Who Is Afraid of The Ontological Wolf Viveiro de Castro
Who Is Afraid of The Ontological Wolf Viveiro de Castro
Who Is Afraid of The Ontological Wolf Viveiro de Castro
This article, which was delivered as the 2014 Annual Marilyn Strathern Lecture, outlines
both some of the stimuli that led to the ontological turn in anthropology and some of
its implications. Ontology is outlined here by the author as an anti-epistemological and
counter-cultural, philosophical war machine.
Keywords: alterity, Anthropocene, anti-epistemological, counter-cultural, ontological
turn
of the research results condensed in those four lectures. I do not regret such singlemindedness, because it gave me, even more unexpectedly, a role as a political actor
(minor, to be sure) in the current cultural renaissance of Latin America, a continent with
an Amerindian (or Afro-Amerindian) face and a definite project to further a different
version of the good life in this crucial moment of global metaphysical dejection. Be that
as it may, the present occasion has a clear and dear emotional meaning to me. I would
never have imagined that those distant lectures would turn out to be the ultimate cause
of my return to enjoy the exquisite privilege of paying homage to Marilyn Strathern.
Marilyn Strathern is not a distant figure but very much alive and a much esteemed
colleague, one who has taught me more than many an anthropological ancestor. Her
work has been a major influence on mine not only ever since we met for the first time
in 1997 but, as I came to realize, before I had even started to read her. When I arrived
in Cambridge I was already in the process of becoming a Strathernian unawares call
it the aesthetic trap of the intellectual gift if you will. In short, were I a Hagener, I would
be owing Marilyn many more fat pigs than I could ever hope to assemble. May the puny
one I present here serve at least as a token of my undischargeable debt.
Moving briefly from Cambridge to Oxford, I have chosen a passage from Lewis
Carroll as a perfect fanciful rendering of a Strathernian analysis of any piece of
ethnographic material (the sense of outlandishness that Stratherns sheer originality
can produce, Holbraad and Pedersen 2009: 372). Reading a text by her is like opening
a chapter of a book titled Marilyns Adventures in Otherland. Allow me then to cite this
little passage from Though the Looking-Glass (Carroll 2010: 62), which describes what
Marilyn, I mean Alice, experiences when she enters the mirror-world:
Then she began looking about, and noticed that what could be seen from the old room
was quite common and uninteresting, but that all the rest was as different as possible
They dont keep this room so tidy as the other, Alice thought to herself.
Lets call this passage learning to see in Anthropology. This moment of traversing the
mirror (in whatever direction, I hasten to add) is strongly evocative of the so-called
ontological turn, to which my name, among those of a few other delinquents, has been
associated.
So here we are: I have chosen to pay homage to Marilyn Strathern by talking about
the current ontological debate since, as I see it, her work is one of the main inspirations
of this debate, even if the fearsome word ontology seems to be quite foreign to her own
mode of expression.
On Ontological Delegation
In a well-known collection entitled Thinking Through Things (Henare et al. 2007), thanks
to which the expression ontological turn acquired its controversial conspicuousness
in anthropology, the editors mention a quiet revolution led by authors like Wagner,
Latour, Gell, Strathern and yours truly. Rarely has such a mild adjective as quiet helped
provoke the very opposite! But what was that revolution about? The editors of the
collection describe it as a shifting of focus of questions of knowledge and epistemology
to questions of ontology. This way of characterizing the move is referred to in the final
The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology 3
same time making knowledge the very model case of practice. For let us not forget
the role that the identification between social action and social analysis plays in The
Gender of the Gift. This is not unrelated, I believe, to other outrageous Strathernian,
subsumptive inversions, namely, the determination of production as a mode and a
moment of exchange, and of exchange as a shift of subjective perspectives rather than
an objective economic transaction.
As to the language/reality gap, let us just recall the visionary semiotics of Roy Wagner
in which what was an ontological chasm became a process of reciprocal co-production
and, most importantly, in which concrete particulars (the really existing reality) were
reconceptualized as symbols that stand for themselves, a move which anticipates some
crucial aspects of Bruno Latours recent An Inquiry into Modes of Existence (Latour
2013). Wagners semiotics may also be seen as anticipating the concept of the material
concept put forth by Holbraad and his collaborators in Thinking Through Things,
through which concepts-as-representations were pre-empted by the duplex circuit of
concepts-as-things (endowed with material efficaciousness) and things-as-concepts
(endowed with thinking capabilities).
The second stimulus was the rise of Science and Technology Studies. The
ethnographic description of science (both of the actual practice of the sciences as
of the political usages of the concept in the singular) had profound consequences for
anthropology as a whole. And that for a simple but far-reaching reason: the modern
opposition between science and non-science is both a model of and a model for
the wider divide separating Western modernity from the others, the barbarians, the
primitives. Such is the founding gesture of our era: the identity of the modern West
depends on this segmentary duplication of two outsides of itself. Because of this,
any attempt to investigate empirically how science establishes its a priori political
discontinuity with politics (and with opinion, religion, ideology) immediately
jeopardizes the other great divide, that between We and They, moderns and nonmoderns, and sometimes even between humans and non-humans. This is how
epistemology insidiously becomes ontology. Note that the anthropology of science did
not abolish (on the grounds of it being non-scientific, as it were) the distinction between
science and non-science; rather it multiplied and differentiated such a distinction in a
cloud of practices with specific demands and obligations. The epistemological break of
Bachelardian fame became, if not mendable, at least bridgeable; transitions multiplied,
continuities were observed, compromises noticed, symmetries proclaimed. This new
state of things made all frontiers, internal as well as external, much more permeable.
Alterity became delocalized. The other (within or without the West) ceased to be the
simple carrier of a mistaken culture that represented distortedly our external nature,
or, conversely, a wild, true representative of the internal nature of the human species,
whose sociopsychobiological evolutionary makeup is always more easily accessible, as
we know, through the examination of the ways of illiterate, ignorant people.
The ontological programme had a reasonably clear idea of what changes it
intended to bring in response to the above-mentioned stimuli, and has now a wealth
of ethnographic as well as theoretical results to present as evidence that those two
challenges have been met by anthropology. The third challenge, however, lies mainly
ahead of us. It is utterly consequential, not to say ominous, from a political and
The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology 5
we normally take them to be. The notion of an ontological delegation means that
the anthropologist is forced to take his/her own ontological assumptions out of the
strongbox and risk their robustness and transportability by letting them be counteranalysed by indigenous knowledge practices, or, to put it differently, he/she defines
whatever he/she is studying as a counter-metaphysics with its own requisites and
postulates. Anthropology becomes comparative metaphysics even as metaphysics
becomes comparative ethnography. And the anthropologist turns into an ontological
negotiator or diplomat. To quote the position paper of the recent AAA symposium
on the politics of the ontological turn, which I co-signed with Martin Holbraad and
Morten Pedersen: The anthropology of ontology is anthropology as ontology; not the
comparison of ontologies, but comparison as ontology (Viveiros de Castro et al. 2014).
Here I think it would be fitting to cite Patrice Maniglier, the philosopher who, after
having remarked that the expression comparative metaphysics should be interpreted as
tautological, proceeded to the exciting suggestion that anthropology is bound to occupy
in the present century the same role, as model science and epistemic paradigm, that
physics played during the modern period. Anthropology would be thus in a position to
furnish the new metaphysics of the Anthropocene, the epoch when humanity became
a molecular multiplicity and a physically molar agent and this is one of the reasons
I have fewer misgivings than some of my colleagues about the appropriateness of the
term Anthropocene to designate the new deep-historical epoch we have entered. As
Maniglier wrote with respect to Latours ongoing project of an anthropology of the
moderns actually an inventory of the different modes of existence recognized (as
through a glass darkly, though) by the ontology of the moderns:
The difference between Latour and his predecessors [Maniglier is thinking of classic
metaphysicians, either early modern or late postmodern] is not in his metaphysics
contents, but in the way that its employed: diplomatically. It is used to negotiate
encounters and confusions of ontologies in the plural. This metaphysics is thus
thoroughly anthropological, if we do define anthropology as the science [savoir] that
uses only the clashes experienced between our most deeply-rooted beliefs to produce not
a body of knowledge [un savoir] about something, but a redescription of ourselves in the
light of alterity. (Maniglier 2014: 40)
Be that as it may, the proud word ontology, as Kant once said, was not a newfangled recirculation of an archaic, ornate concept: suffice it to recall the wonderful
paper by Irving Hallowell (1960), Ojibwa ontology, behaviour, and world view,
published fifty-four years ago. Neither was it the exclusive brainchild of a certain
Cambridge clique, as an anonymous objector dubbed the ontological turn people (the
clique referred basically to the contributors to Thinking Through Things and myself,
with the evil hand of Marilyn Strathern somehow behind all that). The term ontology
appeared more or less at the same time in many a STS context (think of Annemarie Mol,
John Law, Bruno Latour, Andrew Pickering), in the prose of philosophers-historians of
science (think of G.R. Lloyd, Ian Hacking, Peter Galison), even as it was independently
adopted relatively so, of course by many anthropologists (think of Philippe Descola,
Michael Scott, Ghassan Hage, Elizabeth Povinelli or Naoki Kasuga). Recall, also, that
the whole psycho-cognitive sect of our discipline seems perfectly happy with the term,
used, it goes without saying, in their own metaphysical, essentialist and absolutist way.
As a matter of course, ontology can be found a bit everywhere these days, from
political science journals to computer programming lingo. The meaning of the term in
these different contexts and authors varies greatly, for sure, but beyond such diversity,
the current popularity of the term bears witness to some sea changes that affect the
whole zeitgeist: the exhaustion of the critical nomos that separated the phenomenon
from the thing in itself, and the breaking apart of the hierarchical division of labour
between natural and cultural sciences, as well as between pure (theoretical) reason and
practical (moral) reason. But perhaps above all, it expresses the growing feeling that our
own modern ontology (singular), such as laid down by the scientific revolution of the
seventeenth century, not only was made largely obsolete by the scientific revolutions of
the early twentieth century, but that it also turned out to have disastrous consequences
when considered from its business end, i.e., as an imperialist, colonialist, ethnocidal and
ecocidal mode of production. Ontology came to the fore precisely at the moment the
ontological foundations of our civilization and the unquestioned cultural supremacy
8 The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology
of the peoples who founded it are seen as starting to crumble. This led, among other
things, to a growing tendency (not without its fierce enemies, it might be said) to accept
the plural inflection of the word and the thing, either internally (the profession of a
pluralistic ontology) or externally (the idea of an ontological pluralism), and even to
the post-plural awareness of what I would call a performative condition of ontological
anarchy, to borrow a concept from Peter Lamborn Wilson (Bey 1991).
As we shall see, not all political anarchists accept ontological anarchy, i.e. the idea
that the only viable political meaning of ontology in our times depends on accepting
alterity and equivocation as unsubsumable by any transcendent point of view (the
very idea of a transcendent point of view is an oxymoron, which did not prevent it
from being posited by some ontologies). The affirmation of alterity being-as-other
as intrinsic to being-as-being (Latour 2013) and equivocation variation as truth
(Maniglier 2009) is not tantamount to the positing of one ontology, even if a pluralist
one, or of many ontologies for that matter, but signifies rather that ontological questions
are political questions insofar as they come into existence only in the context of
friction and divergence between concepts, practices and experiences within or without
culturally individuated collectives, given, I stress the polysemic value of this word, given
the absolute absence of any exterior and superior arbiter. Ontological differences, to get
to the point, are political because they imply a situation of war not a war of words,
as per the linguistic turn, but an ongoing war of worlds, hence the sudden, pressing
insistence on the ontological import of our ethnographic descriptions, in a context in
which the world (as we know it) is imposed in myriad ways on other peoples worlds
(as they know them), even as this hegemonic world seems to be on the brink of a slow,
painful and ugly ending. No arbiter, no God, no United Nations Protection Force, no
police operation to bring delinquents into line. The war will be as often as not fought
with guerrilla tactics, to be sure. Until the powers that be (I mean BP, Shell, Monsanto
or Nestle) bring their atomics to the scene.
Is this a satisfactory answer to the question of one or several wolves, i.e., ontologies,
then? Maybe yes, maybe no. Were trying. It depends on how you use the word. There
is nothing wrong, in principle, in talking of as many ontologies as there are cultures (I
know Martin Holbraad disagrees; I agree with him, partially), just as you say of a given
physical theory that it has its own ontology.3 Not because ontology is just another word
for culture (the famous 2008 GDAT Manchester question: Carrithers et al. 2010), but
rather because culture may always have been just another word for ontology minus
nature of course; a poor mans ontology if you will. (The only authentically ontological
notion of culture I am aware of is that of Wagner (1981 [1975]) in The Invention of
Culture, precisely because it comprises the variation of natures in parallel to that of
cultures.) I have always found a tad bizarre the Manchester question. Ontology, as
I understand it, is both an anti-epistemological and counter-cultural (in both senses
of counter-culture) philosophical war machine. If ontology were to be just another
word for anything, I would suggest it should have been nature, a term the grammatical
pluralization of which provoked the same uneasiness as that of ontology. Hence my
Amazonian multinaturalism, a sort of ethnographically grounded proof-of-concept of
the argument according to which, if anthropologists were more than willing to accept
a bloated universe when it came to cultures (I am evoking here Heywoods [2012]
The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology 9
Quinian argument that appeared in the pages of this journal), then in the name of what
exactly would one forbid them to go for a bloated how about calling it non-anorexic,
rather? natural universe as well? A multiverse, to recall the celebrated concept of
William James?
As Salmon (2013) observed, in many works that further the ontological programme,
the metaphysics of representation is shown to be much more efficaciously shattered by
means of the ethnographic description of a counter-metaphysics than by the internal
demystification at which postmodern criticism was adept. In the particular case of
Amazonian perspectivism, an ethnographic concept which was consubstantial with
a certain economy of the person, where the position of the self was metaphysically
encompassed by that of the other, the potential affine, the enemy, the problem of
ethnographic authority was completely overtaken or perhaps sublated, forgotten by
incorporation by the ethnoanthropology, or indigenous metaphysics, of alterity.
But the question somehow lingers on. Can we do with ontology what we did with
culture namely, have one Ontology singular, and many ontologies plural? What is the
grammatical number of ontology, after all? Is it a count-noun to begin with, or some sort
of mass-noun? Does it accept an indefinite plural, or must it be inflected only in a dual
form (as in anthropomorphic versus anthropocentric ontologies, as I sometimes feel
inclined to think)? Does it accept a paucal, a greater paucal, a trial, perhaps a quadral
number of inflections (as in Descolas [2013] ontological quadripartite taxonomy)?
Not to mention the already cited post-plural, interdiscursive, fractally multiple, scaleindependent, moving-target-like ontology deployed by Strathernian anthropology with
which I am aligned, and which is a sort of metaphysico-methodological Tardis (Partial
Connections [Strathern 2004] is a little book that is much bigger inside). Or is ontology
better employed as an adjective (ontological) than as a substantive? Or yet again, do
ontologies behave like rigid, impenetrable solids that are solipsistically withdrawn
within their own incommensurability or, as Jensen and Morita (2012: 9) for example
suggest, speaking of the Japanese take on the ontological turn, do they show a wealth
of complex interplays through which different ontologies are often busily interfering
with each other ontologies are never hermetically sealed but always part of multiple
engagements. I find it impossible to disagree with this statement, but would just add
that sometimes it may be pragmatically, i.e., politically, vital to describe ontologies as
intractable sets of presuppositions that are aggressively contradictory with other similar
sets, and/or as crossing one another in the pre-space of chaos without any mutual
interference whatsoever.
As Holbraad has remarked, in the same vein, in ontological turn the word turn
ends up being more important than ontological for a turn has many more senses
than that of a change of direction, a shift towards a better, brighter paradigm, an
anthropological city upon a hill as it were. It may mean the act (Im quoting from the
cheap dictionary on my computer) of moving something in a circular direction around
an axis or point, as in the turn of a screw. And in an important sense, what we have
been advocating was essentially an ontological turn of the epistemological screw a
methodological tightening up of our ethnographic descriptions, which, rather than
allowing us to discover new things about the other, marked the limits ontological,
not critical of what can be known (and then said) about that other. It also meant turn
10 The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology
of multiplying our world, filling it with all of those things expressed that do not exist
beyond their expression (Deleuze 1994: 22). Do not explain too much, do not try to
actualize the possibilities immanent in others thought, but endeavour to sustain them
as possible indefinitely.4 Let me return here to the one or several wolves title of the
last section. In a crucial passage of the homonymous chapter of A Thousand Plateaux,
Deleuze and Guattari (1987) evoke the childhood dream of the Wolf-Man of Freudian
fame, remarking how, although the dreamer mentioned a pack of wolves appearing to
him, Freud could only see one wolf the Wolf in general, the wolf as static concept not
as a dynamic becoming:
The wolves never had a chance to get away and save their pack [becoming as multiplicity
EVC]: it was already decided from the very beginning that animals could serve only
to represent coitus between parents, or, conversely, be represented by coitus between
parents. Freud obviously knows nothing about the fascination exerted by wolves and the
meaning of their silent call, the call to become-wolf. Wolves watch, intently watch, the
dreaming child; it is so much more reassuring to tell oneself that the dream produced a
reversal and that it is really the child who sees dogs or parents in the act of making love.
Freud only knows the Oedipalized wolf or dog, the castrated-castrating daddy-wolf, the
dog in the kennel, the analysts bow-wow. (ibid.: 4950)
It was already decided from the very beginning, as Deleuze and Guattari might
have said, that fetishes could serve only to represent necessary illusions conjured up
by living in society. Marcio Goldman, in an article from which I stole this passage as
well as the general spirit of the commentary, observes that Graebers effort to save the
Marxian notion of fetishism, namely, that fetishes are objects which seem to take on
human qualities which are, ultimately, really derived from the actors themselves, is
somewhat misplaced. Graeber does try somehow to reconcile the Merina with Marx,
arguing that fetishes only become dangerous when fetishism gives way to theology,
the absolute assurance that the gods are real (real as commodities, one might say). The
problem, says Goldman (2009: 114ff), is that this brave effort to save the natives face is
undertaken behind the latters back, so to speak. One wonders, firstly, if the conversion
of fetishism into a will to believe that is at the root of (real, social) power would be
accepted by the natives. And secondly, if such a reduction, which sounds more like an
essay at reconciling one explicit Western ontology (to wit, dialectical materialism) with
the Merinas implicit one, rather than an effort to problematize our own assumptions,
does not end up reinforcing, more than simply leaving untouched, our own ontological
framework. Magical powers, as the Merina conceive them, cannot exist
The so-called ontological turn is nothing more than a change in the disciplinary
language-game that forbids, by declaring it an illegal move, such an analytical
facility on the anthropologists part. I have a feeling that much of the uneasiness or
outright rejection of the ontological turns rhetorics comes from that restriction of the
freedom allowed to the analyst: the freedom to stay put, to not move, to indulge in the
heliocentric trick of making the observed turn (ontologically) around the observer.
Such restriction is what I meant by the maxim always leave a way out for the people
you are describing. This is not a mere anti-holistic position, nor a modest refusal of
ethnographic omniscience. It is about what I would call the good enough description,
a phrase that was actually inspired by the brilliant connection made by Graeber in
the passage above between the paradox of power and the paradox of creativity. The
expression paradox of creativity reminded me of the work of Donald Winnicott
(e.g., 1964) and his crucial concept of the transitional space, that area in between
pure subjective-internal and pure objective-external experiences of the infant, from
which, says Winnicott, all art, all creativity and all culture spring. This area contains a
paradox, is built on a paradox, says Winnicott a sort of Mbius-band situation where
one cant tell the inside from the outside, because there is no such distinction but a
paradox that we should refuse to explain. This paradox, in a sense, is what makes us
human, if I understand Winnicott correctly though there is no reason to insist upon
its human-only specificity (remember the Batesonian this is play problem). Be that
as it may, Winnicott (1953) is also the author of the wonderful concept of the good
enough mother, the mother that is not always there, is not practically perfect in every
way, leaves something incomplete as far as the desire of the infant is concerned, and
therefore ends up by raising unawares, as it were a normal child. A more-thangood-enough mother would raise a less-than-normal-enough child. I like to think
of a good ethnographic description as a good enough description. Dont reduce the
paradoxes. That hateful expression breaking a butterfly on a wheel, which a colleague
was patronizing enough to evoke in order to hedge somewhat his harsh criticism of my
The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology 13
work,6 should be applied to what we do with, or rather, to the existential and intellectual
work of the peoples we study. Anthropologists are butterfly collectors after all, pace
Leach. We are always dealing with, we are only dealing with, butterflies. Delicacy (and
elegance) is required; too much historicizing will crush the butterfly.
And just so I do not end without making a reference to another of my bombastic
admonishments (Viveiros de Castro et al. 2013: 2127), let me say a few words about
the idea of taking seriously the things the people we study tell us. Our colleague Rane
Willerslev (2013) has recently published a paper entitled Taking Animism Seriously,
but Perhaps Not Too Seriously? in which he takes issue with the idea, by observing
that among the Yukaghir, ridiculing the (animal, etc.) spirits is integral to their game of
hunting; the Yukaghir know that spirits are an illusion, but they ironically go along with
it. We should not take indigenous animism (for example) too seriously, he concludes.
I will disregard the irony of having a dour Dane admonishing a happy-go-lucky
Brazilian not to take too seriously whatever there is to be taken. I will just repeat
I thought I had already explained this in The Relative Native (2013) that to take
seriously does not mean to believe (Willerslev seems to believe that Yukaghirs do not
believe in their spirits), to be in awe of what people tell you, to take them literally when
they do not mean you to (not an easy distinction to make at all if it is ever possible to
use this Greek weapon of rhetorical deconstruction in other ethnographic contexts),7 to
take it as a profound dogma of sacred lore or anything of the sort. It means to learn to
be able to speak well to the people you study, to employ a central concept and concern
of Bruno Latour to speak about them to them in ways they do not find offensive
or ridiculous. They do not need to agree with you completely they will never do so
anyway; all we require is that they find our description a good enough one. It will
always be a caricature of themselves, with certain traits exaggerated, others downplayed,
certain points overstretched, others minimized, and so on. Ethnographers are not
photographers they are portrait artists. Every portrait is more or less a caricature,
with no pejorative sense implied. As we know, oftentimes a proper, deliberate caricature
captures the spirit (the invisible likeness, as it were) of the person represented much
more eloquently than a photograph. And finally, those peoples we call animists (for
example) may choose to take whatever they posit, their animal spirits, say, seriously
or otherwise and I am sure context is an exceedingly important consideration here
(think of spirit-induced disease, for instance). But anyway, first they have had to
go to the trouble to invent (or discover) those spirits one wonders if it was just to
have something to make fun of! Before learning not to take them too seriously, we
should learn not to take ourselves too seriously, because, when the chips are down,
anthropology is always in the situation of playing croquet with flamingoes, to end now
with another Alice quotation:
The chief difficulty Alice found at first was in managing her flamingo: she succeeded in
getting its body tucked away, comfortably enough, under her arm, with its legs hanging
down, but generally, just as she had got its neck nicely straightened out, and was going
to give the hedgehog a blow with its head, it would twist itself round and look up in her
face, with such a puzzled expression that she could not help bursting out laughing: and
when she had got its head down, and was going to begin again, it was very provoking to
find that the hedgehog had unrolled itself, and was in the act of crawling away: besides
14 The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology
The problem is, unfortunately, that one often has ones head hacked off in the game.
But thats what we were here for in the first place: anthropology is always about sticking
ones neck out through the looking-glass of ontological difference.
Acknowledgements
This article is the slightly abridged text of the 2014 Annual Marilyn Strathern Lecture,
delivered in Cambridge, UK, May 2014. I am grateful to the Cambridge University
Social Anthropology Society [CUSAS] for the invitation to give this lecture.
Notes
1. Cited by Jerome Neutres in Bill Viola, la metaphysique sans la philosophie. Available at <http://www.
philomag.com/lepoque/breves/bill-viola-la-metaphysique-sans-la-philosophie-9467> (accessed 9
September 2014).
2. Taken from Pastoureau 1976, my translation.
3. Warning: the expression the ontology of a theory is sometimes misleadingly employed to designate
the reference class or universe of discourse of a theory. The expression is misleading because ontologies
are theories, not classes (Bunge 1999: 201).
4. This is what permanent means in another of my bombastic proclamations, namely the definition of
anthropology as the permanent decolonisation of thought (Viveiros de Castro 2009: 4).
5. He refers the reader here to Graeber 2001.
6. To fault Viveiros de Castros elegant, thought-provoking model of perspectivism for its strangely
dehistoricized picture of the Amazon may be a procedure too suggestive of breaking a butterfly on the
wheel (to borrow from Alfred Kroebers complaint about those who dismissed Freuds psychoanalytic
theory without acknowledging its originality and fruitful suggestions) (Starn 2011: 193).
7. See Lloyd (1990: 1920) on the metaphoric/literal distinction, contra Sperber.
References
Bey, H. 1991 TAZ: The Temporary Autonomous Zone, Ontological Anarchy, Poetic
Terrorism.New York: Autonomedia.
Bunge, M. 1998 Ontology. In Dictionary of Philosophy (ed.) M. Bunge, 200209. Amherst:
Prometheus Books.
Carrithers, M., M. Candea, K. Sykes, M. Holbraad & S. Venkatesan. 2010. Ontology is Just
Another Word for Culture. Critique of Anthropology 30(2): 150201.
Carroll, L. 2010. Alices Adventures in Wonderland and Through the Looking Glass. Red Wing,
Minnesota: Cricket House Books.
Chakrabarty, D. 2009. The Climate of History: Four Theses. Critical Inquiry 35: 197222.
Clifford, J., & G.E. Marcus (eds) 1986. Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Deleuze, G. 1994. Difference and Repetition. London: The Athlone Press.
Deleuze, G., & F. Guattari. 1987. A Thousand Plateaux: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (trans. B.
Massumi). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
The Cambridge Journal of Anthropology 15