Meillassoux Dictionary
Meillassoux Dictionary
Meillassoux Dictionary
The
TEXT TO COME
Peter Gratton and Paul J. Ennis
The Lyotard Dictionary provides an exceptionally clear presentation
of his complex and challenging ideas. The entries are written with
Meillassoux
precision, detail and clarity, offering helpful introductions to unfamiliar
concepts as well as fascinating insights for those who already know
Lyotards work. It will be an indispensable guide for students of Lyotard
at all levels.
Dictionary
Simon Malpas, University of Edinburgh
Peter Gratton
www.euppublishing.com and Paul J. Ennis
Th e M e illa s s oux
Dictionary
www.euppublishing.com
A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library
The right of the contributors to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted in
accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and
Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498).
C on te n ts
Acknowledgementsiv
List of Abbreviations for Works by Quentin Meillassoux v
Entries AZ 19
Bibliography175
here will reveal the ethical import of even his most abstract metaphysical
considerations.
It should be noted that there is a further complication regarding his
recption arising from the chronology of the texts as they are appearing
in English. It is easily overlooked that Divine Inexistence precedes After
Finitude by almost a decade. Although the 2003 revision surely improved
the text, it remains the less rounded of the two. While the same confidence
is evident in both it is clear that After Finitude is the more mature text.
This perhaps explains why Meillassoux has been so hesitant to publish an
updated version of Divine Inexistence. The published articles reveal that
there is a consistency to his thinking going back to his dissertation, but it
is difficult to know whether publishing it now would best serve his overall
project. The Number and the Siren is something of an outlier within his
thinking, but it speaks to his commitment, found throughout his works,
to imaginative rationalism. In a recent interview with Sinziana Ravini, he
says there is much more to come and that he is working on topics as varied
as science fiction, Nietzsche, Duchamp, Hegel, and another engagement
with Mallarm (AOTF, 96). In an interview with Harman, he also men-
tions Darwinism and Pyrrho as future topics (IQM, 174). Nevertheless, it
is a fair wager that these specific contributions will supplement rather than
radically alter Meillassouxs architectonic.
Readers of Meillassoux will quickly notice certain tendencies when it
comes to his argumentative strategy. In almost all his texts the same series
of foundational arguments are repeated in condensed form. The reitera-
tions are often based on accounts provided in After Finitude. On occasion
this comes at the cost of clarity. This is also an issue when it comes to the
background his system presupposes. Although rarely engaged outside of
allusive footnotes, he takes it that his reader has a firm grip on everyone
from Immanuel Kant to Martin Heidegger to his mentor Alain Badiou.
This is why we have dedicated a number of entries to key figures in
the Continental tradition. For many commentators, the chief defect in
Meillassouxs system is that it oversimplifies the complex commitments
of his interlocutors until they become mere caricatures. Here we hope to
have provided the space for defenders of these thinkers to respond, which
is but another way to expand the readers context for reading Meillassoux.
Finally it should be said that any critical engagement here comes from
some of the best scholars in the field and thus the reader will have a front
seat to the important debates Meillassouxs oeuvre raises.
Flowing from this is the related issue of Meillassouxs influences.
Again, he is often enigmatic. What is certain is that he is a heterodox disci-
ple of Badiou in as much as his mathematical ontology is clearly modelled
on, but distinct from, that of his mentor. His evocation of Georg Cantors
i n t r o d u c t i o n 3
set theory to solve Humes problem of causal connection is the most direct
example of Badious mentorship. Descartes is another clear influence and
After Finitude is explicitly posited as an attempt to access the in-itself from
a Cartesian rather than Kantian framework. His depiction of hyper-chaos
as the primary absolute that founds a derivative mathematical absolute is
modelled on Descartes argument for extended substance, but with major
surgery allowing for this adaptation. Finally, it is arguable that Gilles
Deleuze is a strong influence since Meillassoux deploys rebooted versions
of immanence and virtuality in his arguments. However, he is careful to
ensure that he renders these distinct enough that his challenge to the prev-
alence of Deleuzes philosophy is clear. This is cemented by Meillassouxs
bracketing of Deleuze under the category of subjectivist metaphysician in
After Finitude (see also Subtraction and Contraction where both Deleuze
and Bergson are engaged indirectly).
On the flipside it is unmistakable that Meillassoux has certain philo-
sophical targets in mind. The critique of correlationism is aimed squarely
at the post-Kantian tradition of Continental philosophy. The term
correlation evokes everything from Kantian transcendental idealism to
phenomenology/post-phenomenology, structuralism/post-structuralism,
postmodernism, and deconstruction. Meillassoux directs especial ire at
the thinkers of the theological turn in French phenomenology since he
believes they have abandoned reason and revised the Kantian in-itself for
their own quasi-religious ends. It is possible to get the impression that
Meillassoux intends to develop a system broadly free from the traditional
problems of post-Kantian philosophy. However, his project does not
disavow the Critical project. Rather the Critical project is critiqued for
its slow disengagement from attempts to think the absolute such that the
forces of dogmatism, fanaticism and ideology have been given free reign
over it. This is the problem of fideism by which philosophers provide
cover for any belief about the absolute because it is a space untouchable by
human reason. This gives his project, which at first seems to be nothing
more than a defence of the natural sciences, a concrete edge.
In what follows we present Meillassouxs thinking in a twofold manner.
We first provide an account of his ontology as developed chiefly in
After Finitude and rounded out in the English-language articles such
as Potentiality and Virtuality and The Contingency of the Laws of
Nature. We then explain his ethical project as developed in Divine
Inexistence and expanded upon in articles such as Spectral Dilemma and
The Immanence of the World Beyond.
The central text of Meillassouxs system is After Finitude: An Essay
on the Necessity of Contingency. It does not deal with the full range of his
thinking and the reader unfamiliar with his others works may miss the
4 introduction
motivation behind it. We will come to see how this essay has a founda-
tional role in his system, providing a set of ontological commitments in
order that we might build an ethics upon them. His belief is that a rational
ethics requires an ontological grounding to motivate one to live ethically.
By this he does not mean that ethics is impossible without rationalism, but
that a rational ethics would be immune to all manner of cynical, despair-
ing, or fanatical impulses following in the wake of the so-called Death of
God. It can even seem, at first, as if his arguments are indifferent to the
status of the human. This is a major error and the central aim in what
follows demonstrates that before all else Meillassoux is concerned with
human dignity.
The fundamental ontological principles guiding Meillassouxs work
are as follows: being is independent of thought and thought can think
being. This seems uncontroversial, but the crux of his argument will be
that philosophers are in practice forced to deny both principles due to
other foundational principles they hold. The first principle reveals to us
Meillassouxs general commitment to materialism. Being is matter inde-
pendent of us. The second principle is evidence of his rationalism, and we
will come to see that being can be thought using formal languages such as
logic and mathematics.1 There is also an important hint that this theory
will lead us to address the nature of thoughts relation to the absolute
(AF, 1). He aims to think this relation by way of the distinction between
primary and secondary qualities. Primary qualities are said to belong to
an object as properties independent of ones relation to it. They subsist
whether one is there or not. Secondary qualities are those sensual qualities
that exist only in ones relation to the thing and they disappear outside that
relation. After Kant, this distinction fell under suspicion for its naivety.2
We cannot claim to think primary qualities outside the entangled poles of
subjectivity and objectivity (and their avatars). Meillassoux will argue that
the attention in post-Kantian philosophy shifts toward the co-constitutive
bond between these poles, but he wishes to reintegrate primary qualities
according to the Cartesian variation where they are considered intrinsic to
the mathematical properties of the object.
Before we can grasp the nuances of his positive commitments in detail
we need to look at his critique of correlationism. He defines it as the idea
1 It is worth mentioning here, given how tempting this critique is, that Meillassoux is
not going to say that being is mathematical in nature: This is not to Pythagorize,
or to assert that Being is inherently mathematical: it is rather to explain how it is that
a formal language manages to capture, from contingent-Being, properties that a ver-
nacular language fails at restituting (CBI, 80).
2 Meillassoux names Berkeley as a precursor to this position (AF, 3). Elsewhere, Berkeley
is given a more central role as the founder of the era of correlation (see IRR, 3).
i n t r o d u c t i o n 5
3 One possibility that emerges from this is subjectivist metaphysics, which involves
the hypostatization of some mental, sentient or vital term (AF, 37). Meillassoux has
called this a proliferation of subjectivations of the real and has renamed it subjectalism
(IRR,3).
8 introduction
not explicitly identified as weak or strong, who holds that both are wrong
since the best position on what happens after death is agnosticism. This
is because knowledge is always of this world and neither believer nor
atheist can claim to know what happens once we exit it. Both outcomes
are possible, but that is as far our knowledge goes. Then into the dialogue
(4) a subjective idealist enters and she argues that the two options are
unthinkable since the only range we have is that of thinking. In response
to both dogmatic positions and subjective idealism, the strict correlationist
must maintain that all three positions are possible and she recuses herself
from the debate.
Then finally a speculative philosopher enters, a stand-in for Meillassoux
himself, and claims that the two dogmatists and the subjective idealist
have misidentified the absolute. It is precisely the capacity-to-be-other
as such, captured through the eyes of the strict correlationist, that the
absolute indexes (AF, 56). This agnosticism means that when it comes to
the in-itself anything is equally possible. We see that in some cases, for
instance atheism, this includes the possibility of non-being (AF, 57).
Non-being is the ontological name for death and the commitment of
strict correlationism to the facticity of the correlation means that the cor-
relationist must recognise absolute possibilities, such as death, which are
intrinsically non-correlational. The possibility of non-correlated realities
is thereby assured from within strict correlationism. Meillassoux takes
this admission of the capacity-to-be-other to be the faultline leading out
of the correlation (AF, 57).4 For Meillassoux, we discover here a way to
think realities subsisting beyond the correlation and not dependent on it.
What subsists in-itself, irrespective of the correlation, is a time of a radical
inhumanity and this is why he will place a strong emphasis on temporality
when discussing the absolute (MSC, 12). In essence, he proposes that we
turn the absence of metaphysical necessity, and the possibility for every
entity to become otherwise, into an ontological principle that refers to
an absolute time affecting all entities. In other words, the correlationist
already takes for granted the existence of the contingency of the correla-
tion; the point is to see that contingency as an index of reality as such.
Many have noted that a problem arises here. This hyper-chaotic time,
ensuring the capacity-to-be-other of all entities, seems at odds with our
4 Strict correlationism cannot escape admitting this capacity due to a structural dilemma
it faces. It wants to de-absolutise the correlation against subjective idealism because it
is anti-absolutist, but to do this it would have to absolutise facticity in order to allow for
non-correlated possibilities. However, it does not want to absolutise facticity because it
is sceptical about non-correlated knowledge. This means it would have to de-absolutise
facticity, which in turn absolutises the correlation as found in subjective idealism.
i n t r o d u c t i o n 9
that is at odds with the claim that things could change for no reason at
all. Hence, there must be constant physical or natural laws ensuring this
stability. In short, if physical laws were actually contingent, we would
have already noticed (AF, 84). Taking Humes example of billiard balls
we know that given the same initial conditions, the same results invari-
ably follow (AF, 85). Humes problem raises a simple dilemma: whilst
we are certainly being reasonable to expect the same results to follow, it
cannot be guaranteed as necessary a priori. Our only recourse in terms of
gaining knowledge is our own experience, which is trapped in the present
and only knows what happened in the past; we mistake our habits for
physical necessity. The principle of non-contradiction can certainly tell
us that a contradictory event is impossible, but as to whether any non-
contradictory event will follow we have no assurance (CLN, 323). This
is one of the most long-standing puzzles in modern philosophy and with
typical confidence Meillassoux promises a novel solution to it.
There are, for Meillassoux, three possible responses to Humes
problem. The first is the metaphysical one. Here one demonstrates the
existence of a necessarily perfect being who acts as a guarantor that our
laws are the optimal ones for governing our universe. The second is the
sceptical or Humean solution. Although we cannot demonstrate causal
necessity a priori we can shift the problem toward the origin of our belief
in their necessity (AF, 88). This is the habituation we build up over time
when confronted with the consistency of outcomes. The third potential
response is the transcendental or Kantian solution.5 It asks us to imagine
what the consequences of the absence of causal necessity would be. For
Kant, the consequence would be the impossibility of structured represen-
tation, objectivity, or even consciousness. The very fact of representation
refutes the contingency of laws (CLN, 325). Meillassoux believes all three
positions adhere to the common assumption that the truth of causal
necessity cannot be called into question (AF, 90). This is precisely what
he wishes to question.
He proposes a fourth speculative solution and from this perspective one
argues not, as with Humean scepticism, that reason cannot demonstrate
apriori the necessity of laws. Instead one claims that reason proves a priori
the contingency of laws. What he does here is flip Humes supposed defer-
ence to the principle of sufficient reason such that we embrace what reason
tells us a priori about causal necessity namely that it does not exist. This
extends, in Meillassouxs ambitious critique, to the physical or natural
laws themselves. If causal connection cannot be demonstrated then we
5 Here Meillassoux has in mind the objective deduction of the categories in the Analytic
of Concepts from Kants Critique of Pure Reason.
i n t r o d u c t i o n 11
must abandon it and trust our rational instincts (AF, 91). However, we
still have the dilemma as to why natural and physical laws are so consist-
ently stable and why, despite what reason tells us, we do not encounter
constant chaos. To destabilise this picture he zones in on what he calls the
necessitarian inference involved in our belief in causal necessity (AF, 94).
This inference takes it that the stability of laws presupposes the necessity
of those laws (AF, 94). It works as follows: (a) if laws could change for no
reason they would do so frequently (b) but they do not and thus (c) they
cannot and should be considered necessary. Accepting that (b) is incon-
testable he focuses on (a), which if undermined collapses the entire argu-
ment. He calls the force of the argument the frequentialist implication,
which boils down to the belief that the contingency of the laws of nature
would result in their frequent transformation (AF, 95).
There is a subtle move here in the suggestion that the argument for
the stability of laws is based on a form of unacknowledged mathematical
reasoning. Drawing on the work of Jean-Ren Vernes (1982), Meillassoux
thinks that the frequentialist implication is enmeshed with probabilistic
reasoning (AF, 95). To illustrate this point, he introduces the example
of a gambler faced with a die that always lands on the same face, leading
him to suspect that it is very probably loaded (AF, 96). In the classic
scenario of the throw of the dice there are equally probable outcomes that
we can calculate. In this scenario that which is equally thinkable [a priori],
is equally possible (AF, 96). Once the dice are thrown and an outcome
occurs we can assign probabilistic reasoning to chance reoccurrences. If,
however, we started with this thesis of equiprobability and the same result
kept occurring, we have reason to assume that we are not dealing with
chance. We suspect a hidden cause is ensuring the outcome. If the dice
landed on the same face not just for the duration of the game, but for our
entire lives, then we are in the situation we find ourselves in with physical
laws. This leads one to accept that there is some underlying reason why
they always re-occur. It is perhaps impossible to ever know this reason, as
Hume believes, but that there is one is not in doubt.
The problem is in treating the universe the same way we treat events
within it, that is, using probabilistic reasoning. This would necessitate
that we are in position to conceive of a complete set of all universes with
alternative physical laws.6 What Meillassoux has in mind here are possible
worlds governed by different laws; each throw of the dice would represent
a new possible world and its laws being put into effect (IWB, 448). In
our example, the dice-universe always lands on ours leading us to make
6 Meillassoux notes that non-contradiction is still applicable here since otherwise they
would not be conceivable alternatives (CLN, 329).
12 introduction
7 Not to be confused with the pure supplements introduced by advents (IRR, 15).
8 See PV, 65 where recourse to experience is eliminated as a feasible option.
9 Meillassoux gives an account of the mathematics involved at various places. See CLN,
3323; AF, 134 fn 11; and PV, 667. See also Gironi 2011: 423.
10 Meillassoux admits that other set-theoretical axiomatics may allow for the totality
required, but the existence of this one axiomatic at least undermines it (CLN, 333).
i n t r o d u c t i o n 13
for allowing such statements to gain traction. This event is linked to the
mathematization of nature, the unleashing of formal languages, that
renders the discourse on anterior and ulterior time meaningful without
recourse to fabulation (AF, 112). This process of de-mystification is
further accompanied by an awareness of the autonomy of the world, its
indifference to us, and its subsistence regardless of our presence (AF, 115).
We approach this non-correlated world in mathematical terms and on that
basis hypothesise meaningfully about it. Thus Meillassoux will suggest
that a more fitting name for the Kantian Copernican turn, which excised
this Galilean-Copernican spirit from its remit, is the Ptolemaic counter-
revolution in philosophy (AF, 118).
While Kant is commended for excising dogmatic metaphysics from phi-
losophy, he is condemned for missing the speculative import of modern
science (AF, 120, italics removed). In a way, Meillassoux is disappointed
that as the natural sciences opened us up to the great outdoors, philoso-
phy went another way and created nothing more than an insular field of
limited possibilities. How then to revive the Galilean-Copernican spirit
for philosophy? What speculative tasks remain ahead of us? After Finitude
ends by outlining what this would require. In particular, Meillassoux
believes we must discover a link between the capacity of mathematics as a
formal language and the principle of factiality.11 The motivation for this
derivation arises firstly from the problem of ancestrality, which requires a
derivation supporting the claim that what is mathematically conceivable
is absolutely possible and hence can subsist beyond correlated realities
(AF, 126). Secondly, this derivation is needed to properly resolve the
problem of causal connection and this would allow us provide ontological
support for the intotalisation thesis in relation to manifest stability since,
as it stands, the intotalisation hypothesis remains merely one possible
reading of set theory amongst others (AF, 127). Two absolutisations are
required then: the ontic one concerning the possibility of ancestral realities
and the ontological one concerning the non-Whole. This is where After
Finitude leaves off, and we can turn now to an entirely different facet of
Meillassouxs thinking: his ethics.
Meillassouxs work is not simply focused on the nature of an abstract
absolute, but includes an important ethical dimension. He is, following
a long line of thinkers in the French and German tradition, not content
with simply propounding a new ontological system, but wants also to
reshape the way in which we regard our common possibilities of being
11 The first provisional attempt occurs in IRR, 1838, but given that this occurs in the
context of a conference paper we will need to await the first complete example of this
demonstration.
14 introduction
a mourning over all those lost in history, those whose deaths we cannot
begin to put in rational order or make any sense of. There is no need to
detail all those kinds of spectres Meillassoux describes the dead child,
the victims of heinous massacres of all sorts since only the most affectless
of us do not feel the existential weight of the horrors of this or that death,
as well as all the Holocausts of history. To be human is to live under the
shadow of this wide work of mourning. For Meillassoux essential mourn-
ing over these spectres is impossible in our current World. What words
could console us concerning them?
This is Meillassouxs way of indirectly addressing the problem of
whether we can accept a God who would allow such deaths to occur. In this
way, Meillassoux follows, from a different direction, the view of Jacques
Derrida, namely that our lives are always lived as a work of mourning.
However, whereas Derrida saw this finitude as inexorable, Meillassoux
argues that the nature of hyper-chaos ensures that it is possible that our
condition could be otherwise. Who would choose to believe in a God who
would allow such deaths? For the believer we have precisely the opposite
problem than that faced by the nihilist. This is the dilemma that arises
from the lack of a transcending principle at work in the world that would
provide justice for the departed. Note well that the argument, as produced
by Meillassoux, takes place at the ethical level. These are not dry proofs for
a clockmaker God or a mere first principle that founds nature. This is not
the God of the philosophers. Rather at its heart, the spectral dilemma con-
cerns a personalist God, one who answers our prayers and who can provide
mercy for the living and the dead alike. This God is not metaphysical, but
ethical: a plea for any light with which to banish away our darkest fears.
The answer Meillassoux provides for the atheist faced with the spectral
dilemma is not in the form of various proofs for Gods inexistence. We hear
nothing of evolutionary theory or physicist accounts of the Big Bang that
disprove the book of Genesis, or about the problematic logics of the cosmo-
logical proof, or all the well-worn paths of the non-believer. The atheist,
rather, responds to the dilemma in precisely ethical terms:
You want to hope, [the theist says], for something for the dead You hope for
justice in the next world: but in what would this consist? It would be a justice
done under the auspices of a God who had himself allowed the worst acts to be
committed You call just, and even good, such a God To live under the reign
of such a perverse being, who corrupts the most noble words love, justice with
his odious practices: isnt this a good definition of hell? To this hell you wish
for them, I prefer, for them as for myself, nothingness, which will leave them in
peace and conserve their dignity, rather than putting them at the mercy of the
omnipotence of your pitiless Demiurge. (DI, 265)
16 introduction
of our current condition, one that gives us every reason, it seems, to find
God unforgivable. Meillassoux gives us a veritable hauntology, a study of
these spectres who, he says, refuse to pass over, who still belong to the
world of the living, even as unending shadows that we can only meekly
begin to countenance (SD, 262). He argues not only that this thinking of
the possible God marks a future just world, but that it should have effects
upon us in this one. Freed by an existential weight of utter hopelessness we
can begin to act differently in this World.
In Kants philosophy, the dignity of the human was founded in its
ability to reason and on this basis give itself over to the moral law. For
Meillassoux, the ultimate being is the one who can think the factial-
ity of reality and thus have a rational hope for an immanent World to
come (IWB, 462). This figure, of whom he suggests the human may
just be one type, is notable for both its cognitive and tragic character:
rational enough to understand the contingency of all, it also knows the
ever-present possibility of its own death. As Meillassoux understands the
fourth World, God will prevent the decay of our bodies, but given that
God is not necessary, we cannot hold out the hope that He is eternal or
everlasting. Thus even in Meillassouxs system, where justice and equal-
ity might one day win out, death is still a contingent possibility given the
unpredictable power of hyper-chaos. While Meillassoux is interested in
working out the fourth Worlds formal possibility, the point is to think
how this dense possibility effects our conduct in this World. This vision
of a future is one that he thinks calls forth what he dubs the eschatological
or vectorial subject, one magnetically attracted by the emancipation of
the World to come (IWB, 463).
The vectorial subject, he argues, is produced through successive specu-
lative stages: (1) first, a removal from despair by recognising the lack of
limits for reason, since the latter can move speculatively to the absolute.
This absolutisation of reason thus counters Kants finite subject while
deciphering a potential God. The vectorial subject provides both a hope
for a future beyond this World and knows that this World may not arrive,
but Meillassoux argues that this is anything but a political quietism. We
know what a future World would be that could deliver us from injustice,
and thus we work, here and now, to bring about the justice we can. (2)The
second stage for the vectorial subject is nihilism, which Meillassoux
understands as this subjects recognition of the coming World as horrify-
ing. Meillassoux argues that the truly difficult moment is the realisation
that the coming of the fourth World could mean an immortality from
which there is no escape. This nihilism was first identified by Nietzsche in
his famed Eternal Recurrence of the Same, which as Meillassoux rightly
argues, is not a consideration of our finitude, but rather the possibility of
18 introduction
our immortality. The greatest weight, the one that grounds Nietzsches
nihilism, is not death, but an everlasting (and tedious) life.
In such a scenario the vectorial subject faces an aporia beyond that which
she faced in the spectral dilemma: either the coming World arrives and the
vectorial subject sees the satisfaction of her greatest hopes, at which point
she becomes meaningless, or it doesnt arrive and these hopes face no
such satisfaction. If its the former, then the vectorial subject, formed by a
quest for justice, no longer has any meaning for going on; her purpose has
been fulfilled and she loses her very reason for being. This also means that
Meillassoux agrees with Marx that any true communism equivalent to a
future World of justice, as he sees it is also the cessation of politics. This
not to say, though, that a World freed of politics, that is, no longer with
material inequities and misery, would be free of disquiet. It would still be
a World with love and its betrayal, a World with the life of thought and
horrific mediocrity, and all the other petty miseries life offers. The vecto-
rial subject, then, looks forward to a World not of happiness, but a World
of disquietude, one from which death cannot provide an escape. Our hope,
then, is a peculiar one: to free human beings from material misery in order
that they may experience the human dignity of disquietude and anxiety.
Having come to this, we conclude our brief entre onto Meillassouxs
thought, a form of thinking that is at once speculative and ethical, highly
rationalist and deeply felt. In the dictionary that follows, our contributors
have done a remarkable job of filling in the details of our broad sketch
above. They dont always agree with Meillassoux, but their admiration
for what is an increasingly audacious body of work means they are always
fair. It is our hope to provide you the tools to follow him with all of his
potential, whether in disquietude of the World to come or in disagreement
with his major claims.
A
ABSOLUTE
Bart Zantvoort
The question of the absolute has historically been posed in two ways.
Firstly: what is the ultimate ground or foundation for reality as a whole?
This is framed in at least three ways: what is the first cause, the uncon-
ditioned, or the highest entity? Secondly: what are the absolute, non-
relative properties of things? That is, what are the attributes of a given
entity independent from the standpoint of an observer?
Meillassoux takes up this classical schema in an unusual way. Taking
Ren Descartes as an example, he distinguishes between a primary
absolute and a derivative absolute (AF, 30). For Descartes, the primary
absolute is the existence of a perfect, all-powerful God (see Cartesian
in-itself). The secondary absolute, which is the capacity of mathematics
to describe the non-relative properties of things, can be derived from the
primary absolute, because a perfect God would not deceive us in our
use of mathematics. Meillassoux agrees with Descartes that we need to
demonstrate the absolute reach of mathematics. But he thinks that after
Immanuel Kants critique of dogmatism and his own destruction of the
principle of sufficient reason, we can no longer invoke God or any
other form of highest entity to do so. Instead, he proposes the principle of
factiality as his own primary absolute.
This principle states that contingency alone is necessary (AF, 80).
According to Meillassoux, all beings are necessarily contingent, and
we can know this absolutely. (It must be noted here that absolute for
Meillassoux seems to entail both that we can know absolutely that contin-
gency is necessary and that this principle is itself absolutely necessary). It
is from this principle that the capacity of mathematics to describe absolute
properties of things is supposed to be derived. Meillassoux uses absolute
20 a b s o l u t e
forms a totality or not. The absolute proof of the stability of the laws of
nature would require him to derive the necessity of Cantors theorem from
the principle of factiality (AF, 110).
Contrary to many interpretations, therefore, Meillassoux is not trying
to prove that the laws of nature could change at any moment. The ultimate
ambitions in After Finitude are, in fact, to prove the following: (1) The abso-
lute necessity of the principle of factiality; (2) The absolute possibility (AF,
117) of the world described by mathematics (the capacity of mathematics
to accurately describe contingent entities, which exist independently from
us); (3) The absolute and ... unconditionally necessary scope (AF, 127)
of the Cantorian transfinite (see Georg Cantor), which will allow us to
legitimize absolutely the stability of natural laws.
Of these aims, only the first is accomplished in After Finitude. In
Iteration, Reiteration, Repetition, Meillassoux takes up the project of
proving the absolute status of mathematics again, but he has to conclude
that he has not succeeded (IRR, 37). If, therefore, After Finitude serves as a
critique of correlationism, demonstrating that the limits of knowledge have
been too narrowly constructed, we are still awaiting Meillassouxs second
critique in which he proves that thought, in the form of mathematics, can
think the absolute.
ADVENT
Christina Smerick
The word Advent means a coming or an arrival. In the Christian tradi-
tion, advent is a liturgical time, before Christmas, when Christians
anticipate the coming of the Christ child and reflect and repent upon the
various ways in which they have failed to live toward the ethic articulated
by Christ in Scripture. Advent is most strongly linked to the Incarnation
of Christ the entry of God into the world in bodily form. Advent is thus
the revelation of God in Christ an indication of the radical reconcilia-
tion between the divine and the human, the spiritual and the material.
The advent of Christ in the world is a radical in-breaking of the divine
not merely as a deus ex machina but as a human being, a material entity.
Advent also implies a second Advent the return of Christ to rule.
Advent thus functions as a time to reflect both upon the past and the
future, and draws attention to the notion that this present time is a time
between between the Incarnation and the Return, a time of already
and not yet. Advent indicates both the yearning for deliverance and the
hope for redemption.
22 a n c e s t r a l i t y
ANCESTRALITY
Rodrigo Nunes
The problem of ancestrality is Meillassouxs opening gambit in After
Finitude, and thus, in a sense, also a major aspect of what his philosophy
as a whole is recognised for. It sets the scene for everything that follows:
the characterisation of correlationisms limits and its unholy alliance
with fideism; the deduction of the principle of factiality and the
attainment of an absolute in the form of hyper-chaos; the derivation
of the determinate conditions facticity imposes on all beings; and the
defence of mathematised sciences capacity to access a nature thought
independently from humans (see Cartesian in-itself). It matters pre-
cisely as a philosophical problem, one liable to make us revise decisions
often considered as infrangible since Kant (AF, 37). The extent of
Meillassouxs attachment to it is nonetheless debatable since the book
itself states the wish only to provide a rigorous formulation of it in
such a way that its resolution no longer seems utterly inconceivable to us
(AF, 37).
The argument starts by defining ancestral statements as those bearing on
any reality prior to the emergence of the human species, or of life on earth
in general, not by distance in time, which makes something merely ancient,
but in terms of anteriority in time in relation to any sentient or sapient
relation to the world. While ostensibly addressing dia-chronicity, the
temporal lag that ancestral statements reveal between world and relation-
to-world, the problem extends to scientific statements as a whole, to the
extent that it concerns the capacity to think the world in itself, separately
from its givenness to us. The problem, in a nutshell, is: how can we have
knowledge of something that was given prior to there being any mind it
could be given to?
a n c e s t r a l i t y 23
(AF, 57). This is the subjective idealists position: in order to know myself
to be mortal, I must be capable of thinking my death as not requiring my
thought of it to be effective, and hence as something outside of the cor-
relational circle (AF, 78).
Yet the question of my death requiring my thought of it to be actual
only arises if I take my thought to constitute its objects in the sense of
causing their ontic existence as something out there in the world. And
for whom, except an extreme subjective idealist, is a subjective act of
thought the cause of somethings existence? It is one thing to say that
xonly is for me if it is for me, a more subtle tautology than it seems, and
another to say that x only is if it is for me, which is the position against
which Meillassoux is arguing. If I subscribe to the former, I can draw a
further distinction between two ways in which x can be for me: experience
of my death is impossible, as the consciousness and sensory apparatus
necessary to register it would be lacking. But I can think myself as mortal,
for example, via the perfectly legitimate inductive reasoning that if I am
similar to other living beings in most aspects, and living beings are, as far
as I know, mortal, I must be similar to them in that respect, too. My own
death can be an object of thought for me as an actual possibility whose
occurrence is independent from my thought, even if it cannot be an object
of experience. This is a much more modest alternative to either believing
things do not exist unless I think them, or hyper-chaos.
That Meillassoux reduces the issue to a choice between the latter two
becomes clear when he states that unless by thinking contingency as an
absolute, like the speculative philosopher, it would never have occurred to
you not to be a subjective (or speculative) idealist (AF, 59). It would seem
that in forcing a choice between the speculative absolute and an extreme,
solipsistic subjective idealism, Meillassoux makes his most important
argument depend on an artificial restriction of our real philosophical
alternatives. As a consequence, he builds his proof on the refutation of the
weakest of all the positions he wishes to oppose and leaves unconsidered
all sorts of possible non-extreme correlationisms for which the problem of
ancestrality in all likelihood would not arise.
ANHYPOTHETICAL
Rodrigo Nunes
He whose subject is being qua being must be able to state the most
certain principles of all things, one that is non-hypothetical and which
every one must have who knows anything about being; this is how
a n h y p o t h e t i c a l 25
thesis, hypothesis etc. (DI2, 534, his emphasis). One could easily expect
this to apply to philosophy, given the ascendancy of correlationism; the
fact that Meillassoux extends it to the hypothetico-deductive reason
deployed by logic and mathematics and the inductive reason deployed
by experimental sciences (DI2, 534), however, complicates the picture
painted at the start of After Finitude. If the sciences understand themselves
as hypothetical, what purchase can the argument of ancestrality retain?
Is there a correlationism of the sciences themselves? What would that
mean for the concept of fideism?
ARCHE-FOSSIL
Rodrigo Nunes
Arche-fossils materials indicating the existence of an ancestral reality
or event; one that is anterior to terrestrial life (AF, 10) are what
ancestral statements are about. They are that which the problem of
ancestrality is meant to show correlationism as incapable of thinking.
Two examples of arche-fossil are an isotope whose rate of radioactive
decay we know, or the luminous emission of a star that informs us as
to the date of its formation (AF, 10). Since speculative materialism
deals only with the necessary conditions that belong to a contingency
delivered of all constraints other than that (or those) of its own eternity,
it does not concern itself with existing things, which are by necessity
contingent (IRR, 12). Thus, as Meillassoux clarifies, the arche-fossil was
employed in After Finitude only so as to problematize the contemporary
self-evidence of correlationism, by way of arguing that the problem of
ancestrality appears insoluble for as long as one stays within the correla-
tional circle (IRR, 12).
It is the fact that the arche-fossil indexes a lacuna of manifestation
rather than in manifestation not a spatio-temporally distant event or
being, but specifically one that is prior to any correlation that allows
Meillassoux to expose correlationisms embarrassment, which comes
in the face of contemporary sciences apparent capacity to think nature
independently from any phenomenological experience of it, or even
a world wherein spatio-temporal givenness itself came into being within a
time and a space which preceded every variety of givenness (AF, 22). Yet
Ray Brassier makes the perspicuous point that, to the extent that his
defence of the absolute rights of objective reality pivots around estab-
lishing a rift between ancestral time and spatio-temporal distance, it
harbours a concession to correlationism, for surely it is not just ancestral
a r c h i - f a c t 27
phenomena which challenge the latter, but simply the reality described
by the modern natural sciences tout court (Brassier 2007: 59). To insist
that only the ancestrality presented by the arche-fossil transcends cor-
relational constitution, therefore, is to create an exception where there
is none: science tells us that we are surrounded by mind-independent
processes all the time, and the fact that these are contemporaneous with
the existenceof consciousness, while the accretion of the earth preceded
it, is quite irrelevant (Brassier 2007: 60).
Meillassouxs choice of isotope dating as an example is perhaps an even
greater trouble for his argument. Not, pace Hallward, because measuring
is a human, convention-based practice the point about the reality of what
is measured still stands but because this being an area in which preci-
sion is paramount, and thus highly dependent on advanced technology, it
displays rectification much more habitually than, say, the formalisation of
certain physical relations into mathematical functions (see the back and
forth between Hallward 2011 and Brown 2011). As such, it brings into
sharper focus the difficult spot in which Meillassouxs defence of math-
ematised science places him in regard to the revisability of scientific claims
(see Johnston 2011). Estimates of the age of the universe have varied a fair
amount throughout the last century, during which the Hubble constant,
the first relatively accurate measurement of the rate of expansion of the
universe, was recalculated several times. It was only with the discovery of
microwave cosmic background radiation in the 1960s that a way was found
to determine the Hubble constant without the need to refer to galaxy
distances, thus increasing accuracy. Throughout the last decade, the exact
measure changed literally every two years, as the data from the Wilkinson
Microwave Anisotropy Probe measurements were released, providing
ever greater precision so that the actual figure has been revised even after
the publication of After Finitude.
A correlationist rejoinder to Meillassoux could therefore be that the
universe coming into existence is something that effectively took place
13.75 billion years ago, at least according to todays best science; but the
event of this becoming an object of our knowledge thus being true for
us only took place as recently as 2010, when scientific consensus stabi-
lised around this measurement.
ARCHI-FACT
An alternative name for the facticity of the correlation. See, for example,
MSC, 1718.
28 a t h e i s m / t h e i s m
ATHEISM/THEISM
Paul OMahoney
Atheism is a profession of non-belief in the existence of any God, which
is opposed by both theism and deism. Theism is the belief in the existence
of at least one God, who evinces a concern for the world. This world can
thus be influenced by God and in many belief systems it is also the crea-
tion of the God. As such, theism is a belief with a specific content, where
the nature of the deity is accessible to human beings, sometimes through
reason, though for others this access can only come through revelation.
With this theism is distinguished from deism. Deism is the assumption
that, although God or gods do exist and may have created the world, they
do not intervene in this world. Deism thus rejects all accounts of religious
revelation or the miraculous interaction of a deity with creation. All
revealed religions therefore count as theistic. The modern origin of theism
is commonly dated to the 1660s, attributed to Ralph Cudworth, who used
it in his The True Intellectual System of the Universe, first published in
1678. Cudworth was concerned to refute atheism, along with all moral
and political philosophy derived from or conducive to atheistic principles.
Two things can immediately be noted about Meillassouxs position.
First, he offers a stronger conception of atheism. Second, though deism
counts as a religious belief, Meillassouxs use of the term the religious
in all cases clearly implies theistic beliefs (see irreligion). Atheism and
the religious are considered opposites. Each denies to the other the power
to refute its position; this is one feature of contemporary fideism, where
even atheism is reduced to a mere belief and can therefore essentially be
equated with religion. It is Meillassouxs stronger and stricter interpreta-
tion of atheism that allows him to propose a third option to these alterna-
tives, which apparently exhaust all possibilities. Rather than the beliefs
that there is or is not a God, for Meillassoux:
The two theses are in truth stronger than these factual statements: for their sense
lies in the supposedly necessary character of either the inexistence or the existence
of God. To be atheist is not simply to maintain that God does not exist, but also
that he could not exist; to be a believer is to have faith in the essential existence
of God. (SD, 268)
posit God as an eternal possibility. This would be the personal God who
brings with Him the promise of justice and the resurrection of the dead
as a real possibility:
B
BADIOU, ALAIN
Christopher Norris
Alain Badiou was Meillassouxs teacher and mentor at a formative stage
in the latters intellectual development and has continued to encourage
and actively promote the younger mans work. Badious influence is
everywhere evident in Meillassouxs thought, although it doesnt always
take the more overt forms of explicit agreement or closely convergent
thinking. Certainly there is a lot of common ground between them, both
as a matter of shared philosophical commitments and the range of topics
to which their work has been addressed. The intellectual kinship comes
out most clearly in the opening section of After Finitude with its now
famous attack on correlationism that is to say, on the epistemology
of Immanuel Kant along with all the proliferating woes in its wake and
its dramatic, not to say imperious, statement of the adversary case for an
outlook of intransigent or hard-line objectivist realism. It is also apparent
in Meillassouxs high regard for mathematics, the physical sciences,
and art (especially poetry) as among philosophys prime conditions or
essential means of critical orientation. Both of them tend to philosophise
30 b a d i o u , a l a i n
on the subject as militant of truth, that is, the subject who comes into
existence solely as a result of taking up that specific challenge and there-
after investing their best efforts in its carrying-through. Meillassoux is
also a realist, as witness most strikingly those now famous pages in
After Finitude where he deploys the arche-fossil, that is, the immemorial
relic of a time before the advent of any sentient life-forms, as a supposed
knock-down argument against all correlationism, whether of a Kantian
(epistemological) or latter-day (post-linguistic-turn) persuasion. However
his realism differs from Badious in finding no such procedurally speci-
fied role for the human subject, perhaps because it might seem to soften
or compromise his hard objectivist stance, and also, as fairly leaps off the
page toward the end of After Finitude, in the kinds of consequences he
draws from set-theoretical reflection on the multiple orders of infinity.
It is here that Meillassoux advances his extraordinary reading of David
Hume where he steals a spectacular march on the latters much-debated
outlook of epistemological scepticism with regard to causal explanations
and our grounds (or lack of them) for supposing the uniformity of nature.
This Meillassoux rejects in favour of a nominally realist outlook according
to which it is reality that changes, for all that we can possibly know, along
with those putative laws of nature that, once acquainted with Cantors
discovery, we must conceive as subject to radical mutation from moment
to moment across the infinities of possible worlds that might pop into and
out of existence.
I shall not here go into the problems with this speculative venture from
the viewpoint of a realist outlook compatible with the sorts of causal-
explanatory reasoning basic to the physical sciences. My point is that it
stands in striking contrast to Badious insistence that if we are capable of
making discoveries or achieving advances in mathematics, the physical
sciences, politics, or art then this entails a number of precepts decidedly
at odds with Meillassouxs version of Hume. These are, firstly, that in
any given situation, there are uncounted multiples that objectively exceed
whatever is known, recognised, or grasped concerning that situation and,
secondly, that for this reason truth exceeds knowledge, that is, it must
be thought of as objective, recognition-transcendent, or epistemically
unconstrained. Moreover, thirdly, if indeed mathematics is ontology
then certain kinds of formal reasoning (from Cantors diagonal proce-
dure to the concept/method/technique of forcing elaborated by Paul
Cohen) are capable eventually of delivering truths that go beyond a
presently existing state of knowledge but that are none the less latent or
(so-far unknowably) contained within it. Scientific revolutions thus occur
not as the result of some obscure Kuhnian process of rationally under-
motivated paradigm-change but by the working-through among faithful
32 b a d i o u , a l a i n
BRASSIER, RAY
Pete Wolfendale
Ray Brassier is a Scottish philosopher largely responsible for popularis-
ing Meillassouxs work in the Anglophone world. He published one of
the first critical engagements with Meillassouxs work in English and
was the translator of the first English edition of After Finitude. He was
also one of the principal organisers and one of the four speakers at the
infamous Speculative Realism conference at Goldsmiths College in
2007, though he has since distanced himself from that term. He has
consistently criticised what he sees as the avoidance of epistemological
problems in Anglophone Continental philosophy, as well as the ignorance
of and sometimes hostility toward the natural sciences often associated
with it. There is a profound affinity between Brassiers criticisms and
Meillassouxs critique of correlationism, in so far as they both insist
on the necessity of taking the results of natural science literally, but there
is equally an affinity between their positive positions, in so far as they
are both committed to the revival of rationalism in contemporary phi-
losophy. Nevertheless, Brassier has a number of important disagreements
with Meillassoux, some of which have grown more serious as his position
has developed and changed in recent years. We will begin by presenting an
outline of Brassiers thought in his book Nihil Unbound, and the criticisms
34 b r a s s i e r , r a y
C
CANTOR, GEORG
Paul Livingston
Georg Cantor was the creator of set theory and the modern theory of the
mathematical infinite. His discovery of a rigorous, mathematical way to
treat actually existing infinite sets revolutionised the foundations of math-
ematics as well as philosophical thinking about infinity, with implications
that continue to be actively explored today. Prior to Cantor, philosophers
had argued that the infinite can exist only potentially and never actually
(for example, Aristotle), that the concept of an actually existing infinite
quantity is contradictory or paradoxical in itself (for example, Locke and
Galileo), or that the actual infinite must be identified with the absolute
or the divine, and hence cannot be understood by a finite intellect (for
example, Aquinas) (Moore 2001: 1744, 7583). Against each of these
interpretations, Cantor showed that it is mathematically possible and
useful to discuss an open hierarchy of infinite sets the so-called transfi-
nite hierarchy and that their ordering and relationships could be rigor-
ously modelled and understood.
Around 1874, working on the problem of finding general trigonometric
representations for functions, Cantor discovered that infinite sets of differ-
ing sizes could be distinguished and that the set of natural numbers or pos-
itive whole numbers (1, 2, 3) is smaller than the set of all real numbers
(numbers with indefinitely long decimal parts). This led Cantor to posit
the bases of what would become set theory, and in 1883 he defined a set
(Menge) as any many [Viele] which can be thought of as one, that is, every
totality of definite elements which can be united to a whole through a law,
commenting also that by this I believe I have defined something related
to the Platonic eidos or idea (quoted in Hallett 1986: 33). His definition of
sets allowed him to introduce the concepts of set cardinality, that is, the
size of sets considered in terms of the possibility of putting them into one
to one correspondence with one another, and the power set, which is the
set of all subsets, the arbitrary re-groupings of the elements of a given set.
These ideas led him to be able to prove what has become known as
Cantors Theorem: any set, whether finite or infinite, has a power set that
is strictly larger than itself (in the sense of one-to-one correspondence). In
proving the theorem, Cantor invented the powerful and general technique
38 c a n t o r , g e o r g
t otalities is not simply unthinkable (and indeed can be modelled with what
is called dialetheiac logics, certain non-well-founded set theories, and
formalisations of critical, dialectical and deconstructive thought about
contradiction), it is not clear that either Badiou or Meillassoux is justified
in interpreting Cantorian set theory as excluding this possibility.
CARTESIAN IN-ITSELF
Sebastian Purcell
Rehabilitating the idea of the Cartesian in-itself after the Kantian Critical
project (see Immanuel Kant) as a means for critiquing contemporary
forms of correlationism, such as phenomenology and the linguistic turn
in mid-century Anglo-American philosophy, is the basic metaphysical
objective of Meillassouxs speculative materialism.
The Cartesian in-itself is best understood in relation to the distinction
between primary and secondary qualities, terms which were first
coined by John Locke, but which are clearly present in Ren Descartes
thought. For the latter thinker secondary qualities are those which exist
both in relation to my own conscious perception and the object itself.
For example, if you were to place your hand over a candle flame, the heat
you would feel is something registered in your own consciousness. The
flame itself does not feel the heat. Yet, your own feelings of heat are not
hallucinations because they are prompted by proximity to the flame. This
means that while secondary qualities exist in relation to you, they do not
exist solely in your mind, but also bear some relation to the object. Primary
qualities, by contrast, are those properties of the object that would exist
even if you were not around to perceive them, and which are thus under-
stood to be inseparable from the object. For Descartes these properties
are those that pertain to spatial extension, and so are subject to geometric
proof. They include width, length, movement, depth, size and figure.
Meillassoux generalises Descartes account of primary qualities and
makes it compatible with advances in contemporary mathematics. The
Cartesian in-itself satisfies the following two conditions: it is all the aspects
of the object that can be formulated in mathematical terms, and it is those
aspects that can be meaningfully conceived as properties of the object itself
(AF, 3). By mathematical formulation and meaningfully conceived
Meillassoux intends those aspects that are subject to proof by means of
modern mathematics most basic abstract algebra, namely set theory
in its standard Zermelo-Fraenkel formulation, and standard non-formal
methods of mathematical proof (see Georg Cantor).
child ( infans ), the 41
CAUSATION
Leon Niemoczynski
According to Meillassouxs ontology described in his theorisation of the
fourth World of justice, the Child can be interpreted to be the birth
of an infant that is the symbol of the rebirth of humanity, or it can be
interpreted as The Child of Man, a mediating Christ-like figure who
brings divinity itself under the universal conditions of contingency (DI,
334). Although Meillassouxs descriptions of the literal birth of the infans
are vague, according to LInexistence divine the birth of the child marks a
key moment in the messianic eschatology (or eschaology as coined in
Immanence of the World Beyond) indicating a knitting together of Greek
reason and Judeo-Christian faith with hope in the contingent conditions of
hyper-chaos that enable future change (IWB, 463).
Meillassoux states that the child represents the God to come present
in humanitys womb (DI, 335). This is to say that humanity can be
42 c o n t i n g e n c y
pregnant with hope for a future to come, to see the birth of a new World,
just as in the past conditions have given birth to Worlds of life, matter
and thought. Thus, the infans represents a spirit of expectation making
each human a forerunner of God (DI, 232). According to Meillassoux,
however, there will always be some ambiguity regarding the birth of the
child during, before, or after the advent of the fourth World of justice.
This is due to the indifferent power of the surcontingent that covers the
predictability of any symbolic birth that is to happen. Regardless of the
unpredictability of this symbolic gesture made by the birth of the child,
Meillassoux ventures that it is a requirement in the advent of the incarna-
tion of universal justice.
The child, or infans in Latin, suggests for Meillassoux the unborn child
or one who does not speak (DI, 225). This symbolisation assures the
impossibility of any specific religious vision for the advent of the fourth
World. The child is the one who teaches us that its power is not the
manifestation of a superior power of providence, but of contingency alone
(DI, 225). The child teaches others that power is not to be had in an authori-
tative transcendent manner in its own right, but is solely an immanent end
(DI, 225). The child also teaches humanity the impossibility of despising
ourselves with respect to what makes us human thus [the child] cannot
be loved as Lord but as one who knows itself to be equal. It is part of
the divine gesture that has made itself human among humans (DI, 225).
In short, the child represents the supreme abandonment of power
during the time in which a Christ-like messianic figure, a mediator,
assumes the power of rebirth, inaugurates a process of bodily resurrec-
tion so that justice can be brought about for the dead, and relinquishes
power once justice is accomplished for which the advent was this events
founding condition. Thus the child is a human mediator between human-
itys current World and universal justice.
CONTINGENCY
Nathan Brown
The centrality of this concept to Meillassouxs enterprise is signalled by
the subtitle of After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. The
primary claim of Meillassouxs philosophy is that only contingency can and
must be thought as absolutely necessary. The absolute, he argues, is the
absolute impossibility of a necessary being (AF, 60). Thus, his effort is to
think contingency in a manner that is speculative rather than either empiri-
cal or metaphysical. Contingency is thought as an absolute, as a property
c o n t i n g e n c y 43
of the in-itself rather than of observable reality. Yet grasping this absolute
does not require the metaphysical assertion than an absolute entity exists;
on the contrary, it is precisely the impossibility of the existence of such an
entity that delivers the veritable concept of contingency. It is through the
concept of absolute contingency that Meillassoux thus opens an alternative
passage between empiricist scepticism and dogmatic rationalism to that
cleared by Immanuel Kants transcendental philosophy.
Several distinctions are required to isolate the specific concept of
contingency that we find in Meillassouxs work. Contingency must be
distinguished from both facticity and chance. Empirical contingency
must be then distinguished from absolute contingency. Empirical con-
tingency is distinct from facticity in so far as the former is predicated
of everything that can be or not be, occur or not occur, within the world
without contravening the invariants of language and representation
through which the world is given to us (AF, 40). Empirical contingency
is that which, within the framework of these invariants, is not necessarily
the case. Facticity, on the other hand, pertains to the modality of these
invariants themselves: these are factical in so far as we cannot establish
their necessity or contingency. That is, these invariants of language and
representation through which the world is given to us constitute a fact
rather than an absolute since we cannot seem to establish whether or not
they are necessarily the case.
The concept of absolute contingency is to be distinguished from empir-
ical contingency, however, in so far as the former results from converting
the deficit of knowledge implicit in the concept of facticity into a positive
item of knowledge concerning the modality of the real. Facticity can be
legitimately identified with contingency, Meillassoux writes, in so far as
the former must not be thought of as comprising a possibility of ignorance,
but rather as comprising a positive knowledge of everythings capacity-
to-be-other or capacity-not-to-be (AF, 62). The burden of the central
chapter of After Finitude is to demonstrate, by way of anhypothetical
demonstration (AF, 602), that facticity can only be thought as an abso-
lute: one can only remain rationally consistent by thinking those factical
constants apparently governing the world as necessarily unnecessary, and
therefore necessarily subject to the possibility of alteration without reason
(without any higher law or constant governing this alteration). While
empirical contingency (or precariousness) designates the perishability of
determinate entities, a possibility of not-being which must eventually be
realized, absolute contingency (or contingency proper) designates a pure
possibility; one which may never be realized (AF, 62). What is absolutely
contingent is a real possibility that may come to pass for no reason what-
soever, but that also may not come to pass, since nothing necessitates it.
44 c o p e r n i c a n r e v o l u t i o n
COPERNICAN REVOLUTION
Fabio Gironi
The expression Copernican Revolution refers to the sixteenth-century
definitive rehabilitation of the heliocentric model of the solar system,
c o p e r n i c a n r e v o l u t i o n 45
from cosmic centrality, both spatial and conceptual. The modern science
spawned by the encounter between the Copernican demotion of the human
and the Galilean mathematisation of nature is uniquely able to deliver a
non correlational mode of knowing (AF, 119) of the glacial reality indif-
ferent and anterior to human thought, a fiercely n on-correlated great
outdoors (AF, 7), stripped of subject-dependent qualities and reduced to
its mathematically describable primary properties.
CORRELATIONISM
Levi R. Bryant
Meillassouxs concept of correlation is arguably among his most s ignificant
and controversial contributions to philosophy. In After Finitude, he defines
correlation as the idea according to which we only ever have access to the
correlation between thinking and being, and never to either term consid-
ered apart from the other (AF, 5). Although Meillassoux does not himself
specify this, correlationism presumably comes in a variety of different
forms, and is therefore not restricted to theories focused on the relation
between mind and being. Thus the relation between transcendental ego or
lived body and the world in phenomenology would be one variant of corre-
lationism, while the relation between language and being in Wittgenstein,
Derrida and Lacan, or between power and knowledge in Foucault, would
be other variants. In each case we encounter the claim that being cannot be
thought apart from a subject, language or power.
Meillassoux argues that correlationism has been the central notion
of philosophy ever since Immanuel Kant, whose core epistemological
hypothesis is twofold. On the one hand, Kant argues that objects conform
to mind, rather than mind to objects. Kant claimed that in traditional
forms of epistemology the mind was conceived as a mirror that reflects
being as it is in-itself, independent of us. He argues that mind does not
merely reflect reality, but rather actively structures reality. Consequently,
on the other hand, he argues that we can never know reality as it is in itself
apart from us, but only as it appears to us. If the mind takes an active role
in structuring reality (for us) we are unable to know what it is in-itself
because we cannot determine what, in appearances, is a product of our
own minds and what is a feature of things as they are in themselves. This is
because we cannot adopt a third-person perspective that would allow us to
compare things as they appear to us and things as they are in themselves.
Consequently, knowledge is restricted to appearances and we must remain
agnostic as to what being might be like in itself.
c o r r e l a t i o n i s m 47
to think the absolute or being as it is in-itself apart from mind, and what
characteristics the absolute might possess. Meillassouxs discussion of
ancestrality or statements about time prior to the existence of human
beings is not an argument against correlationism per se, but is designed
to present readily familiar and widely accepted claims about cosmic time
prior to the existence of life and humans that ought not be permissible
within a correlationist framework. If correlationism is true, what entitles
us to make claims about the nature of the universe billions of years prior
to the emergence of life or mind? Meillassoux presents his account of
how we might break out of the correlationist circle in his discussion of the
principle of factiality in After Finitude.
Michael Austin
Correlationism is the often unstated view that being only exists for
subjects, that there is a direct correlate between subjective mind and the
world of objects, or perhaps more accurately, that thinking beings have no
access to the world except by way of cognition, so that any claim to think
or discuss things-in-themselves is taken as either imaginative whimsy or
pure absurdity. Like tea though, correlationism can be taken either weak
or strong. While correlationism broadly understood maintains that we
have access only to the correlate of Thought and Being, it is the possibility
of anything existing outside of the correlate that ultimately allows for the
distinction between weak and strong correlationism. Meillassoux sug-
gests several historical figures as a way of understanding the distinction
between these positions, with the former represented by Immanuel Kant
and Edmund Husserl and the latter by Ludwig Wittgenstein and Martin
Heidegger.
Weak correlationism accepts the move of Critical philosophy, claiming
that we must take account of how and what we know prior to any talk
of metaphysics. Where various weak correlationists differ is in what
this taking account of means. For instance, Husserl will maintain that
in order to understand the world, we must grasp it as purely through
experience as possible, through phenomenological description. Through
eidetic reduction, we can capture things in their most abstract, as features
or qualities shared across types, grasping the eidos of things. Beyond this
experience, we can know nothing, but like Kant, Husserlian phenomenol-
ogy will not presume to be equipped to dismiss the possibility of things-
in-themselves. Kants agnostic position concerning the in-itself is more
c o r r e l a t i o n i s m : w e a k a n d s t r o n g 49
than simply stating that things in the world could be other than what
they are (e.g. this or that thing need not exist necessarily), but tells us that
it is impossible to claimthat things must necessarily appear as they do.
In other words, by saying that while we cannot know things other than
through rational cognition, that is, that it is impossible to know any object
except through the categories of rationality, it remains possible to think
or imagine that things could in-themselves be otherwise, that things may
not be wholly reducible to their mere appearances. What we have access
to, says the weak correlationist, is merely the correlate of thought and
being, that small space where the two converge, while what lies outside of
this convergence remains thinkable but ultimately unknowable. Things-
in-themselves remain forever unknowable to rationality. The noumenal
remains very much an open question for the weak correlationist, as we can
neither affirm nor dismiss anything about things outside of their givenness
to human experience.
The strong correlationist argument picks up from its weak cousin,
namely with the question, why claim there are things-in-themselves
at all? Simply stating that the idea of things-in-themselves is thinkable
and therefore non-contradictory is not enough, as I can think all sorts
of non-contradictory things which most likely do not exist, from uni-
corns to self-transforming machine elves. In fact, Terrence McKennas
tryptamine-induced elf hallucinations make just as much sense as the
mysterious things-in-themselves, argues the strong correlationist, neither
of which exist necessarily by virtue of not being self-contradicting. The
strong correlationist will insist that we must therefore abolish the very
idea of things-in-themselves as incoherent speculation. We know of no
reality, no being, outside of our own thought and to propose that there
even exists such a thing is entirely groundless and presumes knowledge
attained outside of thought to begin with, which is impossible. There is
no agnosticism for the strong correlationist, as there is an absolute conflu-
ence between thought and being, with neither existing without the other
and the possibility of there being one without the other entirely absurd.
What can be said to exist is what we can know (being-for-thought), with
the limit to our thinking being identical to the limits of existents. There
is no objective knowledge, as all knowledge is knowledge of the givenness
of things, that is to say, we know things only in so far as they are for-us.
For the strong correlationist, there can be no being outside of thought,
as the very possibility of such a thing existing is not only incoherent, but
illogical. That is to say, while the weak correlationist accepts the possibil-
ity of a world outside of the correlation of Being and Thought, the strong
correlationist absolutises the correlation itself since our knowledge extends
only to the bare givenness of the world. This means that it is impossible to
50 creation ex nihilo
think the fact that there is a world at all, as our rational discourse extends
only as far as the givenness of such a world, that is, our relation to it.
CREATION EX NIHILO
Peter Gratton
This is a traditional theological/philosophical term meaning creation
from out of nothing. It is most commonly associated with monotheistic
religions wherein a creator God brings forth the universe from nothing.
The concept acts as a bulwark against the problem of the infinite regress
of causes. Meillassoux dissociates the term ex nihilo from its theological
context and argues that if one drops ones belief in causal necessity then
the idea of events emerging from nothing becomes perfectly conceivable.
His case for hyper-chaos, and the novelty it can produce, means he is
committed to a the idea of a universe that is not constrained by a predeter-
mined set of possibilities and can produce events from out of nowhere or
nothing, that is ex nihilo.
D
DEATH
Daniel Sacilotto
For Meillassoux, death or the mortality of the living is first a corollary of
his theses concerning the necessity of contingency of being in general.
In this sense, death designates the possibility of thoughts non-being or,
put differently, the impossibility of its necessity, since the world goes on
without it. Thought in these terms, the possibility of death corresponds
with the materialist attempt to think that which does not depend on thought
for its being. Death is thus named the pure other of ourselves (IRR, 19).
The possible absence of thought would then be an ontological consequence
of the argument for factiality. For if every entity is necessarily contingent,
it follows that the same applies for thought, or the agents of thought.
However, thoughts contingent being seems to operate also as a premise
that supports the argument for factiality, rather than as a consequence
of the latter. It informs a pivotal point in the dialectic proposed by
d e a t h 51
DELEUZE, GILLES
Jeffrey Bell
Gilles Deleuze (19251995) is probably Meillassouxs most important
interlocutor, the philosopher who is both closest to his own concerns
and yet the one with whom he most strongly disagrees. On the one hand,
both Deleuze and Meillassoux place great emphasis on contingency,
and each draws from the work of David Hume in important respects in
order to make the case for contingency. The central thesis and subtitle of
Meillassouxs After Finitude is that the only thing that is necessary is the
necessity of contingency. Deleuze and Guattari, similarly, will call out
in What is Philosophy? against what they label the cult of necessity and
will reaffirm Nietzsches own advocacy of the roll of the dice, the chance
and contingency inseparable from all things. In What is Philosophy? they
will also give philosophy the task of creating concepts, a task that entails
affirming and embracing a fundamental chaos. Similarly for Meillassoux,
chaos, or what he calls hyper-chaos, is fundamental, and the nature and
role of this chaos is one of the principal themes of his own philosophy.
Despite these similarities, there are three points that Meillassoux
singles out where the differences could not be starker. First, whereas
Meillassouxs project sets out to critique what he calls correlationism,
Deleuze, by Meillassouxs lights, actually affirms a strong version of corre-
lationism in that the correlation itself becomes the absolute in Deleuzes
system. With the traditional understanding of correlationism, the real is
always and only real as correlated to a subject that has access to it. One can
entertain the thought of a world without correlation, but then again this
would be a thought and we are once again within the circle of correlation-
ism (hence the problem of ancestrality). Deleuze, Meillassoux argues,
does not even entertain the possibility of a world without correlation,
but absolutises it. He offers a vitalist hypostatization (AF, 64), to use
Meillassouxs term, of this correlation by arguing that all reality is simply
a correlate of a life.
d e l e u z e , g i l l e s 53
DERIVATION
DESCARTES, REN
fore (4) bodies must exist independently of the cogito, since God is not a
deceiver given that deception is an imperfection.
Meillassoux argues that Descartes metaphysical claims to the specula-
tive problem of the absolute are ultimately untenable. Metaphysics,
on his account, is that type of thinking that holds that the absolute is a
necessary entity or being, such as God, that can be explained through the
principle of sufficient reason. While all metaphysics is speculative,
that is, concerning the absolute, Meillassoux will stake out a position
that he claims is speculative without being metaphysical or correlative,
since first, it does without attempting to demonstrate a necessary being,
and second, it does without relying on the principle of sufficient reason,
as the principle of sufficient reason ultimately fails, since it requires an
infinite regress of reasons for a beings necessity. Rejecting speculative
thought, as correlationism does, leads to the undesirable consequence
of the return of the religious; it legitimates all those discourses [such as
fideism and mysticism] that claim to access an absolute, the only proviso
being that nothing in these discourses resembles a rational justification of
their validity (AF, 445). These discourses can talk about the absolute but
there is no possibility of rationally adjudicating between them thus they
prioritise belief over reason as a means for accessing the absolute.
Though he argues that Descartes metaphysical claims about the
absolute in-itself seem to be irrevocably obsolete, Meillassoux claims
that the speculative solution to demonstrating the intelligibility of the
absolute follows the same procedure. Descartes argument establishes
the existence of a primary absolute from which it derives a derivative
absolute, the absoluteness of mathematics (AF, 30). For Descartes, the
primary absolute is the perfect being that guarantees the existence of
extended bodies that can be described in themselves in mathematical
terms. To avoid falling into dogmatic metaphysics, Meillassoux pro-
poses, we must uncover an absolute necessity that does not reinstate any
form of absolutely necessary entity (AF, 34). He argues that speculative
philosophy must demonstrate the necessary ontological structure of the
absolute rather than a necessary entity. Claiming, as he does, that the
speculative thesis holds the absolute necessity of the contingency of
everything allows him to bypass the use of the principle of sufficient
reason, for the necessity of contingency means that anything could become
otherwise without reason. (However, that the absolute has the ontological
structure of contingency or pure possibility is necessary). Rather than
Descartes necessary God, Meillassoux holds that absolute contingency is
the primary absolute from which it is possible to derive the absolutisation
of mathematics. To complete the Cartesian structure of his speculative
argument, Meillassoux continues by attempting to demonstrate that the
56 d i a - c h r o n i c i t y
DIA-CHRONICITY
Paul J. Ennis
Toward the final stages of After Finitude Meillassoux discusses the idea of
dia-chronicity as the temporal discrepancy that exists between thinking
and being in terms of both anteriority and ulteriority (AF, 112, italics
removed). The dia-chronic statement is one that refers to non-correlated
events whether we mean by this ancestral statements, as in the opening
chapter of After Finitude, or futural events such as the extinction of our
species.
DIALETHEISM
Raphal Millire
Aristotle, in Book of the Metaphysics, famously states that the same
attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same subject
in the same respect, and he adds that this idea, known as the principle
of non-contradiction (PNC), is the most certain of all principles
(1005b1924). In After Finitude, Meillassoux draws the outline of an argu-
d i a l e t h e i s m 57
ment to prove this principle. He writes that such a proof would point
out that paraconsistent logics were not developed in order to account for
actual contradictory facts, but only in order to prevent computers, such as
expert medical systems, from deducing anything whatsoever from contra-
dictory data because of the principle of ex falso quodlibet (AF, 789).
Therefore, he says, paraconsistent logic onlydealswith contradictory state-
ments, and not worldly contradictions; thus it doesnt threaten the idea that
there are no true ontological contradictions, even if we can, for pragmatic
purposes, speak of true logical contradictions.
Meillassoux seems fully aware that paraconsistent logic, in which some
(but not all) contradictions are true, is nothing but a formal system: it has
no bearing, in itself, on reality, and neither can it be used as a metaphysical
thesis to undermine the ontological PNC as found in Aristotle. However,
this shouldnt come as a surprise: arguably, formal systems can never be
used to solve metaphysical issues, and this has nothing to do with the
alleged utilitarian aim of paraconsistent logic as a way to deal with incon-
sistencies in (medical) databases.
Nonetheless, this doesnt mean that a genuine metaphysical thesis
denying the ontological PNC is not defensible; in fact, it has been
minutely advocated as dialetheism, most notably by Richard Routley and
Graham Priest, who coined the term. Dialetheism argues that there are
some sentences such that both they and their negations are true in other
words, there are genuinely true contradictions. Paraconsistent logic does
support dialetheism by showing that its main thesis is logically intelligible,
but the latter is nevertheless independent of the former: indeed, while
paraconsistent logicians provide ways of thinking that some contradictions
are true in some possible worlds, most of them do not really believe that our
world is one of them. Thus dialetheism is a much more radical view, but
Priest has shown at length that it may actually be used to solve classical
paradoxes about time, change and motion (Priest 1987). Moreover, one
cannot rule out dialetheism as easily as Meillassoux thinks; David Lewis,
for instance, acknowledged that his opposition to dialetheism was, in the
end, entirely dogmatic: I am affirming the very thesis that Routley and
Priest have called into question and contrary to the rules of debate
I decline to defend it. Further, I concede that it is indefensible against
their challenge (Lewis 1998: 101).
Interestingly, Priest (1987) also tackled in detail some issues related
to the limits of thought, which are arguably also Meillassouxs main
subject in After Finitude; he has given thought-provoking applications of
dialetheism to such issues, including Berkeleys so-called master argu-
ment (one cannot conceive of an unconceived object), one of the very first
attempts to show how naive realism falls into a pragmatic contradiction
58 d i v i n e i n e x i s t e n c e
DIVINE INEXISTENCE
Leon Niemoczynski
The Divine Inexistence: An Essay on the Virtual God is the title of
Meillassouxs 1997 doctoral thesis. As he remarked in After Finitude, the
divine inexistence is to be the subject and title of a much larger, forthcom-
ing work, as After Finitude covered only the first 150 pages of the whole
of The Divine Inexistence. In addition to the dissertation, there are two
noteworthy pieces that Meillassoux has published that cover important
topics found in The Divine Inexistence. Those pieces are the essay Spectral
Dilemma and a lengthy book chapter called The Immanence of the
World Beyond.
In all of these texts Meillassoux argues against atheism/theism
(foreach accept and work within the terms of theistic thought), q uestions
a/theism or any God after God a/theological perspective and its
anti-realist fideism, and opposes orthodox onto-theological religion and its
corresponding longing for satisfying transcendence (defined as exteriority
in general) (DI, 8). A more admissible alternative, claims Meillassoux, is a
third option that he calls in different places divinology, simply philosophy,
or irreligion. For Meillassoux, knowledge of Gods e xistence is not con-
strained by the limits of human reason and thusrelegatedto be an object
of faith found within some unknowable noumenal realm (see Immanuel
Kant). Rather, divinology does not reject God at all. It places an imma-
nent form of hope in Gods current inexistence and the potential for this
virtual God to appear in the future. Meillassouxs claim is that philosophy
can believe in God precisely because God does not currently exist.
In After Finitude, Meillassoux concludes that only contingency is itself
necessary. This is important regarding the divine inexistence because
Meillassoux does not accept God in terms of onto-theology, as a
necessary being or causa sui. Because metaphysics deals with necessity
and necessity has been rejected through the principle of factiality, we
cannot admit God (a necessary being) into metaphysical theology de facto.
After the death of God we have no grounds to admit God back into our
ontology if necessity demands that re-appearance by way of faith. Later,
Meillassoux equals his rejection of necessity with the insufficiency of
d o g m a t i s m 59
DOGMATISM
Robert S. Gall
Meillassouxs references to dogmatism need to be understood within
the context of Immanuel Kants definitions and analyses of dogmatism
in his Critical philosophy. In The Critique of Pure Reason, Kant defines
dogmatism as:
60 d o g m a t i s m
the presumption that it is possible to make progress with pure knowledge, accord-
ing to principles, from concepts alone ... and that it is possible to do this without
having first investigated in what way and by what right reason has come into pos-
session of these concepts. Dogmatism is thus the dogmatic procedure of reason,
without previous criticism of its own powers. (32 [B xxv], his emphasis)
E
EMPIRICISM
Adrian Johnston
Before addressing Meillassouxs positioning vis--vis e mpiricism proper
as an epistemological orientation in philosophy, I should say a few words
about his relations with things empirical, specifically as per the empirical
sciences resting upon a posteriori observation and experimentation. To
begin with, Meillassoux, following French philosopher and historian
of science Alexandre Koyr, singles out Galileo Galilei of 1623s The
Assayer as the one-and-only father of modern science. On this conten-
tious account of the birth of scientific modernity, the Galilean distinction
between primary and secondary properties of observed objects the
former are mathematisable/formalisable and, therefore, supposedly
indicative of the mind-independent real features of natural beings in
and of themselves, whereas the latter are non-quantifiable qualities
perhaps limited to being phenomena peculiar to the observing mind is
the sole locus of origin for the modern sciences. In other words, Koyr
and Meillassoux, like a number of other French thinkers from the
mid-twentieth century to the present, such as Louis Althusser, Jacques
Lacan and Alain Badiou, among others, believe that the essence of sci-
entificity strictly speaking consists in mathematical or mathematical-style
formalisation.
The reaffirmation of this Koyran thesis apropos scientific modernity
already signals Meillassouxs favouring of a French neo-rationalist
epistemology, with Koyrs narrative completely sidelining and ignoring
the 1620 New Organon of British empiricist Francis Bacon. (I will return
to the topic of British empiricism shortly.) Bacons canonical text lays the
foundations of the empirical and experimental approach that has come to
be known as the scientific method. Against Koyr, Meillassoux, etal.,
Bacon, not to mention Galileo as an observer and experimenter, instead
of as a pure mathematician, cannot defensibly be denied the title of (co-)
founding figure of modern science. In fact, it would not be unfair to
say that Meillassouxs version of the distinction between primary and
secondary qualities he opens After Finitude with a declaration that he
intends to revivify and redeploy this early-modern distinction long ago
having fallen out of general philosophical fashion is Cartesian, rather
62 e m p i r i c i s m
than Galilean, or, for that matter, Lockean, with John Locke, another
British empiricist, also adopting this distinction for his own purposes.
Meillassoux seeks to elaborate a rationalist ontology that is both realist
and materialist, one in which knowing subjects truly can know and not
simply think material objects qua asubjective things-in-themselves. As per
the subtitle of Jean-Ren Vernes Critique of Aleatory Reason (1982), a book
influencing the author of After Finitude, Meillassoux too plays Descartes
contra Kant (more precisely, contra the critical, empiricism-inspired
dimensions of Immanuel Kants transcendental idealism). Although
Meillassouxs ontology and philosophical modus operandi owes much more
to rationalism than empiricism, he partly motivates his system-building
endeavours through recourse to the latter as well as to the empirical sci-
ences of nature.
Meillassouxs arche-fossil argumentative device is extrapolated from
those natural sciences studying entities and events presumably predating
the genesis of sentient and/or sapient life. On a realist interpretation, these
experimental, a posteriori sciences refer to beings enjoying actual exist-
ence utterly independent of whatever statuses they might possibly have as
objects-qua-correlates of any consciousness whatsoever. Through recourse
to such disciplines as cosmology and geology Meillassoux emphasises
that most practising scientists are spontaneous robust realists about their
targets of investigation he aims to manoeuvre Kantian and post-Kantian
anti-realists (that is, idealist and phenomenological correlationists) into
confronting a stark binary alternative between either (1) absolutising as
eternal and ubiquitous the subjectivity of the correlationist version of the
subject-object co-relationship or (2) conceding the sentient and sapient
subject and its co-relationships to be non-absolute, namely, to have arisen
contingently in space and time as factical geneses surfacing out of asubjec-
tive real being an sich. Just as the V.I. Lenin of Materialism and Empirio-
Criticism (1908) contends, following Friedrich Engels, that all alternatives
to militant realist materialism boil down in the end to the solipsistic subjec-
tive idealism of George Berkeley, Meillassoux wields his arche-fossil so as
to force various types of correlationists to choose between an anti-realism
resting on an absolutised subject (an understandably unpalatable option
too implausibly extreme and anti-scientific for most of them) or a realism
at least implicit in acknowledging the factical spatio-temporal emergence of
thereby de-absolutised subjects.
Apropos empiricism per se as a philosophical orientation, Meillassoux
leans heavily on David Hume in particular. More precisely, he pro-
poses an ontological construal of Humes problem of induction, a
gesture akin to G.W.F. Hegels speculative move of ontologising Kants
critical-epistemological Transcendental Dialectic. Although Locke
e s c h a t o l o g y 63
ESCHAOLOGY
ESCHATOLOGY
Christina Smerick
The word eschatology means, in its literal sense, the study of what is last
as a final resolution or completion. Eschatology therefore focuses upon the
final condition of a being, be that a human being (personal eschatology) or
the entire world (cosmic eschatology). Theistic religions tend to under-
stand time as linear and therefore hold to an expectation of a conclusion
to time, an end in which everything is destroyed and something new is
brought into being, or an end in which everything is redeemed and made
64 e s c h a t o l o g y
ETERNAL RECURRENCE
Daw-Nay Evans
Nietzsche calls the eternal recurrence the greatest weight and the
highest formula of affirmation that is at all attainable (Nietzsche 1974:
341; 1954: 1). He introduces the concept in The Gay Science and Thus
Spoke Zarathustra. Some view it as a philosophical embarrassment, while
others see it as the cornerstone of Nietzsches thought. For those who
view the eternal recurrence as crucial to appreciate Nietzsches thinking,
two different interpretations have emerged. The first contends that the
eternal recurrence is a cosmological theory about the nature of time. The
second contends that the eternal recurrence is a thought experiment that
should be construed as an ethical command akin to Kants categorical
imperative. Despite these internecine battles, there is little doubt that the
eternal recurrence is Nietzsches answer to the problem of nihilism that is
the Platonic-Christian worldview. The latter is static and linear, whereas
the world in which things eternally recur (or are said to recur) is fluid and
cyclical.
The presentation of the eternal recurrence as a true doctrine first
appears in 109 of The Gay Science. This version does not contradict the
more popular, hypothetical version presented in 341 of that same text. As
a cosmological theory, the eternal recurrence is non-teleological. There
is no overarching purpose or aim to time as such. Indeed, the narrative
of progress so prominent in many religious and philosophical traditions
is absent in the eternal recurrence. Without a beginning or an end, this
cyclical theory of time stands in stark contrast to its competitors. As a
consequence, the same things that occurred in the past will infinitely
repeat themselves in the same manner in the future. On this reading, at
least two questions arise. First, given the truth of recurrence, how is it sig-
nificant for my life? When one becomes aware of the truth of recurrence,
it should have transformative power such that you change your behaviour
in the same way you changed it countless times before. In other words,
the moment you become aware of the reality of recurrence is the moment
e s s e n t i a l s p e c t r e 67
you decide to live in a manner different than you did in the past. Even
though this is a life you have lived numerous times before, you have yet
to live this particular life in its entirety. Thus, you have no idea what your
future entails until you experience it for yourself. Second, what actually
recurs? Some have argued that to save Nietzsche from the fallacy of mis-
placed concreteness we should think of that which eternally recurs as a
reconfiguration of energy as opposed to the repetition of events, ideas and
persons in their concrete sameness. If we move from a classical atomistic
theory of time to a more dynamic energy theory, then what repeats is not
literally the same things of the past but the energy of which those things
are composed. For these reasons, the eternal recurrence is fatalistic but
fatalistic in a way that leaves room for personal growth and change.
As a thought experiment, the eternal recurrence is a test to determine
if we would choose to affirm our life as it has been lived on the assump-
tion that time eternally recurs. For those who view the eternal recur-
rence as more myth than reality, the psychological disposition it should
motivate does not require it to be literally true. There are two ways in
which Nietzsches eternal recurrence is analogous to Kants categorical
imperative. First, both Nietzsche and Kant view their theories as tests.
Just as Kants categorical imperative is a test to determine if our actions
have moral worth, the eternal recurrence is a test to determine if our lives
are worthy of affirmation. Second, both Nietzsche and Kant view their
theories as having descriptive force. Kants categorical imperative follows
from understanding ourselves as rational agents, while Nietzsches eternal
recurrence, even as a thought experiment, follows from taking a fatalistic
worldview seriously. Kant and Nietzsche are different in terms of the
scope and magnitude of their views. Kants ethics is meant to be univer-
sally applicable to all rational agents. Nietzsches ethics, so to speak,
apply to a select few.
Amor fati means accepting things as they are and not wanting them to
be different. For Nietzsche, only those strong enough to stare into the
abyss of a meaningless universe will accept the truth of eternal recurrence
or, alternatively, affirm the idea of eternal recurrence. The challenge is to
view ones life as a totality whose tragedies and triumphs are woven into a
beautiful tapestry to be repeated again and again.
ESSENTIAL SPECTRE
FACT
Robert Jackson
In Meillassouxs system facts play a crucial part in answering the question
as to why there is something rather than nothing, and more specifically
why anything at all did not necessarily have to be. To see why this
might be so, Meillassoux distinguishes, and then shortly after rejects,
two models of the principle of unreason: a Kantian weak model and an
enforced strong model, both of which follow from the two models of
correlationism. The weak Kantian interpretation of factiality suggests
that if something is (as a fact) then it must be contingent without then
entailing that this something must exist. Maybe nothing exists. The
strong interpretation, emphatically endorsed by Meillassoux, demands
that not only is something contingent, but also that there must be con-
tingent things. The weak principle claims that if a fact exists, it must be
contingent, but the strong principle claims facts do not support whether
or not factual things exist.
Now, endorsing the weak principle means endorsing facticity as a fact,
because if nothing existed, there would not be any factual basis for it. This
leads to an unacceptable regress that is self-refuted by the absolute nature
of the strong interpretation, which evacuates all necessity from those facts
and identifies absolute possibility. For if there was a weak arena of factual
things, there will always be the assumption of a second-order realm of
factual things upon which it can change (AF, 74). Supporting that would
require a third order and so on. Therefore, it is not a fact that things exist;
rather it is an absolute necessity that contingent factual things exist. In
order for contingency alone to be necessary, something must exist. This
is a direct consequence of the principle of factiality because the absolute
facticity of everything that exists cannot be thought as a fact. Meillassoux
refers to this as the non-iterability of facticity, that facticity and facts
cannot be applied to themselves (AF, 79).
f a c t i a l i t y 69
FACTIALITY
Robert Jackson
The principle of factiality (principe de factualit) denotes the final stage
of absolutising the facticity of the correlate. It is the necessity or non-
facticity of facticity. It is also referred to as the principle of unreason. The
typical definition of facticity as Meillassoux uses it is found in the work
of Martin Heidegger. There one understands facticity as the brute, con-
tingent fact of ones existence, which can only be described in terms of its
finitude, and not deduced as something that had to be the case or neces-
sary. Meillassoux is mostly concerned with the facticity of the correlates
contingent existence: that it could be otherwise. Moreover he is especially
concerned with its facticity as an anti-absolutist gesture that only narrows
contingent possibilities for the correlate, that is, there can be no absolute if
facticity is only mine or for me.
Thus his pivotal argument in Chapter 3 of After Finitude is to establish
and expose the contradictory nature of the strong correlationist position,
and convert its facticity into an absolute for speculative materialism,
whilst crucially distinguishing it from absolute idealism. The speculative
materialist thesis is endorsed over idealism, and is favourable, in so far as
the latter cannot pass through the meshes of facticity (AF, 51). Idealist
absolutism maintains that the correlation of being and thought itself is
absolute and necessary. Whilst idealism can only absolutise the necessity
of the correlationist circle, entailing that the in-itself is necessarily consti-
tuted by subjectivist traits, factiality only seeks to absolutise the absolute
other facticity of the correlate, entailing that the absolute other of contin-
gency can be deduced in itself. I can deduce an absolute possibility that
something can happen outside of thought and that a being-other of the
correlates constitutive thought is absolutely possible.
To put it another way, if the facticity of strong correlationism was
believed to be rooted in its finitude, that is, the failure to think the in-
itself, Meillassoux modifies its function as a feature of the in-itself abso-
lutely. It is because of strong correlationisms implicit admission of the
absoluteness of contingency that the unthinkable can occur, and being an
absolute, this entails that nothing, not even the correlationist position, is
necessary. The facticity of the correlate presupposes an absolute within
it. Therefore, not only is the correlate absolutely contingent, but rational
thought can go one further, and know that reality is, in itself, absolutely
contingent. The principle of factiality thus evacuates necessity from
absolutely everything that exists and paradoxically only contingency
alone is absolutely necessary.
70 f e r v o u r
FERVOUR
FIDEISM
Paul OMahoney
Fideism refers to the belief that human reason cannot attain certainty in
metaphysical, religious or moral matters, and that consequently beliefs
formed in these areas must in large measure be a matter of faith.
Historically, there have been prominent fideist strains in Catholicism, but
the Church today proscribes the doctrine, holding faith to be rationally
informed rather than wholly independent of reason. This is worth record-
72 f i d e i s m
FIGURE
Fintan Neylan
A core concern of Meillassoux is discerning what properties we may estab-
lish about the absolute. Because Meillassoux conceives the absolute in the
terms of its classical meaning, that is, as mind-independence, the proper-
ties we may derive must be thinkable by us, but not relative to us. Such
non-relative properties are determined by establishing what he calls figures
and he argues that speculative materialism can derive a number of
them. Traditionally the goal of deducing absolute properties was achieved
through positing necessary metaphysical entities, but ever since Immanuel
Kant this route has been barred. Although agreeing with Kants critique
of metaphysics, Meillassoux points out that his Critical philosophy went
too far in its disqualification of all knowable m ind-independence. For
what Kant missed is that there is a non-metaphysical mind-independence
which speculation can access when it grasps the absolute.
In grasping absolute contingency, speculation may discover certain
features of it: while it is not subject to any higher rule of restraint, there
are instances in which chaos limits itself. Not arbitrary binds, these con-
straints are conditions which even hyper-chaos must not breach. It is
within the capacity of speculation to establish certain statements about
hyper-chaos as instances of such auto-limitation, and hence as conditions
for its existence. These conditions of hyper-chaos are known as figures.
Because such conditions would be invariant across any possible world
which hyper-chaos can muster, the properties of the absolute which those
statements express may be considered absolute, mind-independent prop-
erties. As these conditions, figures give a non-metaphysical account of
mind-independence because they are properties which must hold regard-
less of any situation hyper-chaos manifests.
After Finitude identifies three such figures to be demonstrated: that
the absolute is non-contradictory, that the absolute exists, and finally
that mathematics discourse has both absolute scope and that it requires
possibility to be untotalisable. While the initial two figures are derived as
an immediate consequence of hyper-chaos, this last condition about math-
ematics is an example of how figures are to guide the project of speculative
materialism in future works. The speculative method is defined as the
procedure whereby figures are discerned in order to overcome difficulties
encountered by factial ontology. Thus mathematics ability to discuss
mind-independent entities and the structure of possibility is identified as
a condition in order to resolve the question of how the mathematical sci-
ences are possible the central concern of After Finitude.
74 f i n i t u d e
FINITUDE
Daniel Sacilotto
In its broadest sense, finitude designates an entire configuration of
philosophical thought, roughly corresponding with the emergence in
modernity of what Meillassoux names correlationism, and which
becomes radicalised and reiterated throughout the twentieth century in
various forms. In its germinal weak or Kantian form, the thesis of finitude
designates fundamentally an epistemic limitation in the possibilities open
to the transcendental subject. This constraint has at least two salient
characteristics. First, it exemplifies what Immanuel Kant designates as
the facticity of thinking, and which marks the foreclosure of thought
given the conditions of the categories of understanding. Thus, although
we can have a priori knowledge about the twelve categories that structure
the understanding, and consequentially the way in which things must
appear to us in judgement, we are in principle barred from knowing
why we have twelve categories and why things appear in the way they
do. These conditions are merely given and accessible to us, but we are
foreclosed access to the reasons for why these conditions obtain thus.
Similarly, on the side of intuition or perception understood in the widest
sense, the subject is constrained by the receptivity of the senses, which
for Kant anchors the faculties to the external world as well as ones own
gaze upon the life of ones mind. In contrast, infinitude is conceived in
terms of the absence of such constraints. Thus the mind of God is said
to be infinite in itspower in so far as it is subject to no reasons which it
does not know (it is not factical), and in so far as his thought produces
the thing thought (it is not constrained by the senses onto an external
world).
Finitude has a second, properly ontological dimension, correlated to
what Meillassoux calls the contingency of being or the entity, that is,
the possible non-being of that which is. This is precisely the aspect that
becomes exploited later by the strong correlationists, for whom factic-
ity, not just in terms of our epistemic limitations, must be recognised,
f i n i t u d e 75
FORMALISM
Paul J. Ennis
The second part of Meillassouxs lecture, Essay on the Derivation of
Galileanism, has the aim of providing a factial derivation that would
legitimate the absolutizing capacity of modern science that is to say,
Galilean science (IRR, 18). The derivation required will be in the form
of the capacity to think a meaningless sign as the minimal condition
of any formal language whether we mean this in logical or mathematical
terms (IRR, 18). The derivation will function by establishing that there is
a bond between the meaningless sign, sometimes called the empty sign,
and absolute contingency.
Meillassoux provides us with a new distinction in this lecture. The
properties constitutive of the primary absolute are now named primo-
absolutising properties (IRR, 18). For instance, facticity (in his sense) and
non-contradiction are primo-absolutising properties that apply to all enti-
ties. This is the absolute considered in the ontological register. Deutero-
absolutising properties are those related to the derivate or secondary
absolute and they are absolute separation and persistence (IRR, 19). This
is the ontic register. The ability to generate deutero-absolutising state-
ments is his focus in this essay, but it is approached with the first type in
mind. To grasp the latter Meillassoux wishes to find a criterion of formal
languages and, in particular, to identify one belonging to mathematics
that would help explain its relationship to absolute contingency (IRR, 20).
Meillassoux tells us we will be discussing logico-mathematics in the
modern sense of formalism, that is, post-Hilbert. What is the general
feature of all mathematical formalism? Meillassoux looks at the example
of set theory in its standard Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axiomatic form
(IRR, 20). He characterises it as a first-order logic with a foundational
role for mathematics and claims that it differs from the sense of axiomatic
we find in Euclid. He portrays the Euclidean approach as one that begins
with definitions, then establishes postulates, and then states its axioms.
The definitions precede the axioms and this, for Meillassoux, distin-
guishes Hilberts formal axiomatic from Euclids. In modern formalism
one does not begin with any initial definition (IRR, 21). We have undefined
terms subject to specific relations. For instance, in set theory we have
base-signs as meaningless signs (for example, ) naming undefined sets
(the terms in this context) (IRR, 21). The set is simply this meaning-
less sign with no reference to anything outside itself. Since set theory is
foundational it follows that the meaningless sign is the initial object of
mathematics (IRR, 21). Relations are considered in terms of operator-
f o u r t h w o r l d o f j u s t i c e 77
Fintan Neylan
In the face of the existence of pain and suffering, one might imagine that
the rational, non-religious response consists in shrugging ones shoulders
and accepting that this is just how the universe of immanence is, namely,
a random one full of despair and void of hope (see finitude). Even with
his acceptance of a scientific worldview, Meillassoux takes issue with such
despair being regarded as the only rational response. While acknowledging
that the transcendental option of hope usually provided by religions must
be ruled out, he is adamant that this does not strip an immanent ontology
of hope altogether. For despite the actually existing despair we find at
present, through the principle of factiality one can rationally envision a
just world emerging within the current universe.
Factial ontology considers not just the extremities of what is possible
as real, but the import of such non-contradictory possibilities on what
currently exists (see principle of non-contradiction). To the existence
of a world rife with misery, the factial response is that there may emerge a
World free of injustice, seated within the already existing world. Humans,
78 f o u r t h w o r l d o f j u s t i c e
G
GERMAN IDEALISM
Sean J. McGrath
German Idealism began in the last decade of the eighteenth century with
a variety of responses to unresolved questions generated by Immanuel
Kants Critical project. It lasted until the 1840s, with Schellings Berlin
lectures, alternatively considered the completion of German Idealism (as
depicted by Walter Schulz) or the first act in its overcoming (as depicted
by Horst Fuhrmans). One could root the movement in the rejection on
logical, metaphysical and ethical grounds of Immanuel Kants claim
that the objects of human cognition are appearances and not things-in-
themselves. Where Kant seemed to maintain the realism of objects, at
least as a possibility, it was not clear how this was consistent with his
epistemology. If a subject only ever knows phenomena, and if phenomena
are by definition objects for a subject, the conditions of the possibility of
which lie entirely in the a priori structure of transcendental subjectivity
(space, time, the categories of the understanding and the ideas of reason),
what sense could there be to Kants claim that the matter of cognition (by
distinction from its form, which is a priori), that is, sense data, is a poste-
riori and mind-independent?
Fichte first demolished the notion of things-in-themselves on the
ground that a mind-independent object is a contradiction in terms. This
led to the argument, common to Fichte, the early Schelling and Hegel,
that in order for mind to think a limit, it must already be beyond that
limit, on its other side, as it were. It follows that a reason that sets limits for
itself, that is, reason that has achieved transcendental knowledge, is in fact
limitless or absolute. The thesis that mind or spirit posits its own other in
order to overcome it and in that act comes to know itself or realise a richer
mode of operation, which Fichte first formulated and Hegel perfected, is
the basic presupposition of German Idealism. In its inclusion of intuitive
or non-discursive modes of experience as well as its thematisation of the
unconscious, German Idealism was closely bound up with Romanticism.
Nevertheless it would be a mistake to describe German Idealism as the
philosophy of Romanticism since it was not primarily a literary or artistic
endeavour and stood some critical distance from Romantic art, politics
and literature. In histories of philosophy, German Idealism is generally
g e r m a n i d e a l i s m 81
considered the next step after Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz on the
rationalist side, and Locke, Berkeley and Hume on the empiricist side. As
such it is read as a systematic attempt to heal the split between rational-
ism and empiricism, subjectivity and sensibility. However, the German
idealists created such novel philosophical structures and were possessed of
such seemingly inexhaustible genius that it is a misreading to reduce them
to a response to any previous or contemporaneous intellectual movement.
The German idealist rejection of a real limit to reason precipitated a
resuscitation of metaphysics and inaugurated the most fertile period
for speculative philosophy since the heyday of Greek philosophy. Fichte,
Schelling and Hegel are notable for their systematic treatments of every
dimension of philosophy, from logic to political philosophy.The immedi-
ate reaction to German Idealism, especially in the work of Kierkegaard,
Marx and Nietzsche, should be included in any assessment of its historical
influence since these authors are inconceivable without that against which
they revolted. The inconclusive relation of the parts of Kants Critical
project to one another inspired an intense search for a general system
of philosophy, where system meant, as Karl Leonhard Rheinhold was
the first to point out, that all of its parts could be derived from a single
principle. This first principle could only bethe absolute,the unconditioned
which precedes all conditioned concepts or beings, all that which is limited
by opposites. This assumption made the German idealists sympathetic
to Spinoza and his effort to found philosophy in the concept of the infi-
nite or substance. However, the German idealists criticised Spinozas
insufficiently nuanced account of subjectivity; for Schelling and Hegel,
the absolute must be considered both subject and substance if it is truly
absolute. The failure of German Idealism to achieve an absolute system,
already announced in the lectures of the late Schelling, was the departure
point for the non-foundationalism of Kierkegaard, Marx and Nietzsche.
The rise of German Idealism was closely connected to the panthe-
ism controversy, in which Moses Mendelssohn sought to defend the
Spinozism of Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. At issue here was the ques-
tion of whether Spinozas identification of God and nature amounted to
atheism, and more broadly, whether a deductive rationalist philosophy
was compatible with a theistic and morally oriented worldview.Friedrich
Heinrich Jacobi argued that it was not: any attempt to rationally deduce
truth was fatally flawed since God, the truth itself, entirely transcended
reason. Jacobi allied Spinozism with Kants transcendental idealism and
declared that both produce only a pseudo-religiosity, which he called
nihilism, because it amounts to finite reasons denial of anything other
than itself and humanitys worship of its own image. For Jacobi genuine
religion and morality is grounded in the immediate non-conceptual
82 g e r m a n i d e a l i s m
c ertainty in r evelation which the tradition calls faith, not reason. All three
of the German idealists rejected this argument, albeit in different ways,
and insisted that the basic beliefs of Western religion were fully compatible
with a priori reasoning. In Schellings late lectures a concession was made
to Jacobi: a priori reasoning, however necessary, Schelling argued in Berlin
in the 1840s, is merely negative; the real is excluded from it. Our knowl-
edge of the real is always a posteriori and as such a disruption of the ideal.
The paragon of such an interruption is biblical revelation. However, the
late Schelling held that a posteriori revelation can become the foundation
for a new mode of philosophy, which he called positive philosophy, when
its truths are appropriated by reason. Such an appropriation becomes the
ground for a genuine philosophy of history and metaphysical empiricism.
This represented a radical change of perspective for Schelling, who had
started as a supporter of Fichtes idealism. Fichte argued that reasons
other, which he called the not-I, is generated unconsciously or posited
by reason itself, so that in the activity of overcoming its otherness, either
by reducing the object to conceptual knowledge, that is, science, or by
mastering wild nature so as to make it habitable by rational beings, that is,
ethics, reason can come to know itself for what it truly is, not an object but
a pure subject that subsists only in its proper activity. The early Schelling
pursued this thesis in his first major works but then supplemented it, to
Fichtes dismay, with a philosophy of nature, arguing that the unconscious
self-positing subject can also be approached through a systematic study of
nature in itself. Nature understood as endlessly productive ground (which
Schelling called, after Spinoza, natura naturans), by distinction from its
objects produced (natura naturata), is nothing other than a pure activity
that generates limits (finite entities) for the sake of overcoming them.
Nature annuls the finite by sacrificing the individual to the universal,
in organic life, the single organism to the species through reproduc-
tion. Thus the absolute subject and absolute nature coincide in the early
Schelling; they are to be considered as indifferent to one another. Hence
alongside a transcendental philosophy of the subject, such as Fichtes,
Schelling advocated a transcendental philosophy of the object, such as was
being developed in various ways by romantic scientists under the banner
Naturphilosophie.
Along with the poet Hlderlin, Hegel had been Schellings classmate
in Tbingen from 179093. His first work mediated the dispute between
Fichte and Schelling by describing Fichtes work as subjective idealism
by distinction from Schellings objective idealism. Fichtes absolute
subject is a denial of the identity of the I and the not-I, Hegel argued.
Schelling established the identity of the subject and object by means of
his notion of the objectivity of the subject, on the one hand, the subject
g e r m a n i d e a l i s m 83
philosophy to art and maintained, to the contrary, that art, like its ally,
religion, is mere picture-thinking, a concrete expression of the absolute
idea or notion in an inferior and sensuous form, which is necessary at a
certain stage in the history of spirit but which needs to be cancelled and
preserved (aufgehoben, sublimated) by philosophy.This is the presupposi-
tion for Hegels infamous claim that art comes to an end in the nineteenth
century: its function had been taken over by idealist philosophy.
When Hegel died in 1831, he was without doubt the most influential
thinker of his generation, with a following among both conservatives (right
Hegelians who took the point of the system to be the triumph of reason)
and radicals (left Hegelians who emphasised the necessity of war and
revolution in the dialectic of history). In 1841, Frederick William IV, King
of Prussia, called Schelling to be Hegels successor in Berlin and paid him
the largest salary ever granted a university professor in Germany up to
that time, in the hope that Schelling would purge German intellectual life
of Hegelianism. Schelling had not published in decades. It was, however,
widely known that he had been working on both a critique of Hegel and an
alternative to Hegels system (especially in the Ages of the World drafts and
in the lectures delivered at Erlangen and Munich). On the opening day, the
Berlin lecture hall was filled to capacity with the younger generation, who
were weary of idealism and hungry for change, among them Kierkegaard,
Engels and Bakunin. Most of the auditors left disappointed. While the late
Schelling hardly displaced Hegel in the history of philosophy, his positive
philosophy has recently been recognised by many scholars as the inception
of late nineteenth-century materialism, Marxism and existentialism.
Schellings positive philosophy begins from the assumption that reason
is insufficient to the real; reason is only fully rational when it is ecstatic,
outside itself and receiving the truth of that which it did not itself gener-
ate. In this final act, German Idealism came full circle and returned to the
point of its inception, the notion of self-mediated reason, only to emphati-
cally deny its sufficiency.
GOD
Meillassoux responds to with his vision of a God that may be (or may
come to exist) is not the hope in an all-powerful being to worship. Rather
God is a name for the human hope in an absolute egalitarian justice which
he claims is found in all revolutionary and messianic projects.
While Meillassoux argues for the possibility of a God who may arise in
the future to bring justice, he has not yet gone on to develop a theory of
the character of that God. The name of God is something of a placeholder,
though at points in these essays his conception of God may appear to be
positing simply the standard theistic account of a God who is all-powerful,
all-knowing, eternal, and so on. However, his refutation of the religious
response to suffering includes a rejection of the eternity of God (as it
contravenes the principle that only contingency is necessary), leading
the way to a claim that this irreligious conception of God will require a
new science of the divine to replace theology. Meillassoux calls this new
science divinology, for which his past works appear to provide only a
prolegomena. The future work promises to combine his speculative phi-
losophy with a strong emphasis on a theory of absolute justice in the face
of human suffering.
Peter Gratton
One of the four original participants in the 2007 speculative realism
conference, Iain Hamilton Grants work is focused on renewing a par-
ticular form of Platonism to get past the problems of correlationism in
Immanuel Kant. He is principally known within speculative realist circles
for Philosophies of Nature after Schelling (2006). His task in this work is to
think a philosophy of nature that is not mechanistic, where nature is more
subject than object. Greatly influenced by F.W.J. Schellings reading of
Plato, Grant contends that nature cannot be the mere correlate of human
thought, but is in fact the productive power of all that is. To articulate
this nature, following Schelling, we must have a speculative physics that
would give us a natural history of its processes, which also remain stub-
bornly irreducible to what can be thought. This history would focus on
processes that deeply unthings or de-objectifies all that is. In this way,
Grant is critical of Graham Harmans object oriented ontology, since
the latter would focus only on what are the ephemeral effects of an under-
lying physics. In other words, his principal argument against Harman is
that the productivity of nature is prior to any particular objects. The mark
of being, then, is power, which upends all substantial forms of being.
h a r m a n , g r a h a m 87
HARMAN, GRAHAM
Peter Gratton
Harman was one of the original four speakers at the 2007 speculative
realism conference and is perhaps the most inveterate populariser of
the movement through his books and weblog (http://doctorzamalek2.
wordpress.com). One of four self-identified as following object oriented
ontology, along with Timothy Morton, Ian Bogost and Levi Bryant,
Harman has argued that philosophers have either overmined or under-
mined objects. To undermine them means to take objects as mere epi-
phenomena of some deeper effect, as in the powerful nature of which Iain
Hamilton Grant speaks, empiricism, atomisms, and all manner of process
philosophies, as well as materialisms, whether Marxist or the more tradi-
tional varieties. To overmine objects means to treat objects only in so far
as they relate to one another, as in the actants of Bruno Latours mature
88 h e g e l , g. w. f.
HEGEL, G.W.F.
Bart Zantvoort
By identifying himself as a speculative philosopher of the absolute,
Meillassoux unmistakeably and, without doubt, knowingly places himself
in relation to Hegel. Like Hegel, Meillassoux aims to boldly sweep away
the theoretical clutter of scepticism and the critical project of Immanuel
Kant and claim that thought can think the absolute. But, although Hegel
is mentioned in many places in After Finitude, these references are rather
disjointed, and without exception critical. Despite his dismissal of Hegel
as a subjectalist (IRR, 8), their projects are much more similar than
they might at first appear. Most of Meillassouxs criticisms of Hegel are
not new. He claims, firstly, that Hegel is a thinker of absolute identity.
Because Hegel thinks that all finite entities are contradictory he is forced
to conclude that the true is a self-identical whole, in which all differences
are contained (AF, 70). Meillassoux makes the inverse argument that,
because a necessary entity is impossible and a contradictory entity would
be necessary, contradiction is impossible. Secondly, Hegel subordinates
contingency to necessity. For Hegel, according to Meillassoux, the abso-
lute constitutes a rational totality, in which contingency is a necessary
but secondary moment (AF, 80). And finally, Hegel is a metaphysi-
cian, because he postulates a necessary entity, mind or spirit (Geist), as
absolute.
More interesting, however, is the role Hegel plays in the core argu-
ment of After Finitude, the argument for the principle of factiality. This
principle entails that all determinate things are contingent and could be
h e g e l , g. w. f. 89
otherwise than they are (AF, 79). According to Meillassoux, the correla-
tionist argues, in Kantian fashion, that the laws of nature and logic what
Meillassoux calls the structural invariants of our experience might
appear to be necessary for us, but we cannot know if in reality (in them-
selves) they are actually different from the way they appear to us. But,
Meillassoux argues, this leaves the correlationist fixed on the horns of
a dilemma (AF, 59). Either the correlationist admits that the structural
invariants of our experience could really be otherwise, and that therefore
everything, including the laws of nature and logic, is contingent. Or else,
he has to admit that these laws could not really be otherwise, which means
that they are absolutely necessary. But this is precisely the idealist posi-
tion, which Meillassoux ascribes to Hegel, and which the correlationist
seeks to avoid. According to Meillassoux, Hegels idealism consists in
absolutizing the correlation of thinking and being (AF, 37). While Kant
thinks that the categories that structure our experience are merely a fact
for us we cannot know whether or not they truthfully represent the
world as it is in itself and can therefore only be described, Hegel thinks
that these categories can be deduced, and therefore are proven to be neces-
sary (AF, 38).
Although Meillassoux does not distinguish clearly between the subjec-
tive idealist and the speculative or absolute idealist (AF, 59), it is Hegels
position as described above which is crucial in establishing the principle of
facticity. Meillassoux forces the correlationist to choose between specula-
tive materialism and (Hegelian) idealism. Since he rejects the latter on
the basis of the arguments already given, speculative materialism must be
correct.
While Meillassoux clearly distances himself from Hegel, even as he
takes over his terminology, their positions are similar in a number of ways.
Firstly, although it is true that Hegel thinks the categories of the Logic
(such as being and nothing, identity and difference) are necessary and can
be deduced, isnt Meillassoux doing something similar when he tries to
derive non-trivial knowledge his figures from the principle of factial-
ity (AF, 80)? He demonstrates, firstly, the impossibility of a contradictory
entity, and secondly, the necessary existence of a contingent entity. But
he goes much further than this. The project he outlines in After Finitude,
even if he does not manage to execute it there, is to prove two major
points: firstly, the absolute reach of mathematics, that is, its capacity to
describe the world as it is in itself (see Cartesian in-itself), and secondly,
the absolute and ... unconditionally necessary scope of the Cantorian
transfinite (AF, 127) (see set theory; Georg Cantor). The latter would
allow him to derive the stability of the laws of nature absolutely from the
principle of factiality (AF, 127). But if this stability can be derived, does
90 h e g e l , g. w. f.
this not mean that it is necessary? What is the difference, then, between
the Hegelian deduction and Meillassouxs derivation?
Secondly, one of the core elements of Meillassouxs argument is the
rejection of the principle of sufficient reason. Although Hegel is
undoubtedly a philosopher of reason (Vernunft), he does not subscribe
to the principle of sufficient reason (Grund). As he shows in the section
on Ground in the Science of Logic, every coming into existence of an
entity depends on a moment of irreducible contingency, a groundless
ground that retroactively integrates the conditions for this entity into a
causal chain. Although the existence of a thing or the occurrence of an
event depends on a set of conditions, these conditions do not make the
event necessary. The only reason for something to happen is, ultimately,
just the fact that it happened, or what Meillassoux calls facticity. But
after the event has happened or the thing has come into existence, its
conditions become a necessary part of its causal explanation. In this way,
Hegel allows for contingency while also explaining the obvious existence
of causes in empirical reality, something which one can say Meillassoux
fails to do.
Finally, it could be argued that both Meillassoux and Hegel abolish the
difference between the world as it appears to us and the world as it is in
itself in order to show that thought can think the absolute. Meillassouxs
argument is the following: the correlationist claims that we can only know
things as they appear to us, not as they are in themselves. But in order
to make this distinction, while at the same time escaping idealism, the
correlationist has to admit that the laws of logic and nature could really
be otherwise than they are. For Meillassoux, this shows that there is no
unknowable in-itself that serves as a reason or ground for the world we
experience. The facticity of the given is all there is: there is nothing
beneath or beyond the manifest gratuitousness of the given nothing but
the limitless and lawless power of its destruction, emergence or persis-
tence (AF, 63).
This, however, is also Hegels approach, to show that there is no myste-
rious essential world lying behind the given, but that what appears to us is
the world in itself. The separation between thought and reality is, accord-
ing to Hegel, a necessary illusion, born of the frustrations we experience
in exercising our limited capacity for knowledge and action. Hegel thinks
that we can overcome scepticism by showing its origin in the development
of consciousness, and that philosophy can achieve self-transparency of
method, which allows it to think the world as it is in itself while at the same
time retroactively justifying and securing its own procedure. Through a
very different line of reasoning, the points of convergence and divergence
of which remain to be explored, Hegel and Meillassoux thus work toward
h e i d e g g e r , m a r t i n 91
HEIDEGGER, MARTIN
Marie-Eve Morin
For Meillassoux, the German philosopher Martin Heidegger is one of
the chief representatives of strong correlationism. In Being and Time,
Heidegger seeks to raise anew the question of the meaning of Being. He
looks for the horizon in terms of which Being itself can be understood.
Heidegger sees it as necessary to put ontology, the study of beings
qua beings, on a secure footing. Heidegger first turns to an analytic of
Dasein, that is, to a study of this entity that does not just happen to be
but that also displays, in its relation to all entities (including itself), an
understanding of Being that allows it to relate meaningfully to what it
encounters. In seeking to analyse the ontological constitution of Dasein,
Heidegger hopes to gain insight not only into Being, that is, into the
givenness or intelligibility of entities in so far as they are encountered or
understood, but also into the givenness of this intelligibility itself, the
givenness of givenness if one will.
Here, Heideggers correlationism is evident. For Heidegger Being is
only in so far as there is a Dasein that relates meaningfully to entities, and
Dasein is only in so far as it displays this essential relation to Being. In a
similar way, the world is only in so far as Dasein exists, because the world
is neither the sum total of entities nor their container, but the coherent
milieu wherein Dasein assigns itself to a possibility of being (for example,
house building) and through that assignment lights up some entities or
lets them be encountered in one way rather than another. Truth also exists
only in so far as Dasein is, since the uncoveredness of entities that serves as
the basis for a true assertion is dependent upon Daseins understanding of
Being, which lets these entities manifest themselves. Hence, as Heidegger
will say, Newtons laws were not true before Newtons discovery, but
neither were they false. Rather, it is Newtons assertion of the laws of
motion that made entities accessible as obeying (and as having always
obeyed) these laws.
Nevertheless, Heidegger is clear that, while Dasein is the condition
of the appearance or manifestation of entities, these entities are in them-
selves the beings that they are even when there is no Dasein. Reality,
and not real things, is dependent on Dasein. This means that something
92 h u m e , d a v i d
can only manifest itself as real, that is, in its independence from Dasein,
for a Dasein that can let the entity be encountered as what it is in itself.
Furthermore, Daseins unveiling of entities does not mean that they are
merely subjective, but rather that Dasein, because it is not bound to enti-
ties but transcends them, is thrown forth or opens a world or a space of
meaning in which entities are freed to be encountered. Our being-free for
the manifestation of beings allows these beings to be binding for us, to be
the measure of our comportments and assertions.
After Being and Time, Heidegger will abandon the transcendental-
horizonal way of asking about the meaning of Being because it tends to
represent this horizon in an objectifying way as something present that is
projected by human beings. Heidegger realised that this horizon is tempo-
ral and hence includes an essentially hidden, unpresentable side. Despite
this change, Heideggers fundamental question remains the same: how
to think the truth/manifestation not of entities, but of Being itself as the
source of the meaningfulness (light, intelligibility) of entities. Being itself
is now thought as Ereignis, the event that appropriates the human being
for Being, throws the human being into the clearing of Being and calls
upon it to sustain or projectively hold open this opening. Heideggers cor-
relationism remains unchanged: he will say that Being needs the human
while the human being belongs to Being.
HUME, DAVID
Jeffrey Bell
The philosophy of David Hume plays an important role in the argument
of After Finitude, where the entire fourth of five chapters is devoted to
what Meillassoux calls Humes problem. Traditionally this problem
is known as the problem of induction. Meillassoux refers to one of the
oft-cited passages from the Treatise, where this problem becomes most
evident namely, the passage where Hume points out that there is
nothing in the nature of the billiard balls themselves that necessitates where
the struck ball will go once hit. There is nothing contradictory about the
ball going in any of an infinite number of other possible directions. What
leads us to the expectation that the ball will go where it does is that relative
to the totality and set of experiences one has had with respect to billiard
balls, one outcome is more likely than any of the others. If the ball were to
go in an unexpected direction, then we would look for a reason to account
for this. It is the totality of states of affairs that provides us with the reason
that explains any given outcome.
h u m e , d a v i d 93
HYPER-CHAOS
Robert Jackson
Hyper-chaos is one of the names for Meillassouxs primary absolute
and is used when he wishes to convey its force or power. It resembles
the eternal and lawless possible becoming of every law (AF, 64). As
Meillassoux notes, this conception of absolute is not exactly welcoming.
He dubs our grasping of it a Pyrrhic victory (AF, 64). Unlike the tradi-
tional attributes of an absolute, hyper-chaos doesnt provide us with an
orderly foundation or even an ethical standard. Since it is autonomous
and indifferent anything can happen, without reason, without law, and
without purpose. There is no higher law to govern its reach. Moreover,
it cannot be described as anything fluid, such as flux or becoming, since
this would be to misunderstand the scope of its power: even becoming is
contingent when it comes to hyper-chaos. The possibility of the world
emerging in complete stasis is entirely possible; as is the most frenetic
degree of activity.
This seems paradoxical. For if reality is hyper-chaotic why does it not
appear as such? From the vantage point of thought, causation seems stable
enough, or at least stable enough to retain my experience of consistency.
My fingers do not suddenly turn into wood, nor does the standard model of
physics change incessantly over time, destroying the quantum framework
of everything. It certainly appears that laws do not change, and we can
provide recurring accurate predictions on this basis, that is, until our fal-
libility demands a new law to explain certain contingencies. Meillassouxs
answer is to point to the consequences of the principle of factiality. In
doing so, factiality provides an alternative to the sceptical (David Hume)
and transcendental (Immanuel Kant) approaches to why thought has no
knowledge of any necessary connection between certain events occurring.
What Hume and Kant failed to challenge was their unquestioned posit-
ing of an unfathomable reason behind causation, and they also failed to
unify contingent events with stable ones, that is, how stable events such
as thought and matter emerge from such a putative hyper-chaos. If we
know there is no necessary reason supporting such stability, thought need
not attempt incessantly to grasp a cause for it. Rather it should accept the
knowledge of an acausal absolute.
Meillassoux argues that the stable universe that we experience must be
the result of hyper-chaos and that it is only by way of contingency that
laws are stable. If hyper-chaos continued to emerge with frequently stable
laws, it would make sense that one inferred the existence of a necessary
reason. Yet, this does not disqualify the indeterminate nature of those
i m m a n e n c e 95
I
IDEOLOGY
Paul J. Ennis
Meillassoux links metaphysical necessity with ideology. The ideological
standpoint is to assert that some state of affairs must be one way and cannot
be otherwise. There are many entities that can gain credence from their
association with metaphysical necessity which he defines in this context as
the pretension of proving the existence of a necessary God which, in
turn, leads to the upholding of the necessity of natural laws in our world
or of any other kind of entity for that matter (IWB, 4456). Meillassouxs
own ideological commitments are not always made clear, but a subtle
undercurrent of Marxism runs throughout his work. For instance, he tells
us that the fourth World of justice will resemble Marxs vision of a life
without politics (a communist life, IWB, 473, his emphasis).
IMMANENCE
Jeffrey Bell
As traditionally understood, immanence is how the nature of the reality
of this world is characterised such that it does not depend upon anything
other than this reality itself that is, anything that transcends it. Platos
forms, for example, transcend the particular objects of this world and these
objects depend upon the transcendent forms in order to be the objects
they are the form horseness is the transcendent reality that determines
whether or not a particular object is a horse. Aristotles forms, by contrast,
are immanent to the particular objects that embody these forms, although
96 i m m a n e n c e
ciple of sufficient reason (PSR). For Spinoza, the PSR is integral, for if
nature could be other than the way it is then it would be limited and deter-
mined by the modal possibility that it is not, which contradicts Spinozas
affirmation of an absolutely infinite substance namely, God or Nature.
Since all determination entails negation for Spinoza, an absolutely infinite
substance cannot be other than what it is for then it becomes limited by
the possibility of what it is not. Spinozas philosophy of immanence is
therefore fundamentally tied to affirming the PSR.
It is precisely the concern for substance being other than what it is
that Meillassoux rejects. In fact, a pivotal consequence of the rejection of
the PSR is that there is no reason at all for nature being or not being the
way itis. Key to this argument is the principle of non-contradiction.
Spinozist monism, for example, is a consequence of the law of non-con-
tradiction in that if we propose more than one absolutely infinite substance
then this would mean that this absolutely infinite substance is limited by a
substance that it is not, and hence it is not absolutely infinite after all. Since
this violates the law of non-contradiction the initial proposal must be false
and thus there is only one absolutely infinite substance. Meillassoux also
calls upon the law of non-contradiction but what supports it for him is the
very possibility that each and every thing could be other than it is, and for
no reason, including, somewhat paradoxically, the law of non-contradic-
tion itself. Without the PSR, we cannot provide a rational ground for the
impossibility of a contradictory being, but if we were to presuppose such
a contradictory being then it would become a necessary being for it would
always already entail what it is not. We could never imagine or think of a
thing as not being its other, for as a contradictory entity it would always
already involve its contradictory opposite. A consequence of the thesis
regarding the necessity of contingency, therefore, is Meillassouxs argu-
ment for the law of non-contradiction, and one that does not rely upon the
PSR, as does Spinoza.
For immanence to be beyond this world, therefore, is not for it to be a
possibility other than the actuality of this life, but rather radical immanence
is for life to have no reason that limits it to being or not being the life or
thing that it is. It is this radical equaliser of hyper-chaos and unreason that
comes in the wake of the absence of the PSR that brings us to immanence.
This was precisely the core insight of Nietzsches eternal recurrence and it
is the true meaning of radical immanence according to Meillassoux.
Immanence, however, need not presuppose the radical unreason
of a hyper-chaos that is the necessity that everything has no reason
for being or not being. Crucial to this conclusion was Meillassouxs
response to David Humes problem, whereby if we drop reference to a
totality or set of possibilities, then the explanatory power of the modal
98 i m m o r t a l i t y
IMMORTALITY
Paul OMahoney
Immortality as it has been conceived in mythical or metaphysical specula-
tion is not as straightforward as might be imagined. The most unqualified
form of immortality is that attributed to gods conceived of as eternal
beings. Eternity implies that the deity has always existed and thus is
uncreated, and is, technically, outside of time, rendering its nature, in
many traditions, inaccessible to human reason. An eternal being may be
distinguished from a sempiternal being, which is one created in time but
potentially immortal; many archaic gods such as Dionysus, with a popular
birth story, would technically be sempiternal. However, this immortality
is not unqualified or unconditional. A vampire, for example, is immortal
under certain conditions, but can be killed (and would not survive, for
example, the total destruction of its environment). Angels are sempiternal
beings that are created by God but immortal; the same goes for those
promised resurrection and afterlife by their religions. Even in these
cases, however, the immortality remains conditional: because it is granted
i m m o r t a l i t y 99
INTELLECTUAL INTUITION
Daniel Sacilotto
In its original, Kantian formulation, intellectual intuition designates a pos-
sible apprehension of an object or entity that does not depend on sensible
receptivity. For Immanuel Kant, this power is contrasted with the finite
intuition of the human subject, for which all apprehension of being must
remain submitted to the receptivity of the senses, and which thus anchors
the subject on a reality which the subject did not itself produce. In con-
trast, the intellectual intuition attributed to Gods infinite mind conveys
the idea of a thought that is immediately productive of its object. Thus,
unlike the human mind, Gods mind is not separated from things-in-
themselves; his thought of the thing produces the thing itself, and so the
gap between thought and being that accounts for the subjects enclosure
in the world of appearances does not obtain. In its subsequent elaboration
throughout the history of German Idealism, intellectual intuition is
postulated as required in order to ground even the subjects knowledge
of itself and the objects of experience. Canonically Fichte proposes that
the grounding principle of human knowledge consists in the intellectual
intuition of the free subject itself, as necessarily grounding the identity of
the agent on whose basis every knowledge is acquired. And yet, since this
ground is not itself an empirical datum yielded by sensory experience, it
is thereby identified as the pure practical power of the subject to identify
itself as the agent of every positing, as the condition of possibility even for
our apprehension of appearances.
In his own appropriation of the idea, Meillassoux attempts to wrest the
thesis of intellectual intuition from its idealist and correlationist iterations,
so as to adapt it for his speculative materialism. In the first instance,
it is supposed to be coeval with our grasp of the facticity of the correla-
tion as given, which Meillassoux then uses to derive the contingency
of being itself. In a next step, intellectual intuition would be essentially
connected to the rationalist thesis that, following Alain Badiou, proposes
to reactivate the distinction between primary and secondary properties
in the way of trying to think the absolute.More specifically, Meillassoux
follows Badious ontologisation of mathematics, and claims that it is
through mathematics that we are capable of grasping primary proper-
ties that pertain to being-in-itself, in so far as mathematical discourse
thinks its objects without appeals to phenomenological givenness, and so
irrespective of any experiential relation to a given subject. Put differently,
mathematics thinks the absolute precisely in so far as it thinks being qua
being, by rendering any subjective or phenomenological mediation trivial,
i n t e l l e c t u a l i n t u i t i o n 101
We must project unreason into the thing itself, and discover in our grasp of factic-
ity the veritable intellectual intuition of the absolute. Intuition, since it is well
and truly in what is that we discover a contingency with no bounds other than
itself; intellectual, since this contingency is nothing visible, nothing perceptible
in the thing: only thought can access it as it accesses the Chaos which underlies
the apparent continuities of phenomena. (AF, 111)
being. Furthermore, this is a one for which the thesis of intellectual intui-
tion seems to work as a palliative that cannot but ultimately render the
contingency of being dependent on the factical determinations of thought,
which is the thesis that speculative materialism has sworn to abjure. For
reactivating the transcendental split between being and thought can only
secure access to the former by according to the self-reflexive subject an
exceptional ontological status.
IRRELIGION
Leon Niemoczynski
Irreligion is a speculative condition required for access to the divine.
Irreligions opposite is fideism, characteristic of a postmodern religiosity
that critiques absolutes instead of speculating upon the absolute. In other
words, against fideism, Meillassoux states that only through thought about
the absolute, not a critique of absolutes is access to the divine possible
(IWB, 444). The challenge of irreligion, Meillassoux claims, is to consider
an eschatology of immortality. This immortality is associated with the
possible future appearance of a divine being and its resurrection of the
dead. Hence one strives for a philosophy of immanence that attains not to
finite knowledge, as in postmodernism, but to knowledge after finitude,
not just to the gods of the masses but to the nature of the true gods (IWB,
450).
In The Immanence of the World Beyond, Meillassouxs main target
is post-Kantian transcendental (and no longer speculative) philosophy.
Meillassoux claims that irreligiosity ought to stand against those post-
Kantian philosophers who prohibit the right of access to the real or
absolute in favour of a defense of rights to belief about the real (IWB,
449). The outcome of defending rights to belief over speculative access
entails preserving an unthinkable transcendence that is beyond the limits
of knowledge. Meillassoux claims that since the philosophy of Immanuel
Kant, a restriction upon the rights of reason has only increased, result-
ing in todays postmodern anti-metaphysical philosophy, making Kant a
distant forefather of postmodernism. The restriction of reason has made
possible the recent Continental return to religion wherein all truths reign
equally and thought or reason is left without power to determine with
complete impunity our relationship to the absolute (IWB, 450). Thus,
postmodernism has secured religious fideism in place of speculation.
Meillassoux states that in its current postmodern form, religious fideism
is best evidenced by the weak thought of Gianni Vattimo. According to
k a n t , i m m a n u e l 103
KANT, IMMANUEL
Steven Shaviro
Immanuel Kant (17241804) is not the inventor of what Meillassoux calls
correlationism, but he is its central and most important figure. For it is
Kants Critique of Pure Reason (1781) that decrees, once and for all, that, as
Meillassoux puts it, we only ever have access to the correlation between
thinking and being, and never to either term considered apart from the
other (AF, 5). Or in Kants own words, thoughts without content are
empty, intuitions without concepts are blind (A51/B76).
Kant sought to resolve the great philosophical impasse of his day: the
confrontation between rationalist philosophies derived from Leibniz, on
the one hand, and the sceptical, empiricist thought of David Hume, on
the other. On one side, there was the dogmatic claim that the world could
be understood through reason alone; on the other side, the doubt that we
could know anything beyond the limited data provided to us by our senses.
Kant resolved the impasse by declaring that neither thought alone nor
intuitions (sense-data) alone were sufficient for knowledge. Rather, Kant
104 k a n t , i m m a n u e l
LARUELLE, FRANOIS
i dentity takes various names, though primarily referred to as the One and
the Real. These names are chosen for their highly abstract character in
order to signal that radical identity cannot be philosophically represented
without erasing the identity by relating the One or the Real to Being
or Alterity, thereby erasing the radical nature of this identity. Laruelle
attempts to show how this change in axiom allows for two complimentary
projects: a science of philosophy and the fostering of a democracy (of)
thought. The first refers to the ability to treat philosophy as an object
with an identity that can be described. This flows into the second, which
refers to the idea that philosophy can be treated as one material equal
amongst others before the Real or the One. This, for Laruelle, opens up to
a more productive relationship between philosophy and science and other
regimes of knowledge.
Laruelles non-philosophy is presented by Ray Brassier in his Nihil
Unbound as a corrective to Meillassouxs appeal to intellectual intui-
tion in his speculative materialism. Meillassoux responds to this in
his contribution to the Speculative Realism event held at Goldsmiths in
April of 2007 by contrasting his and Laruelles readings of Fichte. While
Laruelle described his project in its early phases as a transcendental
realism, in recent years he has spoken of being in favour of the Real rather
than realism. Meillassoux charges Laruelle precisely on this point with
an inability to respond to correlationism. On Meillassouxs reading
LaruellesReal is merely posited by a philosopher rather than expressed
in-itself. As Meillassoux claims mathematical qualities provide the in-
itself (see Cartesian in-itself) he sees Laruelles discursively posited
Real as unable to respond to the varieties of the correlationist argument
that confuses to different degrees being and thought.
LAWS OF NATURE
Fintan Neylan
Perhaps one of the better known facts about speculative materialism
is that it conceives the laws of nature to be contingent, subject to possible
change. However, what is less known is that Meillassoux conceives them
as contingent yet stable laws. He advances such laws as a response the core
question of After Finitude: how is the discourse of the mathematical sci-
ences possible? Along with clarifying mathematical discourse about ances-
trality, to answer this question demands an account of the stability found
in the universe, for it is on the basis of this regularity that the sciences can
postulate their various predictive theories.
l a w s o f n a t u r e 107
Because the arche-fossil shows that the literal sense of the math-
ematical sciences discourse cannot be admitted within the framework
of correlationism, clarifying how it is possible requires we find an
alternative route to that taken by philosophy influenced by the Kantian
legacy. This compels one to reconceive completely the apparent law-like
regularity that we find in the universe, for to reject Kant is to relinquish
his nuanced critical account of why the world around us appears to be
ordered. With the critical route barred, one is left to think the regularity
of the universe as the result of mind-independent laws, but this is a path
that has traditionally posited such laws as necessary and eternal entities.
This might be a problem for Meillassoux, for one of the core tenets of
After Finitude is that a necessary entity is not possible. But while he refers
to his programme as classical, speculative materialism does not consist
in a dogmatic embrace of the traditional account of eternally fixed mind-
independent laws. Rather, in reformatting the account of the laws into
one where they are not backed up by any necessity, factial ontology claims
to offer an alternative to both the metaphysical and critical accounts of the
order found in nature.
The thesis that the laws of nature, along with every other entity, are
absolutely contingent occupies the first part of After Finitude. It rests on
the argument that contingency is intellectual rather than phenomenal.
While factiality holds that the laws of nature are immanent and con-
tingent, Meillassoux still admits that it is impossible to phenomenally
discern whether we exist in a world governed by necessary rules or one
governed ultimately by lawless chaos. This impossibility lies in the fact
that for every apparently chaotic occurrence we might discover, there
may be operative a hidden law to which we have been blind. Yet despite
this limitation of the empirical, it is still always conceivable that things
may be otherwise. As his analysis of strong correlationism shows, this
ability to conceive otherwise is not due to our finitude, but is provided
to us by the fact that we can grasp contingency as the absolute. This
ability to grasp the world in its contingency is named as the modicum of
the absolute which we possess. To speculate is to accede to this absolute,
meaning that regardless of our empirical limits, by way of this modicum
we may recognise the absence of necessity in any situation. Through this
speculative capacity, even apparently necessary laws can be grasped in
their ontological contingency.
Having established their contingency, difficulties arise with the quali-
fication that contingent laws may also be stable. The main obstacle posed
is the thesis from probabilistic reasoning that one can allow for contingent
laws or stable laws, but not both. Tackling this challenge takes up the bulk
of After Finitudes latter half, and it is only surmounted by demonstrating
108 l a w s o f n a t u r e
that the means by which we derive this stable contingent status is beyond
the scope of probabilitys logic.
This objection runs as follows: if the laws of nature are contingent,
why have they not changed? For every moment that the laws do not
alter, the fact that they are contingent seems all the less likely. Given
the undeniable stability of the world around us, probabilistic reasoning
states that it is far more feasible that there is a hidden necessity opera-
tive that we have yet to discover. In order to undermine this argument
that some form of o ntological necessity can be assumed from probability,
Meillassoux takes pains to show that the logic of probability is limited
to the p henomenal. Herein lies his utilisation of set theory. He draws
upon it to show that probability cannot be used to make any ontological
statement about the universe and its possibilities. This limit of probability
restricts it from either advancing laws probable necessity or disqualify-
ing their contingency. While it is applicable to particular closed cases
within the universe, his use of m athematics shows we have no grounds
to make the assumption that probability can be extended to the universe
and necessity in general. In relation to laws, mathematics serves two
purposes in After Finitude, with the first being this rejection of probable
necessity, including the implication that stability entails a hidden neces-
sity. Through it Meillassoux establishes that probability can determine
nothing about entities nature in general, that is, their ontological con-
tingency. But by his own admission, establishing this does not positively
prove that the laws are stable, only that it is thus both conceivable and
not unreasonable that there be contingent yet stable laws operative in the
universe. Having fought off a priori disqualifications of the possibility of
laws that are both contingent and stable, Meillassoux turns to outlining a
positive account of laws by introducing a condition on mind-independent
existence: if the laws of nature are to exist, they must exist as stable enti-
ties. This qualification demands that a law is not subject to flux for the
duration of its existence, even though its existence is subject to the radical
contingency of chaos. For as long as a law exists in a possible world, it
will exist as stable, thereby maintaining a minimum amount of regular-
ity that a science of that world would require. Yet even this qualification
still does not establish their existence. This point is to be accomplished
as part of his strategy of d
eriving what he calls figures, invariant truths
which hold across all possible worlds. As conditions of hyper-chaos,
these allow a non-metaphysical account of mind-independence. The
stability of laws is supposed to be entailed by one such Figure, namely,
the ability of m
athematics to make statements that pertain to the in-itself
(see Cartesian in-itself). Proving it would open a third route to account
for stable laws: not a result of metaphysical necessity or a transcendental
m a l l a r m 109
MALLARM
Adam Kotsko
Stphane Mallarm (18421898) was a French poet and literary critic
best known for his experiments with poetic form. Mallarm is considered
a leader of the Symbolist movement, which also included Paul Verlaine,
Grard de Nerval and Arthur Rimbaud, among others. This movement
was distinguished by its embrace of free verse over against the more tra-
ditional poetic forms that dominated mainstream French poetry and by
its use of evocative, indirect modes of communication. Mallarms own
style emphasised the importance of the way the words were laid out on the
page and the exploitation of the many homonyms in the French language
in order to produce ambiguity. This latter quality makes his poetry excep-
tionally difficult to translate, and this has arguably limited his influence in
the English-speaking world.
Meillassoux devotes his second book-length work, The Number and the
Siren, to a decipherment of Mallarms enigmatic final poem, Un Coup
de Ds jamais nabolira le Hasard (A Throw of Dice will never abolish
Chance). As Meillassoux summarises it, Un Coup de Ds centres on
the aftermath of a shipwreck, which leaves a mysterious Master with
one seemingly meaningless final choice: whether or not to throw a pair
of dice. It is never directly revealed whether he actually does so, and he
110 m a l l a r m
was laid in The Divine Inexistence, sections of which have been published
in Graham Harmans book on Meillassoux (DI). These selections, which
build off of the argument for contingency found in After Finitude, repre-
sent an ambitious attempt to account for all of reality within Meillassouxs
philosophical scheme, from matter and organic life to humanity and what
might come to supersede humanity. In the latter regard, he embraces
a possibility that resonates strongly with the Christian doctrine of the
resurrection of the dead, involving a human figure who somehow comes
into possession of divine power but gives it up after returning all those
who have died to life and bestowing upon all of humanity the gift of a new
immortal form of bodily existence.
For Meillassoux, Mallarm has obviously not achieved this miracu-
lous feat, but he could be viewed as a kind of forerunner in so far as his
poetic achievement represents a successful attempt to concretely grasp
the infinite. The Number and the Siren, then, clarifies what Meillassoux is
doing in The Divine Inexistence. It is inaccurate to say that Meillassoux is
embracing or appropriating Christianity. What hes really trying to do is
much bolder and, one might say, more insane: he wants to do Christianity
one better. He wants to create something more powerful than Christianity,
something that would radicalise Christianitys wildest hopes and that
would deliver on them, in so far as its based on the radical contingency of
the universe rather than on the illusion of a transcendent God.
MATERIALISM
Nathan Brown
Meillassoux names his philosophical position speculative materialism.
In After Finitude he offers a concise determination of this term:
Every materialism that would be speculative, and hence for which absolute reality
is an entity without thought, must assert both that thought is not necessary (some-
thing can be independently of thought), and that thought can think what there
must be when there is no thought. The materialism that chooses to follow the
speculative path is thereby constrained to believe that it is possible to think a given
reality by abstracting from the fact that we are thinking it. (AF, 36)
1) the materialist must hold that thought is not necessary (something can
be independently of thought);
112 m a t e r i a l i s m
2) the speculative materialist must assert that thought can think what
there must be when there is no thought.
MATHEMATICS
Sean Dudley
Since the time of the pre-Socratics, philosophy has enjoyed an inti-
mate relationship with mathematics.Indeed, the histories of both disci-
plines, when not directly intersecting, have always run parallel with one
another, sharing methods and developments and exchanging questions
and answers. The cause of this courtship should not be surprising when
one considers that in its essence mathematics provides what philosophy
seeks as its raison dtre: certain knowledge. However, for all the epistemic
riches and gifts that the mathematician has lavished upon the philosopher,
she cannot explain to him just what all this mathematical knowledge
amounts to or what it is about.
114 m a t h e m a t i c s
MAY-BE
Paul J. Ennis
On occasion Meillassoux evokes Mallarms peut-tre from the poem
Un Coup de Ds (A Throw of Dice) a favoured poem of Meillassouxs
mentor Alain Badiou. Ray Brassier translates this in Time without
Becoming as the may-be, but Robin Mackay in The Number and the
Siren chooses the PERHAPS (this is how it appears in Mallarms
poem). Alyosha Edlebi also chooses the PERHAPS in the translation
of Badiou and Mallarm. The term does not appear too often, but does
occur in at least two significant places. In The Immanence of the World
Beyond we are asked to consider the may-be as a dense possibility (463).
In this context, the may-be names the intensive unification that arises
when factial ontology and universal ethics are thought through the vecto-
rial subject (see also TWB, 1011).
MEANINGLESS SIGN
Paul J. Ennis
Meillassoux argues that the meaningless sign is the unacknowledged con-
dition underpinning our capacity to think a mind-independent reality.
This is a sign considered prior to the intervention of meaning (IRR,
25). He takes it that the meaningless sign has the dual character of a type
and its token though he prefers to use occurrence over token. Take the
example of a written sign: here we have a mark on a piece of paper that
you see as a sign. You see the mark as an occurrence of the sign-type.
Although I can generate many tokens, say of the letter a, these are all
occurrences of the type a. When I read the letter a as a sign I see the
limitlessly reproducible occurrence of an intangible sign-type (IRR, 25,
italics removed).
Meillassoux wants to consider these types in their pure state, that
is non-semantically, and he introduces a technical term to reflect this:
the kenotype (IRR, 26). The kenotype is strictly arbitrary and in formal
languages any sensible mark is sufficient to perform its function (IRR,
27). Furthermore, on the basis of its non-semantic arbitrariness it can be
infinitely variable when it comes to its form (IRR, 29). Of especial inter-
est is how in quantitative iteration we grasp identical occurrences of the
same type (IRR, 32). During the process of iteration the meaningless sign
is both intemporal and non-spatialized as type and nonetheless indexed
m e t a p h y s i c s 119
METAPHYSICS
Sean Dudley
Unlike other branches of philosophy, metaphysics is concerned not with
this or that particular domain of inquiry but with knowledge in its broad-
est and most general application. Thus, the task of the metaphysician is
to attain knowledge of the fundamental structure of reality or to think
pure being in its absolute and unconditioned form. At the same time,
the trial of the metaphysician is to lay hold of such knowledge without
thereby contaminating it with the vagaries and vicissitudes of her concep-
tual framework, and deliver metaphysical truths unto the world without
deforming them with the forceps of ones own epistemic apparatus. To
be related to truth as midwife is to child, as Socrates says; this has always
represented the metaphysicians highest aspiration. Thus, in order to do
120 m e t a p h y s i c s
metaphysics properly one must take caution not to distort the object to
be known with the tools thought employs in order to know it. This can
be stated in the form of an imperative: nothing may be posited about the
absolute that is itself not of the absolute.
The history of metaphysics then can be read as a cautionary tale detail-
ing all of the ways philosophers have tried and failed to live up to this
task. It is a task that has moved from being perceived as quite difficult
to being seen as demonstrably impossible. For once thought contem-
plates its own finitude, it is forced to conceive of metaphysics as a fools
errand. Running with the metaphor, we might also say that the history of
metaphysics can be divided into three stages: classical metaphysics, whose
model is Aristotle, and which came before finitude; critical metaphysics,
whose father is Immanuel Kant, and which might be called a metaphysics
of finitude; and now, in the philosophy of Meillassoux (and perhaps for the
first time) we get a glimpse of the possibility of what metaphysics might
look like after finitude.
The key to understanding Meillassouxs relation to the task of meta-
physics is to understand what in each prior stage he retains and what
he rejects. While Meillassoux is openly dismissive of the lions share of
classical metaphysics, it would be a profound mistake to read him solely
as a critical heir of the tradition he inherited. What Meillassoux dispar-
ages in classical metaphysics is its tendency to lapse into what is often
called onto-theology, or the positing of necessary beings either as some
first cause or deity or else as some necessary principle or law be it God,
Nature or Form. What all such dogmatic entities have in common is the
unlicensed order of their derivation: the movement from the apprehen-
sion of a contingent being or principle to the positing of a necessary cause
and sufficient reason for the existence of such a being. Indeed, the banner
of pre-critical philosophy (metaphysics before finitude) is the principle
of sufficient reason: that everything which exists has a reason for
being and for being the way it is. Following David Hume, Meillassoux
vehemently criticises the elevation of this principle, which is every-
where at work in the concept and perception of causality, to the level of
metaphysics and relegates it to realm of the psychological, that is, as one
of the many contingent habits of the mind which, though indispensable
as a tool of the finite understanding, must be dispensed with on the road
to understanding the infinite. Sufficient reason, though it manufactures
necessities, is itself the product of an entirely finite and hence contingent
structure.
No one demonstrated this to a more thorough and detailed degree than
did Kant, whose Critique of Pure Reason of 1781 augured in the age of
finitude, turning metaphysics into a mere sub-discipline of the subject
n e c e s s i t y o f c o n t i n g e n c y 121
N
NECESSITY OF CONTINGENCY
Pete Wolfendale
It is true that thinking beings evolved on Earth, and it is also true that
there are infinitely many prime numbers. Nevertheless, we can intuitively
122 n e c e s s i t y o f c o n t i n g e n c y
distinguish between the manner in which these statements are true using
so-called modal language, for example, could, might, cannot, must,
and so on. We would be inclined to agree that it might not have been the
case that we evolved, and thus that, in so far as it is possible that the world
could have been otherwise, the existence of human life is contingent. By
contrast, we would be inclined to deny that there might have been only
finite primes, and thus that, in so far as it is impossible that the world
could have been otherwise, the existence of infinite primes is necessary.
However, this seemingly intuitive distinction is merely the tip of the
modal iceberg, beneath which lies a variety of options for understanding
how we reason with modal statements (modal logic) and interpreting what
they tell us about reality (modal metaphysics).
Without digging too deeply into this topic, it is necessary to intro-
duce a few technical distinctions that help clarify the significance of
Meillassouxs claims concerning the necessity of contingency. On the
one hand, there are what Meillassoux calls real possibilities or ways the
world could possibly be in itself (see Cartesian in-itself). The technical
name for this is alethic modality, and it is often differentiated into further
kinds. For example, one can draw a distinction between logical necessity
and nomological necessity, or between those truths that are invariant
with respect to the laws of thought (usually including mathematics) and
those truths that are invariant with respect to the laws of nature (usually
defined by physics). This means that there can be a sense in which it is
nomologically necessary that planets orbit stars even though it is logi-
cally possible that they could do otherwise. On the other hand, there are
what Meillassoux calls possibilities of ignorance or ways the world could
possibly be as far as we know. The technical name for this is epistemic
modality and it is usually relative to shared certainty within discursive
contexts. For example, we might agree that JFK was actually assassinated,
but disagree about whether Oswald did it, and thus be inclined to say its
necessary that someone fired the fatal shot, but that its possible it was
Oswald or a gunman on the grassy knoll. Though alethic and epistemic
modals are related, they can diverge, such as when we say that Goldbachs
conjecture might be true (epistemic), even though if it is true, it must be
true (alethic).
Meillassouxs thesis regarding the necessity of contingency is first
introduced negatively as the principle of unreason. He opposes this to
the principle of sufficient reason, which for him is the essence of
metaphysical dogmatism in so far as the claim that there is a reason for
each state of affairs collapses into the claim that there is a reason for all
of them. This inevitably leads to the demand of onto-theology for a
necessary entity, for example, the God depicted by Aristotle, or a set of
n e c e s s i t y o f c o n t i n g e n c y 123
NIHILISM
Sean Dudley
In the most general sense nihilism names a simple, speculative thesis: that
the order of human being, from morality, to phenomenology, to lan-
guage, reflects nothing, not even dimly, about the order of being in-itself,
taken either in the key of nature or in the key of a deeper cosmology.
Nihilism is the result of reasons continual penetration beyond the order
of the human into the order of non-human nature. In its most resound-
ing tenor, nihilism ushers in the collapse of any and all transcendental
philosophy whose topic, were there to be one, would be the excavation
and exultation of the supposedly necessary and therefore transcendental
categories of human thought as well as the phenomenological structures
of first-person conscious experience that underwrite it. Since the forms of
experience reflect the arbitrary and ad hoc morphological constraints of the
human brain, there is no longer any reason to believe that how we think
about and perceive the world has any relationship whatsoever to how the
world really is in itself.
On this view, human cognition is a process no more or less transcen-
dental than is perspiration or egg-laying. Our mental structure is no
more necessary than the structure of our vertebrae, both simply reflecting
the arborous and venal pathway of a by and large arbitrary evolution-
ary history of outward spreading ampliative mutation rather than the
exemplification of some sort of gradual unfolding of the absolute toward a
utopian kingdom of ends. The human categories of possible experience,
for instance as catalogued by Immanuel Kant, deserve no special standing
above or beyond the categories enjoyed by penguins or dust-mites. Our
n i h i l i s m 125
epistemic powers provide us with a view of the world that aims not at truth
but at adaptive advantage within our own ecosystem. Judged this way, it is
not clear at all whether humans have been equipped by nature in any way
more favourable than have the cockroach or e. coli. Like the latter, we have
been armed with our own variety of experience or blooming, buzzing,
confusion in William James words, and we, like any other creature, use
the faculties given to us to gather energy, excrete waste and reproduce.
The rest is window-dressing.
Perhaps the most damning blow nihilism lays on philosophy is the
permanent foreclosure on the possibility of knowledge. In short, episte-
mology, the study of how we distinguish truth from falsehood, becomes
annexed into the ever-expanding microscope of the empirical scientist,
leaving whatever philosophers have said on the matter more or less a topic
for the history of anthropology.The noble and heraldic pursuit of truth
is transformed into the slow march of a slave caravan moving between
the carrot and stick of lust and anxiety, different only in degree from the
motivations that inform the movements of reptiles and microbial slime.
It is this implosion of the old-fashioned notions of universal truth and
knowledge that demote the philosopher from his former position at the
head of the academy of the sciences to the basement office of the library
in the role of the eccentric, broom-wielding custodian. For with truth no
longer on the table, the philosopher has nothing left to do but become
a kind of curator of concepts, polishing arguments here and there and
helping to facilitate and expedite interdisciplinary communiqus between
the sciences and humanities, mopping up any spills that happen in the
hallways along the way.
But what does Meillassouxian philosophy have to say about nihilism?
Any such nihilism, which yokes the frailty of mans cognitive pedigree to
an external necessity, even the necessity of natural law, is itself slave to the
principle of sufficient reason, a principle that Meillassoux explicitly
rejects as pure dogma. For nihilism taken as the narrative of mans drive
to extinction is itself a narrative following its own thread of ontological
necessity. Once we raise the contingency of the correlation between mind
and world from the level of mere possibility to the level of necessity, as
Meillassoux does, we unleash an infinite nihilism powerful enough to
shatter not only every concord between man and cosmos but also every
discord and schism. Paradoxically, nihilism after Meillassoux becomes a
principle strong enough to cradle even the most anthropocentric fantasies
of man who restores in thinking the absolute contingency of necessity, the
permission to believe that anything is possible.
126 n o n - w h o l e / n o n - a l l
NON-WHOLE/NON-ALL
Peter Gratton
Introduced in Lacans Seminar XX, pas-tout translatable as non-
all, non-whole, or even not every refers to the non-totalisability or
subsumability of subjects under a given universal. In Badious Being and
Event, this comes to mean the non-totalisability of the universe given the
outcome of set theory. For Meillassoux, until Cantor, what was possible
was thought under a set of possibilities, even if highly improbable. In each
set or World, there is a given range of chances. For example, for a die,
the chance of rolling a one is one out of six. But what Meillassoux says
is that there is no totalisable set of all possible sets or universes. As such,
while within this World we have a number of possibles, the universe itself
cannot be totalised in terms of its possibilities. This he refers to as world
(lower case) or the virtual, the illimitable non-Whole of possibilities of
creation in hyper-chaos.
This non-Whole rids us of the frequentialist implication, as discussed
in After Finitude. We look at the universes apparent stability and guess
that the chances would be extremely low that this universe could be stable
without some eternal set of physical laws. However, Meillassoux argues
that aleatory reasoning only works when you have a total number of sets
from which to judge (like the six sides of a die), but given his use of set
theory, there is no total set of all sets, and thus one cannot calculate any
probability for this stability, even a minute one. In this way, hyper-chaos
may, yes, have provided for an apparently stable universe, but it also may,
at any time, give rise to a new World out of this one. For Meillassoux this
has already occurred, with the physical laws changing to allow the move
from the World of matter to the World of organic matter, and then to the
World that allows thought, and, foreseeably, perhaps a World beyond this
one, a World of justice.
o b j e c t o r i e n t e d o n t o l o g y 127
O
OBJECT ORIENTED ONTOLOGY
Rick Elmore
Object Oriented Ontology (OOO) is a branch of speculative realism
associated with the work of Graham Harman, Levi Bryant, Ian Bogost
and Tim Morton. Bryant coined the term in 2009, as a corollary to Object
Oriented Philosophy (OOP), a phrase Harman began using in the late
1990s to describe the trajectory of his own work (Harman 2010: 93).
Although the two terms, OOO and OOP, mark different moments in
the history of object oriented thought, they are today used more or less
interchangeably. Despite its relative youth, OOO has a following in the
fields of philosophy, media studies, ecology and cultural studies. Many of
the central proponents of object oriented philosophy have long-running,
influential blogs and their association with publishing companies like Zero
Books and the online publisher Open Humanities Press led to the rapid
release and distribution of works related to OOO.
Like all forms of speculative realism, OOO begins from the critique of
correlationism, that is, the belief that the humanworld correlate forms
the central element of all philosophical investigation (Bryant et al. 2011:
19). Against correlationism, OOO contends that the cosmos is entirely
made up of individual objects: all being is composed of objects (Bryant
2010). The humanworld relation is, from an object oriented perspective,
neither unique nor fundamental, but is rather just an example of object-
to-object interactions. In fact, for OOO, the universe exists as a collec-
tion of autonomous objects interacting through a process Bryant terms
Exo-relation, a process of foreign relations in which objects translate
one another in terms of themselves (Bryant 2010). Morton formulates
this process in his work on causality, where he describes interactions
between objects as a sampling in which, for example, a cup cups the
table, and the table tables the cup, and a human humans the coffee, and
so on (Morton 2013). Because of its central claim that reality is entirely
made up of objects, OOO is a flat ontology, placing all entities in the
universe on the ontologically equal footing of being equally objects. This
is not to say that, for OOO, there is no difference between objects. Rather,
OOO gives no ontological privilege to any particular object, a claim that
strikes to the very heart of correlationism, anthropocentrism and idealism:
128 o b j e c t o r i e n t e d o n t o l o g y
Rick Elmore
The critique by object oriented ontology (OOO) of speculative materi-
alism asserts that Meillassoux fails to articulate a form of correlation-
ism that does not ultimately fall prey to idealism (Harman 2011a: 124).
The clearest formulation of this critique appears in Graham Harmans
Quentin Meillassoux: Philosophy in the Making (2011). In that work,
Harman contests Meillassouxs rejection of the principle of sufficient
reason, privileging of time over space, and commitment to the concept
of law (Harman 2011a: 14158). However, Harmans primary critique,
and the one shared by all proponents of OOO, concerns Meillassouxs
assertion that one cannot think what is outside thought and his reliance on
a notion of the meaningless to ground his escape from the correlationist
circle (Harman 2011a: 13940).
For Harman, Meillassoux accepts the basic truth of the correlationist
position, that one cannot think what is outside of thought. This claim
grounds his rejection of realism, Harman claims, as he contends that to
think what is outside thought necessarily leads to a performative contra-
diction: turning what is other than thought into thought (Harman 2011a:
165). Proponents of OOO find this argument relatively weak, as, for
them, the existence of any object necessarily exceeds all human thought
and knowledge about it. Were this not the case, our knowledge of objects
would be indistinguishable from the objects themselves, and absolute
idealism would win the day (Harman 2011a: 148).
For Levi Bryant, Meillassouxs insistence on performative contradic-
tion problematically assumes all thought to be self-reflexive (a thinking
about thinking). This assumption leads to an infinite regress, since, if one
cannot think something without thinking about it, then thinking becomes
nothing but a thinking about thinking and so on into infinity (Bryant
2010). Hence in order for there to be any possibility of accessing a world
outside thought, a possibility to which Meillassoux is committed, there
must be some form of thought that is not entirely self-reflexive, and, con-
sequently, immune to the claim of performative contradiction. Yet this is
130 o n t o l o g i c a l a r g u m e n t
but one half of the OOO critique of Meillassoux on the issue of thought,
the other having to do with his rendering of what he dubs meaningless.
While committed to the importance of the humanworld correlate,
Harman claims, Meillassoux does not foreclose the possibility of some-
thing existing outside thought. In fact, he insists on it. This insistence
comes from his rejection of the notion that the meaningful must exhaust
the real. The fact that we cannot meaningfully think what is outside
thought does not entail its non-existence. It is this claim that Meillassoux
believes saves him from the charge of idealism, as Harman portrays it,
since it shows that something exists outside thought (the meaningless)
without falling into a performative contradiction (giving this outside any
meaning). Proponents of OOO critique this argument on the grounds that
Meillassoux cannot maintain a concept of the meaningless as necessarily
existing outside thought (Harman 2011a: 13940).
For OOO, it is not enough for Meillassoux to claim that something
meaningless exists in order to establish that it exists outside thought.
One can imagine all kinds of meaningless statements that do not
entail thought-independent existence, for example, non-white white
or square circle (Harman 2011a: 140). The meaninglessness of these
statements does not grant them existence as a real possibility. Hence, it
is not simply any meaningless statement at all that eventually does the work
of dethroning Absolute Idealism, [for Meillassoux] but a specific form of
meaninglessness (Harman 2011a: 140). For Harman, a truly meaning-
less statement would resist any determination of its existence. Hence,
Meillassouxs argument works only by making the meaningless actually
meaningful, ascribing to it the meaningful predicate of existence outside
thought.
Meillassouxs response to these critiques is that any attempt to cir-
cumvent the correlationist circle remains necessarily victim to the
vicious pragmatic circle of the performative contradiction outlined above
(Harman 2011a: 1645). For him, there is simply no ground outside the
humanworld correlate on which to initiate a critique of that correlate.
Hence, in so far as OOO argues for the abandonment of the humanworld
correlate entirely, it remains, for Meillassoux, a kind of naive realism.
ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT
Paul OMahoney
An ontological argument is one which derives and demonstrates the
existence of God using reason alone, unaided by observation. The most
o n t o l o g i c a l a r g u m e n t 131
famous instance of the ontological argument and the most important for
Meillassoux is that articulated by Ren Descartes in his Meditations on
First Philosophy (1641). The argument has a twofold purpose in Descartes:
first, the rational demonstration of the existence of God, aimed at those
for whom faith in revealed scripture is not sufficient; and second, and
more importantly, to furnish a guarantor of the reliability of reason and
human knowledge. The Cartesian God is conceived of as the sum of all
perfections. As existence is deemed superior to inexistence, existence is
a perfection. A perfect being must therefore of necessity exist. As the
idea of a perfect and infinite being could not have been produced by an
imperfect and finite being, such as the finite thinking thing or cogito, nor
encountered by it, the idea of such a being as God is innate: it is implanted
by God in the manner of a craftsmans stamp. The idea is present innately
in every person, and can be arrived at by sufficient reflection.
This perfect being has the three traditional attributes of God: omnipo-
tence, omniscience and omnibenevolence. The last is posited as wicked-
ness and deceit are construed as imperfections, and inimical to the nature
of a perfect being. This allows Descartes to overcome the most radical
hypothesis of his methodical doubt: that an evil demon, or God Himself,
is deceiving Descartes at every turn. Gods perfection implies that he is a
non-deceiver, and this fact allows Descartes to assert that it is impossible
that God Himself would actively deceive Descartes or that He would allow
an evil demon to do so.
God as demonstrated by the argument functions as an absolute: His
existence, though it can be made manifest upon reflection or demonstrated
to us, is not dependent on us. The most prominent precedent to Descartes,
and perhaps the first coherent articulation of the ontological argument, is
that put forth by St Anselm of Canterbury in his Proslogion (c. 1078),
where God is defined as that greater than which cannot be thought.
Anselms work occasioned what remains one of the most celebrated
ripostes to the argument. The Benedictine monk Gaunilos reply On
Behalf of the Fool maintained that if conceiving of a perfect being implied
its existence, this could be extended to a perfect island, and innumerable
other entities. The objection has not been widely accepted. Perhaps the
most famous twentieth-century version of the argument is that proposed
by Alvin Plantinga. Kurt Gdel also offered a proof which, though logi-
cally valid, does not suffice to demonstrate the existence of God.
The most pertinent criticism of the ontological argument for Meillassoux
is that offered by Kant. For Kant, existence cannot be counted as a predi-
cate. There is no contradiction in imagining that God does not exist, and
so the predicate exists is merely part of an analytic judgement and adds
nothing to the subject. For Meillassoux, the (Cartesian) ontological
132 o n t o - t h e o l o g y
ONTO-THEOLOGY
Marie-Eve Morin
Metaphysics, according to Heidegger, seeks to answer the fundamental
question, why are there beings rather than nothing? This question seeks
the ground for beings, yet this project of grounding splits into two. First,
beings are interrogated with regard to their Being: what does it mean for
an entity in general to be? At the same time, beings as a whole are brought
back to a first cause or foundation, to an entity that can ground and
sustain in Being what exists as a whole. As such, metaphysics is both
ontology, the process of grounding beings qua beings in Being, and theol-
ogy, the process of grounding the Being of what is in a highest entity, that
is to say, God. In both branches, the ground or explanation for what
exists will be transcendent, yet it will be so in different ways. Metaphysics
has only one subject matter, beings, but it approaches its subject matter
from two angles: according to what is universal or common, and accord-
ing to what is ultimate or highest. Onto-theology is also essentially a
logic: because beings are questioned with regards to their ground (logos,
ratio), beings appear as what is grounded in, and as the grounding cause
of, Being.
The onto-theological structure of metaphysics, according to Heidegger,
is essentially related to the difference between essence and existence.
Metaphysics studies beings as such and as a whole, that is, it studies
beings with regards to their essence as beings and it studies the whole
of beings, the world, with regards to its existence. The two are related:
ontology determines the essence of the beings whose existence is explained
by theology. Essence (whatness) answers the question: What is x? while
existence (thatness) answers the question, Is there an x? While ontology
lays out the essence of something in so far as it is not only a specific thing
(a table or a chair) but a something in general, theology studies the cause
of the existence of beings. This cause takes the form of a being that is itself
o v e r t u r n e d p l a t o n i s m 133
OVERTURNED PLATONISM
Paul J. Ennis
On occasion Meillassoux uses the term overturned Platonism to describe
his intent to flip the traditional stabilitybecoming opposition (CLN,
134 p h e n o m e n o l o g y
P
PHENOMENOLOGY
Marie-Eve Morin
Phenomenology can be broadly defined as the study or science of phe-
nomena. As Heidegger points out in the introduction to Being and Time,
unlike other sciences such as biology or sociology, the name phenom-
enology does not name a specific realm of objects to be studied, such
as living things or social things, but is a purely methodological concept.
Phenomenon names that which shows itself in itself and logos originally
means letting something be seen. Putting both together, phenomenology
means, to let that which shows itself be seen from itself in the very way in
which it shows itself from itself (Heidegger 1962: 7), without any refer-
ence to a subject matter.
Husserlian phenomenology arises out of critique of both psychologism
and representationalism. Psychologism assumes that because all truths are
achieved by a conscious subject, then all truths are necessarily dependent
on factual conditions of thought. For example, the law of non-contradiction
does not say objectively that something cannot be bothA and not A, but
rather that it is not possible for us subjectively to think both A and not
A. For Husserl, this is a category mistake. When I say that 2+2=4, I say
nothing about counting, even though the truth of the result 4 can only be
achieved through an act of counting. The puzzle of phenomenology is how
subjectively individuated acts of consciousness can give rise to objectivity,
that is, to something that is or is true independently from consciousness.
p h e n o m e n o l o g y 135
refrain from following through with the arrow that consciousness is.
Thanks to this suspension, we are led back and hence gain access to a
forgotten or overlooked dimension, that is, the consciousnessworld rela-
tion. This is the phenomenological reduction. Reduction here does not
mean that something has been removed, that is, that the object has been
lost, but rather that one is led back to (re-ducere in Latin). In the reduc-
tion, I still have the whole of my consciousness with everything that is
presented in it. Furthermore, what is presented is still presented as real,
as illusion, as ideal, and so on, but instead of being interested in what is
presented (what is it? is it real?), I suspend my judgement so that I can
focus on how it is presented as this or that, as real or illusory, and so on.
Hence, we cannot say that, because of the phenomenological reduction,
the phenomenologist does not have access to or disregards reality (or
real things). Rather, being-real now means being given to conscious-
ness in a certain way.
The field of study uncovered by the phenomenological reduction
consists of two interrelated poles, the noetic or act pole and the noematic
or object pole. Phenomenology studies the correlation between these two
poles, for example, how a perceived object gives itself in a perceiving,
how a modification of the perceiving into an imagining changes some
features of the perceived (it is not an imagined object but a perceived
one) but not others (it is still the same blue house, and so on). At this
point, the phenomenologist also needs to perform an eidetic reduction.
This is the reduction that leads from particular facts to essences. This
is achieved through imaginary variations: I vary the perception until it
is not a perception anymore so as to uncover the essential features of the
perceivingperceived correlation, and so on. Finally Husserl thinks that
the phenomenological reduction if correctly and radically performed will
necessarily lead to a transcendental reduction because consciousness (the
dimension uncovered by the phenomenological reduction) cannot itself
be a worldly thing that appears to consciousness. Such a circularity would
lead us to transcendental realism and we would be committing the same
mistake as psychologism.
POTENTIALITY
Leon Niemoczynski
Meillassoux is careful to distinguish between two cases of being: the
potential and the virtual. Similar to how Deleuzes ontology hinges on
a distinction between the virtual and the actual, Meillassouxs ontology
p o t e n t i a l i t y 137
Francis Halsall
The opening sentences of After Finitude are an audacious declaration that
the theory of primary and secondary qualities will be rehabilitated. Hence
Meillassoux revisits an old philosophical theme that had become, he
claims, seemingly obsolete. This is his way back into a speculative meta-
physics that reconsiders the relation between consciousness and the abso-
lute. In short, primary qualities are those which objects actually have;
secondary qualities are produced in experience. They are utterly distinct
from each other. Secondary qualities are those features of the phenomenal
realm by which it is present to consciousness. They are sensible for us
and are not the necessary features of objects. The secondary qualities of
an object do not exist in things themselves; rather, they emerge from the
relation of consciousness to objects. The primary qualities of an object,
in distinction, are autonomous from sensible qualities. They are not part
of the relation of consciousness to objects but those elements of objects
which can be expressed mathematically.
The terms were most famously coined by Locke, although Meillassoux
identifies a significant pre-emption in Ren Descartes discussions of
sensations, such as pain, originating in a subjects relation to an object
and not in the object itself. By returning to a well-worn philosophical
topic Meillassouxs intention is to challenge the transcendental tradition
of post-Kantian philosophy. Hence, he wishes to sidestep both Kantian
arguments regarding the un-knowability of the noumenal world of things-
in-themselves and phenomenological attempts to negotiate these argu-
ments by returning to the primacy of objects in perception and moving
from these to analysis of noematic and noetic content. These philosophical
moves create a problem which is exemplified for Meillassoux in the corre-
lationist position, namely how the primary qualities of the world-in-itself
can be represented without them subsequently becoming available for us.
Meillassoux finds the philosophical route to de-subjectivated nature in
p r i n c i p l e o f n o n - c o n t r a d i c t i o n 139
PRINCIPLE OF NON-CONTRADICTION
Raphal Millire
Whether contradictions can exist or not in the world has been an impor-
tant philosophical issue since Aristotle, if not Heraclitus. Naturally, it
also occupies a central place in Meillassouxs work, since the ontological
principle of non-contradiction is the first of the non-trivial figures he
intends to deduce from the apodictic principle of factuality. Though
this proof appears in After Finitude (6771), Meillassouxs earliest treat-
ment of the principle of non-contradiction is to be found in his PhD
thesis, LInexistence divine (excerpts of which appear in DI, 12871).
Interestingly, it is also his lengthiest examination of this issue, although
it comes from an unpublished academic work. Meillassoux intends to
publish a revised and expanded version of LInexistence divine, which he
has been working on for more than a decade. Since this opus magnum still
remains unpublished, we will focus on the original version, which is in
line with his shorter development of non-contradiction found in After
Finitude. It is however possible that Meillassoux will revise part of his
position on the matter in forthcoming publications, since we may consider
he hasnt yet given his definitive thesis on this central theme.
Meillassouxs main thesis on contradiction is the following: it is
140 p r i n c i p l e o f n o n - c o n t r a d i c t i o n
Sergey Sistiaga
The principle of sufficient reason (PSR) was first stated explicitly by
Leibniz (Monadology, 31), but was implicitly at work from the very begin-
ning of philosophy. It says that everything has a reason why it is, as it is,
rather than otherwise. As such it is the central principle of rationalism,
stating that everything admits theoretically of an explanation, is poten-
tially intelligible, and that the structure of being must be fundamentally
rational. Rigorously applied, as in Spinoza, it entails necessitarianism.
This means everything happens with metaphysical necessity and leads
to the postulation of a first cause or causa sui that had no previous cause,
which is supposed to end the infinite regress of reason/explanations/
grounds by means of a self-explanatory and self-grounding necessary
entity. These extreme c onsequences lead various philosophers to soften its
consequences. In Leibniz, God has the free choice of all possible worlds.
Some have condemned the PSR as unjustified metaphysical speculation, as
David Hume, Immanuel Kant and their post-metaphysical followers did.
Meillassoux explicitly rejects the PSR on philosophical grounds as
absolutely false (AF, 53, 60, 71), but sometimes hints at political motives,
where he claims an incompatibility between the PSR and the critique of
ideology (AF, 334). Proceeding from Leibnizs distinction of two inde-
pendent fundamental principles (Monadology, 31; AF, 71), the PSR and
the principle of non-contradiction (PNC), we find that Meillassouxs
rejection of the PSR is based on two different historically very influen-
tial arguments. Meillassoux uses a controversial Cartesian argument,
which today falls under the name of the conceivability argument, where
one concludes real possibility out of logical conceivability (Descartes,
MeditationVI). With Hume, Meillassoux argues that since the denial of
the PSR implies no contradiction, it is conceivable and therefore possible
that the PSR could be wrong, because the latter is not a necessary truth
or tautology. In addition Meillassoux generalises Kants critique of the
ontological argument into the thesis that every proof for a necessarily
existing entity is impossible. In extrapolating from the impossibility to
prove a necessary entity to the strong claim that no such entity could
exist, Meillassoux thinks the PSR cannot be maintained anymore because
no self-explanatory entity could stop the infinite regress of reasons (AF,
303).
Meillassouxs own argument is based on the Cartesian dualism between
thought and being, transformed through Berkeley and Kant into the
thesis that Meillassoux terms correlationism, which says that thought
p r i n c i p l e o f s u f f i c i e n t r e a s o n 143
can never access being in-itself, because then being would just be being
for-us, because thinking always turns the unthought into thought via the
correlationist circle (see Cartesian in-itself; Ren Descartes).
His rejection of necessary entities and the structure of the correlation-
ist circle, which does not allow us to think any de-correlated entity that
could be the hidden reason of this very structure, preclude the possibility
of absolutising the correlation itself. Having excluded all external and
internal reasons for the correlations existence, Meillassoux concludes
the facticity or groundlessness of the correlation. Rejecting with the PSR
brute and unexplainable facts, Meillassoux turns the only remaining fact
that doesnt fall prey to correlationism into an explanatory absolute, the
facticity of the correlation. If facticity is necessary, which he dubs factial-
ity, then the PSR as a metaphysical absolute is false, because its opposite,
the principle of unreason, a speculative absolute, is true (AF, 5060).
To counter the obvious objection, that this move would only render
thoughts inability to think the absolute into an absolute inability
(AF,52), Meillassoux argues that only by assuming ontological facticity
in the first place is one able to make sense of the distinction between the
in-itself and the for-us. Since for being to be different from thought it
needs to have the potential of being-other than it actually is for us, since
otherwise thought could think being in-itself. The possibility to think
the dualist basics of correlationism implies for Meillassoux that every
epistemic possibility has to be a real possibility, otherwise correlationism
itself would become unthinkable. In holding that everything that can be
thought can become real, Meillassoux denies against Leibniz the comple-
mentarity of the PNC with the PSR, by turning the former against the
latter.
To use the PNC to deny the PSR is no problem, because so far nobody
has come up with a demonstration that the PSR is a necessary truth
whose denial would involve a contradiction. Nonetheless, it could seem
that Meillassouxs argument for his principle of unreason is itself threat-
ened by a set of structurally similar contradictions. On several occasions
Meillassoux denies the premise, which as in the case of correlationism is
indispensable for his argumentation, in the conclusion of his argument.
He argues from the truth of correlationism to its falsity, from dualism to
monism, from the non-absolute to the absolute of the non-All, which may
in-itself be a contradiction. In all cases his conclusions contradict their
premises. Indeed, trying to convert correlationist dualism into an absolute
monism of unreason may well be an impossible task, as the absolute cannot
by definition be fundamentally divided in itself. Seen from this angle it is
not surprising, as Brassier observes, that Meillassoux never gets rid of his
initial dualism of thinking and being (Brassier 2007: 8594).
144 p t o l e m a i c c o u n t e r - r e v o l u t i o n
PTOLEMAIC COUNTER-REVOLUTION
Francis Halsall
The Ptolemaic counter-revolution appears in Chapter 5 of After Finitude
to name the philosophical response to the Copernican Revolution
in science. Meillassoux recognises that the Copernican revolution has
two meanings: a literal and genuine sense from which modern science
emerges; and a metaphorical use in philosophy. In this second sense it
is often used to name the transcendental turn to correlationism taken
by philosophy from Kant onwards. Meillassouxs decision to call this
second sense the Ptolemaic counter-revolution is rhetorical as it suggests
the tradition he ultimately wants to oppose is retrogressive. Meillassoux
recognises that the Copernican revolution in science does not refer to
astronomical modelling but rather the theoretical awareness, developed
also by Galileo and Ren Descartes, that fundamental features of nature
can be described mathematically. Hence the world, by virtue of its math-
ematisation, is separable from human consciousness and is not reducible
to being a correlate of thought.
This Copernican-Galilean revolution leads to the decentring of
thought relative to the world within the process of knowledge (AF, 115).
This creates the catastrophe that science replaces metaphysics as the
guarantor of knowledge, namely that simultaneous to the scientific
positing of a world independent to thought comes the realisation that the
claims of science are naive and secondary to philosophical thought for they
cannot guarantee their own truth. This, Meillassoux claims, is the violent
contradiction at the heart of the schism of modernity: that whilst science
r a t i o n a l i s m 145
R
RATIONALISM
Daniel Sacilotto
Rationalism is first thematised in distinction to empiricism in the context
of the modern philosophical enquiries about the connection between
146 r a t i o n a l i s m
REALISM
Lee Braver
If any question is distinctly philosophical, surely it is the question, what is
reality? The standard answer, so much a default position that it can sound
rather odd when explicitly stated, is that reality is just out there, regardless
of us mind-independent, to use the technical term. The particularities
of our beliefs, language, concepts and so on are to have no impact on the
existence or nature of the world beyond trivial instances of our actually
doing things to it of course. Any properties introduced by the mind are,
at best, a second-rate reality essentially tainted by subjectivity such as
secondary qualities or aesthetic values.
While mind-independence is generally taken to be its core component,
realism tends to bring other ideas in its wake. Truth, for instance, is
usually taken to be a form of correspondence: we must capture the world
148 r e a l i s m
the way it really is or the way it is anyway, as Bernard Williams has said.
Even sceptics agree on this definition of knowledge, only concluding that
it is impossible. Certain ideas about the mind also fit into this view: for us
to be capable of capturing reality, the mind must be able to remain still,
merely reflecting the world like an untroubled mirror or a blank piece of
paper. Some have attributed a certain determinacy to reality in the form of
bivalence: every claim about the world either is or is not true, regardless of
our ability to ascertain this.
Some form of realism has been tacitly assumed throughout the vast
majority of the history of philosophy, with disputes mainly concerning
which entities form the paradigms of reality the realest reality, if you
will: Forms, particular individuals, God, quantitatively measurable sub-
stances, noumena, and so on. It was Immanuel Kant who constructed
the first coherent, thorough alternative to realism with his Copernican
Revolution. Because the mind actively organises experience, necessarily
introducing certain forms and structures into it, he argues that we can
never capture or even encounter reality as it is in-itself, what he called
noumena. Instead, we can only experience and know the world for-us, as
our faculties have shaped it, phenomena. Meillassoux calls this view cor-
relationism because it shifts attention from studying reality in-itself to
studying reality in relation to us. He believes that Continental philosophy
has largely taken this Kantian approach for granted. It has almost consist-
ently operated on the view that we can only talk about the world as it
presents itself to us, in the ways that we talk about it. This idea, sometimes
called anti-realism, has displaced realism as the default, almost self-evident
philosophical view during the last two centuries of Continental thought.
Analytic philosophy in many ways arose from its rejection. Its found-
ers, Frege, Moore and Russell, all vehemently reject idealism, whether
in its Kantian, German, or British varieties. They return to a pre-Kantian
realism where we could achieve unmediated contact with the realist real,
which took the form of logic for Frege and Russell. By the mid-twentieth
century, however, analytic resistance to this naive realism took hold, with
philosophers such as the later Wittgenstein, Quine, Goodman, Davidson,
Putnam and Dummett all pushing back to varying degrees and in various
forms.
Anti-realism or correlationism maintained its dominance in Continental
philosophy, on the other hand, through the end of the twentieth century.
In his later work, Heidegger insists that being only is in relation to human
beings, for Foucault the historical forms various phenomena take exhausts
their reality, and Derrida (in)famously claims that there is nothing
outside the text, that is, that all of our experience and encounters with the
world are essentially mediated by language and other contextual features.
r e s u r r e c t i o n 149
RESURRECTION
Leon Niemoczynski
In Meillassouxs divinology the dead must be bodily resurrected in order
for the most absurd conditions of death to be surpassed. According to
Meillassoux an absurd death is a death where the living have departed
150 r e s u r r e c t i o n
S
SCIENCE
Robert S. Gall
Science and a particular understanding of science lie at the heart of
Meillassouxs philosophical project. Meillassoux sees his task and the task
of philosophy as completing the Copernican Revolution in science. He
thinks that revolution calls for eliminating any consideration of the subject
within the process of knowledge; science has the last word about what
it says. This makes Meillassoux suspicious of post-Kantian critiques of
science, which he does not address specifically but characterises generally
as claiming that science harbours a meaning other than the one delivered
by science itself (AF, 119). This is why in After Finitude Meillassoux
undertakes an analysis of certain kinds of scientific statements, which he
calls ancestral statements, in an effort to undermine the coherence of all
Kantian and post-Kantian philosophies and their corresponding philoso-
phies of science. That analysis reveals a philosophy of science that dove-
tails with his own rationalist philosophy that seeks to explain how science
is able to give a description of the world uncontaminated by experience.
Meillassoux notes that science routinely makes statements about the
state of the universe prior to the existence of human beings, indeed,
prior to the existence of any life on earth. For example, scientists claim
that the accretion of the earth occurred roughly 4.56 billion years ago
and took place over the course of tens of millions of years, occupying
a certain volume in space that varied through time. Meillassoux argues
that Kantian and post-Kantian philosophy, which he calls correlation-
ism, cannot make any sense of such a claim. Since correlationism binds
together thinking and being, correlationism must say the ancestral state-
ment is only true after the emergence of thinking, even though it refers
to a situation prior to the emergence of thinking. That, Meillassoux says,
does not make any sense. This leaves only one alternative: the realist
meaning of the ancestral statement is its ultimate meaning, that is, an
ancestral statement only has sense if its literal sense is also its ultimate sense
(AF, 14, 17, his emphases).
From this we can see that Meillassouxs philosophy of science falls
under the heading of what is known as scientific realism. Generally,
scientific realism is composed of three commitments. First, it holds that
152 s c i e n c e
all those aspects of the object that can be formulated in mathematical terms can be
meaningfully conceived as properties of the object in itself. All those aspects of the
object that can give rise to a mathematical thought (to a formula or to digitalisa-
tion) rather than to a perception or sensation can be meaningfully turned into
properties of the thing not only as it is with me, but also as it is without me.
(AF,3, his emphasis)
SET THEORY
Sebastian Purcell
Set theory is a branch of mathematics that studies sets, or collections
of objects defined exclusively by their membership in that collection.
Because almost every mathematical notion can be defined in terms of sets,
set theory, in conjunction with predicate calculus, is understood to provide
the most basic foundation for mathematical investigation. Historically,
this area of mathematics was developed in the 1870s by Georg Cantor,
who produced the modern account of sets in order to settle questions of
number theory in relation to real numbers. In doing so he also established
the existence of different sizes or cardinalities of infinity, which serve as
the foundation for contemporary number theory. For Meillassoux, set
theory is significant because it expresses the most fundamental aspects of
ontology in-itself, or reality independent of human consciousness, since
he identifies the in-itself with whatever can be formulated in mathematical
terms.
In its initial naive formulation, set theory understands sets to be any
sort of well-defined collection, whether real or imaginary. The collections
of all trees or all unicorns are equally sets. The things that are in the sets
are called either the sets elements or its members, and the symbol is used
to denote the binary predicate is a member of. Thus, for example, if
a is a member of set X, then this would be denoted a X. There are two
common ways to name or denote a set. The simplest way is to use brace
notation. So, for example, the set {1, 3, 5, 7} is the set containing just the
154 s e t t h e o r y
SPECTRAL DILEMMA
Leon Niemoczynski
Meillassouxs spectral dilemma pits the injustice of terrible deaths
(odious deaths, the deaths of children, violent deaths) against the exist-
ence or non-existence of God (SD, 262). Meillassouxs solution to the
dilemma does not appeal to theism (God exists) nor does it reject God
absolutely in a form of atheism (God does not exist). Meillassoux formu-
lates a third position which he calls divinology a position that features
divine inexistence (lInexistence divine), a virtual God, who is not cul-
pable for the injustice of deaths which have occurred in the past due to the
fact that it did not exist during the time of those deaths, but who may come
to be at some point in the future in order to create a new world where the
dead are resurrected and past injustices absolved (SD, 275). This would
be a world where our rational ends and universal aspirations involving
truth, beauty and justice are finally met (DI, 218).
In his article Spectral Dilemma Meillassoux identifies spectres, that
is, those dead who have not been properly mourned and therefore who
haunt us. Meillassoux is here referring to not only the terrible mass deaths
of the twentieth century Auschwitz and genocide, world wars, atomic
destruction but to the senseless and premature deaths throughout all
of history: children, innocents, and deaths with which we cannot come
to terms. Properly mourning these deaths means forming a bond where
we would be able to live in a non-morbid relation with the departed
(SD, 263). Meillassoux asks whether or not it would be possible on the
traditional alternatives of theism and atheism to face properly the sorts of
deaths that have befallen those who have died without life hearing their
complaints (SD, 262). A spectral dilemma becomes apparent: one is either
to believe in the existence of God or not believe in the existence of God
given the injustice of these terrible deaths throughout all of history. (It is
also possible of course to not believe in an existing God in the sense that
one simply revolts against God, thus choosing not to follow God. But
this is more of a matter of disbanding faith in God rather than outright
denying Gods existence.)
156 s p e c u l a t i o n
SPECULATION
Steven Shaviro
Meillassoux defines his own speculative philosophy in opposition both
to classical metaphysics and to modern critical and relativist thought.
Speculation seeks to discover an absolute through the exercise of
s p e c u l a t i o n 157
pure reason alone. This was the metaphysical project of the great pre-
critical thinkers, from Ren Descartes through Leibniz, who claimed
to deduce the necessity of an absolute outside, one that was not relative
to us (AF,7). But all such metaphysical speculation was put to an end
by Immanuel Kant, who questions the limits of thought and seeks to
draw the boundary beyond which thought is unable to go. Kant turns
thought back upon itself, and denies that thought can ever get beyond
or outside itself. We can only know things in the world, Kant says, in so
far as they exist for us; we cannot know anything about how these things
might exist for themselves, without us and apart from the ways that we
think of them. Any attempt to go beyond the limits of thought is sheer
arbitrary dogmatism: metaphysical statements that spin out the empty
forms of rationality, without any actual content to which these forms
might apply. In this way, Kant de-absolutises thought, and outlaws
speculation.
For Meillassoux, Kant succeeds in refuting every proof that would
presume to demonstrate the absolute necessity of a determinate entity,
whether that entity be God or something else (AF, 32). In this way, Kant
outlaws speculative metaphysics. And Western philosophy since Kant
has largely repeated this dismissal. There is a clear line, for instance,
from Kants rejection of the ontological proof of Gods existence to
Heideggers rejection of all forms of onto-theology. Meillassoux does
not seek to overturn such arguments. Rather, he seeks to open the way to
another form of speculation, one that is not dogmatic or metaphysical: We
must uncover an absolute necessity that does not reinstate any form of
absolutely necessary entity (AF, 34). Indeed, Meillassoux concedes that
all metaphysics is speculative by definition (AF, 34). But he denies
the inverse of this proposition: our problem consists in demonstrating,
conversely, that not all speculation is metaphysical, and not every absolute
is dogmatic (AF, 34).
Meillassouxs speculative project therefore leads him to develop an
idea whose elaboration and defence require a novel kind of argumentation
(AF, 76). It is only in this way that he can posit an absolute without an
absolute entity (AF, 34). Meillassoux finds his absolute in the seemingly
oxymoronic form of a reason emancipated from the principle of reason a
speculative form of the rational that would no longer be a metaphysical reason
(AF, 77). Meillassoux seeks to discover an absolute necessity that does not
posit that anything in particular is necessary; and he finds this precisely
in the claim that everything is necessarily non-necessary, or contingent.
In this way, Meillassoux succeeds in, as it were, squaring the circle; he
achieves an absolutizing thought that would not be absolutist (AF, 34).
He obeys the letter of Kants ban on speculation, while c ircumventing its
158 s p e c u l a t i v e m a t e r i a l i s m
SPECULATIVE MATERIALISM
Ben Woodard
Speculative materialism names the proper response, according to
Meillassoux, to the widespread anti-realism of philosophy following the
progressively tighter correlationism between thinking and being. This
deabsolutisation amounts to the prohibition of thinking the absolute (or
anything for that matter) in a place in which there is no thought (AF, 36).
Furthermore, this deabsolutisation applies not only to the limits of our
knowledge but to the relational model as such (AF, 37). As Meillassoux
argues it is not merely that our knowledges relation to the world is
ontologised but that this relation is crystallised as facticity. Given that
Meillassoux wishes to think an absolute, a world without thought (AF,
28), he constructs speculative materialism to combat the devils of correla-
tionism and other pernicious forms of idealism, by transforming the logic
of strong correlationism from within. Why the conjunction of the terms
speculative and materialism?
For Meillassoux the term speculative names the spirit of the origi-
nal and properly scientific Copernican turn whereby the conservative
structures of thought were challenged at base. Kants absorption of this
lesson, according to Meillassoux, necessitated a reversal of the reversal,
a Ptolemaic counter-revolution in which knowledge is protected
from those claims which would potentially mark its frailty (AF, 119).
Philosophically adapted, speculation is that form of thinking which makes
any claims to an absolute (AF, 34). However, Meillassoux claims that a
particular form of speculation is desirable in order to avoid both dogmatic
and metaphysical speculation. While dogmatic speculation assumes an
absolute entity or set of entities (AF, 78), metaphysical speculation, which
Meillassoux aligns with Kant, asserts that the absolute exists as things-
in-themselves and can be described as forms or necessary properties (AF,
76). In opposition to these forms Meillassoux argues that a properly non-
dogmatic and non-metaphysical form of speculation must assert that the
absolute is the very structure of facticity (that we can purportedly claim
that things are a particularly way through description and not foundation)
(AF, 39). As a further step, Meillassoux then applies speculation to the
structure of facticity itself and arises at factiality, namely that facticity is
not factual (AF, 80).
s p e c u l a t i v e r e a l i s m 159
SPECULATIVE REALISM
Rick Elmore
Speculative Realism (SR) is a broad term encompassing an array of
philosophical positions all of which share a general resistance to what
Quentin Meillassoux calls correlationism, the belief that the human
world correlate forms the central element of philosophical investigation
160 s p e c u l a t i v e r e a l i s m
(Bryant etal. 2011: 3). Ray Brassier coined the term in 2007 as the title of
a workshop held at Goldsmiths College. This workshop brought together
Quentin Meillassoux, Ray Brassier, Ian Hamilton Grant and Graham
Harman, thinkers that have, in many ways, become representative of SR.
In addition, SR is intimately tied to a number of online communities and
open access publishing, which have contributed to the rapid distribution
of SR related works (Bryant et al. 2011: 67). Although SR is not a
homogeneous philosophical school, a brief review of the work of the orig-
inal Goldsmiths attendees gives one a sense of its philosophical terrain.
Meillassoux is often credited with catalysing SR with his notion of cor-
relationism (Harman 2011a: vii). In addition, he is the only thinker from
the original Goldsmiths conference that does not abandon the correlation-
ist circle outright. Rather, Meillassouxs work attempts to radicalise the
correlationist project from within, showing that one can have a rational,
mathematical basis for the existence of things outside of human thought
(see Cartesian in-itself). It is on the basis of this claim that Meillassoux
argues for the necessity of contingency, sketching the contours of a
world in which anything is possible including the resurrection of the dead
and the reign of pure justice (Bryant et al. 2011: 8).
Graham Harmans object oriented ontology is perhaps the best-
known school of thought within the SR universe. In connection with the
work of Levi Bryant, Ian Bogost and Tim Morton, Harman develops a
realism based on the inherent inaccessibility of all objects, suggesting a flat
ontological universe in which objects interact only indirectly by translat-
ing one another (Bryant et al. 2011: 8). Ray Brassiers transcendental
nihilism takes the positive project of the Enlightenment to be the destruc-
tion of meaning (Bryant et al. 2011: 7). For Brassier, the realist assertion
that there is a world independent of the human mind leads to the nihilists
conviction that such a world would be necessarily indifferent to our exist-
ence and oblivious to the values and meanings which we would drape
over it in order to make it more hospitable (Brassier 2007: xi). Hence,
nihilism is a speculative project aimed at undermining all that might make
humans feel at home or important in the universe.
Ian Hamilton Grants work returns to the nature philosophy of
Schelling in order to provide a transcendental and ontological foundation
for science (Bryant et al. 2011: 7). Grant takes seriously the insights of
natural science, particularly physics, as a means to push philosophy to
redefine the transcendental and the conditions of thinking in the wake of
a thoroughgoing naturalism (see Iain Hamilton Grant, http://naught-
thought.wordpress.com, 6 September 2012). Hence, his work sketches
a dark reserve of pure productivity that undergirds and produces the
phenomenal world (Bryant et al. 2011: 7).
s u b j e c t a l i s m 161
SUBJECTALISM
Daniel Sacilotto
For Meillassoux, the term subjectalism designates one of the two basic
kinds of absolutism, and is introduced to clarify the distinctions between
materialism, idealism and correlationism as characterised in After
Finitude. In essence, subjectalist philosophers hold that it is possible
for thought to access the absolute, at the price of identifying this abso-
lute with some dimension of subjective existence itself. According to
Meillassoux, these absolutisms do not dispute the closure of thought
upon itself, but rather go on to identify thought, or an aspect of thought,
as the very absolute that is within our grasp. Rather than seeing the
correlation as the sign of an epistemic impasse, the subjectalist sees the
correlation as an ontological fact. Historically and in spite of substantive
differences in their specific contents, the variety of positions associated
with subjectalism rest on a fundamental agreement that, after Berkeley,
there could be no question of returning to the totally a-subjective reality
of Epicurean materialism (IRR, 3). But, unlike correlationism, which
simply forecloses the possibility of metaphysics in the name of an inves-
tigation of the epistemic, existential, historical or discursive conditions
for thought, the subjectalist wishes to preserve the speculative ambition
of philosophy, by marking subjective mediation as part of reality, that is,
by absolutising thought and so the correlation as such, either in its totality
or partially.
To avoid confusion, however, some terminological remarks are in
order. In After Finitude, Meillassoux had used the term correlationism
more broadly to include both positions that de-absolutise thought through
the correlation, and those that absolutise the correlation itself. Refining
162 s u b j e c t a l i s m
SYMBOL
Fintan Neylan
Rejecting traditional ideas of what philosophy should be, for example,
a handmaiden of the sciences, Meillassoux conceives philosophy as that
through which we can orient ourselves toward the universal. In his view,
the philosopher is tasked with explicating the universal in a system where
it can have coherence in the face of sophistries, religious obscurantism,
and the despair of existing in a cold world.
This task is accomplished by means of the symbol, Meillassouxs name
for that in which the philosopher situates the universal as real. There is,
however, a problem with such orientation: the universal does not imma-
nently exist, so one can either conceive it as part of some transcendent
realm, or deny its existence altogether. As transcendent foundationalism
164 s y m b o l
is ruled out for Meillassoux, it would seem the philosopher must orientate
herself to something which does not exist. Factial ontology provides a
further option: the possible universal. Here the universal can be conceived
as a value which may be realised, thus existing as a real possibility, but one
which is not presently actual. This is known as symbolisation: the act of
representing a universal value as a real possibility in order to give a philo-
sophical account of the world, but without committing to the existence
of the transcendental. For humans, the universal is manifest as justice.
Symbolisation constitutes what Meillassoux calls a rational guarantee of
this universal: despite the fact that justice does not currently exist, it is
guaranteed as a possibility to which the philosopher can rationally assent
and thus orientate herself.
A value may serve as a symbol: a rationally demonstrable possible truth
concerning the immanent world. Because of this possibility for values,
Meillassoux rejects the idea that they are but useful linguistic construc-
tions with no ontological traction. The importance of the discourse of
value is that it expresses the universal. This is distinguished from the
discourse of being, which discloses the impersonal world we find around
us. In symbolisation, the philosopher performs what Meillassoux calls
an immanent inscription of a value in being, an elaboration of the world
in which a universal value (justice) has coherence as a possibility. The
inscribed value, for example the symbol, serves as an ontological link
between the universal and being. Philosophy consists in the discovery of
an ontological link through symbolisation, for it serves as a bond upon
which any theoretical account between being and value is tenable. The
symbol, as a link, is thus the cornerstone of any philosophy.
The history of thought is read as a series of divisions and reunifications
of these two discourses. In these divisions the current system of values
which explicates the universal becomes untenable and is forsaken. These
displacements come in light of a radical shift in thinking, such as the
supplanting of myths in favour of mathematical concepts ability to
explain the world. Though these new conceptual discourses open up an
original way to envision existence, they are devoid of the universal. Born
from this original schism between mathematical concepts and myths in
Ancient Greece, philosophys task is to engage in a reunification of the
two discourses of value and being through a new symbolisation. In the
destruction of a symbol by a new discourse of being, philosophy must
reinscribe the universal back into the world, giving it a renewed rational
coherence without attempting to disavow or reverse the content of the
new discourse.
Meillassoux reads in the history of thought numerous attempts to
reinstall the universal, but only what he calls the factial symbolisation
t i m e 165
can fully guarantee the universal as immanently possible, and bring the
two discourses back into alignment. Gathered under three headings (the
Cosmological, the Naturalist, and the Historical symbol) these types all
aimed to place the universal as justice in immanence, but relied on some
form of metaphysical necessity. In their orientation to the universal, the
admission of metaphysics placed justice beyond the reach of any pos-
sible immanent actualisation, fixing it instead as transcendental. Properly
speaking, they were attempts at symbolisation, as they could not meet the
requirement of pure immanence.
Factial symbolisation is different because justice is conceived in a
non-metaphysical manner. The symbol for Meillassoux is a universal
value (justice) inscribed not as established actuality, but as a real possibil-
ity. Afactial symbol is a link which allows one to fully acknowledge the
current world as a brutal and cold one, while still rationally assenting that
the very same world harbours the possibility of becoming a better one.
T
THING-IN-ITSELF/THINGS-IN-THEMSELVES
TIME
Michael Austin
Meillassoux discusses time in two different ways: in terms of chronol-
ogy (past, present, and future) and in terms of time-itself. The former
appears most prominently when discussing advent, ancestrality or the
futural God. The latter is closely connected to his conceptions of virtual-
ity, contingency, and hyper-chaos. Meillassouxs conception of time
requires a basic retelling of important historical precedents, since his own
work operates within the tradition, while also attempting to invert and
radicalise it. The most significant figure in this respect is Plato, specifically
his distinction between the eternal (the forms outside of time) and the
temporal world of becoming and decay. The distinction between eternal
and temporal finds common cause with the theology of the Middle Ages,
166 t i m e
where the eternal forms are replaced or superseded by God, and the shift-
ing world of becoming becomes the realm of creation. Both Platonic and
Christian conceptions of time are grounded on a beginning, an event of
creation out of the eternal, while Neo-Platonism and its Christian heirs
add to this a return to the eternal through contemplation or death.
Immanuel Kants Transcendental Aesthetic is a watershed for philo-
sophical conceptions of time, transforming the exterior, eschatological
and theological conception of time of the Middle Ages into the Modern
conception of subjective duration and the rhythm of thought. Conceptions
of time are radicalised from here, taken to their critical extremes in Anglo-
American debates concerning the reality of time and their subjective
extremes in Heidegger and, most importantly for Meillassoux, Bergson.
While Kant maintains that space and time are coextensive and equipri-
mordial, both beyond empiricism and the basis for rationality, Bergsons
superior empiricism (through the method of intuition) radicalises Kant
by removing space from the equation, determining it to be a derivative
idea and not, as Kant claimed, immediately given to consciousness. It is
time alone, understood as pure duration, that is the ground of conscious
thought. Meillassouxs basic challenge is to invert or Platonise Bergsons
dure, leading to a time outside of universal laws, to an eternal time of pure
contingency and absolute chaos.
There are then essentially two modes of time at work in Meillassoux,
that of worldly time and that of absolute time. When he speaks for instance
of the arche-fossil or ancestrality, this is intra-worldly time, since it
is still governed by our physics. Underlying this chronological time,
however, is the possibility of another time, or perhaps better put, a time
of other possibilities. Time, thus, is capable of transgressing its own laws;
it is the indeterminate par excellence. Time-itself, in opposition to the flow
of past to present, is the absolute power of contingency, the capacity for
being-otherwise at the heart of Meillassouxs ontology, and the source
of all change. When novelty irrupts within the cosmos, it is an irruption
of time-itself. It is not the case however that time-itself for Meillassoux
is equal to Platonic forms, containing all possibilities and pre-existing
the world. Rather, time is the capacity to bring forth situations that were
precisely not contained in the past. While our perception of time remains
tied to various strata (the emergence of matter, life and thought for
instance), such stratification, when viewed through the rational grasping
of contingency, reveals time as the creator and destroyer of all, a power
only understood when there is precisely no continuity between past and
present. In order for there to be novelty in the advent of thought, there
must be not only the principle of contingency, but an excess already at
work within the universe, or else all would remain static and unchanged.
u n i v e r s a l 167
This power to destroy what once was and to create ex nihilo is time-itself.
Pure time contains nothing, no past and no future. It is neither beholden
to what once was, nor is it determined by a goal. Time is pure chaos and
absolute illegality.
U
UNIVERSAL
Fintan Neylan
In Meillassouxs view, the task of the philosopher is explicate the uni-
versal in a system where it can have coherence in the face of sophistries,
religious obscurantism, and the despair of existing in a cold world. As
committing to the universal is traditionally seen as either admitting a form
of metaphysics, or accepting ourselves as within a subject conditioned
world, the presence of the universal seems to go against Meillassouxs
ontology. However, his conception of the factial offers another option: the
virtual universal. Unlike a metaphysical universal or one bound up with
the transcendence of a subject, through factial ontology the universal can
be conceived as that which may be realised at any moment, but one which
is not presently actual. Given the worlds disenchantment, the philosopher
must accomplish her task by finding the possibility of the universal in a
universe void of it. She discovers this possibility as the symbol and thus
builds a philosophical account of the world around it. Whereas previous
philosophers situated it in transcendence, the factial placement of it in the
virtual allows Meillassouxs philosopher to rationally assent and orientate
herself to the universal, while not committing to its current existence.
In their orientation to it, the universal is manifest to humans as justice.
Meillassoux maintains this has been the case for all of philosophy: no
matter how it is phrased, the explication of the universal throughout
history has always been that of justice. In his system, the realisation of the
universal would thus be the emergence of a just world. This manifestation
of an eternal possibility of universal justice is part of Meillassouxs prior-
itisation of the ethical. Its status as a virtual possibility serves to under-
write just acts in the present world of pain as just, rendering the concept of
ethical action both meaningful and rational. For even if it is not realised,
through the factial humans may orientate themselves to the universal: this
allows them to fully acknowledge the current world as a brutal and cold
168 v e c t o r i a l s u b j e c t
one, while still rationally assenting that the very same world harbours the
possibility of becoming a universally just one.
V
VECTORIAL SUBJECT
Peter Gratton
Meillassoux argues that there has not been just the world as we currently
see it, but previous worlds of matter and organic matter. The current
world of thought is one given over to painful injustices. This leads
Meillassoux to posit the spectral dilemma: if I believe in an existing,
personal God, then I make that God responsible for the evils of the
world, including the deaths of children and massacres of whole peoples.
But if I dont believe in that God, then I affirm a hellish existence in
which those who have died in horrible ways have no chance for redemp-
tion. Given the vicissitudes of hyper-chaos, Meillassoux argues that we
cannot foreclose the coming of a fourth World of justice, one in which
a God comes to be who resurrects the dead and oversees a communist-
like community of equals. The vectorial subject is also the eschatological
subject who sees her way past the spectral dilemma, acknowledging that
while God does not exist now, that does not mean God will not come to
exist. Magnetically attracted by the vector of the emancipation to come,
the vectorial subject works in this world without the despair that weighs
down so many others (IWB, 463). Filled with rational hope for a world
that is not yet real, but foreseeable, the militant universalist, the vecto-
rial subject, is led not by an ideal but by a possible world of equality to
come (IWB, 465).
The vectorial subject, however, faces a second challenge more difficult
than the spectral dilemma, namely a true nihilism in which she does not
wish the immortality of the world to come, since it could be unending
creative ineptitude or dissolving loves, and so on. The vectorial subject
would also face the end of the meaning of her existence: she comes forward
in the name of equality and emancipation to come, but if it arrives, then
her meaning as a subject dissolves. Transcending this nihilism means
thus seeing that we must at some point transcend politics, the brutal and
costly ways in which the work for equality occurs. Having faced these two
tests, the vectorial subject moves past potential hatred for existence, as
v e r n e s , j e a n - r e n 169
in the spectral dilemma, and a hate for her fellow beings, as in the test of
nihilism.
VERNES, JEAN-REN
Peter Gratton
Vernes Critique of Aleatory Reason (1982) provides a key resource for
Meillassouxs argument against the frequentialist implication. The fre-
quentialist implication goes as follows: if the laws of nature could change
without reason, since they are not necessary given hyper-chaos, they
would do so frequently. But since the laws do not evidently do so the
world appears stable after all the laws cannot change for no reason
they are necessary (AF, 94). Vernes text is important for Meillassoux
as he identifies the probabilistic reasoning behind the claim, since the
idea is that it would be extremely improbable without necessary laws that
we would have stability in the universe. But, as Meillassoux asks, what
warrants the claim that the constancy of experience opens onto genuine
necessity, whereas the a priori does not open onto veritable contingency?
(AF, 95). Meillassoux uses the example of a set of dice, where we take it
that a priori one side of the dice are to come up more than any other. From
this we calculate the probability that, say, snake eyes (two ones) can occur
one out of thirty-six throws, and if you were getting snake eyes several
times in a row, you are being had by a set of loaded dice.
Now, Vernes takes this to a cosmic level and millions of chances, all of
which we assume are equal, concerning the contingencies of the universe,
where we remain getting the same outcome (a stable world). We assume,
then, that we have a loaded universe, that is, a set of laws that cause it
necessarily to be stable. Meillassoux believes David Hume and Immanuel
Kant take it for granted that the necessity of the laws is self-evident, just
like someone who thinks they are more than unlucky on a bad night at
the casino and blames the craps dealer. But Hume and Kant have merely
extended this probabilistic thinking to the universe as a whole, or better,
construct this universe as one among a total set of conceivable universes,
and then think the changes of this stable universe against that universe of
all universes and consider it highly improbable that this universe would be
a stable one: the nub of the argument consists in registering the immense
numerical gap between those possibilities that are conceivable and those
that are actually experienced (AF, 97). Yet, the whole consideration of
chance requires stable physical laws: the dice remaining the same during
the throw and so on.
170 v i r t u a l , t h e
VIRTUAL, THE
Michael Austin
In order to understand Meillassouxs use of the term the virtual the
concept must be understood in the context of twentieth-century French
thought as employed by Bergson, and the term must be differentiated
from both the actual and the potential. First and foremost, the virtual is
not opposed to the real, as in the phrase virtual reality, but to the actual.
The virtual and the actual are logically and necessarily opposed, while also
being necessarily connected and coming into being simultaneously. The
virtual is as real as the actual and grants us a glimpse of the possibilities
of actualisation. The prototypical case of virtuality for Bergson is that of
memory, which is real but not actual, yet affects us as if it were actual.
Memory is a capacity of matter for Bergson, the carrying forward of the
past into the present, a display of the fluidity of time.
While it seems in some cases that Bergson will speak of the virtual as
something of a reservoir of potentiality from which the actual emerges
and argue that the virtual and actual are synonyms for process and
product, nevertheless the virtual does not pre-exist the actual. Nor
should we believe that the virtual is the target of true ontology, while the
actual is determined to be illusory or somehow false once its conditional-
ity is grasped. The virtual is an emergent product of the actual, granting
the observer insight into the power and possibilities of becoming. For
Meillassoux, the virtual maintains this capacity for knowledge, as the
epistemological arm of After Finitudes ontology of hyper-chaos, and
LInexistence divines advent. While potentiality defines the realm of
possibilities concerning intra-worldly affairs, that is to say, possibilities
v i t a l i s m 171
under a given set of laws, the virtual is the realm in which all laws or
sets of laws are possible. For example, while certain actions are possible
given the law of gravity, Meillassoux maintains that it is possible for new
laws to take its place, that is, for a new World to come into being. The
example given by Meillassoux in Potentiality and Virtuality is helpful
here: while the roll of a die presents us with six intra-worldly possibili-
ties, that is to say, given the six-sided nature of a standard die all sides
are equally probable, the virtual nature of the die is infinite; the die could
burst into flames, melt on impact, or present us with A Tale of Two Cities;
while none of these results are as probable as the numeric sides, all are
equally possible given the contingent nature of reality. The virtual is the
index of the possible, or to state it even stronger, the virtual is the infi-
nite set of all possibilities. Virtuality is the possibility for total universal
ungrounding, the power and potentiality for creation and annihilation at
the heart of time itself.
VITALISM
Rodrigo Nunes
For Meillassoux, only the materialist absolutizes the pure non-subjective
the pure and simple death, with neither consciousness nor life, without
any subjectivity whatsoever, that is represented by the state of inorganic
matter that is to say, matter anterior to and independent of every subject
and all life (IRR, 6, his emphasis). It follows that vitalism, as he under-
stands it, is inherently anti-materialistic: it absolutises the correlation
through the hypostasis of some vital term (Nature, Will, Memory, Habit,
Life), thus ascribing human and/or organic traits to the inorganic/
non-human. Ironically, this is often done in the name of de-centring the
human, which makes vitalism into a humanism-in-denial (IRR, 5).
Vitalism falls under the general heading of subjectalism, meaning
all those positions that absolutise the correlation. While correlationism
proper absolutises facticity, subjectalism may select from among various
forms of subjectivity, but it is invariably characterized by the fact that
it hypostatizes some mental, sentient, or vital term (AF, 37). The term
therefore encompasses both the absolutisation of the subject that After
Finitude also calls speculative idealism (Fichte, Hegel) and vitalism; and
even in those cases where the vitalist hypostatization of the correlation
(as in Nietzsche or Deleuze) is explicitly identified with a critique of the
subject or of metaphysics, it is still equivalent to speculative ideal-
ism in understanding that nothing can be unless it is in some form of
172 v i t a l i s m
W
WORLD
Peter Gratton
For Meillassoux the World (Monde) (with a capital letter) is a given uni-
verse of particular laws, which he also calls orders (ordres). These Worlds
were created ex nihilo. The utter contingency of hyper-chaos means the
appearance of these Worlds can occur without reason. That is, each World
comes about as an effect unexplainable from a given previous World.
Meillassoux argues that there have been at least three different Worlds:
So far there seem to have been three [Worlds] of irreducible facts: matter (reduc-
ible to what can be theorized in physico-mathematical terms), life (understood
more specifically as a set of terms, that is, affections, sensations, qualitative per-
ceptions, etc., which cannot be reduced to material processes), and finally thought
(understood as a capacity to arrive at the intelligible contents bearers of eternity,
and which as such is not reducible to any other terms). (IWB, 461)
Laws have no reason to be constant, and nothing entails that they will not contain
new constants in the future. Such cases of advent [surgissement] can be divided
into three orders [that is, Worlds] that mark the essential ruptures of becoming:
174 world
matter, life, and thought. Each of these three appears [my emphasis] as a Universe
that cannot be qualitatively reduced to anything [my emphasis] that preceded it.
(DI2, 284; DI, 187)
Badiou, Alain (2007), Being and Event, trans. Oliver Feltham, London:
Continuum.
Brassier, Ray (2007), Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction,
London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Brassier, Ray (2008) The View from Nowhere, Identities: Journal for
Politics, Gender, and Culture, 8:2, pp. 723.
Brassier, Ray (2011), Concepts and Objects, in The Speculative Turn,
ed. Levi Bryant, Nick Snricek, and Graham Harman, Melbourne:
re.press.
Bryant, Levi R. (2010), Lexicon of Onticology, Larval Subjects (blog),
<http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2010/05/22/a-lexicon-of-
onticology> (accessed 1 September 2013).
Fichte,J.G. (1982), The Science of Knowledge, ed. Peter Heath and John
Lachs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Grant, Iain Hamilton (2006), Philosophies of Nature after Schelling,
London: Continuum.
Hallett, Michael (1986), Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size,
Oxford: Clarendon.
Harman, Graham (2010), Toward Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures,
Winchester: Zero Books.
Harman, Graham (2011), The Quadruple Object, Winchester: Zero Books.
Heidegger, Martin (1962), Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and
Edward Robinson, New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, Martin (1969), Identity and Difference, trans. Joan Stambaugh,
New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, Martin (1973), The End of Philosophy, trans. Joan Stambaugh,
New York: Harper & Row.
Heidegger, Martin (1982), Nietzsche IV: Nihilism, ed. David F. Krell,
trans. Frank A. Capuzzi, New York: Harper & Row.
Husserl, Edmund (1965), Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy, New
York: Harper.
Husserl, Edmund (1981), Husserl: Shorter Works, Notre Dame: University
of Notre Dame Press.
176 bibliography
SECONDARY LITERATURE
Ayache, Elie (2010), The Blank Swan: The End of Probability, United
Kingdom: Wiley.
Brassier, Ray (2007), The Enigma of Realism: On Quentin Meillassouxs
After Finitude, in Robin Mackay (ed.), Collapse Volume II: Speculative
Realism, Oxford: Urbanomic, pp. 5581.
Brown, Nathan (2011), The Speculative and the Specific, in Bryant et al.
(eds), The Speculative Turn, pp. 14263.
Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman (2011) (eds), The
Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism, Melbourne:
re.press.
Burns, Michael ONeill (2010), The Hope of Speculative Materialism,
in Anthony Paul Smith and Daniel Whistler (eds), After the Postsecular
b i b l i o g r a p h y 177
to 2011. The product of that research is his The Dark Ground of Spirit:
Schelling and the Unconscious (2012). He is currently working on a book on
Western spirituality and a major study of the contemporary relevance of
Schellings Philosophy of Revelation.
and Event: A Readers Guide (2009) and Derrida, Badiou and the Formal
Imperative (2012). His most recent publications are Philosophy Outside-In:
A Critique of Academic Reason (2013) and The Cardinals Dog (2013), a
collection of verse-essays on philosophical, musical and literary themes.
Devin Zane Shaw teaches in both the Department of Philosophy and the
Department of Visual Arts at the University of Ottawa. He is currently
writing a book on Jacques Rancire and philosophy, which is a loose sequel
to his Freedom and Nature in Schellings Philosophy of Art (2012).
Ben Woodard is a PhD student at the Centre for Theory and Criticism
at the University of Western Ontario. He is currently writing his disserta-
tion on the connection between speculative physics and the intuition of
space in the work of F.W.J von Schelling. He has published two short
monographs, Slime Dynamics: Generation, Mutation, and the Creep of Life
(2012) and On an Ungrounded Earth: Towards a New Geophilosophy (2013).