Sense, Category, Questions: Reading Deleuze With Ryle: Peter Kügler
Sense, Category, Questions: Reading Deleuze With Ryle: Peter Kügler
Sense, Category, Questions: Reading Deleuze With Ryle: Peter Kügler
Peter Kgler
University of Innsbruck
Abstract
Gilles Deleuzes notion of sense, as developed in Difference and
Repetition and The Logic of Sense, is meant to be a fourth dimension
of the proposition besides denotation, manifestation and signification.
While Deleuze explains signification in inferentialist terms, he ascribes to
sense some very unusual properties, making it hard to understand what
sense is. The aim of this paper is to improve this situation by confronting
Deleuzian sense with a more or less contemporary, but otherwise rather
distant philosophical conception: Gilbert Ryles theory of categories and
category mistakes. The leading idea is that to understand the sense of a
proposition regarding X is to know the category of the concept X, which
requires that one knows which questions may appropriately be asked
with regard to X. Thus, sense, category and questions are intimately
related to each other. Finally, it seems to be consistent with Deleuzes
views to assume that abstract signification is contextually generated by
concrete sense.
Keywords: Deleuze, sense, signification, Ryle, category, question
325
327
under which the proposition would be true (Deleuze 2004b: 18). But
the context makes clear that here Deleuze does not appeal to truthconditional semantics, that is, to the view that the signification of a
proposition is given by its truth conditions. Again we must think of
inferential relations, which can be understood as concerning possibly
true propositions. A deductively valid inference, in particular, is one
whose conclusion would be true if the premises were true. Neither the
premises nor the conclusion need to be true in reality. This is probably
why Deleuze mentions truth conditions at all, and why he refers to
signification as the possibility for the proposition to be true (Deleuze
2004b: 22).
As to sense, in Deleuzes theory, we get a first understanding of this
notion by considering some features that distinguish it from signification.
Deleuze, following the terminology of traditional syllogistics, explains
that sense is neutral as to the quality, quantity and modality of a
proposition. Quality refers to the distinction between affirmation and
negation; hence a proposition has the same sense as its negation.
Differences in quantity do not count either; hence a proposition about all
things of a kind does not change its sense when all is replaced by some.
And finally, p has the same sense as possibly p and necessarily p, as
these are just differences in modality.
Deleuze even goes so far as to say that sense is affected neither by the
order of subject and predicate nor by that of antecedent and consequent.
Referring to the work of Lewis Carroll, he gives examples such as cats
eat bats and bats eat cats, as well as I breathe when I sleep and I sleep
when I breathe. Another quite surprising claim is that inconsistent
propositions like squares are round have sense but no signification
(Deleuze 2004b: 41).3
In the face of these statements, it does not seem helpful to express the
sense of a proposition by means of another proposition. If you do not
know what the sense of cats eat bats is, you will not gain much if you
are told that it is identical to the sense of bats eat cats, cats do not eat
bats, or cats possibly eat bats. Deleuze therefore tries some alternative
approaches, indicating that the sense of a sentence could perhaps also be
expressed in infinitive, participial or interrogative form (Deleuze 2004a:
194). For example, the sense of The sky is blue might be rendered as
the being-blue of the sky or Is the sky blue?
It is tempting to assume that these ways of expressing sense add up
to an account of propositional content. The sky is blue arguably has
the same propositional content as the being-blue of the sky and Is the
sky blue?4 However, propositional content cannot be what Deleuze has
329
to sense.5 Another one is idea, one of his examples being the idea of
physical atomism (Deleuze 2004a: 232f.), which is the idea that matter
consists of particles some of which are indivisible. Here we are using
a propositional clause, that matter consists of particles. But Deleuze
denies that the idea is itself a proposition or something akin to it. Rather,
the idea is a problem, and the problem is a set of questions. Strictly
speaking, The problem is a set of questions is a kind of slogan that we
may use for the sake of convenience. It would be more precise to say that
the problem is an entity in its own right whose various parts or aspects
can be grasped by asking appropriate questions.6
The problem of physical atomism includes questions like the
following: Does matter consist of atoms?, What types of atoms exist?,
What shapes do atoms have?, What masses do they have?, Do they
move?, In which ways do they move?, Why does a particular atom
move?, and also, What is an atom?7 Any one of these questions
could be answered by an appropriate proposition, and this proposition
would be a partial solution of the problem, solving that part of the
problem which is covered by the question. For example, the question
Do atoms move? is answered by the proposition Atoms move. But in
order to understand more of the problem, it is not enough to ask this
single question. We must also have an understanding of other questions
associated with the problem of atomism.8
331
Consider again the example of the window from section one. The
proposition The window is open, in conjunction with the premise
that most windows are rectangular, implies that the open window is
probably rectangular, having a diagonal of a length that is the square
root of a2 + b2 , where a and b are the sides of the rectangle. This is a
remote geometrical consequence that has no relevance at all in typical
cases in which the proposition The window is open is used. It might
be important in a classroom, say, as part of a mathematics exercise.
But usually we would not assume that a person must know how to
calculate the length of the diagonal in order to know the meaning of
The window is open. The same goes for the word window. In order
to know its meaning, one need not be aware of the question as to how
the length of the diagonal is to be computed from the lengths of the
sides.
The inferences Ryle utilises in his book to explain the notion of
category form only a subset of all the inferences that make up the
complete signification of a proposition. How is this subset determined?
What makes some inferences relevant and others not? In the following,
I will argue that this subset of inferences is delineated by questions. Thus,
as far as categories are concerned, the asking and answering of questions
is the type of operation that counts. In fact, Ryle frequently exhibits the
category of concepts by discussing questions.
Before we go on with Ryle, however, let us see whether Deleuzes
philosophy of sense provides any indication of a theory of categories.
The place to look for it is in Deleuzes discussion of paradoxes which
draws on the work of Lewis Carroll. As in other areas of philosophy and
science, the investigation of pathological cases helps to illuminate the
normal ones. Nonsense, the absence of sense, can teach us something
about sense. In the preface of The Logic of Sense, Deleuze even purports
to present a series of paradoxes which form the theory of sense
(Deleuze 2004b: ix).
At least some of Carrolls violations of sense discussed by Deleuze can
be interpreted as category mistakes as envisaged by Ryle. The following
is an instructive example from Alice in Wonderland (quoted by Deleuze
2004b: 31):
. . . and even Stigand, the patriotic Archbishop of Canterbury, found it
advisable
Found what? said the Duck.
Found it, the Mouse replied rather crossly: of course you know what it
means.
The wit of this little dialogue rests on the confusion of finding a thing and
finding something advisable. As these belong to different categories, it is
not appropriate to ask What did the archbishop find? instead of asking
What did he find advisable? A comparable example is given by Ryle:
She came home in a flood of tears and a sedan-chair is a well-known
joke based on the absurdity of conjoining terms of different types (Ryle
1949: 22). Classical rhetoric registers this figure of speech as zeugma or
syllepis. On Ryles account, the rhetorical effect is caused by a category
mistake.
Another paradoxical case from Alice in Wonderland mentioned by
Deleuze (2004b: 38; 2004a: 195) is the well-known grin of the Cheshire
Cat:
All right, said the Cat; and this time it vanished quite slowly, beginning with
the end of the tail, and ending with the grin, which remained some time after
the rest of it had gone.
Well! Ive often seen a cat without a grin, thought Alice; but a grin
without a cat! Its the most curious thing I ever saw in all my life! (Carroll
1994: 78)
333
335
337
Notes
1. The nature of this causation arguably depends on the ontological nature of
mental states, but we need not go into this here. This article is mainly concerned
with an interpretation of Deleuzes philosophy of language; ontological issues
will be touched upon only tangentially.
2. In the above quotation from The Logic of Sense, Deleuze just talks of theoretical
inferences (syllogistic and mathematical demonstration, physical probabilities)
and practical commitments, such as the commitment to keep a promise. He does
not mention entitlements, but these can safely be added to his account.
3. Deleuze does not substantiate the claim that inconsistent propositions lack
signification. Perhaps he relies on the fact that these propositions cannot enter
into inferences as possibly true statements. Classical logic, however, does ascribe
an inferential role to them, if only a rather trivial one: ex contradictione sequitur
quodlibet.
4. I am using propositional content roughly as in Chapter 2.4 of Searle 1969.
Although an utterance of the being-blue of the sky is at best an incomplete
speech act, it works as an indicator of propositional content, as Searle would
say. Searle, however, prefers that-clauses for indicating propositional content
(that the sky is blue). Note also that for him a proposition is the propositional
content of a speech act, whereas Deleuzes usage of that term is wider.
5. The term event belongs to this list, too, as sense is said to be an incorporeal,
complex, and irreducible entity, at the surface of things, a pure event which
inheres or subsists in the proposition (Deleuze 2004b: 22). Another surface
entity is the concept, which speaks the event (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 21).
All concepts are connected to problems without which they would have no
meaning [sens] (16). Except that concepts are supposed to be solutions of
problems, they have much in common with the latter. In particular, they are
not propositional (22). To keep the discussion simpler, however, I refrain from
considering these notions of event and concept. I will reserve the word concept
for Ryle who uses it for a linguistic entity.
6. As indicated in the previous note, sense inheres or subsists, but does not exist.
Furthermore, it is a dual entity on the border between world and language: It
is rather the coexistence of two sides without thickness, such that we pass from
one to the other by following their length. Sense is both the expressible or the
expressed of the proposition, and the attribute of the state of affairs. It turns
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
one side toward things and one side toward propositions (Deleuze 2004b: 25).
Thus, sense is something very peculiar, to say the least.
A superficial reading might suggest that Deleuze rejects questions of the type
What is X? per se. But in fact he only rejects the Platonic-Socratic tradition in
which these questions are understood as aiming at essences. Apart from that,
Deleuze acknowledges their propaedeutic function in the Platonic discourse:
Once it is a question of determining the problem or the Idea as such, once it is a
question of setting the dialectic in motion, the question What is X? gives way
to other questions, otherwise powerful and efficacious, otherwise imperative:
How much, how and in what cases? The question What is X? animates
only the so-called aporetic dialogues in other words, those in which the very
form of the question gives rise to contradiction and leads to nihilism, no doubt
because they have only propaedeutic aims the aim of opening up the region of
the problem in general, leaving to other procedures the task of determining it as
a problem or as an Idea (Deleuze 2004a: 236f.).
It would lead us too far astray to discuss in detail how these questions are related
to each other. A possible point of departure could be what Sylvain Bromberger
calls a cluster of questions (Bromberger 1966: 602). According to Bromberger,
a cluster of questions is raised by some proposition, and a question belongs to
this cluster if it stands to the proposition in a relation of mutual implication.
That is, if the proposition is true, the question must have a correct answer, and
conversely.
In his article Categories, published about a decade before The Concept of Mind,
Ryle prefers to talk of concepts without the adjective logical (Ryle 1937/8).
I follow him in this. Others may choose to replace logical by ontological,
as differences between logical categories are arguably related to ontological
differences. This logical/ontological ambiguity of category seems to correspond
to the two-sidedness of sense mentioned in note 7 above. Compare Deleuzes
distinction between the logical and the ontological proposition in The Logic of
Sense (Deleuze 2004b: 138).
Here, to know does not necessarily refer to knowing-that, that is, knowledge
expressible in propositional form. There are cases in which it is possible to say
that a word means such-and-such, thus giving the meaning of the word by using
other words. But the knowledge in question is primarily a linguistic kind of
knowing-how. A person who knows the sense of a word knows how to use it in
the course of utterances, in accordance with its category.
The glove example suffices for our purposes, but in The Concept of Mind
cases not based on a part-whole relation are more salient. In particular, there
is the distinction between occurrences and dispositions which, in Ryles opinion,
provides a solution (or rather, dissolution) of the mind-body problem. There are
questions about occurrences that cannot be asked about dispositions.
Thus, we could analyse the question as consisting of two parts, the first one
expressing its content: The two gloves on the couch belong together. Yes or
no?
References
Brandom, Robert B. (1994) Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and
Discursive Commitment, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bromberger, Sylvain (1966) Questions, The Journal of Philosophy, 63,
pp. 597606.
Carroll, Lewis (1994) Alices Adventures in Wonderland, London: Penguin.
339
Deleuze, Gilles (2004a) Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton, London:
Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles (2004b) The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester with Charles Stivale,
ed. Constantin V. Boundas, London: Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles and Flix Guattari (1994) What Is Philosophy? trans. Hugh
Tomlinson and Graham Burchell, New York: Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Claire Parnet (2006) Dialogues II, trans. Hugh Tomlinson and
Barbara Habberjam, London: Continuum.
Dummett, Michael (1981) Frege: Philosophy of Language, London: Duckworth.
Ryle, Gilbert (1937/8) Categories, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 38,
pp. 189206.
Ryle, Gilbert (1949) The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson.
Searle, John R. (1969) Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.