DEFENDING DEMOCRACY THROUGH FOREIGN
INTERVENTION*
David Wippman†
TABLE OF CONTENTS
I.
INTRODUCTION ................................................................................ 659
II.
DISAGREEMENTS ON DEMOCRACY.................................................. 662
III. LEGAL CONSTRAINTS ON INTERVENTION ....................................... 668
IV. PRACTICAL CONSTRAINTS ON INTERVENTION ................................ 673
A. Institutional Mechanisms for the Promotion of
Democracy .............................................................................. 674
B. Political and Resource Limitations ......................................... 676
C. The Difficulties of Targeted Sanctions .................................... 677
D. Uncertain Benefits of Intervention .......................................... 678
V.
CONCLUSION ................................................................................... 679
I.
INTRODUCTION
[A] great principle is spreading across the world like wildfire.
That principle, as we all know, is the revolutionary idea that the
people, not governments, are sovereign. This principle has, in
[the last] decade, . . . acquired the force of historical necessity. . . . Democracy today is synonymous with legitimacy the
world over; it is, in short, the universal value of our time.1
* This article is based on remarks made during a panel presentation entitled Defense of
Democracy and Non-Intervention at a conference on The Role of International Law in the
Americas: Rethinking National Sovereignty in an Age of Regional Integration, which was held in
Mexico City, June 6–7, 1996, and was co-sponsored by the American Society of International
Law and El Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de
México. Joint copyright is held by the Houston Journal of International Law, the author, and El
Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México.
† Associate Professor, Cornell Law School. The author wishes to thank Professor John J.
Barceló, III, for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.
1. BUREAU OF PUB. AFF., U.S. DEP’T OF STATE, CURRENT POL’Y NO. 1240, PANAMA: A
JUST CAUSE 2 (1990) (statement of Luigi R. Einaudi, U.S. Permanent Representative to the
OAS), quoted in Brad R. Roth, Governmental Illegitimacy Revisited: ‘Pro-Democratic’ Armed
Intervention in the Post-Bipolar World, 3 TRANSNAT’L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 481, 490 (1993).
659
660
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
This claim was advanced by the United States before the Organization
of American States (OAS) in 1989, in rhetorical justification of the U.S.
invasion of Panama.2 At the time, the international community was not
impressed. Both the U.N. General Assembly and the OAS voted overwhelmingly to condemn the invasion,3 even though it was common
knowledge that the advent of democracy in Panama had been frustrated by
General Manuel Noriega’s refusal to seat the government of President-elect
Guillermo Endara, and that Endara and most other Panamanians appeared
to welcome the invasion.4 Most states, Latin American countries in
particular, rejected the notion that foreign nations could legitimately
employ armed forces or other measures of coercion to seat a democratically elected government against the will of an indigenous political elite in
effective control of the state.5 Indeed, many states questioned the propriety
of any attempt by foreign states to influence domestic political processes.6
In the next several years, however, the OAS condemned attempted
coups in Surinam and Venezuela, and opposed the now famous “autogolpes” in Peru and Guatemala.7 The OAS also sent election monitors and
human rights observers to join U.N. personnel in overseeing the electoral
processes in Nicaragua, Haiti, and other member states. Most significantly,
the OAS, along with virtually the entire international community, condemned the Haitian military’s unconstitutional overthrow of President
Jean-Bertrand Aristide.8 The OAS even took the lead, at least initially, in
promoting coercive sanctions against the de facto authorities in Haiti,9 and
it acquiesced in the Security Council’s decision to authorize U.S. military
intervention to restore the deposed President to power.10
This new interventionist spirit was not confined to the OAS. On all
sides now, we hear that democracy is an idea whose time has come.
2. Id. Although the promotion of democracy figured prominently in the public statements
of U.S. officials regarding the objectives of the U.S. invasion, the United States did not claim any
right of pro-democratic intervention as part of its legal justification for the invasion. Instead, the
United States relied primarily on the right of self-defense (premised on an alleged threat to
American lives and to the United States itself) and a claimed right to preserve the integrity of the
Panama Canal treaties. See David J. Scheffer, Use of Force After the Cold War: Panama, Iraq,
and the New World Order, in LOUIS HENKIN ET AL., RIGHT V. MIGHT: INTERNATIONAL LAW
AND THE USE OF FORCE 109, 121–22 (1991).
3. See G.A. Res. 240, U.N. GAOR, 44th Sess., at 1, U.N. Doc. A/RES/44/240 (1989);
CP/RES. 534, OAS Permanent Council, OEA/ser. G /P/RES.534 (800/89) corr. 1 (1989).
4. See Abraham D. Sofaer, The Legality of the United States Action in Panama, 29
COLUM. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 281, 288–90 (1991).
5. See Scheffer, supra note 2, at 123.
6. See id.
7. See Domingo E. Acevedo, The Haitian Crisis and the OAS Response: A Test of
Effectiveness in Protecting Democracy, in ENFORCING RESTRAINT: COLLECTIVE INTERVENTION
IN INTERNAL CONFLICTS 119, 141 (Lori Fisler Damrosch ed. 1993).
8. See id. at 132.
9. See id.
10. See CP/RES. 534, OAS Permanent Council, OEA/ser. G /P/RES.534 (800/89) corr. 1
(1989).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
661
Prominent international law scholars tell us that representative government
is an emerging international legal entitlement.11 Historians and political
scientists tell us that democracies almost never make war on other democracies,12 while politicians assert important security interests in the spread of
democratic governance.13 International civil servants proclaim a new
shared consensus that democracy, human rights, and peace are inextricably
linked.14 Heads of state routinely announce their fealty to democratic
norms, and insist that leaders of other states do so as well.15 International
organizations pass resolutions announcing that governmental legitimacy
rests on the consent of the governed, and some condition membership in
the organization on acceptance of democratic principles.16 Even developing
countries, once near-monolithic in their opposition to any external involvement in domestic politics, now commonly seek international legitimacy through external monitoring and even supervision of their electoral
processes.17 Perhaps most remarkable, both the Organization on Security
and Cooperation in Europe (OSCE) and the OAS have pledged to take
11. See Thomas M. Franck, The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance, 86 AM. J.
INT’L L. 46, 47 (1992) (arguing that representative democracy is gradually evolving from moral
prescription to an international legal obligation in part based on custom and in part on the
collective interpretation of treaties); cf. Gregory H. Fox, The Right to Political Participation in
International Law, 17 YALE J. INT’L L. 539, 540–41 (1992) (noting that the number of
democratic governments has increased from nine to over sixty-five countries since the turn of the
century) [hereinafter Fox, Political Participation].
12. See, e.g., Fernando Tesón, The Kantian Theory of International Law, 92 COLUM. L.
REV. 53, 74–81 (1992) [hereinafter Tesón, Kantian Theory]; Michael W. Doyle, Kant, Liberal
Legacies, and Foreign Affairs Part I, 12 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 205, 213 (1983) [hereinafter Doyle,
Part 1]; Michael W. Doyle, Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2, 12 PHIL. &
PUB. AFF. 323, 323 (1983).
13. See, e.g., Text of Address by President Clinton to the 49th U.N. General Assembly,
Sept. 26, 1994, reprinted in FRANK NEWMAN & DAVID WEISSBRODT, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN
RIGHTS: LAW, POLICY & PROCESS 377, 378 (2d ed. 1996).
14. See, e.g., BOUTROS BOUTROS-GHALI, MAINTAINING INTERNATIONAL PEACE AND
SECURITY: THE UNITED NATIONS AS FORUM AND FOCAL POINT (1993), quoted in Gregory H.
Fox & Georg Nolte, Intolerant Democracies, 36 HARV. INT’L L.J. 1, 5 (1995).
15. See Franck, supra note 11, at 47 (noting that “leaders of other democracies around the
world” have aligned themselves against coup leaders).
16. The Council of Europe, for example, makes democracy a pre-condition for membership. See Statute of the Council of Europe, May 5, 1949, art. 3, 87 U.N.T.S. 103, 106. Similarly,
the OAS Charter now provides for the suspension from the General Assembly of any member
state whose “democratically constituted government has been overthrown by force.” See Protocol
of Amendment to the Charter of the Organization of American States, Dec.14, 1992, art. 9, 33
I.L.M. 1005 [hereinafter Protocol of Washington] (while not ratified by all OAS member states
yet, this protocol amends the OAS Charter); Christina M. Cerna, Universal Democracy: An
International Legal Right or the Pipe Dream of the West?, 27 N.Y.U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 289,
293 (1995).
17. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 541; see, e.g., Acevedo, supra note 7,
at 119–20 (noting that the presence of monitors from the OAS and the United Nations legitimized Aristide’s government when he won the election in Haiti). This trend began in 1989, when
the Nicaraguan Government invited both the United Nations and the Organization of American
States to help supervise its electoral process in order to verify the validity of the 1990 elections.
See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 579–80.
662
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
action to reverse unconstitutional seizures of power within democratic
member states.18
Was the United States therefore right, if perhaps premature, to announce democracy’s triumph in 1989 and to suggest that, in some cases,
outside states may legitimately intervene to support democratic outcomes
in internal political contests? Clearly, recent years have witnessed a
dramatic increase in the number, diversity and proportion of states formally committed to democratic principles.19 Many states have also displayed a greater willingness to countenance foreign intervention in the
name of democracy and human rights than at any time in this century.20
But in many respects, the rhetoric in this area has outpaced reality. Although intervention to promote democracy may be more politically
palatable than it was in the recent past,21 no broad right of pro-democratic
intervention has emerged, or is likely to emerge any time soon. There are at
least three reasons why. First, international consensus on the content and
even the desirability of what Professor Tom Franck has labeled the
“democratic entitlement”22 often proves elusive, at least in the context of
particular cases. Second, international law remains strongly antiinterventionist, despite the increasingly common but still largely exceptional cases of Security Council consensus on the need for intervention in
particular cases. Third, practical obstacles, especially a lack of resources
and political will, continue to hamper external efforts to promote democratic governance in undemocratic states. The existence of these problems
should not obscure the importance of recent changes linking democracy to
governmental legitimacy in the international system. However, change in
this area is neither as extensive nor as legitimacy-oriented as many have
suggested.
II.
DISAGREEMENTS ON DEMOCRACY
The international community has long paid lip service to basic principles of democratic governance. However, it has proven extremely difficult
18. See Santiago Commitment to Democracy and the Renewal of the Inter-American
System, OAS General Assembly, 21st Sess., 3d plen. sess., at 1, OEA/ser. P/AG/doc.2734/91
(1991); Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe: Document of the Moscow Meeting
on the Human Dimension, Emphasizing Respect for Human Rights, Pluralistic Democracy, the
Rule of Law, and Procedures for Fact-finding, Oct. 3, 1991, 30 I.L.M. 1670 [hereinafter
Document of the Moscow Meeting]; Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe:
Document of the Copenhagen Meeting of the Conference on the Human Dimension, June 29,
1990, 29 I.L.M. 1305 (1990) [hereinafter Copenhagen Document].
19. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 540.
20. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 141 (recognizing that “the notion that the illegal
replacement of a democratically elected government is still a matter essentially within the
domestic jurisdiction of its member states, and thus immune from international scrutiny, is no
longer the axiomatic precept it once was”).
21. See id.
22. See Franck, supra note 11, at 46.
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
663
to translate this agreement on basic principles into a consensus for prodemocratic intervention in particular cases. In part, this is because at the
global level the principles at issue have been stated at a high level of
generality—high enough to mask important substantive differences among
states on the content of those principles. As a result, large numbers of
states have been able to sign on to international instruments proclaiming
support for democracy and associated values, without any real agreement
on the meaning of democracy or the means by which it should be given
effect. Such differences among states surface when concrete measures are
contemplated in specific cases.
Additionally, even when states agree on the kinds of changes necessary to initiate or restore democracy in a particular country, they may
disagree sharply on the role the international community should play in
seeking such changes. Such differences reflect strong philosophical and
political differences over the extent to which external actors may legitimately seek changes in the domestic politics of other states. In practice,
therefore, cases in which broad international agreement on intervention can
be achieved are the exception rather than the rule.
Within the U.N. system, broad statements in support of democratic
governance date back to 1948, when the U.N. adopted the Universal
Declaration on Human Rights by consensus.23 Article 21 of the Declaration
states that “[t]he will of the people shall be the basis of the authority of
government,” and that “this will shall be expressed in periodic and genuine
elections.”24 Implicitly, then, Article 21 links governmental legitimacy to
respect for the popular will. But this linkage does not appear in the subsequent, and legally binding, International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights (ICCPR).25 Article 25 of the Covenant speaks of the right to
participate in public affairs—including the right to genuine and periodic
elections—but it does not purport to condition governmental authority on
respect for the will of the people.26 The language of Article 25 was
intentionally drafted broadly enough to accommodate the wide range of
governmental systems in place among the initial parties to the Covenant.27
As a result, even Soviet-bloc states felt free to ratify the Covenant.28 From
their perspective, communist states satisfied the requirements of Article 25
by affording voters access to various participatory mechanisms as well as
an opportunity to ratify their leadership in periodic, albeit single-party,
23. See Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A(III), U.N. Doc. A/810
(1948).
24. Id. art. 21.
25. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Dec. 16, 1966, 999 U.N.T.S. 171,
6 I.L.M. 368.
26. Id. art. 25.
27. See Henry J. Steiner, Political Participation as a Human Right, 1 HARV. HUM. RTS.
Y.B. 77, 87–88, 90, 93 (1988).
28. See id. at 91 (noting that an amendment requiring a pluralist political party system was
withdrawn as a concession to the Soviet Union).
664
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
elections.29 Thus, the cost of consensus was language broad enough to
obscure sharp differences among states on the nature of their commitment
to democratic rule.
During the Cold War, it was nearly impossible for the international
community as a whole to agree both that a particular state was undemocratic and that international action should be taken against that state. The
single exception concerned the process of decolonization. A consensus
gradually developed within the U.N. that the denial of majority self-rule in
the colonial territories of Africa and Asia should be treated as an international delict.30 When white minority regimes in South Africa and elsewhere
resisted the transition to majority rule, states could agree, within the
context of the U.N. system, to apply economic and diplomatic sanctions.31
By defining apartheid regimes as per se violative of international law,32
states could treat the character of the white minority governments as a
legitimate subject for international action, without exposing all undemocratic regimes to similar scrutiny and pressure.
Outside of the decolonization context, however, there was little international consensus on the requirements of democratic governance beyond
the general but limited insistence on periodic and genuine elections found
in the ICCPR and a number of other international legal instruments. As a
result, states lacked generally accepted criteria by which to judge other
states’ compliance with substantive democratic principles.33
With the end of the bi-polar ideological competition that characterized the Cold War,34 there has been a widely publicized shift in the
character of public pronouncements about democracy. More states have
made, through treaty or by means of non-binding but still influential
declarations, formal commitments to democratic governance.35 In addition,
states, international organizations, human rights tribunals, and legal
scholars have sought increasingly to imbue that commitment with some
real content—to move beyond the simple but vague commitment to free
elections contained in the ICCPR.36
The greatest progress in specifying the elements of democratic governance has been made in regional systems and, in particular, within the
29. See id. at 93.
30. See, e.g., Ibrahim J. Gassama, Reaffirming Faith in the Dignity of Each Human Being:
The United Nations, NGOs, and Apartheid, 19 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 1464, 1472–88 (1996)
(discussing the comprehensive global campaign launched against apartheid in South Africa).
31. See id. at 1480–88.
32. See id. at 1478–80.
33. See Franck, supra note 11, at 80–85 (discussing the problems associated with
examining and monitoring elections for compliance with the existing ambiguous standards).
34. See Fox & Nolte, supra note 14, at 3.
35. See, e.g., Joint Communique of United States-Mexico Binational Commission, Aug. 7,
1989, in 29 I.L.M. 18 (1990); Document of the Moscow Meeting, supra note 18, at 1670.
36. See Fox & Nolte, supra note 14, at 3–5 (1995) (describing efforts of “the international
community to address the perennial question of what makes a state ‘democratic’”).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
665
OSCE.37 At a 1990 meeting in Copenhagen, for example, members of the
OSCE (then referred to as the CSCE) spelled out some of the characteristics of democratic systems and the rule of law.38 This list included: 1) free
elections; 2) the need for representative government; 3) accountability of
the executive to an elected legislature or the electorate as a whole; 4) a
clear separation between the State and political parties; 5) an independent
judiciary; 6) military and police forces under civilian control; and 7) a
panoply of related human rights.39
At the international level, however, support for democracy is still expressed in general terms. Most important, there has been relatively broad
(though by no means uniform) acceptance of the principle that elections
should entail competition among multiple political parties—something
Soviet-bloc states rejected until recently.40 Additionally, substantial
international agreement now exists on many of the procedural and substantive prerequisites for free and fair elections.41
Elections, however, are only part of any democratic system.42 They
may assist in the formation of a government responsive to the popular will,
but they do not guarantee such a government. In many countries, systemic
problems override the positive effects of free elections. In a number of
Latin American states, for example, entrenched militaries, powerful
business elites, lopsided patterns of resource distribution, and a history of
human rights abuses all sharply constrain the ability of elected governments to alter existing political relations.43 In some countries, in Europe
and elsewhere, the problem is just the opposite: elections result in governments that are too responsive to the popular will of an ethnic majority, and
insufficiently attentive, or openly hostile to, minority group interests.44 In
37. Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe: Final Act, Aug. 1, 1975, 14 I.L.M.
1292 [hereinafter Helsinki Accords].
38. Copenhagen Document, supra note 18, at 1305.
39. See id. at paras. 5.1–5.21, at 1308–09.
40. See Roth, supra note 1, at 506–07.
41. Such prerequisites include near-universal adult suffrage, the right to vote in secret and
to have one’s vote counted equally with that of others, the right to campaign, to form political
parties, to express political opinions without interference, to seek and receive information, to
have reasonable access to mass media, and to have an effective remedy for violation of political
and electoral rights.
42. See Franck, supra note 11, at 57 (arguing that the right of self-determination is at the
core of democracy and that freedom of expression and electoral rights are the other two
components); see also Acevedo, supra note 7, at 143 (discussing Professor Franck’s argument);
Cerna, supra note 16, at 295 (stating that “[t]he existence of a democratic form of government
[is] evidenced by fair and free periodic elections, three branches of government, an independent
judiciary, freedom of political expression, equality before the law, and due process”).
43. See Stephen J. Schnably, The Santiago Commitment as a Call to Democracy in the
United States: Evaluating the OAS Role in Haiti, Peru, and Guatemala, 25 U. MIAMI INTER-AM.
L. REV. 393, 518–23 (1994).
44. See Edward D. Mansfield & Jack Snyder, Democratization and War, 74 FOREIGN AFF.
70, 87 (1995).
666
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
still other countries, elected governments abandon democratic principles
after attaining office.45
As yet, no international consensus exists on the best way to deal with
such cases, or even on the criteria that should be used to judge whether or
not a particular government is substantively “democratic.”46 In part, this is
because many states still do not share the West’s enthusiasm for liberal,
parliamentary democracy. Some states, in particular Islamic and Asian
states, view much of the recent rhetoric about democratic governance as a
misplaced attempt to transplant western institutions and structures of
governance to countries with radically different cultural and political
traditions.47 In their view, any attempt to impose a western blueprint for
democracy constitutes nothing short of cultural imperialism.48 Accordingly, although many such states have joined halfheartedly in the promulgation of resolutions and declarations proclaiming support for democracy
and the right of political participation,49 they also stress that each state has
the “sovereign right freely to choose and develop its political, social,
economic and cultural systems, whether or not they conform to the
preferences of other states.”50
Even within regional systems with a relatively strong commitment to
democratic government, evaluation of actual cases may prove very
difficult.51 The problem is particularly acute in the case of new or emerging
democracies attempting to overcome a long legacy of authoritarian
mismanagement in a climate of economic decline and political instability.52
45. See Robert I. Rotberg, Democracy in Africa: The Ballot Doesn’t Tell All, CHRISTIAN
SCI. MONITOR, May 1, 1996, at 19.
46. See Brad R. Roth, Evaluating Democratic Progress: A Normative Theoretical
Approach, 9 ETHICS & INT’L AFF. 55 (1995).
47. Cf. Ann Elizabeth Mayer, Universal Rights Versus Islamic Rights: A Clash of Cultures
or a Clash with a Construct?, 15 MICH. J. INT’L L. 307, 318 (1994) (citing statements by
representatives of Islamic governments to the 1993 Human Rights Conference in Vienna).
48. See id.; Jim Mann, Policy-Makers Race to Keep Up with New Asia, L.A. TIMES, July
12, 1993, at A1 (quoting President Clinton’s denial that “democracy and human rights are
somehow unsuited to parts of Asia or that they mask some cultural imperialism on the part of the
West”).
49. See, e.g., Daniel A. Bell, The East Asian Challenge to Human Rights: Reflections on an
East West Dialogue, 18 HUM. RTS. Q. 641, 656 (1996) (noting that most East Asian states
endorsed the Universal Declaration on Human Rights “for pragmatic, political reasons and not
because of a deeply held commitment to the human rights norms it contains”).
50. G.A. Res. 150, U.N. GAOR 3d Comm., 45th Sess., Supp. No. 49A, at 255, U.N. Doc.
A/45/766 (1990).
51. For example, the states of the European Union (then the EC) agreed on criteria for
recognizing new and emerging states in the former Soviet Union and Eastern Europe. See
Declaration on the Guidelines on the Recognition of New States in Eastern Europe and in the
Soviet Union, EPC Press Release 128/91 (Dec. 16, 1991), reprinted in 31 I.L.M. 1486, 1486–87
(1992). Those states then failed to follow the criteria in decisions concerning the recognition of
Croatia and Macedonia. Compare id., with Declaration on Yugoslavia and on the Guidelines on
the Recognition of New States, reprinted in 31 I.L.M. 1485, 1485–86 (1992).
52. See Mansfield & Snyder, supra note 44, at 88–94 (describing problems experienced by
newly democratizing states); Richard Falk, The Haiti Intervention: A Dangerous World Order
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
667
In the states of the former Soviet Union, for example, it is relatively easy to
make judgments about whether national elections have been fairly conducted.53 It is much harder to assess the extent to which those states can
reasonably be characterized as democratic, and harder still to predict the
consequences of taking action on the basis of such evaluations.
Even when states can agree on the character of a particular state’s
government, they may disagree strongly on the approach the international
community should take to dealing with that government.54 Many states
remain firmly convinced that the character of a state’s government is
fundamentally a matter of domestic concern.55 Some states, however,
acknowledge that democratic governance has become a subject of international commitments and therefore of international concern, but believe
strongly that change should be effected through dialogue and negotiation
rather than through coercive measures.56 Still other states, such as Mexico,
are willing to countenance the use of limited coercive measures in exceptional cases, but nonetheless strongly oppose military intervention on the
ground that it is almost invariably “traumatic,” subject to abuse, and often
ineffective in attaining its objective.57
As a result of these differences among states, departures from democratic principles are likely to prompt a significant collective international
response only in exceptional circumstances. When an elected government
is overthrown by overtly anti-democratic forces, it is clear that international norms have been violated, and international condemnation can be
anticipated.58 On rare occasions, as in Haiti, it may even prove possible for
states to agree on coercive measures to restore the ousted government to
power.59 But in general, easy cases of the sort represented by Haiti are
likely to be few and far between.
Precedent for the United Nations, 36 HARV. INT’L L.J. 341, 352–53 (1995) (recognizing Haiti’s
still fragile state due to the acute poverty plaguing 90 percent of all Haitians).
53. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 570 (listing four criteria used to
judge whether an election is “free, fair and legally sufficient: 1) universal and equal suffrage; 2)
secret ballots; 3) regularly scheduled elections; and 4) no discrimination based on certain voters,
parties, or candidates”).
54. See generally Lori Fisler Damrosch, Politics Across Borders: Nonintervention and
Nonforcible Influence Over Political Affairs, 83 AM. J. INT’L L. 1 (1989) (discussing the debate
over foreign intervention: when and how it should be done).
55. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 590–91.
56. See Damrosch, supra note 54, at 4.
57. See Verbatim Record of the Security Council Proceedings, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess.,
3413th mtg. at 4, U.N. Doc. S/PV.3413 (1994) [hereinafter Security Council Proceedings, July
31, 1994] (statement of Mr. Flores Olea articulating Mexico’s opposition to military intervention
in Haiti).
58. Cf. Tesón, Kantian Theory, supra note 12, at 68 (arguing that “the right to resist
tyranny is extremely important in international law”).
59. See Report of the Secretary-General on the United Nations Mission in Haiti, U.N.
SCOR, 49th Sess., at 3, U.N. Doc. S/1994/828 (1994) [hereinafter Haiti Report].
668
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
III. LEGAL CONSTRAINTS ON INTERVENTION
When states and international organizations decide that a threat to or
absence of democracy in a particular state warrants a response, they have a
wide range of tools from which to choose. The available tools range from
diplomatic pressure to economic sanctions to military intervention.60 The
international legality of the response will depend on the tool chosen and
the authority under which it is employed.61
In general, measures which do not entail coercion, or that are undertaken with the consent of the affected state, do not amount to prohibited
intervention under international law.62 Thus, external actors are free to
assist incumbent governments in carrying out agreed measures to institute
or strengthen democratic practices, particularly in the electoral arena, and
free to criticize states that do not employ such practices.63 Indeed, states
seeking to end internal conflicts or to obtain international approval now
routinely accept and solicit international assistance to supervise and
monitor national elections,64 even though some states still regard the
presence of international observers as an affront to state sovereignty.65 In
addition, states may place conditions on diplomatic recognition, trade,
financial or military assistance, loans, airline landing rights, visas, and
numerous other benefits based on the character of another state’s government. Although many states bitterly object to such conditions, states are
generally free in international law to give or withhold such benefits as they
see fit, in the absence of contrary international agreements.66 More coercive measures, such as withdrawal of favorable trade treatment and total
trade embargoes, are more controversial, but such measures are generally
deemed legitimate when directed toward encouraging compliance with
human rights norms—including the right of political participation.67
60. See Damrosch, supra note 54, at 28–34, 47–48.
61. See id. at 30–31.
62. See id.
63. See id. at 13–28 (discussing the appropriateness of foreign support of domestic political
parties and candidates).
64. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 541.
65. See id. at 590–91.
66. See Damrosch, supra note 54, at 28–31 (noting that state practice “suggest[s] that
affirmative economic leverage to influence political developments [in other states] is legitimate”); see also Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.),
1986 I.C.J. 4, 116 (1986) (stating, with reference to the U.S. decisions to terminate aid to
Nicaragua, reduce its sugar quota, and impose a trade embargo, that the Court “is unable to
regard such action on the economic plane as is here complained of as a breach of the customarylaw principle of non-intervention”).
67. See Damrosch, supra note 54, at 31–34, 42–44 (arguing that economic sanctions are
permissible if “directed at enhancing internationally protected rights”); see also RESTATEMENT
(THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW OF THE UNITED STATES § 703 cmt. f (1987) (“A state
may . . . shape its trade, aid or other national policies so as to dissociate itself from [a state
violating international human rights standards] or to influence that state to discontinue the
violations.”).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
669
By contrast, measures involving the use of force must be authorized
by the Security Council in response to a threat to international peace and
security, unless consent of the recognized government is obtained.68 The
issue here is whether and under what circumstances the Security Council
may treat a particular government’s failure to respect human rights or
democracy as a threat to international peace grave enough to warrant a
collective response.
In recent years, the Security Council has authorized military intervention to restore democracy in Haiti,69 end the repression of Kurds in Iraq,70
curb famine in Somalia,71 stop ethnic cleansing in Bosnia,72 and limit
genocide in Rwanda.73 In each of these cases, the Council cited a threat to
international peace as the principal legal justification for intervention.74
The existence of internal disorder in these cases, with the exception of
Bosnia, did not entail the kind of “aggressive use of force across a boundary” traditionally understood to constitute a threat to international peace.75
This has prompted a debate within legal circles as to whether, in any of
these cases, the Council has exceeded its authority under the U.N. Charter,
or whether the Council effectively has unlimited discretion to determine
the existence of a threat to the peace based solely on political criteria.76
68. See U.N. CHARTER art. 42; see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS
LAW OF THE UNITED STATES § 703 cmt. g (1987). “The U.N. Charter renounces intervention ‘in
matters essentially within the domestic jurisdiction’ of Member States, unless issues of
international peace and security are present.” Falk, supra note 52, at 342.
69. See S.C. Res. 940, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/940
(1994).
70. See S.C. Res. 688, U.N. SCOR, 46th Sess., 2982d mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/688
(1991).
71. See S.C. Res. 794, U.N. SCOR, 47th Sess., 3145th mtg. at 3, U.N. Doc. S/RES/794
(1992).
72. See, e.g., S.C. Res. 770, U.N. SCOR, 47th Sess., 3106th mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc.
S/RES/770 (1992); S.C. Res. 816, U.N. SCOR, 48th Sess., 3191st mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc.
S/RES/816 (1993).
73. See S.C. Res. 929, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3392d mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/929
(1994).
74. See S.C. Res. 940, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/940
(1994); S.C. Res. 929, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3392d mtg. at 1, U.N. Doc. S/RES/929 (1994);
S.C. Res. 816, U.N. SCOR, 48th Sess., 3191st mtg. at 1, U.N. Doc. S/RES/816 (1993); S.C. Res.
794, U.N. SCOR, 47th Sess., 3145th mtg. at 1, U.N. Doc. S/RES/794 (1992); S.C. Res. 770,
U.N. SCOR, 47th Sess., 3106th mtg. at 1, U.N. Doc. S/RES/770 (1992); S.C. Res. 688, U.N.
SCOR, 46th Sess., 2982d mtg. at 1–2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/688 (1991).
75. See Falk, supra note 52, at 342 n.3.
76. See W. Michael Reisman, Comment, The Constitutional Crisis in the United Nations,
87 AM. J. INT’L L. 83, 93 (1993) (questioning whether there are any substantive limits on the
Security Council when it is operating under Chapter VII, and finding the Council’s application of
the term “threat to the peace” to be “quite elastic”); Vera Gowlland-Debbas, The Relationship
Between the International Court of Justice and the Security Council in the Light of the Lockerbie
Case, 88 AM. J. INT’L L. 643, 671 (1994) (arguing that the Council is constrained by Charter
provisions, but that its finding of a threat to the peace will be challenged only in the event of “a
manifest irregularity or abuse of power”). See generally Jose E. Alvarez, Judging the Security
670
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
However that question might be answered as a matter of law,77 it appears in
practice that in almost any case of significant internal disorder, there will
be sufficient transboundary effects to permit the Council to find a plausible
threat to the peace if it wishes to authorize intervention.
It does not follow, however, that the Council will utilize its power to
authorize intervention with any frequency. Although the flurry of Councilauthorized military interventions in the last six years has led some commentators to celebrate (or lament) the Council’s apparent willingness to
intervene on behalf of human rights or democracy,78 the reality is that the
Council remains extremely reluctant to authorize intervention against the
will of a sitting government or to rely on humanitarian motives as the basis
for installing a particular government or defeating a particular party to an
internal conflict.79 U.N.-authorized military intervention in Rwanda and
Somalia came only after the incumbent governments, each with an appalling human rights record, had collapsed.80 Similarly, the U.N. arms embargo on Liberia post-dated the fall of the notorious Doe government by
two years.81 The United States and its allies did intervene to protect Iraqi
Council, 90 AM. J. INT’L L. 1, 2–4 (1996) (discussing the debate between “realists,” who oppose
the idea of judicial review of the Council’s actions, and “legalists,” who favor such review).
77. In Prosecutor v. DuŠko Tadi, Decision on the Defense Motion on Jurisdiction, the
trial chamber of the International Tribunal for the Prosecution of Persons Responsible for Serious
Violations of International Humanitarian Law Committed in the Territory of Former Yugoslavia
held that the question of the Security Council’s authority to determine the existence of a threat to
the peace was non-justiciable. See Prosecutor v. Du©ko Tadi: Decision on Defense Motion for
Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction, IT-94-1-AR72, at 6 (Oct. 2, 1991) [hereinafter Tadi
Decision], reprinted in 35 I.L.M. 32, 39 (1996) (“[T]he question whether the Security Council in
establishing the International Tribunal complied with the United Nations Charter raises ‘political
questions’ which are ‘non-justiciable.’”). The Appeals Chamber of the Tribunal disagreed. It
held that the issue was justiciable, and that the Security Council does not have “totally unfettered
discretion” to determine the existence of a threat to the peace. See Tadi Decision, supra, at 16–
17, reprinted in 35 I.L.M at 44. The Appellate Chamber found that such a determination must
“remain, at the very least, within the limits of the Purposes and Principles of the Charter.” Id. at
14, reprinted in 35 I.L.M at 43. Nonetheless, the Appellate Chamber had no trouble finding the
existence of a threat to the peace sufficient to warrant the establishment of the International
Tribunal, noting in part that even if the conflict in the former Yugoslavia “were considered
merely as an ‘internal armed conflict’, it would still constitute a ‘threat to the peace’ according to
the settled practice of the Security Council and the common understanding of the United Nations
membership in general.” Id.
78. Compare Fernando R. Tesón, Collective Humanitarian Intervention, 17 MICH. J. INT’L
L. 323, 370–71 (1996) (defending the legitimacy of interventionary policies), with Falk, supra
note 52, at 342–43 (arguing that interventionary initiatives are problematic at best and criticizing
their use in foreign policy).
79. See David Wippman, Change and Continuity in Legal Justification for Military
Intervention in Internal Conflict, 27 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. 435, 471–74 (1996).
80. See S.C. Res. 929, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3392d mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/929 (1994);
S.C. Res. 794, U.N. SCOR, 47th Sess., 3145th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/794 (1992).
81. See David Wippman, Enforcing the Peace: ECOWAS and the Liberian Civil War, in
ENFORCING RESTRAINT, supra note 7, at 157, 168, 173.
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
671
Kurds against the established government,82 but the legal basis for that
intervention was tenuous at best, rendering it of little precedential value.83
In Bosnia, the U.N. authorized the use of force to deliver humanitarian aid
and to protect designated safe areas, but the authorization was directed
primarily at the Bosnian Serbs, not at the Bosnian government.84
Only in Haiti has the U.N. actually authorized military intervention
against a sitting government.85 But Haiti is an exceptional case. The U.N.’s
supervision of the 1990 elections gave the international community a stake
in restoring Aristide to office.86 Additionally, the military’s human rights
violations, the misery caused by U.N. sanctions, and U.S. concern over
refugee flows all combined to create pressure on the Security Council to
authorize the use of force.87 Even so, there was considerable opposition
within the U.N. to the proposed intervention.88 Indeed, even within the
OAS, which took prompt action to impose economic sanctions on Haiti
following the coup,89 many OAS member states were strongly opposed to
the use of force.90
Thus, the Haitian precedent is a limited one. Few other cases are
likely to generate as vigorous a response. It is therefore not surprising, for
example, that Nigeria’s refusal to seat the elected government of Mashood
82. See Jane E. Stromseth, Iraq’s Repression of its Civilian Population: Collective
Responses and Continuing Challenges, in ENFORCING RESTRAINT, supra note 7, at 85–90.
83. See id. at 91; S.C. Res. 688, U.N. SCOR, 46th Sess., 2982d mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/688
(1991). The United States claimed that Security Council Resolution 688, which demanded that
the Iraqi Government allow a humanitarian mission to provide relief aid to Iraqi Kurds, provided
the legal space necessary for the intervention. See Stromseth, supra note 82, at 91. However, the
U.S. interpretation of Resolution 688 was somewhat farfetched. Certainly, the Security Council
never directly authorized military intervention against the Iraqi government on humanitarian
grounds. See id. Moreover, the Secretary-General insisted that any effort to provide relief to the
Kurds required the consent of the Iraqi government, which was ultimately forthcoming. See id.
84. See, e.g., S.C. Res. 819, U.N. SCOR, 48th Sess., 3199th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/819
(1993) (establishing Srebrenica as a “safe area,” and demanding the “immediate cessation of
armed attacks by Bosnian Serb paramilitary units against Srebrenica”).
85. See Cerna, supra note 16, at 319.
86. See id. at 315. During this period, the OAS and the U.N. were called upon more often
to monitor elections in various nations. See id. Thus, the military coup obviating the results of the
Haitian elections clearly called for international action. See id.
87. See, e.g., Schnably, supra note 43, at 483–88 (discussing the role of sanctions in
worsening the economic plight of Haiti’s poor); Acevedo, supra note 7, at 134–35 (commenting
on U.S. actions prompted by the prospect of a massive influx of Haitian refugees).
88. This opposition is reflected in the debate preceding adoption of Resolution 940. See
generally Security Council Proceedings, July 31, 1994, supra note 57 (recording the discussion
concerning the necessity of military intervention in Haiti).
89. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 133.
90. See generally Security Council Proceedings, July 31, 1994, supra note 57 (recording
the statements of representatives from Mexico, Cuba, Uruguay, Venezuela, and Brazil—all
opposed to military intervention—during debate in the Security Council).
672
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
Abiola, although it generated considerable criticism and limited sanctions,
has not produced any concerted or effective international response.91
In many respects, what the U.N. did not do in Haiti is as important legally as what it did do. Most important, the U.N. did not adopt any
generally applicable test of democratic legitimacy as a basis for disregarding a government’s right to speak for the state on questions of intervention.
The international community’s response to the military’s forcible overthrow of Haitian President Jean-Bertrand Aristide did, at least initially, call
into question the authority of the de facto government to oppose external
intervention.92 Both the OAS and the U.N. refused to recognize the
military authorities as the government of Haiti, and both continued to
recognize President Aristide and his designated representatives as “the
only legitimate representatives” of that Government.93 Since military
intervention with the consent of the recognized government is not unlawful, it could be argued that Aristide, acting unilaterally, possessed the
power to authorize external military intervention to remove the usurpers.
But when the U.N. Security Council finally authorized military intervention to restore Aristide to power, it relied primarily on its authority to
maintain international peace under Chapter VII of the Charter.94 The
authorizing resolution took note of Aristide’s consent to intervention,95 but
the Security Council was evidently unwilling to treat that consent as
sufficient in and of itself to permit military action.96 This may be attributable in part to the grudging character of Aristide’s consent. More important, though, is the fact that international law continues to place
91. See Makau Wa Mutua, The Politics of Human Rights: Beyond the Abolitionist
Paradigm in Africa, 17 MICH. J. INT’L L. 591, 613 n.47 (1996) (noting only the protests of human
rights groups and pro-democracy advocates following the military coup).
92. See S.C. Res. 940, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/940 (1994);
see also Support to the Democratic Government of Haiti, MRE/RES. 1, Ad Hoc Meeting of
Ministers of Foreign Affairs, OEA/ser. F/V.1 (1991) [hereinafter Ministers of Foreign Affairs
Resolution 1/91].
93. See Ministers of Foreign Affairs Resolution 1/91, supra note 92; The Situation of
Human Rights and Democracy in Haiti, U.N. GAOR, 46th Sess., Agenda Item 145, at 2, U.N.
Doc. No. A/46/L.8/rev.1 (1991).
94. See S.C. Res. 940, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/940
(1994) (“[d]etermining that the situation in Haiti continues to constitute a threat to peace and
security in the region,” and authorizing “Member States . . . to use all necessary means to
facilitate” the restoration of the Aristide government).
95. The resolution cited two letters, one from Aristide (S/1994/905, annex) and another
from Haiti’s Permanent Representative to the U.N. (S/1994/910). See id. Both letters implicitly
supported U.N.-authorized military intervention. See id.
96. In adopting Resolution 940, the Security Council considered the options outlined in the
Report of the Secretary-General on the United Nations Mission in Haiti. See S.C. Res. 940, U.N.
SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg., U.N. Doc. S/RES/940 (1994). In that report, the SecretaryGeneral states that an expanded U.N. force should operate with the consent of the legitimate
authorities in Haiti, but also notes that such a force “would have to use coercive means in order
to fulfil its mandate,” and that it would therefore “be necessary for the Security Council to act
under Chapter VII of the Charter in authorizing its mandate.” Haiti Report, supra note 59, at 3.
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
673
considerable importance on effective control as an indicator of a government’s authority to act in the name of the state.97
If the Security Council seriously believed that Aristide constituted the
only legitimate authority in Haiti and relied on Aristide’s consent as a
sufficient basis in itself for military intervention, that would have signaled
a significant shift in international law. It would have severed, at least in
part, the link between a government’s control of territory and its right to
represent the state in international affairs. Under that approach, any state
could use coercive measures to aid a deposed democratic government. But
the Security Council did not pursue this avenue—presumably because of
the risks of abuse associated with such an approach.
Alternatively, the Security Council could have pressed further the
connection between democracy and peace. It is now popular to claim that
the two are inextricably linked.98 In this vein, the Security Council could
have declared the unconstitutional overthrow of an elected government to
be automatically, or at least presumptively, a threat to the peace.99 Instead,
the Council did just the opposite: it chose to emphasize the fact that Haiti
was a “unique” case.100 In short, the Council did its best to minimize the
precedential significance of the Haitian intervention.
Overall, the recent interventions in Haiti, Rwanda, Somalia, and Iraq,
though dramatic, have had relatively little effect on contemporary international law. Coercive measures, whether to promote democracy or human
rights, still require Security Council authorization. Such authorization,
though far easier to obtain now than it was six or seven years ago, is still
and will likely continue to be the exception rather than the norm.
IV. PRACTICAL CONSTRAINTS ON INTERVENTION
Even when the conceptual and legal obstacles to intervention can be
surmounted, cases of coercive intervention to promote democracy are still
likely to be few and far between. First, formal institutional structures for
the promotion of democracy are weak, and are likely to remain so for the
foreseeable future.101 Second, only extraordinary cases are likely to
generate the international political will required to challenge a determined
indigenous elite unwilling to relinquish political power.102 Third, it is
97. See Fox, Political Participation, supra note 11, at 600–01.
98. See, e.g., Tesón, Kantian Theory, supra note 12, at 74–81; Doyle, Part 1, supra note
12, at 213.
99. C.f. S.C. Res. 940, U.N. SCOR, 49th Sess., 3413th mtg. at 2, U.N. Doc. S/RES/940
(1994) (calling the situation a “threat to peace and security in the region”).
100. See id. at 2.
101. Cf. W. Michael Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention and Fledgling Democracies, 18
FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 794, 796 (1995) [hereinafter Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention]
(suggesting that until the U.N.’s 1995 involvement in Haiti, its commitment to democracy had
been somewhat “rhetorical”).
102. See, e.g., Acevedo, supra note 7, at 132 (describing the OAS response to a Haitian
military coup as “the strongest resolution the OAS had adopted against any government”).
674
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
extremely difficult to calibrate existing tools for coercing state behavior to
produce the desired ends without imposing unacceptable costs on the very
people intervention is designed to help.103 And fourth, prospects for
success in such cases are uncertain at best. For all these reasons, drastic
measures such as economic embargoes and military intervention are likely
to be rare. Instead, efforts to promote democracy in other states are likely
to take other forms, including, most notably, continued efforts by international organizations and individual states to condition access to various
benefits on good governance, broadly defined.
A.
Institutional Mechanisms for the Promotion of Democracy
The U.N., the OSCE, and the OAS all have subsidiary organs devoted
to promoting the spread of democracy. These organs lack enforcement
powers, however. They are designed essentially to provide technical
assistance to states that request it.104 Decisions that might amount to
intervention under international law are left to the political organs of each
organization.105
Within the U.N. there is no special set of institutional procedures for
handling interruptions in democratic governance, much less for addressing
undemocratic regimes generally. As a result, any effort to promote democracy through the political organs of the U.N. is subject to all the vagaries of
U.N. politics.
The procedures within the OSCE are little better—and in some ways
worse. The Moscow and Copenhagen documents commit the member
states, morally if not legally, to “defend and protect” the “democratic
order” in any participating state against a violent overthrow.106 But the
steps to be taken are not specified, not even to the extent of outlining the
institutional procedures to be followed to determine what those steps
should be. Although one author has argued that the Copenhagen Document
implicitly authorizes military intervention to protect democracy,107 it seems
unlikely that the signatories would interpret it this way. In any event,
OSCE decision making requires a consensus among the participating
103. See, e.g., id. at 143 (describing how economic sanctions intended to punish coup
leaders in Haiti had the most severe impact on the poorest Haitians rather than on the perpetrators
of the coup).
104. See Cerna, supra note 16, at 327; see also M. Margaret Ball, THE OAS IN TRANSITION
494 (1969) (noting that the OAS committee responsible for promoting democracy had some right
of initiative, but was precluded from acting without the assent of the state directly involved).
105. See, e.g., U.N. CHARTER art. 2, para. 7 (refusing to allow intervention in a state’s
internal affairs except in response to threats to peace and acts of aggression as defined in Chapter
VII of the U.N. Charter).
106. See Copenhagen Document, supra note 18, at para. 6, 1309 (mandating that the
participating states defend democracy); cf. Document of the Moscow Meeting, supra note 18, at
1677–78, para. 18 (affirming their dedication to democratic principles).
107. See Malvina Halberstam, The Copenhagen Document: Intervention in Support of
Democracy, 34 HARV. INT’L L. J. 163, 166–67 (1993).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
675
states,108 thus greatly limiting the likelihood of coercive action by the
organization in response to any but the gravest political upheavals in a
member state.
Among international organizations, the OAS alone has developed at
least minimal procedures for responding to an unconstitutional seizure of
power within a member state.109 In such cases, the OAS Permanent Council
must meet “to examine the situation, decide on and convene an ad hoc
meeting of the Ministers of Foreign Affairs, or a special session of the
General Assembly, all of which must take place within a ten-day period.”110 Although the steps to be taken are not specified, the requirement
of a meeting by itself puts the organization under some pressure to do more
than simply issue toothless condemnations. Additionally, a recent amendment to the OAS Charter authorizes the organization to suspend the
participation of a state whose democratic government has been forcibly
ousted.111 It seems probable that the existence of even these modest
institutional procedures facilitated the rapid OAS condemnations of the
auto golpes in Peru and Guatemala, and the initiation of economic and
political sanctions against the Haitian military.112
Nonetheless, the OAS is constrained by the non-intervention provisions of its Charter113 and even more by the continued opposition of many
of its members to anything that might open the door too widely to intervention in their internal affairs.114 Moreover, the OAS can only authorize and
recommend coercive sanctions; it cannot legally compel its own members,
much less other states, to implement such sanctions.115
108. See Helinski Accords, supra note 37, 14 I.L.M. at 1293.
109. See Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention, supra note 101, at 795–96 (noting that “the
Santiago Declaration of the Organization of American States . . . has committed the members of
the OAS to some regional action when a democracy has been overthrown”).
110. Res. 1080, OAS General Assembly, 5th Plen. Sess., OEA/ser. P/XXI.O.2 (1991).
111. See Protocol of Washington, supra note 16, at 1005.
112. See Schnably, supra note 43, at 416 (noting the OAS’s condemnation of coups in Peru,
Guatemala, and Haiti). The OAS foreign ministers “strongly deplore[d]” the coup in Peru, and
demanded that Peru return to democracy within six weeks. See id. at 462 (quoting Support for
the Restoration of Democracy in Peru, M.R.E. Res. 1, OAS Ad Hoc Meeting of Ministers of
Foreign Affairs, OEA/ser. F/V.2, paras. 1, 8 (1992)). Similarly, the OAS issued an “urgent
response” and condemnation of the Guatemalan coup. See id. at 473. Finally, the OAS sanctions
against Haiti included “suspension of all diplomatic relations with the military government, an
end to economic and military aid to Haiti, and a break in all commercial ties.” Id. at 420.
113. See Charter of the Organization of American States, Apr. 30, 1948, 2 U.S.T. 2394, 119
U.N.T.S. 3, as amended by the Protocol of Buenos Aires in 1967 and the Protocol of Cartegena
in 1985, art. 3(e), 33 I.L.M. 987, 990 (in force as of November 16, 1988). For a more recent
integrated text of the OAS Charter, including the 1993 amendments from the Protocol of
Managua, see Charter of the Organization of American States, OAS Permanent Council,
OEA/ser. G CP/INF.3964/96 (prov. ed. 1996) (entered into force Jan. 29, 1996).
114. See Ball, supra note 104, at 52 (noting that most of the OAS members rejected any
attempt to authorize collective action in response to domestic tyranny).
115. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 136.
676
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
At present, there is simply no consensus, within the OAS or within
other international organizations, on strengthening significantly their
institutional capacity to promote democracy and to respond to unconstitutional seizures of power with coercive measures. OAS members remain
divided on the extent to which they are willing to tolerate departures from
the organization’s traditional emphasis on non-intervention.116 Division
within the U.N. on intervention to promote democracy is even greater. Any
substantial departure from present practice must survive the critical
scrutiny of veto-wielding states such as China and Russia117 as well as
potentially hostile regional blocs in the Middle East and Asia. The prospects for enhanced procedures are brightest in the OSCE. However, those
prospects are still not very bright, given the organization’s emphasis on
consensus decision making.
B.
Political and Resource Limitations
The biggest potential obstacle to successful intervention to promote
democracy is the difficulty of generating the necessary political will. A
coup in a politically marginal state may have little direct impact on states
outside the immediate vicinity.118 But a decision to intervene implicates the
interests of virtually all states—most of which wish to limit carefully the
situations under which coercive measures can be employed in international
relations and view coercive efforts to promote democracy with skepticism
or hostility.119 In many cases, states whose cooperation is essential to
successful employment of coercive measures may find that their own
economic or security interests militate against cooperation. In the case of
Haiti, for example, many European states continued to trade with Haiti
even after the OAS called for a trade embargo, arguing that they were
obligated to do so because of prior trade commitments.120 Military intervention poses even greater obstacles. To obtain Security Council authorization for such intervention in Haiti, the United States and its allies on that
issue had to engage in a delicate mix of political pressure and political deal
116. See Schnably, supra note 43, at 400 n.18 (discussing the division in OAS members’
sentiments toward OAS action in the event of a coup; for example, a 1962 OAS proposal to
authorize intervention was approved by thirteen nations but blocked by Mexico, Argentina, and
Chile).
117. See U.N. CHARTER art. 23, para. 1 (listing the permanent Security Council Members,
which include China and the former Union of Soviet Socialist Republics).
118. See Shibley Telhami, Is a Standing United Nations Army Possible? Or Desirable?, 28
CORNELL INT’L L.J. 673, 680–81 (1995) (noting that states that border on areas of conflict are
most affected by it).
119. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 137–38 (noting “the continuing view of many governments that the U.N. Charter does not authorize the Security Council to act as enforcer of
democracy”).
120. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 136–37 (listing the countries which “routinely ignored”
the embargo against Haiti by continuing to ship petroleum there; and noting that the United
States, while initially supportive of the embargo, modified its policy because American
businesses were sustaining “severe losses” from the embargo).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
677
making.121 The United States had the incentive to push through an authorizing resolution because it wanted to stem refugee flows and repair the
political damage to the Clinton administration caused by domestic critics
of its Haiti policy.122 Even so, obtaining the necessary authorization was
not easy, and it is not something likely to happen with any frequency.
In addition to the political barriers, military intervention is expensive
in money, in political capital, and often in human lives.123 Most states do
not desire to incur a significant share of the costs and the uncertainties of a
coercive intervention without substantial security or economic interests at
stake.124 As a result, military intervention usually requires the lead of a
committed and powerful state, one that is willing to invest the necessary
resources and to stay long enough to accomplish the goals of intervention.125 However, because promotion of democracy through force may
prove to be a time-consuming and painful venture, few such states will be
willing to risk it with any frequency.
Less coercive measures are much easier to deploy, and will likely be
somewhat more frequent. Thus, it is not improbable, for example, that the
OAS would suspend a member state from participation in the organization
following a coup, or that it would authorize economic sanctions in egregious cases.126 Unfortunately, such measures are often ineffective, and in
the case of economic sanctions, highly destructive.
C.
The Difficulties of Targeted Sanctions
The OAS, with the eventual support of the U.N., employed a wide array of economic sanctions in its efforts to force the Haitian military to
accept the restoration of President Aristide.127 Unfortunately, restrictions
on trade and fuel threatened to hurt many of Haiti’s poorest citizens,128
121. See Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention, supra note 101, at 799 (noting U.S. pressure
on the U.N. for authorization to intervene militarily).
122. See John Sweeney, Stuck in Haiti, 102 FOREIGN POL’Y 143, 150 (1996).
123. See, e.g., David J. Scheffer, Peacekeeping, Peacemaking, & Peacebuilding: The Role of
the United Nations in Global Conflict, 28 CORNELL INT’L L.J. 649, 656 (1995) (noting that a
standing U.N. military force to respond to overthrown governments would be prohibitively
expensive; and relating Rep. Madeleine Albright’s argument that setting aside national troops for
quick response to coups could lead to “high costs with low utility”).
124. See Telhami, supra note 118, at 680 (arguing that “[s]tates are not likely to commit
substantial resources to resolve an international conflict, especially in the military arena, if
important national interests are not at stake”).
125. See Falk, supra note 52, at 354 (arguing that “carrying a commitment to completion
should be a precondition for undertaking [an intervention]”).
126. See Schnably, supra note 43, at 407 (detailing the “diplomatic pressure, trade
embargoes, aid cut-offs, even military intervention” used by the OAS in response to coups in
Haiti, Peru, and Guatemala).
127. See Acevedo, supra note 7, at 132–33.
128. See id. at 143 (describing the “crushing impact” the economic sanctions have had on the
poorest Haitians).
678
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
who were ironically among Aristide’s strongest supporters.129 To make
matters worse, sanctions did more to open up highly lucrative black market
trading opportunities for the Haitian military than they did to force negotiations.130 Recognizing this, the United States and other countries attempted
to find measures that could be more narrowly targeted at the military and
its wealthy supporters. Among other steps, the Clinton Administration
froze the U.S. assets of the military’s supporters, and restricted travel to the
United States to cut off weekend shopping sprees to Miami. But the
military and its supporters had ample time to find ways to circumvent these
restrictions, which in the end did little to achieve their intended goals.131
Unfortunately, the problems encountered in attempting to use economic sanctions in Haiti are not unusual. Such measures almost always fall
most heavily on those members of society least able to bear the consequences and least responsible for the policies that resulted in sanctions in
the first place.132 As a result, there has been a great deal of talk about the
need to find better targeted sanctions for use in future cases. However, the
reality is that effectively targeted sanctions are largely a myth. In most
cases, they are too easy to avoid, and they are unlikely in any event to
outweigh the incentives that lead authoritarian rulers to seize power in the
first place.133
D.
Uncertain Benefits of Intervention
Finally, the benefits of coercive intervention are often uncertain.
Some scholars, relying on arguments associated with political philosopher
John Stuart Mill, claim that democracy cannot be imposed from without,
and that attempts to do so are counterproductive.134 In this view, the
citizens of the state must earn their freedom if it is to be meaningful.135
129. See id.
130. See Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention, supra note 101, at 799 (noting the economic
sanctions created “economic opportunities for the military elite,” and that the military elite
merely “added the contraband business to their narco-traffic portfolios”).
131. For example, the military had time to stockpile oil and other supplies and to find a less
vulnerable place for its assets when economic pressures eased from the end of August to midOctober 1993. See Amy Wilentz, Thwart Haiti’s Thugs with a Naval Blockade, HOUS. CHRON.,
Oct. 14, 1993, at 19B.
132. See Reisman, Humanitarian Intervention, supra note 101, at 803 (noting that economic
sanctions “more often than not . . . severely punish the victims while enriching the villains”).
133. One exception to this arose in connection with the recent “auto-golpe” in Guatemala. In
that case, international sanctions, and the threat they posed to the Guatemalan economy, played
an important role in persuading the military to cooperate in the restoration of constitutional
government. Schnably, supra note 43, at 483.
134. See MICHAEL WALZER, JUST AND UNJUST WARS: A MORAL ARGUMENT WITH
HISTORICAL ILLUSTRATIONS 87–88 (1992) (discussing John Stuart Mill’s argument that a state
may be self-determining even if that state’s people fail to establish free institutions, and that
“[n]o one can, and no one should, do it for them”).
135. See id. at 87 (arguing that “[t]he members of a political community must seek their own
freedom, just as the individual must seek his own virtue”).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
679
Recent experience, however, suggests that the consequences of intervention are variable. In some cases, democracy, or at least multiparty electoral
politics, can be furthered, if not imposed, by external intervention. In other
cases, however, intervention may make a bad situation worse.
In Panama, Grenada, and Haiti, for example, intervention did result in
the substitution of electoral politics for dictatorial rule, and although the
democratic transformation is not complete in any of these countries, each
seems generally to have benefited from intervention.136 In other countries,
such as Liberia and the Central African Republic, intervention may end up
making matters worse. In Liberia, a group of West African states intervened in an attempt to end a destructive civil war and permit formation of a
democratically elected national government.137 Seven years later, however,
war continues to ravage that country138 and, although it is too soon to be
certain, it may be that intervention simply prolonged the conflict to no
good end. In the Central African Republic, France recently intervened to
help suppress an army mutiny against a democratically elected government
which was corrupt and authoritarian once in office.139 In that case, French
intervention seems to have preserved a government that is democratic in
name only, against the will of a substantial majority of the state’s population.
Ultimately, the success of intervention depends on the strength, commitment, and resources of the intervenors and, more importantly, on the
extent to which the leaders and the population of the affected state view the
intervention (and democracy) as in their interest. Factors of this sort are too
subjective to incorporate into a legal rule governing intervention, and must
necessarily be left to the political judgment of the actors who engage in or
authorize intervention. As a result, there is ample room for states skeptical
of the wisdom of pro-democratic intervention to oppose such intervention
on utilitarian grounds in the large majority of cases where intervention
might be suggested.
V.
CONCLUSION
Few will see the international community’s present ambivalent approach to pro-democratic intervention as optimal. For some, the U.N.’s
reluctance to intervene forcefully in the vast majority of those states still
subject to dictatorial rule may represent a failure of political will: a refusal
to shoulder the burden of bringing the benefits of democratic governance
to populations ruled by military thugs and parasitic elites. For others, the
136. See generally Schnably, supra note 43.
137. See David Wippman, supra note 81, at 158 (describing the August 23, 1990 intervention in Liberia by five member states of the Economic Community of West African States).
138. See id. at 158 (noting that “fighting has continued on a sporadic basis” since the 1990
intervention).
139. See Howard W. French, Anger at French Troops Grows in Central Africa, N.Y. TIMES,
May 24, 1996, at A8.
680
HOUSTON JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
[Vol. 19:659
U.N.’s recent willingness to authorize intervention in Haiti, Rwanda,
Somalia, and elsewhere represents a revival of western imperialism: a
cynical pursuit of western economic and strategic interests in the name of
universal values.140
Plainly, both views greatly oversimplify a complex issue. Decisions
about intervention typically reflect a broad constellation of interests. Not
surprisingly, though, the perceived self-interest of the intervening states
tends to predominate, even when those interests are filtered through an
international organization such as the U.N. Many western states now
believe that a policy favoring the extension of democracy and human rights
is the best way to promote both their own security and economic interests
as well as the interests of people in states not yet democratic.141 At the
same time, however, more immediate geostrategic interests often demand
that potential intervenors tolerate or even support governments that are
either undemocratic, or only marginally democratic. Such is the case, for
example, with the attitude of some western states toward the government
of Boris Yeltsin.142 Of necessity, then, attitudes toward pro-democratic
intervention are “awkwardly selective.”143
In some cases, that selectivity may be morally indefensible, but politically inescapable. It is hard, for example, to defend the West’s anemic
response to the civil war in Liberia—but it is easy to explain that response.
Various suggestions have been made for circumventing problems of
selectivity, including, for example, the creation of a standing U.N. intervention force.144 But these ideas hold little appeal for most governments
which, though generally unwilling to intervene themselves, are reluctant to
let others do so for them. The result is that in the rare cases in which
intervention is authorized, it is effectively delegated to the most interested
available actor.145 For the Haitian situation, it was the United States; for the
Rwandan crisis, it was France. Those actors often press for outcomes
which are noted as much for their compatibility with the actors’ own
140. See Falk, supra note 52, at 345 (noting that an influential magazine rejected “the
allegation that interventionary diplomacy was really imperialism carried forward under the
banner of humanitarian intervention”).
141. See id.
142. See Greg McDonald, Ex-Envoy Strauss Tells Clinton to Stand by His Man—Yeltsin,
HOUS. CHRON., Mar. 18, 1993, at 21A (noting former ambassador to Russia Robert Strauss’
advice that the West should support Russia to assist in its continuing economic and political
reforms).
143. Falk, supra note 52, at 345 n.23.
144. For a critical discussion of the prospects for and desirability of creating a standing U.N.
force, see Lamin J. Sise, Illusions of a Standing United Nations Force, 28 CORNELL INT’L L.J.
645 (1995); David J. Scheffer, United Nations Peace Operations and Prospects for a Standing
Force, 28 CORNELL INT’L L.J. 649 (1995); Alex Morrison, The Theoretical and Practical
Feasibility of a United Nations Force, 28 CORNELL INT’L L.J. 661 (1995); Telhami, supra note
118.
145. See Falk, supra note 52, at 356 (describing Haiti’s potential precedent that only the
U.N. member with some “direct interests at stake” will bear the burden of intervention).
1997]
FOREIGN INTERVENTION AND DEMOCRACY
681
interests as for their compatibility with universal norms or the specific
interests of the affected state.146
Even so, recent interventions cannot fairly be characterized as “imperialist.” They do not constitute “the imposition of one country’s power on
another, and the removal of the victim’s freedom.”147 The United States,
for example, may have pressed Aristide to modify his populist policies, but
on balance U.S. intervention did far more to restore than to impair Haitians’ control over their own political destiny. In the absence of much
stronger international organizations than we now have, episodic interventions that on balance benefit the affected state may be the best for which
we can reasonably hope.
146. See, e.g., id. at 356 (noting that U.S. intervention may be due as much to a desire to
preserve a market economy in Haiti as to promote democracy).
147. See id. at 345.