the
United States, the earlier notion of a culture of
poverty drew attention to the ways in which a
subculture, marked by fatalism, an inability to
defer gratification, and pathological behavior, was
passed down through the generations. Although
Oscar Lewis, who coined the term in the 1960s,
emphasized that the culture of poverty represented
an adaptation to rather than cause of poverty, it
was used to argue with the latter meaning by
others who blamed the poor for their poverty, as
both supporters and critics of Lewis have observed.
A related notion in the United Kingdom, in the
1970s, was that of the cycle of deprivation.
In The Other America (1967), a pivotal intervention
in the United States, Michael Harrington linked
the culture of poverty to a structural analysis.
Structural explanations of poverty focus on economic, social, and political structures and processes – from the global to the local/familial.
Examples are unemployment, low pay, and
women’s position in the family. Another perspective is institutional, which points to the failure of
government policies. For example, the term poverty trap was coined in Britain to highlight the
way in which means-tested benefits can trap the
463
poverty line
working poor: the interaction of the withdrawal of
means-tested supplements with taxation and insurance contributions meant that a pay rise could
leave a low-paid worker worse off. Although the
system has since been reformed to avoid this extreme situation, large numbers of lower-paid
workers can still lose a significant proportion of
a pay increase because of the poverty trap. An
example of an explanation that combines the behavioral and institutional is that which locates
the cause of poverty in a dependency culture
said to be created by welfare benefits.
Recently, some poverty analysts who subscribe
to a structural explanation have married this approach with a sociological account of agency in
order to understand better the ways in which
people cope with poverty. One formulation, taken
from the development literature, is of people
deploying a range of resources (personal, social,
cultural, and material) to compose their livelihoods. Structure and agency also combine in
some sociological accounts of the concept of social
exclusion, which emphasize the agency of the
more powerful in excluding the less powerful.
Labels such as “socially excluded,” “poor,” and
“underclass” are examples of how the more powerful name those without power. They are not labels
with which those experiencing poverty necessarily
want to identify. Organizations of people in poverty are, however, developing alternative discourses that have also been promulgated by some
more powerful bodies such as the United Nations.
This is a discourse of human rights, citizenship,
voice, and power. Two key principles underpin
the conceptualization of poverty in terms of
human rights and citizenship: recognition of the
dignity of all humans and the interdependence of
civil, political, social, and cultural rights. In addition, this perspective emphasizes participation in
society and the polity and the right to be heard in
decisionmaking. In both North and South, people
in poverty identify lack of voice and associated
powerlessness as critical to understanding their
situation. Calls for their voices to be heard in policymaking and campaigning are becoming more
emphatic. In the South and, to a lesser extent, the
North, the case is being made for participatory
research that involves people in poverty as experts
in their own lives. The argument is that sociological accounts will provide a better understanding of poverty if they reflect the analyses of those
with experience of poverty.
RUTH LISTER
poverty line
– see poverty.
464
power
poverty trap
– see poverty.
power
In a discipline such as sociology, notorious for the
difficulty it experiences in establishing widely and
durably agreed definitions of its concepts, that of
power (at any rate social power, which is our only
concern here) stands out as one whose definition
is particularly contentious and unstable. This in
spite (or perhaps on account) of the fact that,
however understood, this concept signals a particularly significant social phenomenon, arguably
entitled to a central position in the discipline’s
vocabulary and discourse.
The most significant of the controversies taking
place among sociologists and political scientists
in the twentieth century around the concept-ofpower concern, expressly or otherwise, concerns
the definition of power (Macht) offered at the beginning of the century by Max Weber. In Economy
and Society (1922 [trans. 1968]), that definition characterizes power as “the chance of a man or a group
of men to realize their own will in a communal
action even against the resistance of others who
are participating in the action.”
In fact, some expressed or implied elements of
this definition were not widely considered as controversial. In particular, it was generally agreed
that one should think of (social) power not as a
substance but as a relationship – a point implied
in Weber’s reference to both parties’ “participation” in “communal action.” In other terms,
power is not something to be held, so to speak,
in one’s hand or pocket, but as something
obtaining between two parties, such that A may
hold it vis-à-vis B, but not vis-à-vis C.
Weber’s expression “chance” entails two further
plausible, closely related characteristics of power.
First, power refers to a probability, not so to speak
to a “dead cert,” to the complete assurance of a
given party’s success. Second, power is always potential because it refers not so much to the doing
of something (to the actual “production of
effects,” proposed by others as an alternative definition of power) but to the capacity of doing
something, of producing effects if and when one
chooses.
In other words, power does not need to be exercised (by overcoming opposition or otherwise) in
order to exist. Paradoxically, the exercise of power
may consume it and/or expose it, when actually
brought to bear, to the risk of being found
wanting, of failing to do its number as it were.
Rather, power is at its most powerful when those
power
subject to it practice their subjection to it without
its being actually exercised, when it operates
through the power subjects’ memory of past exercises of it or their imagination of future ones,
when it needs to be at most symbolically represented rather than actually put into action. (One
may connect to this intuition a number of enlightening discourses by political scientists, historians,
and sociologists, on the symbolism of power – and
of related phenomena.)
Other aspects of Weber’s definition became controversial in a wide ranging post-World War II
discussion of the power concept, involving both
political scientists – for instance Robert Dahl,
Modern Political Analysis (1963) – and sociologists
such as Steven Lukes in Power: A Radical View
(1974) and Dennis Wrong in Power: Its Forms, Bases,
and Uses (1979). In particular, Weber’s reference to
the “will” of the party in power became an issue. It
was questioned whether that reference implied
intentionality. Does the existence of a power relationship depend on the powerful party’s awareness of its own preference for a given, existent,
or future state of things and its conscious commitment to obtaining it? Does it depend on its ability
to superimpose its own over the other party’s will?
Is the overcoming or the potential overcoming of
actual or virtual resistance an essential component of the relationship? What of situations where
the asymmetry between the parties is so great that
the inferior party is not even aware of having
interests contrary to those of the superior party,
but routinely cooperates in the attainment of the
latter, or at any rate does not seek to hinder that
attainment? Is not the superior party’s ability to
keep certain present or future states of things
from becoming an issue between itself and the
other party – its ability to control the agenda, it
was said – a particularly privileged condition?
Some contributors to the debate, while assuming that Weber’s conceptual construct was essentially acceptable – whatever the qualifications
and modifications to it suggested by the answers to
some questions we have mentioned – labored to
establish its boundaries by comparing and contrasting it with cognate concepts, such as authority
(or domination), influence, force, or manipulation.
In the second half of the twentieth century the
concept of power, with reference to the Weberian
definition or otherwise, was also the object of
methodological arguments concerning the possibility of grounding it empirically. The discussion
involved both sociologists and political scientists,
especially those associated with the behaviorist
approach, itself much inspired by sociology. It
power
often concerned, besides the power concept itself
and its elaboration in the notion of “power structure,” the analysis of elites. Attempts to put such
concepts to use in empirical research, through
varying methodological approaches, were conducted both at the local level – for instance by
Floyd Hunter, Community Power Structure: A Study
of Decision Makers (1953), and Robert Dahl, Who
Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City
(1961) – and at the national level – for example
by C. Wright Mills, The Power Elite (1956). This led to
interesting developments, for instance the study
of “interlocking directorates,” carried out with
reference to numerous corporations or other economic units, such as banks and firms, or the study
of decisionmaking within political bodies.
Some scholars went further in the attempt to
operationalize the power concept and indeed to
measure various parameters of a power relationship. Some aspects of these are in principle amenable to quantitative assessment. For instance,
over how many subjects can the holder of power
exercise that power? Over how many aspects of
their existence? How significant are those aspects?
Also, assuming that power entails the ability to
inflict negative sanctions on those subject to it,
one can put those sanctions in some kind of ordinal sequence. The power over life and death
which Roman law attributed to the paterfamilias
can plausibly be assumed to stand at the high end
of that sequence, although there are variations in
the manner in which a subject can be put to
death. This side of killing lies, for example, banishment from the polity, often accompanied by
the confiscation of the patrimony of the banished.
The sequence goes down to a rich variety of less
and less blatantly damaging sanctions, such as the
dismissal from employment of a worker, the
blackballing of someone seeking admission to a
club, or the exposure to gossip of a member of a
social circle. But it is a demanding task to subsume this ordinal arrangement of sanctions into
a more sophisticated metric, comprising other
aspects of the power relations, and allowing their
comparison – the comparison, say, between the
threat of a lockout and the threat of a strike. In
fact, some scholars adopting high standards of
methodological rigor were led by the difficulty of
measuring power to the conclusion that one
might as well dispense with the concept itself!
Fortunately, few scholars took that suggestion
seriously. The rest continued, more or less explicitly and consistently, to abide by the notion that
power was an indispensable concept, pointing to a
most significant social experience or indeed a
465
power
critical dimension, overt or covert, of all social
structures. From the late 1950s through the mid
1970s, in the protracted sociological argument
over a theoretical perspective focused on order
versus one focused on conflict, the power concept
was often invoked by students associated with the
latter perspective. However, it could be employed
also to challenge that alternative, arguing that
order need not be grounded on normative consensus among all involved in systematic interaction,
but rather on the pressure which one part of
society, the powerful part, imposed upon the other,
powerless part. Even those situations where significant structures were in fact underwritten by some
kind of normative consensus valid across society
could be interpreted as outcomes of particularly
protracted, routinized, long-unchallenged power
inequalities.
Another advantage of the emphasis on these
was that it gave some conceptual purchase even
on social change, on situations where existent
arrangements were called into question and order
broke down. In its Weberian framework, the concept of power implied the possibility of resistance.
It thus allowed that sometimes the power-less but
resistant part of society could gain the upper hand
and succeed in restructuring society to suit its
own interests. Or, a group not favored by the
existent power structure could challenge it by
developing alternative power sources. Finally,
even within a stable power structure, its very existence gave rise to contentions over the occupancy of the favored positions within it, and
thus to further occasions for change.
Arguments of this kind, as we have seen, often
appealed to Weber’s intellectual authority. The
debate became more intense, and more significant, when the central imagery of the Weberian
construction was called into question. To simplify
matters, an intrinsically tough-minded view of
power was challenged by a tender-minded one.
The Weberian imagery, we have suggested, emphasized the asymmetry between individuals or
between groups acting in the presence of one
another, and the advantages enjoyed by those
located at the upper end of the asymmetry. It
implied that, at any rate in a stable and consistent power relationship, whatever its sources
and scope, all the power there was lay at that
end – in other words, the relationship was a
zero-sum one.
Yet Weber himself had connected that relation
with the involvement of both parties in “communal action.” Whether Weber meant this or
not, this consideration suggested to some authors
466
power
that one could view the power relation, in spite of
its intrinsic asymmetry, as a functional feature of
that communal action, a fixture, as it were, of a
shared social space, rather than something appropriated by one party and by the same token denied
the other party and used to keep it at bay. A given
party’s power over the other could be viewed also
as something both parties benefited from, as a
component of their power to attain some shared
end, as a collective facility.
This bold reconceptualization of power was put
forward in the late 1950s by Talcott Parsons, in a
belated but impressive rebuttal of a criticism
often made of his theories, to the effect that these
ignored the phenomenon of power and the related reasons for conflict and change. It was taken
further by Niklas Luhmann, who expressly reproached Parsons’s critics, and his own, for their
bloody-minded insistence on the asymmetry of
power, on the distribution of power within a
group. The time had come to consider the extent
to which the institutionalization of power relations empowered the group as a whole, made it
more capable of pursuing collective goals.
Power should be considered as a medium
through which selections made in one part of
society could be transmitted to others, and thus
as analogous to money. In the same way that
money allows and fosters the rationalization of
economic activities in a society where it has been
invented or adopted, the development within it of
power relations could strongly assist a society’s
pursuit of non-economic goals.
The gain a group or society derives from being
the locus of a power relationship deserves serious
consideration, irrespective of the way in which or
the extent to which such a relationship favors in
the first instance one part of society over the
others. It allows the society as a whole to respond
more promptly and energetically to new opportunities and dangers in its environment, to promote and manage new modes of cooperation. It
can be likened to a cybernetic device, monitoring
the environment, collecting, storing, elaborating
information, forming decisions which can be the
more promptly, coherently and predictably implemented, to everybody’s advantage, the more they
are backed by sanctions available in principle exclusively to one part of society – the superior part.
Put otherwise, power does not empower only
those who hold it.
The fact that power can be, and, according to
this argument, typically is, generated and accumulated on behalf of the whole society, although
managed by one part of it, is suggested by one
power
significant aspect of political power, namely its
tendency to seek legitimacy, that is to generate
in those subject to power a disposition to obey,
grounded on a sense of moral obligation. Yet, Parsons’s own strong emphasis on legitimacy (and the
attendant processes of legitimation, and its variety), while in keeping with his own strongly normative (and Durkheim-inspired) conception of the
social process at large, is only to a limited extent
supported by Weber’s own discourse on power.
Here, the ideal-typical discussion of the subjective
processes presiding over the subjects’ obedience
points also to other motivations to obey – a
subject’s totally unreflected, automatic habit of
submission, or a subject’s calculation of the advantages and disadvantages of obedience versus nonobedience and of the probability of the attendant
application or non-application of sanctions. Obedience grounded on a sense of moral obligation
comes in only as a third answer – though one on
which Weber himself lays emphasis, by offering a
particularly creative treatment of it.
Weber in fact treats legitimacy itself as a significant but contingent qualification of a power
relation previously established on strictly factual
grounds, and which can if necessary reassert
itself and maintain itself, at any rate in the short
to medium term, even in the presence of a legitimation crisis. Furthermore, in the context of
big-time politics – the context, that is, of international relations, where the competitive interactions between sovereign polities take place – there
is not much place for legitimacy, which is instead
a property, if of anything, of domestic political
relations. In the international realm, instead,
sheer, military might is necessarily the ultimate
stake and medium of political action. Because
legitimacy is irrelevant to such might, only its
effectiveness counts.
Furthermore, Weber was keenly aware that political power itself, that to which the notion of
legitimacy could apply, as we have seen in the
domestic context, was only one form of social
power. Weber argued that social classes, status
groups, and political parties are all phenomena
of the distribution of power within a community.
In Weber’s view, power exists between a community’s component groups if, and to the extent that,
one of these secures exclusive or highly privileged
access to and control over a critical social resource. This allows the group to lay enforceable
boundaries on the activities of the other groups.
The powerful group can induce the others to
desist from opposing or hindering the pursuit of
its own interests, or indeed direct them to commit
power
some of their own activities, willy-nilly, to that
very pursuit.
The power phenomenon, then, can be differentiated conceptually by considering the social resources a group must appropriate in order to gain
this degree of control over others. In Marxian
language, those resources are of three kinds:
means of production (on which is based economic
power, the main theme of the relations between
classes); means of violence (these ground political
power, and the possession and employment of
them is contended over by parties – in a very
broad meaning of this expression); and means of
interpretation.
This last concept needs some further elaboration, for it points to the elusive domain of the
imaginary. Michael Mann, in The Sources of Social
Power (1986), without using the expression “means
of interpretation,” convincingly argues its significance on the basis of three “anthropological”
considerations. Human beings need cognitive
frameworks by means of which to experience
and to handle reality; need normative frameworks
to sustain and routinize their cooperative activities and to moderate and settle their contentions; and need ritual and aesthetic practices by
means of which to express particularly meaningful emotions and symbolize and sustain their
identities. “Ideological” power emerges to the
extent that a distinctive group establishes privileged control over the social activities and the cultural artifacts relating to the satisfaction of these
needs, and to that degree can direct those social
activities and the access to those cultural artifacts.
Mann, however, dissents from this tripartite
classification of the power phenomenon by giving
separate conceptual status also to military power.
Other students dissent from it by explicitly
or implicitly subscribing to the identification of
power itself with political power.
A sustained argument to the effect that social
power can manifest itself in different ways was
developed, towards the end of the twentieth century, by the German sociologist Heinrich Popitz
(1925–2002). The title of his book, Phänomene der
Macht: Autorität, Herrschaft, Gewalt, Technik (1986)
conveys this meaning, for Phaenomene is a plural
noun. In particular, Popitz argues, power can be
acquired and managed also to the extent that,
through “technical action,” some people can
shape and modify to their own advantage the
objective circumstances under which other people
live, the constraints under which they operate.
Technical action has three essential moments, all
in the first place relating individuals with things:
467
power
“making use of,” “modifying,” and “producing”
objects.
But such subject-to-object relations always
affect also those between subject and subject.
This does not simply mean that technical action
has social conditions and consequences. Rather,
such action plays a role in establishing the social
conditions of human beings. Behind the “making
use” of objects necessarily lies the question of property claims, behind the “modifying” of objects a
particular form of the exercise of power – and not
just power over the objects themselves – and their
“producing” entails the differentiation of activities and thus a form of division of labor.
Another of Popitz’s significant contributions,
however, is chiefly concerned with political
power, which he, with Weber, grounds in violence, and particularly with its institutionalization. He conceptualizes three main aspects of
this process: the depersonalization of power, the
formalization of its exercise, and its integration
(the latter meaning the increasing extent to which
power gears itself into other social activities, is
supported by them, and contributes to them).
Popitz also outlines an ideal-typical sequence
of phases in the institutionalization of political
power. The recourse to violence (or the threat of
it) as a way of inducing others’ compliant behavior
may go beyond its sporadic phase insofar as
means of violence are made ready for repeated
uses, and brought to bear on recurrent situations, from which those threatened with violence
cannot easily escape. Power can then move on to a
norm-making phase, where it does not just induce
the subjects to momentary compliance but seeks
to program and routinize their compliant activities and dispositions. Further, it can be positionalized, that is, connected with the occupancy of
distinctive social roles (the earliest of which have
been those of the patriarch, the judge, and the war
leader). In the next phase, those and other such
positions come to be surrounded and supported
by a staff, an apparatus – a set of individuals who
steadily and reliably collaborate with each position’s holder. The final phase sees the emergence
of a state. Here the ensemble of the holders of
power positions and of the related administrative
agencies effectively claims the monopoly of three
essential functions: norm-making, jurisdiction,
and enforcement.
The recognition that social power has different
sources and takes different forms, including at
least political and economic power, brings to
bear a specifically sociological perspective on a
phenomenon – power itself – which for centuries
468
power
has been attributed primarily or indeed exclusively to the political sphere. Indeed, according
to Luhmann, until the advent of modernity
western philosophers and other students of social
and cultural affairs “thematized” society itself
chiefly in its aspect as a polity, as a “realm,” as
the bounded territory whose inhabitants are perceived in the first place as suitable objects for rule.
Only in the course of modernization has the
sphere of the economy strongly asserted its autonomy from that of politics, and economic power
has separated itself institutionally from political
power. But according to Franz Neumann, this historically unique development has by the same
token posed the problem of how those two power
forms would relate to one another, whether and
how they would assist or contrast with one another, establish alliances with one another or
seek to maximize their own autonomy over one
another, their own superiority over one another.
This problem cannot be settled by conceptual
fiat, for it has different aspects, and finds different
solutions, in varying empirical circumstances. For
instance, the Marxian characterization of the
state as “the executive committee of the bourgeoisie” was not wide of the mark when it was
proposed, but it needs at the very least strong
qualifications and modifications, if one wants to
apply it in later circumstances. Here it became
more enlightening to think of politics and the
market as the institutional loci of intrinsically
different, and potentially competing, power processes. The title of Thomas H. Marshall’s Citizenship
and Social Class (1950) points in this direction.
The duality in question finds an echo in other
contemporary theoretical debates in the social
sciences. The superiority of the economy is implicitly asserted in the extension of the rational
choice approach to spheres of social existence,
including the polity, where previously other approaches prevailed. In particular, the economist
Oliver Williamson construed the emergence of
hierarchy itself (the key political phenomenon)
as the outcome of particular circumstances where
the individuals’ purely market behavior, which
he viewed as the paradigm of all social conduct,
generated inefficiencies. These are remedied by
complementing the mechanism of coordination
constituted by mere exchanges by a different
one – “do as I say.”
Whatever the insights yielded by these economic perspectives, one must note their persistent tendency to identify power with political
power, and thus to treat the power phenomenon
itself as something in principle extraneous to the
pragmatism
economic realm. Power so conceived can be at best
complementary to that realm, servicing its need
for political support and regulation. At worst, it
tends to prey upon it, and thus to damage its
unique capacity to produce efficiency (once more
an intrinsically economic criterion, unproblematically put forward as the one criterion by which to
judge all social arrangements).
As long as such perspectives prevail, they do
little to prepare the sociological imagination to
deal with the continuing story of the relationship
between economic and political power. The main
content of that story is, in the early twenty-first
century, the globalization process. This can be
roughly conceived as a (partly) novel way in which
economic processes seek to proceed with a maximum of support, and a minimum of interference,
on the part of political power centers. The novelty
lies in the ever-growing availability to economic
forces of largely deterritorialized spaces and resources. This deeply challenges the still prevalent
power centers – states which exercise jurisdiction
over distinctive territories, and extract resources
from economic units stably located within those
spaces.
An appreciation of the extent to which these
ongoing phenomena find in social power both
their target and their medium requires among
other things the continuing awareness of the significance and complexity of the power concept
itself. Once more it is not a conceptual question
whether the relationship between political power
and economic power, in particular, is primarily
one of collusion or collision. But one can assume
that the answer to that question – or indeed the
answers, since these will continue to vary from
time to time and from place to place – will throw
light on historical phenomena of great human
significance.
GIANFRANCO POGGI
pragmatism
This philosophical school, founded in the United
States in the nineteenth century, originates in the
belief that philosophical standards, and especially
the standards of truth, should be grounded in the
efficacy of the practices that would result from
their use. Pragmatism is averse to all metaphysical, moral, and social ideals that claim priority
over the solutions to practical problems.
While several current sociological projects draw
inspiration from C. S. Peirce (1839–1914), the
father of modern pragmatism and the scholar
who made communication central to pragmatic
thought, Charles Horton Cooley and John Dewey
(1859–1952) built more well-established bridges to
pragmatism
topics of sociological interest from pragmatic
philosophical positions. George Herbert Mead
expanded and extended these bridges. Thereafter,
some of Mead’s leading insights were institutionalized in sociology via Herbert Blumer’s interpretations of him. The Chicago School of symbolic
interactionism followed Blumer’s lead.
However, the influence of pragmatism in sociology extends beyond the symbolic interactionist
school. After arriving in the United States, Alfred
Schutz worked several pragmatic insights into his
social phenomenology, paying special attention
to the works of Dewey and the pragmatically inspired psychology of William James. Erving Goffman was inspired by James as well when writing
Frame Analysis (1973). Arlie Russell Hochschild
draws central elements of her groundbreaking
conception of emotion work from Mead, which is
quite helpful because most pragmatists other
than James are inclined to emphasize cognition
over emotion. On a more abstract level, Mead’s
pragmatic analysis of social action is reworked
and plays a central role in Jürgen Habermas’s
extraordinary model of communicative action.
Though Mead is far more widely cited by sociologists than any other pragmatist, John Dewey’s
analysis in Human Nature and Conduct (1922) provides the most clear-cut illustration of the application of pragmatic principles to sociological
theory. Dewey builds a theory of social action
upon an insight into social praxis that more recently has figured prominently in Anthony Giddens’s structuration theory and the ideas of
habitus and field devised by Pierre Bourdieu. The
insight is that most actions in everyday life are
performed with only tacit consciousness in habitual ways. This widely shared view does not derive
from pragmatism per se. But Dewey takes the
pragmatic turn when he observes that, when habitual routines are blocked, sharply focused
thought concentrates on eliminating the blockage, whether by removing it or by creative innovation. Dewey proposes that basic human psychic
impulses become associated with habits. Their
frustration motivates the actor to conscious
thought. However, these efforts may be derailed
through various kinds of dissipation. Drug abuse,
promiscuous sexuality, daydreaming, and psychological distress all follow from the dissipation of
impulses to overcome frustrating problems. The
proper aim of scientific practice is to expedite an
end to these frustrations. Dewey, like most pragmatists, underrates the role of domination in both
social routines and focused thought. His social
psychology also lacks a deep appreciation of the
469
prejudice
structured nature of social conduct. Moreover,
unlike Peirce and Mead, Dewey neglects communication. Nonetheless, his emphasis on cycles of
routine and frustration in action epitomizes the
pragmatic view of social conduct.
IRA COHEN
prejudice
In sociology the concept of prejudice refers broadly
to systematic and durable subjective assessments of
groups, or members of those groups, in unfavorable terms. The concept has been at the center of
sociological research on race and ethnicity for
many years but has also played an important role
in sociological research pertaining to age, social
class, disability and impairment, gender, and sexuality. Research on prejudice overlaps to a considerable extent with research on the closely related
phenomena of discrimination and stigma. However, the study of prejudice tends to focus more
on the causes and characteristics of people’s prejudicial attitudes, discrimination research focuses
more on their prejudicial or injurious behavior,
and research on stigma tends to focus on the experiences and behavior of those who are victimized
by prejudice, discrimination, and stigmatization.
While some social scientists believe prejudice
entails evaluations based on erroneous preconceptions regarding an out-group, others suggest it can
be based on objective conflicts of interest between
in-group and out-group members. Scholars
belonging to the first school of thought tend to
take a more optimistic view of the prospects for
overcoming prejudice insofar as they see the
problem as essentially one of changing people’s
attitudes through a sustained campaign of enlightened education. Proponents of the second school of
thought see the problem as more deeply entrenched in people’s social structural circumstances
and relationships, and hence are rather less optimistic about the prospects of remedies that do not
attend to the social structural, as well as the social
psychological, causes of people’s prejudices.
Another important and pervasive distinction in
the literature on prejudice concerns the extent to
which prejudicial attitudes are conscious or unconscious. The earliest research on prejudice
tended to focus on overt forms of bigotry or the
explicit espousal of prejudicial attitudes towards
various out-groups or individual out-group members. However, it is now much more common
for social scientists to consider how systematic
biases against particular out-groups or systematically discriminatory behaviors towards them are
maintained despite research subjects’ conscious
commitments to an image of themselves as
470
prejudice
non-prejudiced against that group. This issue is
particularly salient in debates as to whether prejudice is maintained primarily by social psychological or by social structural processes. Those
who lean towards social structural explanations
of prejudice tend to be more amenable to the view
that individuals may often be unwitting, or unconscious, agents of prejudice and discrimination
despite consciously espousing egalitarian values.
At least as far back as Émile Durkheim’s classic
work on the value of deviance ascriptions for the
maintenance of in-group solidarity in his analysis
of crime in The Rules of Sociological Method (1895
[trans. 1958]), sociologists have recognized a certain social functionality in explicitly designating,
and discriminating against, groups other than
one’s own.
While sometimes drawing on this longer legacy
from classical sociology, research on prejudice has
more recent origins. It was only in the wake of
World War II, following revelations about the
Holocaust and other horrors of Nazi Germany,
that social scientists began to investigate how it
was possible for such powerfully chauvinistic sentiments to arise. While ethnocentrism, xenophobia, and chauvinism were certainly recognized
features of the social landscape before this time,
they were not made the topic of systematic sociological analysis until World War II. One early approach to explaining prejudice against minority
groups in society drew upon the frustration–
aggression hypothesis formulated by John Dollard
and his colleagues in Frustration and Aggression
(1939), wherein it was argued that an agent frustrated at the hands of a more powerful actor will
sublimate the sentiments of aggression created by
these frustrations by focusing them on less powerful scapegoats. Thus, met with the frustrations
surrounding World War I, the Versailles Treaty,
and subsequent reparations, Germany was held
to have taken this out on the Jews because they
could not express their aggression directly towards the Allies. Another major theoretical approach to emerge on the topic of prejudice was
that put forward by Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno
and his colleagues regarding what they called
the authoritarian personality. Drawing upon the
principles of Freudian psychoanalysis, Adorno
focused on early childhood learning processes to
explain the propensities of some people to adopt
rigid, inflexible, and prejudicial attitudes towards
certain minority groups and their members.
According to this theory, the early childhood experience of growing up in a highly regimented,
strictly disciplined household could often produce
prejudice
a personality structure in children that is highly
submissive to the dictates of established authority
figures and intolerant of people(s) who do not
conform to those dictates. This personality structure predisposes individuals to chauvinistic persecution of people who do not subscribe to the
ethnic and/or cultural values to which they were
compelled to adhere as children. Once established
in the deep psyche of the individual, this personality structure becomes relatively impervious to
rational critique and hence relatively resistant
to change. These earliest approaches tended to
locate the cause of prejudice in psychopathological learning processes and thereby to delimit
the focus of analyses to only those people thought
to have undergone them. While certain segments
of the human population were held to be guilty of
prejudice, the vast majority were not seen to be
implicated in the reproduction of prejudice and
discrimination.
Research following on from the pioneering
work of Harvard social psychologist Gordon
Allport (1897–1967) has suggested that prejudice
is not only the result of psychopathology but
also results from much more routine and pervasive learning processes. This research opened the
door to much more encompassing theories concerning both the causes and the prevalence of
prejudice. According to Allport, the human mind
cannot dispense with what he called categorical
thinking, and what is now more commonly
known as stereotypical thinking, because it is the
function of the mind to simplify and systematize
the diverse sensory and cognitive inputs to which
it is exposed. Were it not to do so, we would be
hopelessly ill-equipped to act in the world. However, this natural mental function can serve to
create significant social problems when our
stereotypes are based on flawed information and
are applied indiscriminately to whole minority
groups and their members. While acknowledging
the role played by psychodynamic pathologies in
creating prejudice, Allport insisted in The Nature
of Prejudice (1954) we must supplement psychodynamic explanations with explanations that
speak to the whole spectrum of processes, both
normal and abnormal, that figure in the development of our personalities. These include social,
cultural, and economic processes as well as psychodynamic ones. Allport properly insisted that any
adequate understanding of prejudice must allow
that it can be caused by many different kinds of
things occurring in a person’s life. However, as a
social psychologist he was quite understandably
predisposed to focus on the personality of the
prejudice
individual actor as the critical apparatus upon
which these various processes must act if they
are to become manifest as prejudice. For Allport
and his followers, prejudice was most fundamentally an “antipathy based on a faulty and inflexible generalisation.” And just as he focused on the
social psychological processes that give rise to
prejudicial attitudes, his proposals for alleviating
prejudice focused on efforts to correct the erroneous mental predispositions of individual actors
rather than the social structural circumstances
that compel those mental predispositions. From
this social psychological perspective, the basic
nature of prejudice is seen to reside in the mistaken judgments of particular individuals rather
than in the inter-group conflicts and tensions endemic to a social system. As one might imagine,
sociologists have sometimes been dissatisfied with
what they have taken to be the over-emphasis
on individuals in this approach and the concomitant under-emphasis on macro-structural causes
of persistent prejudice and discrimination.
Several theoretical approaches have been taken
in research aimed at exploring such macrostructural causes. One suggests that prejudicial
attitudes express what are in fact realistic group
conflicts. Far from expressing mistaken understandings of the threat posed by out-groups and/
or their individual members, members of ingroups are prejudiced against members of those
out-groups with whom they actually, or might
potentially, struggle over objectively scarce resources. Another related theoretical approach
follows in the tradition of Herbert Blumer’s group
position model. According to Blumer, in a variety
of publications relating to “Collective Behavior” in
A. M. Lee, New Outline of the Principles of Sociology
(1946), and “Social Movements” in A. M. Lee, Principles of Sociology (1955), members of an in-group
must share an outlook comprised of four key features for prejudice to arise: (1) a feeling of superiority, (2) a belief that an out-group is intrinsically
different and alien, (3) a sense of proprietary claim
to certain privileges and resources, and (4) a sense
of threat from members of subordinate groups
upon the dominant group’s prerogatives. In
contrast to the realistic group conflict model,
Blumer’s group position model focuses on the
perceptions of in-group members that their prerogatives are under threat rather than the objective reality of the threat itself. This highlights not
only that prejudice may arise from perceptions
that may or may not be accurate, but also the
notion that there is an affective, as well as a purely
instrumental, dimension to the felt conflict
471
pressure group
between members of an in-group and an outgroup. More than merely observing an objective
conflict of interest, in-group members feel a normative sense that this conflict ought to be resolved in favor of their own group and that not
only their own personal prerogatives but the prerogatives of their group as a whole ought not to be
threatened. This highlights how prejudice must be
understood as not just the negative attitudes of an
individual towards an out-group, but negative attitudes necessarily mediated by a sense of group
membership and commitments to the well-being
of that group as a whole in comparison with other
groups. Other important approaches to the study
of prejudice include the ideological control and
paternalism model, the social dominance model,
and social identity models. While not necessarily
conflicting with the realistic group conflict and
group position models, these models tend not to
focus as much attention on overt conflict and
threat. The ideological control and paternalism
model argues that prejudice arises when efforts
are made by members of a dominant group to
legitimize their expropriative relationship with a
subordinate group ideologically. In this effort they
will seek to minimize overt hostilities by proffering deflated images of the aptitudes of subordinated group members and a paternalistic sense of
obligation to look after them. This approach suggests that prejudice may not always be expressed
in hostile terms but may also be expressed in
terms connoting warmth and concern for the welfare of subordinated group members. The social
dominance model highlights a sense of entitlement felt by in-group members to dominance in
their relations with out-group members, but does
not call so much attention to their felt sense of
competition with and threat from members of an
out-group. Finally, social identity models point to
the fact that prejudices against out-groups and
their individual members may often arise as a
consequence of in-group loyalties as such and the
wide range of instrumental and affective satisfactions that come from our self-categorization as
members of an in-group.
DARIN WEINBERG
pressure group
– see group(s)
prestige
Referring to influence, reputation, or popular
esteem, this concept is often mistakenly treated
as a synonym for social status. Status refers to
the social position a person occupies in a social
472
prestige
hierarchy. Prestige refers to the esteem assigned
to social position. Prestige comes in two general
forms. Ascribed prestige refers to the generation
of esteem based upon rank. For example, a people
assign prestige to a monarch by virtue of bloodline; or to a physician on the basis of the honorific
value of the occupation. Achieved prestige refers
to the assignment of esteem on the basis of the
accomplishments of the individual. For example,
John Lennon (1940–80) of the Beatles was esteemed
as a result of his success as a popular entertainer
and campaigner for peace, and Nelson Mandela
(1918– ), the founder of the African National
Congress in south Africa, is honored for his stance
on human rights and anti-racism. The trend in
modern democracies is for ascribed prestige to
be replaced by achieved prestige. However, because democracies create opportunities for
achievement that generate unequal rewards in
economic wealth and distinction, they support
new types of ascribed prestige. For example, in
the United States, Caroline Kennedy does not
occupy a formal rank in society. Nonetheless, she
commands a type of ascribed prestige by virtue of
the accomplishments of her parents, John and
Jackie Kennedy. Democracies weaken traditional
status hierarchies, but they create the conditions
for new hierarchies based on achievement, which
in turn confer prestige through inheritance.
Because esteem has value it is subject to contrivance and imposture. In traditional society this
often took the form of illegal claims to bloodline.
In contemporary society they more commonly take
the form of the tabloid media constructing celebrities for public consumption and pecuniary gain.
The magnification of celebrity culture is often
held to result in the leveling down of prestige
and is linked with secularization, rationalization,
and bureaucratization.
Prestige may wax and wane according to the
performance of the individual who occupies a
status position. For example, a monarch may
behave in ways that offend his people, or a doctor
may misplace the trust placed in his occupation
by behaving in a way that is harmful to others. In
cases like this, we speak of dissonance between
prestige and social status. The inverse of prestige
is notoriety, which is a condition in which the
dissonance between status and performance has
been scandalized.
In mainstream American sociology the concept
is more narrowly associated with research on
occupation and occupational ranking. Quantitative sociology has devised a series of scales which
purport to measure prestige.
CHRIS ROJEK
primary group
primary group
– see group(s).
primitive society
In prototype, primitive society was an explicit
object of philosophical speculation and naturalhistorical curiosity from the moment that the first
European explorers returned from Africa and the
Americas. By the middle of the nineteenth century
and until the 1920s, it was the analytical preserve
of anthropology and analytical attention accorded
it was anthropological by definition. As Adam
Kuper points out in The Invention of the Primitive
(1988), it was, for nineteenth-century theorists, of
a piece with ancient society; if distinguished from
the latter at all, it was distinguished as the most
ancient of the forms of society that, as a matter of
historically particular fact or general evolutionary
law, had preceded the modern present. Examples
of it survived, but they were in the present without being of it, “living fossils” that had somehow
refused or failed to change.
If the first hallmark of primitive society was
thus its primordiality, the second was its simplicity or elementariness. It manifested little if any
institutional differentiation. Its primary matrix
of the distribution of roles and statuses was that
of kinship and its typical system of kinship a
classificatory system that pressed relationships
of differing degrees of mutual propinquity into
a common pigeonhole. Technologically, it constrained its members to hunt and gather. Cognitively and intellectually, it exhibited an analogous
lack of rigor and discernment. Most theorists
could agree that primitive man was endowed
with the same basic powers of perception and
judgment as his modern counterpart, but those
powers had yet to develop beyond those of a child.
He might be practical enough to survive, but not
yet sufficiently astute to recognize even the
principle of physiological paternity. He could
engage in the wildest flights of mythological fancy,
but had no sense of history and no means either of
fashioning or of grasping moral and conceptual
abstractions.
The concept of primitive society underwent
three notable changes in the course of the twentieth century. At the vanguard of the first are
Bronislaw Malinowski and American cultural anthropologists such as Ruth Benedict (1887–1948).
With them, primitive society is divested of its
primordiality and retains a simplicity no longer
differing in kind but only in degree from the
societies that abut or otherwise invite comparison
with it. The second change owes something to the
Privacy
ethnography of India but even more to Claude
Lévi-Strauss. In its aftermath, primitive society is
neither bereft of intellectuals nor ignorant of history. It instead joins its qualitatively more complex but still traditional societies in resisting the
existential and social significance of the difference between the past and present and future.
The third of the changes comes with the rejection of the subliminal evolutionism and the
subliminal progressivism that inform the distinction between primitive and modern. Its key
texts remain Renato Rosaldo’s Ilongot Headhunting (1980), Richard Price’s First-Time (1983), and
Johannes Fabian’s Time and the Other (1983).
JAMES D. FAUBION
Privacy
The importance of privacy is often associated with
the “quarrel between the ancients and moderns.”
This expression came from the title of a famous
lecture on “The Liberty of the Ancients Compared
with that of the Moderns” in 1819 by the French
political philosopher Benjamin Constant (1767–
1830), which is reprinted in his Political Writings
(1988). This lecture compared the respect for
public institutions and public space in the ancient
world with the emphasis on conscience and individual subjectivity in modern society. Constant
argued that the liberty of the ancients, which
arose from their active engagement in politics,
required the sacrifice of their personal interests
to those of the polis. By contrast, the moderns
pursue their personal pleasures, regarding politics
as merely a means to protect their private lives.
The concept of privacy is thus interconnected
with a range of other key concepts in political
and social theory, such as individual rights, the
state and the social contract.
In contemporary thought, privacy is closely associated with individualism, because private space
outside the public realm is assumed to be important for cultivating and protecting the individual
from social scrutiny and political surveillance. In
the liberal theory of John Locke (1632–1704), the
protection of the rights of individuals is held to be
essential to guard against the threat of arbitrary
rule by authoritarian governments. Civil rights
refer to the legal entitlements of free and rational
agents, who combine, by means of a social contract, to form a state, whose sole purpose is to
guarantee their enjoyment of these privileges.
The minimalist theory of the state, for example
the night watchman state, is a product of liberalism, because the only justification for the state is
the protection of the liberties of individuals to do
as they please, namely to enjoy their privacy.
473
Privacy
In classical Greece, private affairs were often
negatively defined in opposition to the public
sphere and public duty. The private arena was
associated with deprivation (privatus), while the
public sphere was one of freedom and reason,
where citizens congregated for political debate
and economic exchange. The autonomous individual could only exist and develop in the public
domain. In political philosophy, this contrast has
been an important aspect of the modern theory of
totalitarianism. In The Origins of Totalitarianism
(1958), Hannah Arendt argued that in modern
society people are forced out of a shared public
world into a lonely, isolated, and interior space.
In their isolation, pressures towards social uniformity undermine their individual autonomy, and
they are psychologically exposed to totalitarian
forces.
According to Arendt, this clear distinction between private and public has been confused in
modern times by the emergence of “the social.”
In modern society, people are bound together, but
these common threads are paradoxically the private desires of consumption and a common mass
culture. In a mass society, the social becomes the
basis for mass conformity and the moral calling of
the political sinks into petty politics. The noble art
of politics as a life of virtue becomes merely a
trade in power and influence.
Arendt’s vision of modern society was debated
by David Riesman in The Lonely Crowd. A Study of the
Changing American Character (1950), in which he
contrasted the tradition-directed personalities
who are conformists and merely reproduce traditional culture with the inner-directed personality
who emerged with the Renaissance and the Reformation. By contrast, the other-directed personality
of modern America (and other societies dominated by the mass media) craves approval from
others. The social relations of the other-directed
character are mediated by the flow of mass communication, and their demand for social approval
is an aspect of liberal, middle-class socialization.
Riesman’s criticisms of American society in
the 1950s bore a close resemblance to Herbert
Marcuse’s analysis of the ‘happy consciousness’
in his One-Dimensional Man (1964), but they were
also related to the study of individualism in colonial America by Alexis de Tocqueville. In his The
Idea of the Self (2005), Jerrold Seigel has shown how,
especially in the social philosophy of J.-J. Rousseau
(1712–78), there is a well established view that the
conscience of the individual requires protection
from public opinion, and this protection is an
important aspect of privacy.
474
profession(s)
In contemporary sociology, writers like Amitai
Etzioni in The Limits of Privacy (1999) have raised
critical questions about the benefits of the protection of privacy for public life, but one can also
argue that privacy has been further transformed
by modern technologies (such as closed-circuit
television) which allow the individual to be under
constant surveillance. In addition, changes to the
law relating, for example, to notions of sexual
harassment in the workplace mean that the
private /public distinction has broken down, because the law can intervene into people’s “private”
sexual activities.
BRYAN S. TURNER
private and public spheres
– see public sphere.
process sociology
– see Norbert Elias.
professionalization
– see profession(s).
profession(s)
A group of occupations (for example, doctors,
lawyers, and clergy) who provide highly specialized services, based typically on an esoteric body
of knowledge, which only they can assess. They
thus experience autonomy over their own work,
and direct others in the conduct of their occupations. They have monopolistic control in their area
of expertise (only doctors can practice medicine),
and they exercise dominance over subordinate
occupations. Their claims to monopoly and dominance are backed by state legislation. In return
for this autonomy, they govern themselves by abiding to a code of ethics by which they are required to
put their client’s interests ahead of their own,
are in a fiduciary relationship with their client
(that is, one of trust), and put their client’s needs
ahead of any self-interested profit-making.
For Émile Durkheim professional associations
played a central role in fostering trust and stability in a society otherwise driven by utilitarian selfinterest, an argument captured in the title of his
work Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1957), a
posthumous translation of the Leçons de sociologie
(1950). This line of analysis was further developed
by Talcott Parsons in the Social System (1951, especially chapter 10). Taking the medical profession as an example, Parsons argued that it was
characterized by a number of distinctive practices
which distinguished medical practitioners from
other occupations in a market economy. They are
universalistic in their orientation; they provide
profession(s)
services independently of the particular characteristics of their patients, such as gender; they are
affectively neutral in that they do not stand in
moral judgment of their patient’s condition; they
are oriented to the good of the collective; and they
are functionally specific, dealing only with the
issue at hand and using the best scientific knowledge. In contrast, contemporary sociologists of
the professions emphasize their self-interested
practice of social closure, thereby maintaining
occupational autonomy to enhance their incomes
and keeping competitors out. While Parsons
pointed to the long period of training for professionals as central to their socialization into
the profession’s ethical standpoint, contemporary
sociologists regard such training as a protracted
gate-keeping exercise. Eliot Freidson in Profession of
Medicine: A Study of the Sociology of Applied Knowledge
(1970) and Professional Dominance: The Social Structure
of Medical Care (1970) argued that the medical
profession dominates in the health sector, not as
a consequence of its scientific, humanitarian
ethos, but because it is politically well organized.
Medicine maintains its aura of high standing, despite the often degrading nature of its work, effectively passing such dirty work onto subordinate
occupations such as nursing. Sustained analysis
of the actual ways in which doctors practice,
carried out by sociologists in grounded theory,
demonstrated that doctors were not universalistic
in their orientation to treatment, with significant
variations in their dealings with women and
ethnic minorities. In fact, the profit motive was a
significant factor in their clinical decisionmaking.
Overall then, the positive evaluation of the professions that is the legacy of Durkheim and Parsons
has not fared well following empirical analysis of
the ways in which the professions actually operate
in society.
Other social changes, particularly the rise of
neoliberalism in the political sphere, are having
a substantial impact on the structure and work of
professionals. Economic policymakers in the state
sector are now disposed to view professional associations as anti-competitive cartels, and to regard
professional self-regulation and exclusion of competitors (who may perform the same services more
cheaply) as merely self-interested. Other social
changes, such as the rise of an educated public,
make consumers of professional services more
cautious and skeptical of professional knowledge
claims. The organization of consumer groups provides a platform to question such expert systems.
Furthermore, the inability or lack of will on the
part of professional organizations to discipline
progress
errant members has led to far greater legal control over practitioners as the public takes to the
courts as the first line of action. Technological
changes have led to the routinization of much
professional work and the claim to practice on
the basis of an esoteric body of knowledge has
been considerably weakened, especially in medicine, engineering, and architecture as computer
programs replace professional judgment. Linked
with a decline in self-employment and the rise
of corporate employers, it has been argued, following Karl Marx, that the professions are being
proletarianized. This proletarianization can take
two forms: ideological proletarianization refers to
the loss of autonomy over the setting of policies,
goals, and objectives of and by the profession;
and technical proletarianization refers to the
loss of control over work practices by the professional. While there is considerable debate over
this claim, it is clear that there has been significant de-professionalization as doctors, lawyers,
and architects, for example, perform work under
the control of bureaucratic superiors. Furthermore, under these conditions of employment their
responsibility is not to their client but to the shareholders who expect a profitable return on their
investment. In turn the professions themselves
have started to fragment, a process in which the
elite within the profession continues to enjoy considerable autonomy, and a dependent stratum are
supervised by superiors. This erosion of autonomy
occurred especially in law and general practice,
where, increasingly, female employees perform
routine tasks that are monitored by superiors in
the professional hierarchy. These changes in professional medicine were clearly documented in
Paul Starr’s The Social Transformation of American
Medicine. The Rise of a Sovereign Profession and the
Making of a Vast Industry (1982). While the professions may still enjoy reasonable social status, high
incomes, and have more freedom than those in
other occupations, they have also experienced significant inroads into their autonomy and all indications are that this will increasingly be the case.
KEVIN WHITE
progress
The view that the human world has advanced, is
advancing, and will continue to advance in the
future. It is opposed to all ideas of a past Golden
Age, or the sense of decadence and decline. It
expresses a basic optimism and confidence in
the ability of humans to resolve their problems,
and to increase in prosperity, morality, and
understanding with the passage of time.
475
progress
Historically speaking, the idea of progress is
relatively new. It first arose in western Europe in
the second half of the seventeenth century. In a
battle of the books between the Ancients and the
Moderns, the Moderns achieved a decisive victory
in arguing that modern people could advance as
far and indeed farther than the ancient Greeks
and Romans, who for much of the past thousand
years had continued to be accepted as the unsurpassable leaders in learning and civilization. What
made the arguments of the moderns convincing
then, in a way that they had not been earlier, was
undoubtedly the dazzling achievements of the
seventeenth-century Scientific Revolution. The
work of scientists such as Kepler (1571–1630),
Copernicus (1473–1543), Galileo (1564–1642), and
especially Newton (1643–1727), with their unlocking of the basic mechanisms of the universe, indicated that modern societies had the capacity to be
as enlightened and creative as any past society.
The philosophers Bacon (1561–1626) and Descartes
(1591–1650), with their call for a new method in
the understanding of nature and society, also expressed a sense of the originality and novelty of
the times, together with a confidence that the
modern age had within it the seeds of unlimited
progress.
The idea of progress became a central feature of
most of the leading social philosophies of the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. It was
accepted by most Enlightenment thinkers, even
as they criticized the conditions of their own societies and times. Their faith in reason gave them
the confidence that they could discover and
remedy the outstanding abuses in their societies.
Nineteenth-century thinkers, such as Herbert
Spencer, Auguste Comte, and Karl Marx, similarly
looked forward to a future of freedom, equality,
and prosperity for all, even as they lambasted the
forces holding back progress in their own times.
The idea of progress appeared to find satisfyingly
scientific confirmation in the evolutionary theory,
in which a misunderstood Social Darwinism was
applied to the idea of the ascent of man from
savagery to civilization.
There was, from the time of the French Revolution onwards, always a contrary current of
thought that radically questioned the idea of progress, which in the case of some thinkers of a
religious persuasion, such as Joseph de Maistre
(1754–1821), was thought actually impious and
blasphemous. European Romanticism, with its
criticism of industrialism and materialism, and
its idealization of the Middle Ages, added its own
passionate and persuasive critique. Towards the
476
property
end of the nineteenth century, a fin-de-siècle
pessimism became a distinct and increasingly
powerful strand of thought among European
thinkers, such as Friedrich Nietzsche, Max Weber,
and Sigmund Freud. World War I and its aftermath, with the unprecedented slaughter of men
followed by two decades of economic depression
and the rise of totalitarian dictatorships, buried
the idea of progress for most artists and intellectuals. But the defeat of fascism in World War II,
and the strong economic recovery of the postwar
era, brought about a significant revival of the idea
of progress, though it has never regained the
central position that it held in previous centuries,
being subject now particularly to the criticisms of
ecologists.
KRISHAN KUMAR
proletarianization
– see profession(s).
proletariat
– see Marxist Sociology.
property
Property implies ownership, to which may be attached rights. In liberalism, property rights have a
distinctive and foundational role. Distinctive because since John Locke (1632–1704) property
rights have been attached, not just to possession
of land and movable objects, but also to a human
being’s own person and the person’s capacities,
especially the capacity to labor. The notion of a
person’s proprietorship of their own capacities
has become foundational in liberal theory for
other rights of the person, including civil and
political rights. In Marxism, on the other hand,
property is not primarily a right but a relationship, especially a production relationship. Thus
property is concerned with (but not reducible to)
power.
Karl Marx holds that ownership or possession of
property is the principle of organization within
relations of production and distribution. Those
who possess property have direct access to the
means of consumption; those who do not must
offer their labor services to owners, who pay
them wages in order to bring their property into
productive use. In this exchange the reciprocity
between property owners and property-less workers is asymmetrical, with the material benefits
being greater for owners and the opportunity
costs being greater for non-owners. This Marx
characterizes as exploitation. Marx adds that the
form of property yields to historical variation,
corresponding to historical stages of societal
Protestant Ethic Thesis
development, namely primitive Communism,
Asiatic society, feudalism, and capitalism.
Sociological discussions of property typically
derive from either liberal or Marxist accounts.
Max Weber offers an account of property in his
Economy and Society (1922 [trans. 1968]) in terms of
appropriation and closed social relationships or
closure. The appropriation of economic opportunities, from which others are excluded, is the basis
of an advantage, according to Weber, which may
take the form of a right. If this right is enduring
and can be transferred between individuals, then
the appropriated advantage is property. Weber
goes on to discuss how appropriation and property have taken different forms under different
historical conditions and in different economic
settings. Émile Durkheim argues in The Division of
Labor in Society (1893 [trans. 1960]) that inheritance
of property is responsible for a forced labor,
through which a natural distribution of talents
is distorted and anomie results. Apart from this,
Durkheim does not develop a theory of property,
even though his largely descriptive account of
property rights in Professional Ethics and Civic Morals
(1950 [trans. 1957]) is historically insightful.
Frank Parkin in Marxism and Class Theory: A Bourgeois Critique (1979), following Marx, distinguishes
between personal property and property as capital. Property as capital, he argues, following
Weber, is exclusionary closure. Out of these relations arises class exploitation. The problem with
Parkin’s account is its exclusive focus on distributional relations and competition for resources; it
considers only the production of life chances and
fails to address the question of the production
of means that are necessary to bring those life
chances into existence. Marx does this by treating
property as an economic relation, and Weber
and Durkheim by treating property as possessing
a legal dimension. Parkin treats property as an
essentially political facility.
JACK BARBALET
Protestant Ethic Thesis
– see Max Weber.
psychoanalysis
This refers to the type of psychotherapy that was
founded by Sigmund Freud. In psychoanalysis the
therapist, or analyst, seeks to aid patients to recognize their unconscious motivation. According to
psychoanalysts, all people have unconscious desires and thus everyone would benefit from undergoing psychoanalysis. The term psychoanalysis is
also sometimes used to describe the ideas of Freud
and his followers about the unconscious structure
psychoanalysis
of the mind. It is in this second sense, as a theory
of mind rather than as a psychotherapeutic practice, that psychoanalysis has had a major effect on
sociological thinking.
Initially Freud began his career as a psychiatrist
using hypnosis to treat patients who displayed
neurotic symptoms. He found that the symptoms
often disappeared when patients could be induced
to recall forgotten memories under hypnosis.
Freud, with his colleague Josef Breuer (1842–
1925), hypothesized that the symptoms were related to painful memories or shameful desires
that the patients had pushed, or repressed, from
conscious awareness. Although the experiences
and desires may have been repressed from awareness, they continued to exert an unconscious influence. If the patients could be encouraged to
recognize their unconscious thoughts, then,
according to Freud, it would be possible to treat
their neurotic symptoms. Thus, there could be a
talking cure.
Freud and Breuer published their results in Studies on Hysteria (1893–5 [trans. 1953–74]). In this
book, Freud outlined the concept of repression,
which he later was