Three Cultural Boundaries of Science, Institutions, and Public Policy: A Theory of Co-Production
Three Cultural Boundaries of Science, Institutions, and Public Policy: A Theory of Co-Production
Three Cultural Boundaries of Science, Institutions, and Public Policy: A Theory of Co-Production
A Theory of Co-production
Brendon Swedlow
Paper prepared for presentation at the American Political Science Association annual
A Theory of Co-production
Abstract
the ways in which the boundaries among science, institutions, and public policy are
culture, Gieryn is not able to identify different kinds of cultural boundaries of science nor
can he explain why these boundaries are constructed when and where they are. This
paper uses Sheila Jasanoffs concept of co-production and Mary Douglass cultural
conditions for the co-production of science, institutions, and public policy and the co-
Douglass cultural theory as a theory involving three critical social and institutional
personal space of individuals this paper shows how members of political subcultures
use pollution and purity claims to align themselves and the domain of science with
scientists whose constructs of nature are functional for their preferred social and
institutional relations, while excluding scientists from subcultures and from the domain of
science whose constructs are not functional for those relations. The plausibility of this
theory is illustrated with examples from the cultural co-production of the boundaries of
science surrounding forest and wildlife science and management in the Pacific
Northwest.
2
Introduction
examples of the ways in which the boundaries among science, institutions, and public
policy are culturally constructed. But, because he relies on the same thickly described
atheoretical account of culture as do most others studying science (see, e.g., Cetina, 1994,
1999; Jasanoff, 2004, 2005), Gieryn does not provide a theory of how or why these
boundaries are constructed when and where they are. This paper uses Sheila Jasanoffs
(2004) concept of co-production and Mary Douglass cultural theory (as further
developed in Thompson, Ellis, and Wildavsky 1990; and Schwarz and Thompson 1990)
to identify four recurring states of knowledge, specifying political cultural conditions for
the co-production of science, institutions, and public policy and the co-production of
scientific, cultural, institutional, and policy change (Swedlow 2012). Then, re-casting
Douglass cultural theory as a theory involving three critical social and institutional
personal space of individuals to predict how and why scientists and non-scientists use
themselves and the domain of authoritative science with scientists whose constructs of
nature and public policy are functional for their preferred social and institutional
relations, while excluding scientists from subcultures and from the domain of
authoritative science whose constructs and policies are not functional for these relations.
The plausibility of this theory is illustrated with examples from the cultural co-production
of the boundaries of science surrounding forest and wildlife science and management in
3
Renewed efforts to conceptualize the relationship between science and society
(Cozzens and Gieryn 1990; Shapin 1992) and science and politics have attained their
most developed and fertile expression in States of Knowledge (2004), edited by Sheila
Jasanoff. She and her contributors argue that science and social and political orderings
co-produce each other. That is, science, society, culture, and politics constitute and
(Jasanoff and Wynne 1998; Miller and Edwards 2001; Reardon 2001; Jasanoff, 2004;
Martello 2004; Tuinstra, Hordijk, and Kroeze 2006; Tuinstra 2008; and Kemp and
Rotmans 2009) show its promise, they also show its limitations. Namely, as Jasanoff and
This article argues that the cultural theory developed by Mary Douglas and others
(Douglas and Wildavsky 1983; Schwarz and Thompson 1990; Thompson, Ellis, and
Wildavsky 1990) may help science studies scholars develop a theory of the co-production
of science and social order, a possibility that Jasanoff appears to anticipate (Jasanoff and
Wynne 1998). Douglass cultural theory derives four political cultural types from two
dimensions of social relations and specifies some of the political values and beliefs about
human and physical nature that may be associated with particular patterns of social
relations or social order. In cultural theory, these four packages of values, beliefs, and
cultures. Since scientists are centrally involved in constructing beliefs about the physical
environment in modern societies, and cultural theory claims that these beliefs are co-
produced with functionally related political values, beliefs about human nature, and
4
patterns of social relations (which scientists often also contribute to constructing, as
Jasanoff and her colleagues show), Douglass cultural theory would appear to get a
Moreover, Douglass cultural theory is not just a theory of how patterns of social
order in political cultures are constructed, but, as developed by others, is a theory of how
change in social orders occurs when beliefs about human and physical nature that are
beliefs. Thus, Douglass cultural theory potentially offers a dynamic theory of how the
In cultural theory, culture and institutions are not seen as competing concepts or
mutually exclusive explanations (Chai 1997; Grendstad and Selle 1995; Lockhart 1999).
Rather, institutions are seen as manifestations of social and political relations or orders,
which are one aspect of political culture. The other aspect is cultural bias, or political
values and beliefs about human nature, the environment, and economics, among other
things. Cultural bias is similar to ideology in some respects but not in others (Gastil et al.
2011; Michaud, Carlisle, and Smith 2009; Song et al. 2011; Swedlow 2002b, 2008;
Swedlow and Wyckoff 2009). Thus, cultural theorists do not distinguish culture from
institutions but rather distinguish cultural bias from institutions, while also hypothesizing
that cultural bias and institutions come in distinct packages of values, beliefs, and
types of institutions that can exist as well as some conditions that can lead to institutional
5
and fatalistic institutions. Hierarchical and egalitarian institutions have strong external
group boundaries, but hierarchical collectives are also strongly demarcated internally,
usually from top to bottom, whereas egalitarian institutions typically strive to avoid
institutions, such as free markets and protections of civil liberties, however, emphasize
freedom of choice and their property and bodily integrity. Individuals in fatalistic
institutions can defend neither collective boundaries nor personal ones; their choices are
made by others and their lives are subject to forces beyond their control.
Cultural theory also specifies the kinds of policy processes that different political
actors consider to be most legitimate and the political values and beliefs that these actors
seek to transform into public policy. In other words, cultural theory specifies the contents
of four means-ends pairings that should be at the heart of political conflict and coalition
forest and wildlife science and management by scientists, environmentalists, and judges
concerned about spotted owls and their associated old growth forest ecosystems in the
by Jasanoff and her colleagues and presents Douglass cultural theory, with a particular
emphasis on the constructs of nature and policy associated with the four cultures. The
6
over land and wildlife management in the Pacific Northwest championed cultural
constructs and policies. The paper next presents the cultural theory of change, wherein
new scientific claims about nature become catalysts for cultural and policy change. The
plausibility of this theory of change is illustrated by analyzing the role forest and owl
scientists, environmental lawyers, and Ninth Circuit federal judges played in dramatically
altering land and wildlife management policy while co-producing new identities,
Finally, the paper suggests how cultural theory can be re-cast as a theory of the co-
examples of how these claims operated in this case. The conclusion outlines ways further
to test and develop Douglass cultural theory as a theory specifying the political cultural
conditions for the co-production of three cultural boundaries of science, institutions, and
public policy.
this study, most of whom were scientists, as well as on archival research and secondary
sources. Unless otherwise indicated, all reports on or quotes from research subjects are
because they gave permission to use their names or because quotes come from publicly
available sources. Otherwise, respondents were promised confidentiality, and so are not
identified by name.
7
Scientists, Judges, and Spotted Owls: Policymakers in the Pacific Northwest
Federal land management agencies in the Pacific Northwest that until the late
1980s were engaged primarily in timber production are now overwhelmingly concerned
with ecosystem management. The US Forest Service, which manages most of the federal
lands in the region, had been an exemplary hierarchically organized federal agency since
its founding in the early 1900s, so much so that in World War II it was held up to the US
to produce a sustained yield of timber, managing forests much as one would manage any
other crop. The Service called for the harvest of old-growth forests not set aside as
decadent, diseased biological deserts with faster growing, healthier, younger stands that
would provide more and better quality lumber (Yaffee 1994, 3-8, 256-82).
challenged the Forest Services view that old-growth forests were lifeless cellulose
Forest in Oregon found that these older forests were home to a wide variety of
interdependent life forms. Environmental groups were excited by this research because it
gave them a further reason to value and preserve older forests. Research specifically on
the relationship between the Northern Spotted Owl and old-growth forests became a
particular focus of these groups because threatened species were protected by various
In other words, research on old growth forest ecosystems and specifically on the
relationship between spotted owls and old-growth constructed nature in ways that were
8
functional for egalitarian environmental groups. The development of this research and
environmental groups interest in this research thus are one significant area where
political cultural conditions were ripe for the co-production of three cultural boundaries
of science, institutions, and public policy (see, generally, Yaffee 1994; Chase 1995; and
Luoma 1999).
Accordingly, in 1987, as will also be discussed in this paper, a public interest law
firm, the Sierra Club Legal Defense Fund (SCLDF), began suing the federal land and
wildlife management agencies on behalf of the Northern Spotted Owl. The SCLDF
argued and federal judges agreed that federal land and wildlife managers were not doing
enough to protect the owl, violating several environmental laws. One federal judge went
further than this, however, reading these laws to require management of biological
further timber sales pending the protection of ecosystems, frequently relying on the
testimony and affidavits of federal and university scientists, and adopting their egalitarian
constructs of nature, while largely ignoring scientists affiliated with the timber industry
Shortly after his election in 1992, President Bill Clinton appointed a scientific
advisory committee of nearly 700 scientists and other experts to advise him on how to
respond to court orders to manage ecosystems. Scientists affiliated with the timber
industry were largely excluded from this effort. In 1993, on the advice of his Forest
than 24 million acres of federal lands in Washington, Oregon, and Northern California
under ecosystem management, seeking to protect old growth forests and over 1000
9
species associated with them. This policy shift also reduced federal timber sales by more
than 75 percent, adversely affected about 300 rural communities, and effectively
institutionalized an egalitarian construct of nature for an area nearly six times the size of
The spotted owl cases thus resulted in a transformation of federal land and
federal timber sales reflected the egalitarian view of nature as fragile, while court orders
can be understood as attempts to institutionalize the policies and social and political
The Concept of Culture, the Social Study of Science, and the Need for Theory
ethnographic study of scientists working in their laboratories that culture has shown its
laboratory studies are studies of unfinished knowledge, "knowledge that is yet in the
process of being constituted" by scientists, "one of the most powerful and esoteric tribes
in the modern world (1994, 141). Cultural constructions of nature, in these studies, are
the result of local scientific practices, centered in the laboratory. Indeed, Cetina titled her
review of this research "Laboratory Studies: The Cultural Approach to the Study of
Science," implying that laboratory studies were exhaustive of cultural approaches (Ibid,
10
Were this so, it would be unfortunate, because laboratory studies would then share
ethnographic studies of other tribes, laboratory studies of scientists are mostly (thickly)
suggests that laboratory studies need to be done on a comparative basis, for the few
comparative studies that exist indicate that scientific constructions take place "within
epistemic (and national) cultures (Ibid, 158). Concepts developed for analysis of
patterns and dynamics that are on display in expert practice and that vary in different
settings of expertise (Cetina 1999, 8) and to the symbols and meaning associated with
these varying patterns and dynamics of practice (10; citing Geertz 1973, 89). In her
Cetina finds that high energy physics labs have communitarian patterns, dynamics, and
Members of high energy physics labs cooperate with each other and other labs to
advance their research, while members of microbiology labs do not. High energy physics
labs work through collective frameworks built on communitarian principles rather than
the logic of exchange (236). [E]verything everybody does is shared participants use
each others results continually, and they combine them in common products and goals
(234). In the molecular biology laboratories studied, the opposite scenario dominated
daily work. Researchers, structurally set up in individuated units, could survive, everyone
11
thought, only as individuated units (236). But the things that unite individual
unitstend also to be the things that divide that create tension, conflicts, resistance,
laboratories, but arguably have their own epistemic cultures that, in Peter M. Haass
and-effect relationships, truth tests to assess them, and shares common values. As
problems in the same manner and process information similarly. They also share a
be addressed, and a common network in which findings are exchanged and shared
Haas does not try to specify types of epistemic communities or types of epistemic
2.1).
Sociologist Andrew Jamison is among those who seek refuge from the
12
interests, and vice versa, via institutions (Brickman, Jasanoff, Iglen 1985).1 Yet the
are not entirely solved by making national biases, interests, and institutions the
nations. While having gained points of comparison, we are still left with American
science vs. British science vs. French science vs. German science vs. Swedish science vs.
Danish science vs. Japanese science. One has to wonder if this is this any better than
[update with material from Jasanoff, Designs on Nature 2005, 17-29, which
describes problems with national styles of regulation approaches and the need to re-
The challenge for those suffering from what Jamison calls his "comparative
general, abstract terms, so that the terms will have equal purchase on disparate social
organizations. In other words, the challenge is to find concepts that travel well, while
avoiding excessive conceptual stretching (Collier and Mahon 1993; Sartori 1970, 1983).
society) need to direct their attention not to laboratories or nations or even science itself,
but to the types of social organization of which laboratories, nations, and science are
comparing the activities of scientific tribes (and their interaction with other societal
13
Gieryns Cultural Boundaries of Science
enduring, essential characteristics, but that what science is at any given time and place
varies with culture. In other words, the boundaries that define the domain of science are
including cultural practices like politics, religion, and sports at that time and place.
What science is and is not, then, is nothing more nor less than what cultural cartographers
say it is and enact it to be and others accept it to be or cannot resist it being in a given
(1996), Gieryn provides a contemporary example of how cultural cartography works that
also provides a nice set-up for the case-study of wildlife and forest management that
existence will either have their claims dismissed as wails from a politicized and
misdirected Cassandra or see them translated from fact into environmental policy
depending upon where they and their claims are positioned in the culturescape
movement organizers, and citizens. Evidence, models, and theories are not
sufficient for these biologists to move policy and save the earth: a cartographic
case for the credibility and reliability of these claims must also be put forth to
persuade audiences that our nature (but not theirs) is the way it is really
14
Losers see their claims moved out from fact to illusion, lie, ulterior motive, or
faith while they (and their methods, practices, organizations, and institutions) get
for science and its genuinely licensed practitioners (Gieryn, 1999, 13-14).3
These cultural maps [demarcating science from pseudo- and non-science] are
contextually tailored selections from a long menu [of possible attributes of science],
Gieryn observes, where context is defined by the players and stakeholders, their goals
and interests, and the arena in which they operate (21). With respect to the players and
stakeholders, Gieryn notes that The skin and innards of science will vary depending on
who draws the map and against whom, and for whom (21). Meanwhile, the borders
and territories of science will be drawn to pursue immediate goals and interests of
cultural cartographers, and to appeal to the goals and interests of audiences and
stakeholders (23). Finally, Gieryn notes that Cultural cartography takes place in a
in part because people have to figure out not only which science and scientists to trust but
do so by deciding which cultural cartographers to trust and, Gieryn implies, there are no
(17-18). The problem is not that there is that there is no real science behind the
cartographic representations, but that there are too many real sciences Selections
from this [multiplicity of] real science must be made by cultural cartographers, and they
are strategically (19). In the end, consequently, One must look to the contingencies of
15
each local and episodic contest for credibility in order to find out what science becomes
On one view, then, Gieryn does not attempt to provide a typology, much less a
theory, of the cultural contexts of cultural cartography of science, nor of the kinds of
players and stakeholders, goals and interests, or arenas in which they operate.4 To the
contrary, he repeatedly implies that creating such a theory is impossible. At the same
time, however, Gieryn appears to embrace the possibility of theorizing about the cultural
cartography of science. First off, it bears noting that in implying that it is impossible to
theorize about the cultural cartography of science Gieryn is offering a rather robust
generalization and an implicit theory of how cultural cartography occurs. His theory
appears to be that cultural cartography is a fluid, episodic, localized, and highly culturally
considerably beyond his data. The five episodes taken together leave yawning gaps in
sociological understanding of the shifting cultural spaces for science My tiny sample is
further suggests that his conclusions are more in the nature of theories or hypotheses than
empirically validated generalizations. And, importantly for this study, he notes that
None of these cases takes place in an arena where boundary-work involving science has
acknowledges that compared to others his contribution (Gieryn and Figert 1990) yield[s]
most willingly to the idiographic impulse (Cozzens and Gieryn 1990, 8), but he and his
16
Sociologistshave never given up their search for the general laws of social life.
or less necessary kind that hold for all instances of a designated set are the
Gieryn argues that sociologists of science should move away from the study of laboratory
cultures to investigate the "cultural maps" used by non-scientists to construe the activities
of scientists, and, very importantly for this study, he thinks Mary Douglass cultural
If science studies has now convinced everybody that scientific facts are only
contingently credible and claims about nature are only as good as their local
of the cultural categories that people in society use to interpret and evaluate those
As Gieryn acknowledges, his search for "interpretive cultural categories" that allow
"multiple and variable accountings" of scientific "facts and claims," and his desire to
discover the relationship between these "cultural maps" and the constitution of authority,
proposition that the ways in which we know and represent the world (both nature and
society) are inseparable from the ways we choose to live in it. Accordingly, in States of
Knowledge: The Co-production of Science and Social Order (2004), she argues that we
17
gain explanatory power by thinking of natural and social orders as being produced
analytical lens is its descriptive richness, which derives from providing fuller, deeper
accounts of how particular configurations of science and social and political order are
braided together (2004, 42, 276). Jasanoff and many of her contributors situate the
concept of co-production as a stepping stone toward theory development and the ability
to predict (3). While [i]ts aim is not to provide deterministic causal explanations of the
ways in which science and technology influence society, or vice-versa (38), the concept
may help identify deep cultural regularities (42, 280) that allow such explanations and
predictions.
This paper argues that Douglass cultural theory, as further developed by others,
is a good candidate for characterizing deep cultural regularities that may help explain and
predict co-production. Douglass four political cultural ideal types, also called ways of
life (Thompson, Ellis, and Wildavsky 1990), can help specify four recurring ways in
which we know and represent the world, both natural and social, which are inseparable
from, because functionally related to, four possible ways we [can] choose to live in it
(Jasanoff 2004, 2). Notably, the social relations of the four ways of life specified by
18
constituting authority, and exercising power core concepts and concerns among those
political relations will be accompanied by beliefs and values, including beliefs about
human and physical nature, that allow people to justify these relationships to each other.
In other words, different kinds of social and political relations, beliefs, and values are
these different kinds of relations, beliefs, and values cannot be mixed and matched. To
live one way and think another is unsustainable, a pathway for cultural change. Changes
in beliefs and values are expected to lead to changes in relations, and visa versa. Thus,
relations constrain beliefs and values, and beliefs and values constrain relations.
Compatible co-productions of relations, beliefs, and values are what Douglas and others
call cultures, and beliefs and values taken together are what they call cultural biases
or ideologies (Thompson, Ellis, and Wildavsky1990; Swedlow 2001, 2002b, 2008, 2009).
attempt to characterize these cultural packages in a way that is parsimonious and still
scientists, they think that much of the variation in social and political relations is captured
by the extent of individual autonomy and collectivism in those relations. 6 But unlike
other social scientists, they think that these conditions are independent of each other
rather than inversely related. Instead of lying on opposite ends of the same continuum,
individual autonomy and collectivism vary separately on their own dimensions. More of
19
one does not necessarily mean less of the other. These dimensions and the resulting
This conceptual shift allows analysts to account for four rather than two patterns
of social and political relations. People in individualistic and fatalistic relations are not
part of a collective undertaking, but individualists retain their autonomy, while fatalists
collective undertaking, but egalitarians retain much more of their autonomy than
hierarchs.
Hierarchical relations are highly structured, with everyone and everything having
his, her, and its place, represented by an organizational pyramid in Figure 1. In this
cultural environment, legitimate decisions are made by persons with the proper authority
to make particular types of decisions. In other words, the decision rule is that the proper
authority decides.7 Individualistic relations, by contrast, are highly fluid, and subject to
relations, meanwhile, are tenuous and unreliable, driven by the "whim and caprice" of
people in egalitarian relations retain their autonomy by giving everyone an equal voice in
(and thus the power to veto) collective decisions. Here,we decide. The egalitarian
desire to have it all is represented here by something that looks like a chocolate chip
cookie in Figure 1.
Figure 1
[about here]
20
justified by and in turn justify (and make plausible) particular kinds of beliefs and values.
Perhaps not surprisingly, cultural theorists hypothesize that individualists value freedom,
egalitarians value equality, hierarchs value order, and fatalists value (good) luck (see
The Cultural Construction of Nature and Public Policy in Cultural Theory and the
Pacific Northwest
cultural constructs of nature in Douglass theory (Schwarz and Thompson 1990, 8-13;
Thompson, Ellis, and Wildavksy 1990, 26-33; as discussed in Jasanoff and Wynne 1998).
Adapted from Thompsons work, the constructs of nature that are functional for the
different patterns of social relations are mapped onto the dimensions of social relations in
The egalitarian construct of nature is most nearly the opposite of this: the ball is
The hierarchical construct of nature combines these two constructs: the ball is in a
shallow pocket; small disturbances will not dislodge it, but large ones will; nature
ephemeral, or unpredictable. 9
In the fatalistic construction of nature, the ball is on a flat surface; it can roll any
21
sometimes benign, resilient, or even robust or cornucopian, sometimes fragile or
The scientific debate regarding owls and ecosystems in the Pacific Northwest can
sympathizers on the one hand and federal and industry scientists on the other over how
shallow the pocket was, or whether the ball was in a pocket at all. However, federal
scientists came fairly close to arguing that ecosystems were unpredictable being not
only more complex than we think, but more complex than we can think -- while
scientists working for industry argued for the resiliency and adaptability of the owl and
academic sympathizers persuaded federal judges that the ball was teetering on the lip of
the pocket or, alternatively, about to fall off its pinnacle perch (Sher 1993; Swedlow
Figure 2
[about here]
policies that will be pursued toward the environment. Individualists will take a very
hands-on, transformative approach, which is what the timber industry advocated: Tell us
what owl habitat looks like and well grow it. They also suggested constructing nest
boxes and breeding owls in captivity and trucking them between habitat areas rather than
retaining old trees with nesting cavities and providing forested migratory routes.
environmentalists wanted when they advocated the complete halt of timber harvests that
22
was mostly achieved. Hierarchs will be activist, but only to a point that is sustainable,
which was the approach taken historically by the Forest Service with respect to timber
harvesting and by Forest Service ecologist Jerry Franklin and his New Forestry ideas
about selective harvesting and leaving biological legacies like decadent and fallen trees
in place. Fatalists will remain passive in the face of natures fickle moods, a position that
(in addition to the egalitarian tread lightly approach) significantly influenced the
approach taken by federal research biologist Jack Ward Thomas and the Forest
Chase 1995; Swedlow 2002a, 2003, 2007, 2009; see also Coyle 1994; Ellis and
justify particular patterns of social relations, how does change ever occur?, ask
Thompson, Richard Ellis, and Aaron Wildavsky in their seminal refinement of Douglass
theory (1990, 69). Much the same way, they answer, as scientific theories lose and
and surprises occur because nature, for all its accommodating ways, does not meekly
accept every cultural construction we try to impose on it, and, in fighting back, it
In other words, cultural theorists locate a catalyst for scientific, cultural, and
policy change in surprises generated by encounters with nature in which nature displays
23
generated expectations. Stipulating the world is one way and finding out that it actually
appears to be another leads to a variety of predictable consequences, and can lead to such
changes. 11 This is one reason constructs of nature can become so heavily contested: they
are a major way that cultures justify and stabilize themselves. Successfully casting doubt
on a constructs correspondence to reality is to unmoor social and political life from its
that scientific, cultural, and policy change is hypothesized to occur (see also Wildavsky
The Cultural and Scientific Construction of Nature and Forest Policy in the Pacific
Northwest
Since European settlement in the 1840s, the history of the cultural construction of
nature and forest policy in the Pacific Northwest can be recounted as individualistic
constructs being displaced by hierarchical constructs, which in turn have given way to
egalitarian ones. Some of these constructs were co-produced with science, while others
were co-produced with religious or philosophical teachings. This history will be briefly
sketched here to show that cultural constructions of nature in the Pacific Northwest have
taken the forms and are associated with the values and/or social relations hypothesized by
cultural theory. The more recent history will then be analyzed in greater detail,
demonstrating that changes in science, policy, and social order have occurred in the
the frontier with hierarchical religious notions of doing the Lords work by clearing
forests for farming (Nash 1984: 103). The Forest Service sought to sustain an internal
24
frontier on its lands in perpetuity as the American frontier closed around 1890 by using
scientific management to set limits on harvests (Yaffee 1994, 3-8, 256-82). This
founder and first chief of the Forest Service, triumphed (for the next 70-80 years) over a
Wilderness Areas, spearheaded by naturalist and closet radical egalitarian John Muir,
founder of the Sierra Club (Nash 1984, 107-10, 125-26; 1989, 41; Coyle 1994). Publicly,
Muir argued that preserving forests was important primarily for people, for rest and
recuperation, for aesthetic satisfaction, for spiritual nourishment, and for the protection of
mountain watersheds (Nash 1984, 41). Privately, he saw national parks as places where
snakes, redwood trees, beavers, and rocks could exercise their natural rights to life and
liberty (Ibid).
Meanwhile, the Save the Redwoods League, founded in 1920, was influenced by
victors in the struggle for survival, a master race of trees, counterparts of League
These trees also proved that free struggle in evolution or, in social terms,
League member] know this; they do not ask for equality any more than those
This hierarchical view of the redwoods also drew on an applied version of evolutionary
biology called eugenics, which sought to improve humanity through selective breeding.
25
At least 11 of the 26 founding members of the League subscribed to eugenics (43).
construct of nature. Goethe wanted the laws of eugenics taught to the general public and
He was one of the first to sponsor park naturalist programs and subsequently
financed the early interpretive work of the National Park Service He believed
The League shared a common leadership, membership, and understanding of nature with
the Sierra Club until the late 1950s, from which point on the Sierra Club was influenced
increasingly radicalized the Sierra Club leadership in the 1960s and 1970s to adopt more
challenged the Forest Services view that old-growth forests were cellulose cemeteries
Oregon found that these older forests were home to a wide variety of interdependent life
forms. Environmental groups were excited by this research because it gave them a further
reason to value and preserve older forests. Research specifically on the relationship
between the Northern Spotted Owl and old-growth forests became a particular focus of
these groups because animal species were protected by various environmental laws
passed in the early and mid 1970s. The development of this research and environmental
26
groups interest in this research thus are one significant area where political cultural
conditions were ripe for the co-production of three cultural boundaries of science,
institutions, and policy (see, generally, Yaffee, 1994; Chase, 1995; and Luoma, 1999).
Meanwhile, Deep Ecology concerns for species and forests, and the suspicion
that mainstream environmental groups were too ready to compromise with other interests,
led in 1980 to the creation of Earth First!, an environmental guerilla group that sabotaged
and blockaded logging equipment and operations, sometimes resulting in serious bodily
injury to loggers, before adopting more peaceful methods of protest, staging a Redwood
Summer in 1990, modeled on the Freedom Summers of the civil rights movement (Chase
1995, 308-12). Deep Ecology is a philosophy that, among other things, assigns equal
moral worth to human and nonhuman species, and distinguishes radical environmental
groups like Earth First! from more mainstream environmental groups like the Sierra Club
(Ellis 1998, 228-51; Ellis and Thompson 1997). Earth First! did not much care about
science because they did not need scientists to tell them that nature was valuable, fragile,
One area where the natural destruction of science, culture, and policy appeared to
occur in the Pacific Northwest was in the influence changing scientific understandings of
older forests had on forest and wildlife science and management. The research at H.J.
Andrews Experimental Forest that helped produce these changes began in the early 1970s
and was led by Jerry Franklin, the chief plant ecologist at the Forest Service research
27
In 1977, a forest planner approached Franklin looking for a definition of old-
growth forest, so that the Forest Service could manage it properly under the newly passed
National Forest Management Act (NFMA), which mandated management of all types of
forest. To come up with a definition, Franklin convened his researchers. The paper
Forests, described all the interdependencies among life forms that the researchers had
at Oregon State University. A compendium including this interview, titled Saving All
the Pieces: Old Growth Forests in Oregon (LaFollette 1979), prompted the Audubon
research teams paper publicly for the first time (Chase 1995, 161-62). Chase reports that
Environmentalists badly wanted to see the paper published as proof that science was on
their side13The entire Northwest conservation community began to rally around the
issue of old growth. Within the space of five years from 1975 to 1980 its interest had
shifted from setting aside rock and ice wilderness [at higher elevations] to saving mature
forests at lower elevations, bringing environmentalists into direct conflict with forest
Eric Forsman, Andy Stahl, Russell Lande, and the Scientific Basis for the Owl
Litigation
Proceeding roughly in parallel with the research of the H.J. Andrews team was the
research of wildlife biologist Eric Forsman, also begun in the early 1970s, on the
relationship between the Northern Spotted Owl and old-growth forests (Yaffee 1994, 14-
28
19). Forsmans research became a focal point for the co-production of science and social
and political order, and a catalyst for the most dramatic scientific, cultural, and policy
Aided by the fact that his academic advisor occupied two powerful positions
straddling the border between research and regulatory science, 14 Forsmans masters
thesis research became the basis for Oregons land and wildlife management agencies to
agree to protect 300 acres of 200-year-old forest for each of 400 pairs of owls, about two
percent of the states remaining old-growth (Yaffee 1994, 34). Further studies by
Forsman led the agencies to expand per pair set-asides to 1000 acres, which the timber
industry estimated would cost one million dollars per pair (Yaffee 1994, 53).
Meanwhile, Forest Service biologists, influenced by concepts from the new field
include not only diversity of species, but genetic diversity within a species, as well as
conservation biology, Michael Soule, claimed that the minimum population size
necessary to preserve genetic diversity was 500 pairs of a species, Forest Service
biologists decided that at least 500 pairs of owls had to be protected (Yaffee 1994, 62).
Then, the distribution of the population in the landscape was also recognized as an
developed a rule that a species had to be well distributed throughout the planning area
(Yaffee 1994, 58). Their modeling effort led to doubling the size of the habitat areas,
which was anticipated to cause a five percent reduction in allowable agency timber sales
29
While environmental groups agreed with industry groups that agency modeling
efforts had a poor biological basis, they did not think gathering more data was the
solution; data collection would take too long (Swedlow 2002a, 206-08). Instead, they saw
in the agencys shift from studying owl populations to modeling them an opportunity to
challenge the agency on new scientific territory. If they could find a scientist to do a
better modeling job than agency scientists had, modeling that supported the inference that
the owl was endangered by plans to protect it, they would be able to challenge those
No one understood better how to displace the agencies presumed expertise with
outside scientific authority than Andy Stahl, then working at the National Wildlife
Federation, later a resource analyst at the Sierra Club Legal Defense Fund (SCLDF).
With Soules help, Stahl located Russell Lande, a theoretical biologist at the University
of Chicago (Chase 1995, 246). Stahl explained the problem: he needed a paper to prove
logging hurt owls, [which] not only wouldhave to exhibit impeccable scholarship,
but also [would have] to be timely and written in terms that a judge could understand
(246-47). Landes paper was ready in June 1985, when Stahl published it at a press
conference (247).
Landes paper modeled both owl habitat needs and population declines. Lande
predicted that if old growth were reduced to less than 21 percent (+/- 2 percent) of the
region owls cannot persist, and that the owl would in fact go extinct under the Forest
Services management plans because they called for harvesting all but seven to sixteen
percent of the remaining old-growth. Even a plan that would double or triple the
[Spotted Owl Management Areas], assuming these to consist of 1000 acres of old growth,
30
would be likely to rapidly extinguish the population (Lande 1988, 605). Landes paper
and its importance to the owl litigation are further discussed in Swedlow 2003, 196-202.
environmentalists needed to shut down federal timber sales on a large scale. Its a
perfect species to use as a surrogate [for protecting old growth forests], Stahl told the
Western Public Law Conference. First of all, it is unique to old-growth forests and
theres no credible scientific dispute on that fact. Second of all, it uses a lot of old growth.
Thats convenient because we can use it to protect a lot of old growth. And third . . . it
appears the spotted owl faces an imminent risk of extinction (as quoted in Yaffee 1994,
215-16).
Andy Stahl, Victor Sher, Todd True and the Sierra Club Legal Defense Funds owl
litigation strategy
While the lead plaintiffs in the owl suits were the Portland and Seattle chapters of
the Audubon Society, and the Sierra Club Legal Defense Fund (SCLDF) represented
these and other environmental groups, the owl litigation strategy originated with Andy
Stahl, working for SCLDF by 1987, and Victor Sher and Todd True, the SCLDFs lead
attorneys, who recruited these groups to serve as plaintiffs. SCLDF believed that they
could get much more environmental protection from Ninth Circuit federal judges under
existing law than they could from Congress, where they would have to compromise with
timber interests. For their part, established national environmental groups were reluctant
to join the movement that SCLDF claimed to serve.15 They saw SCLDFs owl litigation
strategy as high risk and feared that it would provoke a political backlash leading to a
31
weakening of the Endangered Species Act (ESA), which required the protection of
SCLDF feared this too and hoped to avoid weakening the ESA by basing its owl
suits on other environmental laws. This is one reason Stahl tried to talk others out of
petitioning the FWS to list the owl as threatened or endangered under the Act. But there
were other reasons that SCLDF did not want the owl listed as threatened. Once the owl
was listed, SCLDF feared that federal judges would defer to FWS expertise on the owl
and the FWS would not do enough to enforce the ESA against the land management
agencies, particularly not against the Forest Service, the premier federal environmental
agency. At the same time, SCLDF believed that federal judges would be less likely to
defer to the wildlife expertise of the land management agencies than that of the FWS.
Consequently, SCLDF needed to find laws that would allow them to mount their
scientific critique directly against federal land managers. The National Environmental
Policy Act (NEPA) and the National Forest Management Act (NFMA) fit the bill
Helen Frye, Thomas Zilly, William Dwyer and the Ninth Circuits Spotted Owl
SCLDF began suing the federal land and wildlife management agencies in 1987,
gaining their first injunctions in 1991. SCLDFs suits were directed at the BLM, FWS,
and Forest Service and were heard by six district court judges, with Judges Helen Frye,
Thomas Zilly, and William Dwyer issuing the bulk of the 18 published district court
32
SCLDFs litigation strategy was initially frustrated in Judge Fryes courtroom in
their suits against the BLM, while finding unexpected success in Judge Zillys in their
suits against the FWS. But SCLDF achieved its greatest success in Judge Dwyers
courtroom in their suits against the Forest Service. Ninth Circuit appellate panels were
uniformly supportive of SCLDFs suits from the beginning, claiming that It was and is
no secret that the northern spotted owl disappears when its habitat is destroyed by
logging before the district courts had even held hearings or made factual findings on the
Judge Frye initially did not accept academic scientists (recruited by SCLDF)
claims that there was sufficient new information to require the BLM to reassess the
impact of its planned timber sales on the owl under NEPA. This was in part because
Judge Frye deferred to congressional amendments that removed suits based on new
information from judicial review. But Ninth Circuit appellate panels signaled their strong
support of SCLDFs suits, finding grounds to reverse Judge Frye on every appeal, going
so far as holding that Congress had acted unconstitutionally when it prohibited judicial
This ruling was in turn reversed by a unanimous Supreme Court, but the reversal
would have no effect on the continuing owl litigation because annual congressional
restrictions on judicial review were not renewed after three years when environmentalists
had built sufficient support in Congress to stop them. Judge Frye ultimately held that the
BLM had acted unreasonably when it decided not to consider new information about the
owl, even as she claimed not to be choosing among experts. This new information
consisted of models of owl population and habitat dynamics, not of new knowledge
33
regarding owl biology. A Ninth Circuit appellate panel strongly endorsed Judge Fryes
ruling, claiming that it was supported by a body of scientific evidence (Swedlow 2003,
209-225).
Meanwhile, when the FWS declined to list the owl as threatened under the ESA
due to missing population trend and other biological data, the SCLDF had little
difficulty in getting Judge Zilly to rule that the agency had not adequately justified its
decision. Judge Zilly did not defer to FWS expertise on the owl as SCLDF had feared
federal judges would. When the agency listed the owl, Judge Zilly further ruled that the
FWS should have designated the owls critical habitat concurrently with that decision. In
so ruling, Judge Zilly was undoubtedly influenced by the owl conservation strategy that
mandated by Congress in one of its appropriations riders (Swedlow 2003, 225-228, 235-
239).
This 1989 rider, known as the Northwest Timber Compromise, required federal
land management agencies in the region to sell specific amounts of timber, mandated that
no sales were to come from spotted owl habitat areas identified in agencies planning
documents, added specific protected areas for the owl, and directed the agencies to
(ISC) charged with developing a scientifically credible conservation strategy for the
The ISC conservation strategy vastly expanded forest set-asides for the owl
because it recommended that owls be protected in groups of twenty pairs rather than in
34
individual pairs. The ISC claimed that models played a secondary role in developing their
conservation strategy, with empirical studies of owls playing the primary role. Yet they
readily conceded that apparent owl population declines observed in a couple of study
areas could not be used to predict declines in owl populations. They also conceded that
forest structure was a more important determinant of owl habitat than forest age, and that
owls could be found reproducing in stands as young as 80 years, and even 50 years,
provided that there were a few remnants of old growth (Thomas et al 1990). Industry
lawyers claimed that the ISC created a faade of science to obscure a series of
professional judgments (Swedlow 2003, 229-235). When the FWS designated the owls
critical habitat, the agency built on the ISC recommendations, expanding owl set-asides
management in the Pacific Northwest than Judge Dwyer. Not only was he the first to
enjoin federal timber sales to protect the owl, but his injunction alone fundamentally
altered the politics of the issue because the Forest Service owned most of the federal
lands in the region. This temporary but 100 percent reduction in sales (when extended to
BLM lands by Judge Fryes injunction) created the policy window for FEMAT (1993)
and President Clinton to propose a 75 percent permanent reduction for all federal lands in
the region, going significantly beyond the ISC recommendations in an effort to protect
Judge Dwyer also ordered the agencies to develop plans that would protect not
only the owl but biological communities. This order implied that only an owl
management plan that also managed ecosystems would be sufficient to lift the injunction.
35
This order was the result of considerable judicial activism, with Judge Dwyer finding a
Forest Service biologists. These regulations required the agency to maintain viable
populations of vertebrates on agency lands, arguably going beyond the ESAs focus on
the recovery of individual species, but not requiring ecosystem management per se, nor
the protection of biological communities. Judge Dwyer also read NEPA to require
Judges Frye, Zilly, and Dwyer adopted very different postures toward the
scientists before them, which had significant consequences for the co-production of
scientific, cultural, and policy change. Judge Frye was very reluctant to choose among
scientists, and she was the only one to give any space in her opinions to the critique of an
owl expert testifying on behalf of the timber industry. She relied primarily on owl
assessments produced by BLMs own biologists to hold that the agency must reassess its
timber sale program. Judge Zilly, on the other hand, sided with a lone FWS dissenter and
three concurring outside scientists to find that the agency had acted arbitrarily and
capriciously in deciding not to list the owl as threatened. He selectively quoted the
industry owl expert to make it appear that all scientists outside the agency thought the
For his part, Judge Dwyer barely even acknowledged industry experts in his
opinions that lead to an injunction of Forest Service timber sales, but lent an especially
sympathetic ear to critiques of agency owl plans offered by scientists testifying on behalf
36
of SCLDF. Even though the ISC conservation strategy afforded vastly more protection
for the owl than set-asides for owl pairs, and Judge Dwyer initially was impressed by the
ISC report, he was soon persuaded that their plan might not go far enough when FWS
biologists produced an analysis suggesting that owl populations were declining faster
than previously thought and academic scientists testified that the owls decline might
even be worse than that, having passed a threshold from which it could not recover
(Swedlow 2003, 243-263, 267-272). Judicial rulings in the owl cases consequently
depended on resolving contested factual and legal issues in ways that required a dramatic
38; italics in the original). The concept of co-production helps us understand how
knowledge and its production shape and sustain social and political identities and give
them power and meaning (39). And because [i]nstitutions serve as sites for the testing
and reaffirmation of political culture they are also sites for the co-production of science
and social and political order (40). When knowledge changes specifically, when
be recognized and given political effect (40). Finally, science and social and political
Solving problems of social order frequently takes the form of producing new languages
or modifying old ones In the process, scientific language often takes on board the tacit
37
models of nature, society, culture, or humanity that are current at any time within a given
individuals and institutions, particularly in the Forest Service. At the individual level, the
identities of foresters were transformed from model agency employees into narrow
Non-game wildlife biologists, by contrast, moved from the periphery of the land
concepts became the basis for owl management plans in the region. These changes in
identity are also associated with changes in power and authority, with foresters losing
power and authority and wildlife biologists, and particularly conservation biologists,
gaining them.
Soules influence on Forest Service owl management occurred while he was self-
biology differs from most other biological sciences in one important way: it is often a
crisis discipline, Soule wrote in 1985. Its relation to biology, particularly ecology, is
disciplines, one must act before knowing all the facts; crisis disciplines are thus a mixture
of science and art, and their pursuit requires intuition as well as information. A
conservation biologist may have to make decisions or recommendations about design and
38
Thus, the rise of conservation biology co-produced in part by scientists,
environmentalists, and judges in the owl litigation not only changed the identity of
biologists relative to foresters and other agency scientists and professionals, but it may
have contributed to changing the identity of wildlife biologists and more generally what it
means to be a scientist within the land and wildlife management agencies. These changes
in the identity of scientists and their institutional participation in policymaking were co-
At the institutional level, the identity (and power and authority) of the land and
wildlife agencies changed in ways parallel to that of the professionals most associated
with each agency. Ninth Circuit rulings radically changed identities, authority, and power
relationships among and within the land and wildlife management agencies, effectively
handing control of land management to nongame wildlife biologists, previously the least
influential members of these agencies. Within the land management agencies this
inverted the previous relationship between foresters and wildlife biologists, while among
agencies previous relationships were also turned upside down, with the FWS effectively
gaining control of much of the land management done by the BLM and Forest Service.
transforming each of these institutions. Changes in the Forest Service have been
particularly well documented. Commensurate with the direction of external pressure from
interest groups, Congress, and the courts (Sabatier, Loomis, and McCarthy 1995;
Farnham 1995; Jones and Callaway 1995; Jones and Taylor 1995), as well as internal
pressures from employees (McCarthy, Sabatier, and Loomis 1991; Kennedy, Krannich,
39
Quigley, and Cramer 1992; Brown and Harris 1992a, 1992b, 1993), the agency has been
Farnham, Taylor, and Callaway 1995), although it is probably most accurate to view
regime familiar to cultural theorists (Wildavsky, 2006b [1986], 2006c [1995]; Lockhart
1997; Verweij and Thompson 2006; and Swedlow 2002b, 2006a, xxii-xxiii,
forthcoming).
Thus, whereas the Forest Service used to be concerned primarily with efficiency
and economy in producing timber and other commodities from national forests, these
values are now applied to a wider range of outputs, including producing non-commodity
values, and the agency is now additionally concerned with being responsive to and
representative of the public (Tipple and Wellman 1991). Before 1960, forest rangers
were seen as the expert, local authority, and manager-in-charge (Tipple and Wellman
1991, 423). By 1990 forest rangers have become public servants and facilitators of
public dialogue (424). The old, hierarchical system relied on dog loyalty
authority, and power in the Forest Service has been endorsed by its chiefs and
40
founded by Andy Stahl. Dale Robertson, chief of the Forest Service during the owl
litigation, described the forest managers new role as one of guiding, educating,
advising, and encouraging rather than regulating and controlling (Robertson 1989, as
quoted in Tipple and Wellman 1991, 425). Various pressures, including civil rights law
suits, have also led the agency to diversify its hiring practices (Kennedy 1991; Brown and
Harris 1993; Thomas and Mohai 1995). Once exclusively male and white, Forest Service
employees now include women and minorities, an inclusiveness and leveling of the
production of forest commodities has been displaced by a discourse that represents nature
hierarchical and egalitarian, but particularly with egalitarians because, as in the human
communities they are trying to create, all members of the biological community are
Ecosystems are also complex, requiring lots of varied expertise to understand let alone to
while egalitarians like the inclusiveness and equalization of experts that studying and
managing ecosystems invites (see, generally, Cortner and Moote 1999; Fitzsimmons
1999). Along the way from multi-use forestry to ecosystem management, Chief
Franklins New Forestry ideas. But when the discourse around ecosystem management
41
appeared to have more support, Robertson embraced it, seeking to shape it into
This might be the end of the story, and, indeed, in other accounts it has been
(Swedlow 2011, 2012). However, the main drivers of scientific, cultural, institutional,
and policy change here are not just cultural surprise and co-production of science and
social order. Boundary-work relying on pollution and purity claims was also very
important in producing the changes analyzed here (Swedlow 2007). What remains, then,
this challenge is made easier by the fact that Douglass early formulations of cultural
theory characterized its cultural dimensions and types in terms of social boundaries, and
was centrally concerned with understanding efforts to maintain the purity of bounded
social units and how social worlds could be corrupted by breaches of these boundaries.
Thus, in re-stating cultural theory as a theory of boundaries, this paper is in many ways
simply returning to Douglass initial formulation, which already joins many of the
concepts it seeks to re-combine here in order to provide a more unified, fuller explanation
(1966), Douglas adapted Emile Durkheims concepts of the sacred and profane
(developed for the study of western religions in Durkheim, 1915) to the study of
primitive religions, where they became purity and pollution. Douglas identified four
sources of social pollution: (1) danger pressing on a groups external boundaries, (2)
42
danger from transgressing the internal boundaries, or lines, of a group, (3) danger in the
margins of the boundaries, a sort of no-mans borderland, and (4) danger from internal
contradiction, when some of the basic organizing principles are denied by or clash with
other such basic principles, so that the group seems to be at war with itself. Douglas
further developed these ideas in Natural Symbols (1970) and (with Aaron Wildavsky) in
Risk and Culture: An Essay on the Selection of Technical and Environmental Dangers
(1982).
Wildavsky and others, became the cultural theory described in this piece. To re-cast
the social boundaries in the theory. The collectivist cultures, hierarchy and egalitarianism,
share a strong external boundary, separating those who are inside the group from those
who are outside the group. However, hierarchy and egalitarianism differ with respect to
further social boundaries. Hierarchy further bounds individuals within the group,
maintaining and even multiplying distinctions, while egalitarians are concerned to erode
these kinds of divisions, particularly the kinds of stratification that lead to differences in
collectives or individualists, and are at the mercy of the comings and goings of the other
cultural types.
43
Pollution and Purity Claims and Boundary-work
Stated most generally, pollution claims are claims that some social boundary,
such as that between law and politics, religion and politics, or science and politics has
been breached, impermissibly allowing activity in one sphere to intermingle with activity
in another, polluting it. Purity claims are claims that such social boundaries remain intact,
that no boundary has been breached, no pollution has occurred. In the way these concepts
are applied here, scientific pollution claims are effectively attempts to use contamination
by some aspect of non-science to lower the standing of scientists. Purity claims are
elements.16
between good and bad work (and, not trivially, between good and bad workers)
within a single discipline, between different disciplines, and between science and other
Scientific pollution and purity claims can be and are used to construct and
maintain boundaries between science and non-science (see Gieryn 1983, 1999). But this
is not the only possible purpose or result of such claims. As can be inferred from David
Bloors work, which extends Durkheim and Douglass concepts to the study of science,
people contrast sacred, pure versions of scientific activity with profane, polluted ones to
make distinctions not just between scientists and non-scientists, but among better and
44
In other words, pollution and purity claims also can and do use the boundary
between science and non-science to help create and maintain boundaries within science,
allowing distinctions to be made among scientists. Thus, the boundary-work that creates
and maintains the boundary between science and non-science becomes a rhetorical
the extent to which they have been polluted or compromised by contact with non-science.
In a different way of putting it, pollution and purity claims allow the boundary-work that
resource for making distinctions among scientists. Of course, every time pollution and
purity claims are made, even where their primary purpose is to distinguish among
scientists, they also do double-duty reaffirming the location and nature of the boundary
Pollution and purity claims may be understood as elements of what Nigel Gilbert
and Michael Mulkay call the contingent repertory of scientific discourse, where
scientists claim that scientific findings are contingent on personal inclinations, social
positions, and other factors outside the realm of empiricalphenomena (Gilbert and
Mulkay 1984: 57; for analysis relying on contingent repertories that recognizes the
Pollution and purity claims were first encountered when attempting to define the
population of scientists to be included in this study. Who was an owl or forest scientist
for the purposes of this research? The literature suggested that the best way to build this
45
kind of sample was to identify a few people known to be part of the sample and ask them
to help you identify others. This is called referral or snowball sampling. The idea is that
when you keep coming up with the same names, you have defined the population you
Industrial Pollution
Owl and forest scientists were identified from government planning documents
and public critiques of them by industry and environmental groups. These scientists were
then asked to help identify other scientists who were knowledgeable and differed about
forests and spotted owls in the Pacific Northwest. For some scientists these turned out to
be mutually exclusive categories. One claimed that scientists who were knowledgeable
did not differ, and that those who differed were not scientists. There might be six or
seven PhDs who disagree, he conceded, but of course I dont count them because they
work for the timber industry. That is, for this scientist, the scientific status of these
claim of industrial pollution was intended to place these scientists outside the relevant
confrontation federal wildlife biologist Jack Ward Thomas had with one of three
statisticians hired by an industry group to critique his committees owl protection plans. 18
I asked, Have you ever been to the Pacific Northwest? Thomas recalled. He
said no. I asked, Have you ever seen a spotted owl? He said no. I asked if he
46
was paid. He said he spent five days on his report for six thousand dollars and six
hours reading our plan. I said, Youre a pimp (as quoted in Dietrich 1992, 73).
Thomass questions are good examples of the variety of ways in which scientists who
lent their support to industry were deprived of their scientific authority. None of these
scientists, which might have resulted in boundary-work and pollution and purity claims
geared to the internal politics of science. Rather, Thomass questions are examples of
boundary-work based on claims that science had been polluted by breaches of the
outside the relevant scientific community, or at least severely degrade their authority
within it.
First, Thomas suggested that these scientists were literally outsiders, and that they
were therefore not part of the relevant, regionally defined scientific community that had
the authority to speak on behalf of the owl. They had never been to the area and had
never seen the owl. Here is an instance where the cartography that Gieryn (1999) uses as
geographic distinction among scientists. In pointing to these facts and by noting that this
scientist (only) spent six hours reading Thomass owl plan and five days preparing his
critique, Thomas was also implicitly making a claim that these scientists had a
substantially lesser understanding of the owl than those who had prepared the plan -- and
perhaps even were incompetent. The clincher, however, was Thomass asking whether
this scientist had been paid. The implication here was that this scientist had sold out to
timber interests. His statistical skills were a prostitute pimped to industry for thousands of
47
dollars. Thomass metaphorical reference to prostitution, an illegal activity in most states
and an immoral activity for many people, also helps suggest compound boundary
their implementation. He chaired the first interagency scientific committee on the owl,
the so-called Thomas Committee, leading President Clinton to appoint him to head his
Forest Ecosystem Management Assessment Team (FEMAT) and then the Forest Service,
the first time a wildlife biologist and not a career forester had led the agency. Thomass
the owl, proudly recounted by Thomas, suggests that pollution and purity claims were
policy-making power.
It is worth noting that the concept of a pollution claim, while not explicitly
discussed, is intuitively understood by at least some scientists, helping to validate it. For
example, when an academic scientist who consults for industry was asked to comment on
anthropologist might. Ive circled certain words [in the governments rebuttal] that form
a very interesting pattern, he noted. Whenever they refer to [the critique by the
[being] that something related to industry is therefore tainted and not ecologically
sound.
48
Industrial pollution claims were the ones most frequently heard. Their constitutive
effect for the scientific community, and consequently their constructive effect on nature
industry-affiliated scientists, or at least severely degrading their authority, the rest were
able to constitute themselves as the scientific community that counted for purposes of
characterizing owl populations and habitat and forest history and processes, as well as for
If the most polluted scientists were seen as the ones who worked for industry, the
purest were those who worked for universities, according to the scientists and non-
scientists who helped construct the scientific community in this case. Former academics-
turned-industry scientists noted that academic scientists were treated like gods and
were the arbiters of this thing. Since he had begun working for industry, one said, he
did not experience the same level of deference accorded him as a professor; his work was
scientific activity that conferred scientific authority while dissociating themselves from
aspects that did not. Thus, because academic scientists were assigned greater scientific
authority than government and industry scientists, these latter emphasized academic
affiliations whenever possible. Among academic scientists, some kept mentioning their
research projects at the prestigious Harvard University Forest to elevate themselves over
academic rivals. Among government scientists, research biologists were accorded greater
authority than field biologists or naturalists. Some scientists tried to associate themselves
49
with great scientists of the past, including Isaac Newton, Charles Darwin, and Max
species extinction crises to secure government funding. Here, the implication was that
ecologistsbought into current theory because it [provides] research money, a steady job
in a tenured position, and makes you popular with the girls. Some of these older
professors, he intimated, have gotten onto these popular issues and left their wives.
This, of course, is another example of a compound pollution claim, with pollution arising
from financial and job security considerations, not to mention pollution by baser, more
venal urges or affairs of the heart. These pollution claims are not designed to transform
university and government scientists into non-scientists, but rather use these claimed
Industry scientists also claimed that the work of government scientists was polluted by
50
motivated, bad, bad science [that] were seeing in action here. In addition to claiming
pollution from political sources, scientists referenced a number of political concepts, such
as ideology, philosophy, myth, bias, beliefs, and group think when making pollution
claims about rivals work. Thus an industry-affiliated scientist claimed that FEMAT was
the public all excited [and] the President all excited and now one of them is Chief of
the Forest Service, so they achieved the political ends they were looking for19
Assuming that because you have a bunch of experts theyll come up with a
rational, balanced solution, another claimed, citing the book, Groupthink, is whats
brought us such things as the Vietnam War and the Bay of Pigs invasion (referencing
Janis 1972). Such analogies to political events widely perceived as debacles were of
course attempts not only to color the FEMAT effort as political, but as a political debacle.
forestry professor Bill Atkinsons critique of Franklins New Forestry ideas. Atkinson
Luoma, 1999, 169) to Chinas Cultural Revolution, where Mao Zedong had proclaimed
flowerbeds. Of course, we dont have Chairman Mao. Weve got Jerry (quoted in
pollution from political and ideological sources. I would flat out call [this] their
51
mythology, one said. Another industry-affiliated scientist joined this criticism, writing
that the FEMAT assessment reflects a dangerous myth [and] ideology [that] have led
some people to believe that humans are not part of nature... (Bonnicksen 1993, 14).
[adopted by FEMAT] is based on the steady state approach and other philosophies: that
humans can not/should not try to interfere with natural processes to promote their values;
[and] that humans do not understand enough to intervene in natural processes (Oliver
1993, 3). FEMAT scientists countered that the emphasis industry-affiliated scientists
placed on natural disturbances was political, i.e., politically motivated, and that more
active forms of management were like a religion to them, the analogy suggesting a
dogmatic faith that some would associate with religion, thus serving as a claim of
In preparing this testimony, I was overwhelmed with frustration over the extent to
which [the FEMAT Report] is being portrayed as both the voice of the scientific
strongest possible terms that the FEMAT Report is not a scientific document
Based on his count of how infrequently FEMAT scientists were cited in the scientific
literature, the industry-affiliated scientist testified that he was forced to conclude that the
52
bureaucrats, and below-average scientists cloaked in a false mantle of scientific certainty
that they have not earned the right to wear (Ibid, 5-6). This compound set of pollution
claims suggested that some FEMAT scientists really were non-scientists, placing them
administrators and lesser scientists, lowering their standing and authority within science.
Jack Ward Thomas, the leader of the FEMAT effort, tried to give these pollution
stains a good laundering. The FEMAT Report, he said, was a management document
produced by scientists, not a scientific product, implying that its failure to have been
produced by scientific methods should not soil the reputations of FEMAT scientists. With
authority to the Report while preventing the Report from tarnishing the very authority
from which it drew its strength. Our work as scientists, economists, analysts, and
relying on subtle purity claims. Whatever decisionsmay emerge from this work are
now, most appropriately, in the hands of elected leaders (FEMAT Report 1993, I-3).
created no apparent barriers to making scientific pollution and purity claims in this case.
53
scientific pollution and purity claims and in doing scientific boundary-work. In so doing,
they helped elevate some scientists and their views to prominence and policy
The decisions of this plan do not have a solid grounding in biology; they are
entirely political in nature, environmentalist Cameron LaFollete wrote in the first public
evaluation of the first agency owl plan (quoted in Yaffee 1994, 47). Andy Stahl, a
resource analyst for the Sierra Club Legal Defense Fund, criticized the Forest Services
Regional Guide on similar grounds. I set myself to finding out what was behind the
biology of the plan, he recalled, which turned out to be nothing more than the
political expediency (Ibid: 75-6). Again, in a bid to degrade the authority of government
environmentalist.
criticize government owl plans: This guy is now the worlds top population geneticist.
His only interest is science. Hes a total babe in the woods when it comes to politics or
people. Hes been in the ivory tower all his life. Heck, Im amazed hes married. But hes
a total genius (quoted in Dietrich 1992, 220). The compound purity claim here is that
despite working for an environmental group, this scientist was the top scientist in his
54
In large measure the [Interagency Scientific Committee] report presents a facade
of science to create the appearance that the ISC Strategy is firmly grounded in objective,
verifiable science when in fact it is not, an industry law firm wrote, in attempting to de-
[The] aura of objective science that has been cast over the ISC report is not
justified, and should not inhibit close scrutiny of every component of the ISC
1991, 2)
Here the pollution claim is that the ISC had engaged in management rather than scientific
activities, and that since the ISC was not doing pure science, politicians and
administrators should not fear entering its realm. Or, in another way of putting it, the
pollution claim was that the ISCs activities were already outside the realm of science, so
on pollution and purity claims. Despite industry views to the contrary, Judge William
Dwyer wrote that The ISC report is widely regarded as thorough, careful, and
scientifically credible. It has been described by experts on both sides as the first
scientifically respectable proposal to come out the executive branch. Still, he noted,
The ISC strategy may or may not prove to be adequate. While it is endorsed by well-
55
qualified scientists, it is criticized by others, equally well-qualified, as over-optimistic
and risky.20
President Clintons appointees also did their share of scientific (and legal)
boundary-work relying on purity and pollution claims. The land allocations and
standards and guidelines that are adopted here satisfy all of the objectives set forth by the
President, wrote the Secretaries of Agriculture and Interior, in signing off on Clintons
management plan. They comply with the requirements of federal law.... They are based
on the best available science and are ecologically sound (Espy and Babbitt 1994, 3). Not
pollution claims. This is war, declared Brock Evans, vice-president of the National
Federal judges put an end to this war, at least temporarily. Judge Dwyer swept
aside challenges to President Clintons Northwest Forest Plan from both industry and
environmentalists. On their way to doing so, Judge Dwyer and other judges did their own
witnesses for environmentalists. Only one federal judge gave any space in her opinions to
the opposing views of a professor testifying on behalf of the timber industry. Ninth
Circuit appellate panels provided strong support for the rulings of Judge Dwyer and other
district court judges (see Swedlow 2002a, 2003). Moreover, they did their own very
significant boundary-work very early in the litigation. Before any fact-finding had been
done by the lower courts, a Ninth Circuit panel asserted that Bird experts generally
agreed that the continued logging of old growth fir would probably exterminate the
56
species in the logged off areas.21 This suggested that those who disagreed either were
not bird experts or held marginal, minority views within the scientific community.
This paper has argued that Douglass cultural theory is a good candidate for
specifying, explaining, and predicting the political cultural conditions under which the
institutional, and policy change, are likely to occur. The plausibility of this theory was
suggested here by showing how scientists involved in struggles over land and wildlife
predicted by the theory. Moreover, as the cultural theory of change predicts, these
constructs and policies and the hierarchical culture and organization of their associated
understandings of older forests and their associated species, like the northern spotted owl,
anticipated by Jasanoff, and they took forms and changed for reasons and in ways
boundaries, this paper showed how boundary-work relying on pollution and purity claims
were used by cultural combatants to align themselves and the domain of authoritative
science with scientists whose constructs of nature and public policy were functional for
their preferred social and institutional relations, while excluding scientists from
subcultures and from the domain of authoritative science whose constructs and policies
57
While heuristic or interpretive uses of cultural theory are probably particularly
simultaneously constitute variables and cause them to act on each other (Jasanoff 2004,
274-278), making it difficult to specify variables for analysis a priori, interpretive case
studies of the kind undertaken here (and typically used in science studies) can and
probably should feed into advancing a more rigorous operationalization and testing of
cultural theorys claims. Recent efforts to operationalize and test cultural theory through
surveys, content analysis, and experiments can be found in a recent symposium (in PS:
Political Science & Politics, fall 2011) and should provide ways to build on similar
efforts cited in this article (Ellis and Thompson 1997; Porknoy and Schanz 2003) and in
There are also several additional ways to test and develop this cultural theory of
co-production using interpretive case studies. First, one might study other
plausibility and to develop it, laying the foundation for more systematic testing and
evidence that co-production takes the forms and makes changes for the reasons predicted
by cultural theorists. Existing case studies applying cultural theory could be examined to
see whether scientists and other actors co-produce identities, institutions, discourse, and
2006 for applications). To the extent these studies lack evidence to support these
investigations, their subjects could be studied further so that the claims made by co-
58
Second, the cultural theory of the co-production proposed here might be
systematically tested and developed by studying cases of co-production that are most
likely or least likely to validate the theory (a method discussed and applied to test,
invalidate, and revise a different theory in Swedlow 2009) or, third, through comparative
Unlike the case study methods discussed so far, comparative nested analysis will
allow scholars to make inferences about the external or general validity of the co-
production processes found in the cases studied. Seeking to exploit these methods in
environmental, health, safety, and other risks and are studying a random, representative
sample of them (Hammitt et al 2005; Swedlow et al 2009, 2011). Among other things,
nested analysis of these risks will allow testing and development of theories of science in
the regulatory process (Swedlow 2006c), including the cultural theory of co-production
References
Bloor, David 1978. Polyhedra and the Abominations of Leviticus. British Journal for the
History of Science 11, 243-72. Reprinted in Essays in the Sociology of Perception, ed.
Mary Douglas 1982, pp. 191-194. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Bloor, David 1986. Knowledge and Social Imagery, 2nd edn. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Bloor, Celia and David Bloor. 1982. Twenty Industrial Scientists: A Preliminary
Exercise. In Essays in the Sociology of Perception, ed. Mary Douglas, pp. 83-102.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
59
Ecosystems: A Report to the American Forest and Paper Association. In Comments on
the Draft Supplemental Environmental Impact Statement onManagement of Habitat for
Late-Successional and Old-Growth Forest Related Species within the Range of the
Northern Spotted Owl, Exhibit A. The Northwest Forest Resource Council, et al.
Brickman, Ronald, Sheila Jasanoff, and Thomas Ilgen (1985) Controlling Chemicals:
The Role of Regulation in Europe and the United States (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press).
Brown, G., and C. Harris. 1992a. The U.S. Forest Service: Toward a new resource
management paradigm? Society and Natural Resources 5: 231-245.
. 1992b. The U.S. Forest Service: Changing of the guard. Society and Natural
Resources 32: 449-466.
Cetina, Karin Knorr (1994) Laboratory Studies: The Cultural Approach to the Study of
Science, in Handbook of Science and Technology Studies, eds., Sheila Jasanoff, Gerald
E. Markle, James C. Peterson, and Trevor Pinch (Beverly Hills: Sage Publications).
Chase, A. 1995. In a dark wood: The fight over forests and the rising tyranny of ecology.
Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Cetina, 1999.
Collier, David and James E. Mahon, Jr. (1993) Conceptual Stretching Revisited:
Adapting Categories in Comparative Analysis, American Political Science Review 87,
4:845.
Coyle, D. J. 1994. This land is my land, this land is your land: Cultural conflict in
environmental and land use regulation. In Politics, policy, and culture, edited by D. J.
Coyle and R. J. Ellis, 33-50. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Coyle, Dennis J. and Aaron Wildavsky. 1987. Requisites of Radical Reform: Income
Maintenance Versus Tax Preferences. Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 7
(1): 1-16.
60
Cozzens, S. E. and T. F. Gieryn, eds. 1990. Theories of science in society. Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press.
Dietrich, William 1992. The Final Forest: The Battle for the Last Great Trees of the
Pacific Northwest. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Douglas, M. 1986. How Institutions Think. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
and A. Wildavsky. 1983. Risk and culture: An essay on the selection of technical
and environmental dangers. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Durkheim, Emile 1915. The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. London: Allen and
Unwin.
Ellis, Richard J. 1998. The Dark Side of the Left: Illiberal Egalitarianism in
America. Lawrence: Kansas University Press.
Ellis, R. J., and F. Thompson. 1997. Culture and the environment in the Pacific
Northwest. American Political Science Review 91 (4): 885-97.
Espy, Mike, and Bruce Babbitt 1993. Record of Decision for Amendments to Forest
Service and Bureau of Land Management Planning Documents Within the Range of the
Northern Spotted Owl. U.S. Department of Agriculture, Forest Service, and U.S.
Department of the Interior, Bureau of Land Management.
Farnham, T.J. 1995. Forest Service budget requests and appropriations: What do analyses
of trends reveal? Policy Studies Journal 23 (2): 253-267.
and P. Mohai. 1995. National Forest timber management over the past decade: A
change in emphasis for the Forest Service? Policy Studies Journal 23 (2): 268-280.
61
Franklin, J. F. et al. 1981. Ecological characteristics of old-growth Douglas-Fir forests.
U.S. Department of Agriculture, Forest Service, General Technical Report PNW 118,
Pacific Northwest Forest and Range Experiment Station.
Freeman, R. 2002. The Ecofactory: The United States Forest Service and the political
construction of ecosystem management. Environmental History 7: 632-658.
Geertz 1973
Geiryn, Thomas F. 1983. Boundary-work and the Demarcation of Science from Non-
Science: Strains and Interests in the Professional Ideologies of Scientists. American
Sociological Review, 48(6), 781-95.
Gieryn, Thomas F. and Anne Figert 1986. Scientists Protect Their Cognitive Authority:
The Status Degradation Ceremony of Sir Cyril Burt. In The Knowledge Society, ed.
Gernot Boehme and Nico Stehr, pp. 67-86. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Gilbert, G. Nigel and Michael Mulkay 1984. Opening Pandoras Box: A Sociological
Analysis of Scientists Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Grendstad, G. and P. Selle. 1995. "Cultural Theory and The New Institutionalism."
Journal of Theoretical Politics 7(1): 5-27.
Haas 1990
Hammitt, James K., Jonathan B. Wiener, Brendon Swedlow, Denise Kall, and Zheng
Zhou 2005. Precautionary Regulation in Europe and the United States: A Quantitative
Comparison. Risk Analysis, 25(5), 1215-1228.
Jasanoff, Sheila 1995. Science at the Bar: Law, Science, and Technology in America.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
62
Jasanoff 2005
___________ ed. 2004. States of Knowledge: The Co-production of Science and Social
Order. London: Routledge.
and B. Wynne. 1998. Science and decisionmaking. In Human choice and climate
change, vol. 1, The societal framework, edited by S. Rayner and E. Malone, 1-87.
Columbus, OH: Batelle Press.
Kerr, Anne, Sarah Cunningham-Burley, and Amanda Amos 1997. The New Genetics:
Professionals Discursive Boundaries. The Sociological Review 45, 279-303.
Lamont, Michele and Virag Molnar 2002. The Study of Boundaries in the Social
Sciences. Annual Review of Sociology 28, 167-195.
Jones, E.S. and C.P. Taylor. 1995. Litigating agency change: The impact of the courts
and administrative appeals process on the Forest Service. Policy Studies Journal 23 (2):
310-336.
Kemp, R., and J. Rotmans. 2009. Transitioning policy: Co-production of a new strategic
framework for innovation policy in the Netherlands. Policy Sciences 42: 303-322.
Kennedy, J.J. 1991. Integrating gender diverse and interdisciplinary professionals into
traditional Department of Agriculture-Forest Service culture. Society and Natural
Resources 4 (4): 165-176.
, R.S. Krannich, T.M. Quigley, and L.A. Cramer. 1993. Employee perceptions of
USDA-Forest Service values and the agency reward system. Paper presented at the 1993
Society of American Foresters Annual Convention, Indianapolis, IN.
LaFollette, C. 1979. Saving all the pieces: Old-growth forests in Oregon. Oregon Student
Public Interest Research Group.
Lande, R. 1988. Demographic models of the northern spotted owl (Strix occidentalis
caurina). Oecologia 75: 601-607.
63
Lockhart, C. 1997. Political culture and political change. In Culture matters: Essays in
honor of Aaron Wildavsky, edited by R. J. Ellis and M. Thompson, 91-104. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Luker, Kristin 1984. Abortion and the Politics of Motherhood. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Luoma, J. R. 1999. The hidden forest: The biography of an ecosystem. New York:
Henry Holt and Company.
Martello, M. L. 2004. Expert advice and desertification policy: Past experience and
current challenges. Global Environmental Politics 4 (3): 85-106.
McCarthy, C., P. Sabatier, and J. Loomis. 1991. Attitudinal change in the Forest Service:
1960-1990. Paper presented at the 1991 Annual Meeting of the Western Political Science
Association, Seattle, WA.
Miller, C. A., and P. Edwards, eds. 2001. Changing the atmosphere: Expert knowledge
and environmental governance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Mody, CCM 2001. A Little Dirt Never Hurt Anyone: Knowledge-Making and
Contamination in Materials Science, Social Studies of Science, 31(1), 7-36.
Nash, Roderick Frazier. 1989. The Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics.
Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Preston, et al. 1991. A Faade of Science: An Analysis of the Jack Ward Thomas Report
Based on the Sworn Testimony of Members of the Thomas Committee. In A Report for
the Association of O & C Counties and the Northwest Forest Resource Council.
64
Sabatier, P.A., J. Loomis, and C. McCarthy. 1995. Hierarchical controls, professional
norms, local constituencies, and budget maximization: An analysis of U.S. Forest
Service planning decisions. American Journal of Political Science 39 (1): 204-242.
Schrepfer, S. R. 1983. The fight to save the redwoods: A history of environmental reform,
1917-1978. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
Shapin, S. 1992. Discipline and bounding: The history and sociology of science as
seen through the externalism-internalism debate. History of Science 30: 333-69.
Sher, V. M. 1993. Travels with strix: the Spotted Owls journey through the federal
courts. Public Land Law Review 14:41-79.
Swedlow, Brendon. 2001, 2006. "Postscript: Aaron Wildavsky, Cultural Theory, and
Budgeting," in Aaron Wildavsky, Budgeting and Governing, Brendon Swedlow, ed.,
Transaction Publishers, 335-357.
65
. 2009. Reason for Hope? The Spotted Owl Injunctions and Policy Change.
Law and Social Inquiry 34 (4) : 825867.
Swedlow, Brendon and Mikel Wyckoff. 2009. Value Preferences and Ideological
Structuring of Attitudes in American Public Opinion, American Politics Research, 37, 6
(November), 1048-1087.
Swedlow, Brendon, Denise Kall, Zheng Zhou, James K. Hammitt, and Jonathan B.
Wiener. 2009 Theorizing and Generalizing about Risk Assessment and Regulation
through Comparative Nested Analysis of Representative Cases, Law & Policy, 31(2)
(April), 236-269.
Swedlow, Brendon, Denise Kall, Zheng Zhou, James K. Hammitt, and Jonathan B.
Wiener. 2011. A Quantitative Comparison of Relative Precaution in the United States
and Europe, 1970-2004, in The Reality of Precaution: Comparing Risk Regulation in the
United States and Europe, Jonathan B. Wiener, Michael D. Rogers, James K. Hammitt,
and Peter H. Sand, eds., Resources for the Future Press, 377-408.
Taylor, Charles Alan 1991. Defining the Scientific Community: A Rhetorical Perspective
on Demarcation. Communication Monographs 58, 402-420.
Taylor, Robert 1992. Testimony at The Administrations Response to the Spotted Owl
Crisis, Joint Oversight Hearings, United States Congress, Committee on Interior and
Insular Affairs, Subcommittee on National Parks and Public Lands, Committee on
Agriculture, Subcommittee on Forests, Family Farms, and Energy, Committee on
Merchant Marine and Fisheries, Subcommittee on Fisheries and Wildlife Conservation
and the Environment, 102nd Congress, 2nd Session, March 24.
Thomas, J.C., and P. Mohai. 1995. Racial, gender, and professional diversification in the
Forest Service from 1983 to 1992. Policy Studies Journal 23 (2): 296-309.
Thomas, J.W. et al. 1990. A conservation strategy for the Northern Spotted Owl.
Portland, OR: United States Department of Agriculture, Forest Service; United States
Department of the Interior, Bureau of Land Management; United States Department of
66
the Interior, Fish and Wildlife Service; United States Department of the Interior, National
Park Service.
Thompson, M., R. Ellis, and A. Wildavsky. 1990. Cultural theory. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Tipple, T.J. and J.D. Wellman. 1991. Herbert Kaufmans The Forest Ranger thirty years
later: From simplicity and homogeneity to complexity and diversity. Public
Administration Review 51 (5): 421-428.
Verweij, M. and M. Thompson, eds. 2006. Clumsy solutions for a complex world:
Governance, politics, and plural perceptions. Hampshire: Palgrave MacMillan.
Wildavsky, A. 2006a. Cultural analysis: Politics, public law, and administration, edited
by B. Swedlow. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Yaffee, S. L. 1994. The wisdom of the Spotted Owl: Policy lessons for a new century.
Washington, DC: Island Press.
67
Figure 1. Dimensions of Culture, Patterns of Social
68
Figure 2. Dimensions of Culture, Patterns of Social
69
Notes
1
Brickman and colleagues, while focusing on national differences in the regulation of
chemicals, inadvertently also suggest how ideology, interests, and institutions differently
their laboratories. It is instead used to specify (1) when (and which) societal interests will
become important in constituting scientific communities and constructing nature, and (2)
when (and which) constructs of nature (and scientists) will become important in
cartography: not only do their claims become real enough for others to act on them, not
only is their authority to make truth provisionally sustained, but they enjoy (for awhile
anyway) the soaring esteem, cascading influence, and possibly abundant material
resources (cash, equipment, bodies-and-minds) needed to make still more truthful tales.
4
He does not even explicitly define culture, although, implicitly, he appears to accept
[verify], noting that My book is just a sociological follow-up to Geertzs suggestion that
further noting that Geertz thought that To analyze symbol use as social action isand
exceedingly difficult business, requiring one to attend to such muscular matters as the
Studies, 440.
70
6
By the extent of collectivization, I mean the extent to which those in a pattern of social
relations make Us versus Them distinctions, i.e., the extent to which the pattern is defined
by an external group boundary. By the extent of individual autonomy, I mean the extent
to which individuals in a pattern of social relations are free from coercion and are free to
act as they please; individual autonomy implies some personal power or efficacy. The
(1990) fairly closely. However, I have relabeled their dimensions to make their theory
translate better into terms that social scientists already understand. Thus, the extent of
extent of grid.
7
These characterizations of appropriate decision-making authority are adapted from
has a remarkable ability to fly long distances in search of habitat and an untapped
71
12
But a successor group, The Wildlands Project, relied significantly on conservation
biology to argue that half of the U.S. should be returned to its wild pre-Columbian
condition (www.wildlandsproject.org).
13
The paper was published three years later (Franklin et al 1981).
14
Forsmans adviser, Howard Wight, was simultaneously chairman of the department of
wildlife sciences and director of a special research unit of the US Fish and Wildlife
Service at Oregon State University (Chase 1995, 133; Yaffee, 1994, 15-19; as discussed
sued SCLDF for trademark infringement, which caused SCLDF to have to rename itself
Earth Justice.
16
These are not the only ways that Douglass concepts of pollution and purity can be
extended to the study of science. Related but different uses can be found in Bloor (1978,
of nature which (sic) is signalised by many distinctions, e.g., that between pure and
applied, science and technology, theory and practice, popular and serious, routine and
fundamental. In general we may say that knowledge has its sacred aspects and its profane
side Its sacred aspect is whatever we deem to be highest in it [T]he sacred aspects of
science can be thought of as informing or guiding the more mundane, less inspired, less
vital parts.
18
The so-called Thomas Committee or Interagency Scientific Committee (ISC) was
72
owls population decline and habitat needs and to develop a plan to protect it (Thomas, et
al., 1990).
19
The reference here is to President Clintons subsequent decision to appoint Jack Ward
Thomas, the wildlife research biologist he had appointed to head FEMAT, to head the
73