A Finite BCI-algebra of KL-Product: Ahmad Habil
A Finite BCI-algebra of KL-Product: Ahmad Habil
A Finite BCI-algebra of KL-Product: Ahmad Habil
24, No 1, 2008
ABSTRACT
A non-empty set X with a binary operation * and a distinguished element 0 is called a BCI-algebra if the following axioms are satisfied: I) ((x y ) (x z )) (z y ) 0 II) (x (x
Let be X a finite BCI- algebra, it is known that X is of KL- product if and only if the following condition is satisfied:
(a e ) (0 e ) a ;
a X , e L (X )
We present a necessary and sufficient condition for BCI-algebra X to be of KL- product, this condition is pure numerical, that is the number of elements of the row which is opposite to the zero element in the Cayley table of the operation * divides the number of elements in each row of the mentioned table. Key words: BCI- algebra, KL -product.
- KL
BCI
BCII)
X :
((x y ) (x z )) (z y ) 0
II)
(x (x y )) y
III) x x 0 IV) x y :
0, y x
x
- KL
y
.X X
x , y ,z
BCIX
(a e ) (0 e ) a ;
KLBCIX
a X , e L (X )
KL- BCI-
10
Introduction
The notion of BCK- algebras was proposed by Y. Iami and K. Iseki in 1966. In the same year K. Iseki [3] introduced the notion of BCI -algebra, which is a generalization of BCK- algebra. After that, many mathematical papers have been published investigating some algebraic properties of BCK/BCI-algebras and their relationship with other universal structures including lattices and Boolean algebras. 1) - Basic definitions and results Definition (1): A non-empty set X with a binary operation * and a distinguished element 0 is called a BCI - algebra if the following axioms are satisfied for every x , y , z X :
y ) (x z )) (z y ) 0 (x y )) y 0 x 0 y 0, y x 0 x y
Definition (2): A BCI -algebra X is called BCK-algebra if it satisfied: V) 0 x 0 ; x X A partial ordering relation can be defined on BCI -algebra X for some x , y X by: x y if and only if x y 0 Remark: the axioms in definition (1) can be rewriting by using the symbol in the following simpler way: I ) (x II ) III )
y ) (x z ) z y
x (x y ) y
x y
x x IV ) x y , y x
11
V) 0 x ; x
Definition (3):[5] An element a in BCI -algebra X is called an atom if and only if : x a 0 x a ( x X ). Definition (4): [2] A BCI - algebra X is called p-semisimple when the following condition is satisfied: 0 (0 x ) x ( x X ) J. Meng and X. L. Xin [6] introduced the notion of KL-product BCI-algebras. Definition (5): Let X be BCI -algebra. If there exist BCK- algebra Y and p-semisimple BCI -algebra Z such that X Y Z , then X is called BCI -algebra of KL-product. Lemma (1): [7] An element a in BCI - algebra X is an atom if and only if x (x a) a ( x X ) Notation: We shall denote the subset of all atoms in BCI -algebra X by L(X) Lemma (2): [7] Let X be BCI -algebra then L (X ) 0 X . Theorem (1): [7] A BCI -algebra X is of KL- product if and only if it satisfies the condition:
(a e ) (0 e ) a ;
a X , e L (X )
Proposition (1): [4], [1] In any BCI -algebra X the following Proprieties hold for every x , y , z X : (1) x 0 (2) x (x
(x y )) x y (3) (x y ) z (x z ) y (4) (x y ) (z y ) x z
a
2) - Main Results Definition (6): Let X be BCI -algebra, then for any element X the subset T is defined by:
a
T a {x X :a (a x ) x }
12
a X
, then:
(2)
0, a T a
0 (0 x ) x
x 0 X , so T 0
0 X
x 0 X y X ;x 0 y 0 (0 x ) 0 (0 (0 y )) 0 y x
the other inclusion, 0 X (2)(i) a (a 0) a a 0 (ii)
x T 0 , So we have
0 Ta
a (a a) a 0 a
a Ta
a L (X ) T 0 ( a X )
Ta ( x X )
Ta
X Ta
Tx Ta
(6) x T a (7) T
0
T a if a is an atom.
y a (a y )
a X , so we have:
Ta
a X
a X
x X ;y a x
13
a (a y ) a (a (a x )) a x
This implies
y Ta
a X
T a . So, T a a X .
X}
(2) T a {(a x ) a : x a
{(a a) x : x
(3) Let y T a then: y
X}
{0 x : x X } 0 X
x
L (X ) T 0
(a x ) ((a x ) y )
y Therefore we have: a (a y ) y
Ta
Let y
a
y Ta .
T0 Ta
Ta
x X ;z a x .
X then by (3):
Tz
So
T (a
z y
x) y
Ta
Ta .
Ta
T a and T a X
Ta a X
Ta X
x Ta
u X ; x a u.
u
T a , therefore T x
T a.
a L (X ) T 0
Ta
T0.
Ta
T0
Ta
, hence we have: T 0
14
(ii) If T 0
T a then a T 0
0 (0 a) a , so by lemma (2)
a L (X ) . Definition (7): Let X be a BCI- algebra, then for any element a X the subset S is defined by: a
S a {x X : x (x a) a}.
Proposition (3): Let X be a BCI- algebra, then for any elements a,b X we have the following Proprieties: (1) a S
a
(2) (3)
x Sa
Sa Sb
Sx
Sa
Tb T a
(4) S a
S a x for any x X
(5) S X , if a is an atom in X. a (6) S X . 0 (7) If a is not an atom then (X \ S ) X a Proof: (1) We have a (a a) a 0 a (2) Let
X \Sa
a Sa
x S a and
let
y S x then
x (x a ) a
and
15
S b and x T b then b (b x ) x
b Sx
Tb T a
Sb
Sx
Sa
S x , So a S x
x T a Concluding
Sa Sb
Tb T a
0 0 0 0 X
0 is an atom
S0 X .
x
y
Sx
X \ S a which implies (X \ S a ) X
(X \ S a ) X
x x 0 and finally (X \ S ) X X \ S . a a As a consequence of the preceding proposition we can write the following: Corollary (1): In any BCI -algebra X, the following properties are equivalents: (1) S S a b (2) T T
a b
b Sa Ta (4) a S Tb b
(3) Notation: We define a relation x y on BCI - algebra X by: T T .
x y
16
It is clear that is an equivalence relation, and by corollary (1) the equivalence class of an element a X is S T .
a a
Proposition (4): In any BCI - algebra X the function :S T S T ; x a x is well defined and injective,
a a 0 0
a X
Proof: If x S T then: a a
(x ) a x
(x (x a)) x
(x x ) (x a )
0 (x a)
So
a
(x ) 0 X
a
T0 X
T0 S0 T0
Therefore If
is well defined.
Therefore
(3) Card (0*X) divides Card (I) ( I X : I X I) Proof: (1) (2) By proposition (4) the function is well defined and injective. a Also is surjective. a For e S T X T T 0 X L (X )
0 0 0 0
17
e Is an atom Let
a (a e ) e .
x S a because
x (x a) (a e ) ((a e ) a) (a e ) ((a a) e ) (a e ) (0 e )
a
Finally So, for
a
x Sa Ta .
e S0 T 0 we have found
x S a T a such that
is surjective there
exists some x
S a T a such that
(x ) e a (a x ) a e .
a
a (a e ) ((a e ) a) (a e ) ((a a) e ) (a e ) (0 e )
Which prove (1). (2) (3) let I be any subset of X such that I X I , in this case it is easy to see that I is the union of disjoint subsets of the form S T ,
a a
because if a I then:
Ta a X
Sa Ta
so subsets S
a
I X
(S a
, but S T a a where
I.
I
a C
Ta)
18
defined above, so we
a have: Card(S a
Since
Card(I )
= CardC Card(0 X )
Which implies that: Card (0 * X) divides Card (I). (3) (2): If Card (0 * X) divides Card (I) ( I X : I X For any a X we have: T X T
a a
I ) then:
(S a (X \ S a )) T a (S a T a ) ((X \ S a ) T a )
This implies CardT a Or Card(S a
Card(S a T a ) Card((X \ S a ) T a )
T a ) CardT a Card((X \ S a ) T a )
We have tow cases: (i)If a is not an atom then: (X And T X a Hence ((X \ S ) T ) X a a This implies: Card(0*X) [ Card(T ) a
\Sa) X
(X \ S a ) (Proposition 3)
T a (Proposition 2)
(X \ S a ) T a By (3) we have:
Card((X \ S a ) T a ) ]
Card(S 0 T 0 ) Card(S a T a )
Card(S 0 T 0 )
Card(S a T a )
19
is surjective, because it a is an injective function of finite subsets which have the same cardinality. (ii) If a is an atom, we know that S X S by Proposition (3), a 0 by Proposition (2). T T
Card(S a T a ) Card(S 0 T 0 )
Therefore, we have: S a
Ta S0 T0
similarly, as in (i),
is surjective. So is surjective a X , which prove (2). a Which conclude the proof of the theorem. By the preceding theorem and by theorem (1) we have: Corollary (1): A finite BCI - algebra X is of KL- product iff: Card (0 * X) divides Card (I) ( I X : I X I ). Remark: let I be a subset of finite BCI- algebra X such that I X I then we can see that if x I then T x X I , now
x
I
x I
T x Or
j
I Ta Ta
..... T a in
s
such
way
that
Ta
T a whenever i
written. Theorem (3): Let be X a finite BCI - algebra, then the following conditions are equivalents: (1) Card (0 * X) divides Card (I) ( I X : I X I) (2) Card (0 * X) divides Card (0 * X) ( a X ) Proof: (1) (2) Let I T a where a X .
20
By the property (5) of the proposition (2) the subset I satisfies the condition I X I , so, by (1) Card (0 * X) divides Card (I), but I T a X , which is clear by the proposition (2), and condition
a
X n {x
X :Card(T x ) n } ,
for n any natural number, then we have a sequence of natural numbers: n n n .... n .... where we suppose that for
0 1 2 k
any number
nk
X such that:
m n k 1 then there is no
It is clear by propriety (4) of the proposition (2) that Card(T ) n . 0 0 We will prove (1) by induction on k the index of the numbers n . Now, the statement of induction for k-1 is: If I is any subset of Xsuch that: I X I and Card(T x ) nk 1; x I then: Card (0 * X) divides Card (I). Now for k 0 , Suppose that I is a subset of X such that I X I and Card(T ) n ; x I , but T T by proposition (2), so
x 0
Card(T 0 ) Card(T x ) n0 then it is clear that card(T x ) n0 , because the fact mentioned above that Card(T ) n , also we have: T Tx , 0 0 0
I however I
x I
So, Card(T ) divides Card (I), or Card (0 * X) divides Card (I), and 0 the statement of induction is true for k=0. Now, we prove the statement for k: Suppose that I is any subset of Xsuch that I X
I and
21
Card(I )
i
Card(T ) ai
i j
Card(T T ) ai a j
i j k
Card(T T T ) ... ai a j ak
Now it is clear that the first sum is divisible by Card(0 X ) , because this number divides Card(T ), i by (2).
ai
Ta , Ta
j
Ta
Ta ,
k
J Ta
Ta
,
j
which we can do with the remaining subsets in the same way. It is clear by property (5) in the proposition (2) that the subset J Satisfies the condition: J X J and can be written as the union of subsets of the form T , just as it was remarked above so:
x
J Ta
Ta
j
bt
Tb
Tb
1)
t
t t
r then we have:
i i
T a ) Card(T a ) nk
j
i
Ta
Ta
Ta
in
Ta
the
Written
form
I Ta Ta
1
..... T a
so
22
Card(T b ) n(k
t
1)
Card(T x ) n(k
1)
Ta )
j
In the same way we proceed for the remaining subsets in the Other sums, so Card (0 * X) divides each of these sums, hence: Card (0 * X) divides Card (I). Which prove (1). So the theorem is proved. By the preceding theorem and corollary (1) of the theorem (2) we have: Corollary (1): A finite BCI- algebra X is of KL- product iff Card (0 * X) divides Card(a X ) ( a X ) . In other words a finite BCI -algebra X is of KL- product iff the number of atoms in X divides the number of elements of any row in the Cayley table of the binary operation*. Example: The last corollary gives us a simple method for examining if a BCI -algebra is of KL- product or not. Here we have these tow examples: 0 1 2 3 4 5 0 1 2 3 4 5 0 0 0 0 3 3 3 0 0 0 0 3 3 3 1 1 0 0 4 3 3 1 1 0 0 3 3 3 2 2 2 0 5 5 3 2 2 2 0 5 5 3 3 3 3 3 0 0 0 3 3 3 3 0 0 0 4 4 3 3 1 0 0 4 4 3 3 1 0 0 5 5 5 3 2 2 0 5 5 5 3 2 2 0 Where the first table represents a BCI- algebra of KL- product but the second does not. Because the number of atoms in the first and the second BCI-algebras is 2 (the number of the elements of the first row in the tow tables), it is clear that the condition of the precedent corollary is satisfied in the first table but not in the second.
23
REFERENCES
[1] Dudek, W. A. (1988). On the axioms system for BCI-algebras, Prace Nauk. Wsp, Czestochows, Mathematyka 2. [2] Hoo, C. S. (1990). Closed ideals and p-semisimple BCI-algebras, Math. Japonica. 35, 1103-1112. [3] Iseki, K. (1966) An algebra related with a prepositional czlculus, Pros. Japan. Acad. 42, 26-29. [4] Iseki, K. (1980). On BCI-algebras, Math. Sem. Notes 8, 125-130. [5] Meng, J. and Xin, X. L. (1992). Characterizations of atoms in BCIalgebras, Math. Japonica, 37, 359-361. [6] Meng, J. and Xin, X. L. (1993). A problem in BCI-algebras, Math. Japonica, 38, 723-725. [7] Wei, S. M., Bai, G. Q., Meng, J. and Wang, Y. Q. (1999). Quasi- Implicative BCI-algebras, Math. Japonica 50, No. 2, 227- 233.
24