Situation Ethics - J. Fletcher
Situation Ethics - J. Fletcher
Situation Ethics - J. Fletcher
liiiiiiniiii
Fletcher, Joseph F.
NEW COLLEGE OF CALIFORNIA (SF)
'^
BJ 1251 .F53
Fletcher, Joseph F
Situation ethics
#15766
DATE DUE BORROWER'S NAME
//15766
Fl etcher fJoseph ¥•
.^^\^^^^^^^^^^^ics the new morality /
^r«*«r^^ Fletcher. Philadelphia x"^ ^
Hfestminster Press, cl966«
176 p* ; 20 cm.
and'^^iSex!
^^^^^^^raphical references
#15766 GiitlJSon McBride $ • .
^..IZ
^^^^stian ethics — Anglican
DUE DATE
Printed
in USA
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2010
http://www.archive.org/details/situationethicsnOOflet
Situation Ethics
SITUATION
ETHICS
THE NEW MORALITY
by
Joseph Fletcher
Foreword 11
I Three Approaches 17
II Some Presuppositions 40
III Love Only Is Always Good 57
IV Love Is the Only Norm 69
V Love and Justice Are the Same 87
VI Love Is Not Liking 103
VII Love Justifies Its Means 120
VIII Love Decides There and Then 134
IX Postscriptum: Why? 146
X An Appendix: Two Other Corruptions and
Four Cases 160
Index 169
Foreword
Foreword 1
with the cab driver. (An English movie in the same genre
is The Mark, in v^hich a man is sexually attracted to little
girls until a woman his own age rescues him by seducing
him and releasing him from his pathology.^ At least it
worked in the movie!)
As Paul Ramsey has pointed out, with some distaste,
my approach both personalistic and contextual. ^° These
is
Foreword 1
Three Approaches
Approaches to Decision-Making
1. Legalism
With this approach one enters into every decision-
making situation encumbered with a whole apparatus of
prefabricated rules and regulations. Not just the spirit but
the letter of the law reigns. Its principles, codified in rules,
are not merely guidelines or maxims to illuminate the
situation; they are directives to be followed. Solutions are
preset, and you can "look them up" in a book —
a Bible or
a confessor's manual.
Judaism, Catholicism, Protestantism —
all major West-
ern religious traditions have been legalistic. In morals as in
doctrine they have kept to a spelled-out, "systematic"
orthodoxy. The ancient Jews, especially under the post-
exilic Maccabean and Pharisaic leadership, lived by the
law or Torah, and its oral tradition (halakah).^ It was a
code of 613 (or 621) precepts, amplified by an increas-
ingly complicated mass of Mishnaic interpretations and
applications.
Statutory and code law inevitably piles up, ruling upon
ruling, because the complications of life and the claims of
—
mercy and compassion combine even with code legalists
— to accumulate an elaborate system of exceptions and
compromise, in the form of rules for breaking the rules!
It leads to that tricky and tortuous now-you-see-it, now-
3 Abraham
J. Hcschel, The Prophets (Harper & Row,
PubHshers, Inc., 1962), pp. 225, 307-315.
* There are, however, atypical works such as Richard
one soul, I will not say should be lost, but should com-
mit one single venial sin."^
A Mrs. X was convicted (later cleared in appellate
court) of impairing the morals of her minor daughter.
She had tried to teach the child chastity but at thirteen
the girl bore the first of three unwanted, neglected babies.
Her mother then had said, "If you persist in acting this
Why 1 Am Not a Christian (Simon and Schuster, Inc.,
s
1957), p. 33.
J. H. Newman, Certain Difficulties Felt by Anglicans in
^
2. Antinomianism
Over against legalism, as a sort of polar opposite, we
can put antinomianism. This is the approach with which
one enters into the decision-making situation armed with
no principles or maxims whatsoever, to say nothing of
rules. In every "existential moment" or "unique" situation,
it declares, one must rely upon the situation of itself,
there and then, to provide its ethical solution.
The term "antinomianism" "against law")
(hterally,
was used first by Luther Johannes Agricola's
to describe
views. The ethical concept has cropped up here and there,
as among some Anabaptists, some sects of English Puri-
tanism, and some of Wesley's followers. The concept is
certainly at issue in I Corinthians (e.g., ch. 6:12-20).
Paul had to struggle with two primitive forms of it among
the Hellenistic Jew-Christians whom he visited. They took
his attacks on law morality too naively and too literally.
—
One form was libertinism the belief that by grace, by
the new hfe in Christ and salvation by faith, law or rules
no longer applied to Christians. Their ultimate happy fate
was now assured, and it mattered no more what they did.
(Whoring, incest, drunkenness, and the like are what they
did, therefore! This explains the warning in I Peter 2:16,
"Live as free men, yet without using your freedom as a
pretext for evil; but live as servants of God." This license
led by inevitable to an increase of legahsm,
reaction
under which Christians still suffer
especially in sex ethics,
today.) The other form, less pretentious and more endur-
ing, was a Gnostic claim to special knowledge, so that
Three Approaches 23
neither principles nor rules were needed any longer even
as guidelines and direction pointers. They would just
know what was right when they needed to know. They
had, they claimed, a superconscience. It is this second
"gnostic" form of the approach which is under examina-
tion here.
While preoccupied with law and its stipula-
legalists are
tions, the Gnostics are so flatly opposed to law —
even in
principle —that their moral decisions are random, unpre-
dictable, erratic, quite anomalous. Making moral decisions
is a matter of spontaneity; it is literally unprincipled,
3. Situationism
1955), p. 8.
1^ E. LaB. Cherbonnier, unpublished address. Trinity
College, December 14, 1964.
Three Approaches 29
20
An Outline of Biblical Theology (The Westminster
Press, 1946), pp. 163-164.
21
Article, "MoraHty, Situation," in Dictionary of Moral
Theology, ed. by Francesco Cardinal Roberti and Msgr. Pietro
Palazzini (The Newman Press, 1962), pp. 800-802.
22 Matt. 5:43-48 and ch. 22:34-40; Luke 6:27-28;
10:25-28 and vs. 29-37; Mark 12:28-34; Gal. 5:14; Rom.
13:8-10; etc.
1
Three Approaches 3
^"^
Church Dogmatics (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1961),
Vol. Ill, Bk. 4, pp. 420-421.
^^ Ethics, p. 185.
34 SITUATION ETHICS
Abortion; A Situation
Some Presuppositions
Some Presuppositions 4
2. Relativism
Sitz-im-lehen —
as in Biblical hermeneutics.) It shows our
sharp sense of relativity and a far greater humility than
ever emerged in the classical intellectual tradition. The
same temper makes us more dialectical than men of the
past, recognizing polarities rather than either-ors. In
Christian ethics the three polarities of law and love, of
authority and experience, and of fixity and freedom are
"fruitful tensions" typical of contemporary discussion. The
first one, law and love, is the predominant issue posed by
the Christian form of situation ethics but all three are at
stake in all forms of situation method.
Ethical relativism has invaded Christian ethics pro-
gressively ever since the simultaneous appearance in 1932
of Emil Brunner's The Divine Imperative and Reinhold
Niebuhr s Moral Man and Immoral Society.^ Both theo-
logians built their conceptions of the Christian ethic on
the principle that the divine command isalways the same
in its Why but always different in its What, or changeless
as to the What How, We are
but contingent as to the
always, that is commanded to act lovingly, but how
to say,
to do it depends on our own responsible estimate of the
situation. Only love is a constant; everything else is a
variable. The shift to contemporary
relativism carries
Christians away from code ethics, away from stern iron-
bound do's and don'ts, away from prescribed conduct and
legalistic morality.
The Pharisees' kind of ethics, Torah, is now suffering
a second echpse, a far more radical one than it endured
® Charles Scribner's Sons, 1932.
46 SITUATION ETHICS
under Jesus' and Paul's attacks. Our milieu and era are far
unfriendlier to law ethics than were the apostolic and
nothing of the medieval period. "The
patristic times, to say
truth of ethical relativism," says Paul Tillich, "lies in the
moral laws' inabihty to give commandments which are
unambiguous both in their general form and in their
concrete applications. Every moral law is abstract in rela-
tion to the unique and totally concrete situation. This is
true of what has been called natural law and of what has
been called revealed law."^
Contemporary Christians should not underestimate this
relativism, in either its secular or its Christian form. Chris-
tian ethics was drawn into it long ago when Jesus attacked
the Pharisees' principle of statutory morality, and by Paul's
rebellious appeal to grace and freedom. Even earlier, the
Biblical doctrine of man as only a finite creature of
imperfect powers and perceptions was voiced in the docta
ignorantia of Isa. 55:8: "For my thoughts are not your
thoughts, neither are your ways my ways, says the Lord."
This concept of human creatureliness at the very heart of
Christian ethics cries, "Relativity!" in the face of all smug
pretensions to truth and righteousness. Christians cannot
go on trying to "lay down the law" theologically, about
either creed or code.
3. Positivism
1961), p. 584.
—
50 SITUATION ETHICS
virtues (I Cor., ch. 13). But still, these are the faith
commitments which identify the Christian.
4. Personalism
Ethics deals with human relations. ^^ Situation ethics
puts people at the center of concern, not things. Obhga-
tion is to persons, not to things; to subjects, not objects.
The legalist is a what asker (What does the law say?); the
situationist is a who asker (Who is to be helped?). That
is, situationists are personalistic. In the Christian version,
Some Presuppositions 51
Conscience
Situation ethics is interested in conscience (moral con-
sciousness) as a function, not as a faculty. It takes con-
1965).
^^ Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1960), p. 5.
Some Presuppositions 53
22
Thomas tied conscience to a faculty, synteresis; for a
critique, see Eric D'Arcy, Conscience and the Right to
Freedom (London: Sheed & Ward, Ltd., 1961).
23
Martin Heidegger calls conscience "the call of Nothing,"
i.e., of the ultimate in the finite. It is nothing, all right: no
thing! Cf. Beingand Time (Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc.,
1962), pp. 312-348.
2^^
The Complete Works of Mark Twain, ed. by Charles
Neider (Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1964), Vol. I, p. 921.
54 SITUATION ETHICS
Another feature of situation ethics is its concern with
antecedent rather than consequent conscience, i.e., with
prospective decision-making rather than with retrospective
judgment-passing. The ancient world ordinarily thought
of conscience Qsyneidesis') as a review officer, weighing an
action ex post facto and rendering approval or disapproval.
(We all do this, head on pillow, after a long, hard day!)
An example is Ernest Hemingway's famous definition,
"What's good is what I feel good after, and what's bad is
what I feel bad after." Savage cultures have often thought
of conscience with the model of a sharp stone in the breast
under the sternum, which turns and hurts when we have
done wrong. Conscience here is remorse or reassurance.
Paul spoke of conscience in two of his letters, to Rome
and Corinth, and tended to give a new twist to the Greco-
Roman idea by treating it as a director of human decisions
rather than simply a reviewer.^^ It acquired a future ref-
erence, directive and not merely reactive. So it is with
situation ethics. By contrast, the morality of the confes-
sional ex post facto and retrospective, backward-looking.
is
Nominal Good
The medieval realist-nominalist debate, in part carried
on around this basic question of ethical understanding, is
by no means merely archaic or an outworn argument.
Everything hangs on it, as we saw in the preceding chap-
ter.For an intelligent adult grasp of the problems of ethics
it isthis question which has to be settled first. It is a most
pervasive issue in Christian ethics even if it lurks mostly
beneath the surface, unrecognized by the simpleminded.
Ockham and Scotus in the Middle Ages, and Descartes in
modern postulated the view that any "good" is
times,
nominal, i.e., it is what it is only because God regards it
as good. This was opposed to the "realist" view that God
wills a thing because it is good. God finds "valuable" what-
ever suits his (love's) needs and purposes. Situation ethics,
58 SITUATION ETHICS
p. 62.
5 Nature, Man and God, p. 211.
Love Is a Predicate
Apart from the helping or hurting of people, ethical
judgments or evaluations are meaningless. Having as its
supreme norm the neighbor love commanded of Chris-
tians, Christian situation ethics asserts firmly and defi-
nitely: Value, worth, ethical quality, goodness or badness,
right or wrong — these things are only predicates, they are
not properties. They are not "given" or objectively "real"
or self-existent.^ There is only one thing that is aWays
good and good regardless of the context,
right, intrinsically
and that one thing is love. Yet we should not, perhaps,
call love a "thing." Neutral as it is as a word, it may tend
in the reader's mind to reify love, to suggest that it is a
tangible, objective existent. (The New
Testament some-
times speaks of love as if it were a property, sometimes as
a predicate. Paul and the Gospel writers were entirely
innocent of the problem we are discussing. It never oc-
curred to them.)
—
But love is not a substantive nothing of the kind.
It is a principle, a "formal" principle, expressing what
type of real actions Christians are to call good. (Exactly
the same is true of justice.) It is the only principle that
always obliges us in conscience. Unlike all other principles
you might mention, love alone when well served is always
good and right in every situation. Love is the only univer-
Only Extrinsic
This posture or perspective sets us over against all
"intrinsicalist" ethics, against all "given" or "natural" or
"objectively valid" laws and maxims, whether of the
natural law or the Scriptural law varieties. It means, too,
that there are no universals of any kind. Only love is objec-
tively valid, only love is universal. Therefore when John
Bennett pleads, in the pecca fortiter, that
spirit of Luther's
"there are situations in which the best we can do is evil,"
—
we have to oppose what he says much as we admire its
spirit. ^^ On Bennett's basis, if a small neighborhood mer-
chant tells a lie divert some "protection" racketeers
to
from their victims, no matter how compassionately the
lie is told, he has chosen to do evil. It is, of course, excused
Tablets of Stone
The first one is: "I am the Lord your God, you shall
have no other gods before Jbut?] me." This causes situa-
tion ethics no difficulty. "Aha," say the legalists, "how can
you get around that one?" The situationist has no wish to
get around it for two obvious reasons. (1) It is only a
"law" in the sense that we can speak of the "law of love"
or the "law of one's being." It is a tautology, not a true
commandment. One does not worship idols, i.e., other
gods, if one does not. It only says (to primitive Semitic
henotheists) that if you have faith in one God, you won't
have faith in any other! It only states a fact, a "fact of
72 SITUATION ETHICS
—
Christian love is not desire. Agape is giving love non- —
reciprocal, neighbor-regarding "neighbor" meaning "ev-
erybody," even an enemy (Luke 6:32—35). It is usually
distinguished from friendship love Cphilia') and romantic
love C^ros^y both of which are selective and exclusive.
Erotic love and phihc love have their proper place in our
human affairs but they are not what is meant by agape,
agapeic love or "Christian love." Erotic and philic love are
emotional, but the effective principle of Christian love is
willy disposition; it is an attitude, not feeling.
Situationists welcome the German label for this con-
ception, Gesinnungs-ethik, an attitudinal ethic rather than
a legal one. "Have this mind among yourselves, which
you have in Christ Jesus" 2:5), and then, as
(Phil.
Augustine says, whatever you do will be right! The mind
^2 Ep. Joan., vii. 5, Migne, Patralogiae cursus com-
in J. P.
pletus, series Latina Gamier Fr., 1864), Vol. 35,
(Paris:
col. 2033. "Semel ergo breve praeceptum tibi praecipitur,
Dilige, et quod vis fac."
80 SITUATION ETHICS
Objections
A common objection to situation ethics is that it calls
^'^
See D. B. Stevick, Canon Law (The Seabury Press, Inc.,
1965), pp. 158-159.
J. A. Davidson, A New Look at Morals
^^ Quoted in
which it is not lawful for any but the priests to eat, and
also gave it to those who were with him?" At least the
Christ of the Christian ethic leaves no doubt whatsoever
that the ruling norm of Christian decision is love: nothing
else.
Love and Justice Are the Same
Love Is Careful
This is why he
used the dilectio Qdiligere') —
^not amor
or caritas — emphasize the love that not only cares but
to
is careful, "diligent" in serving the neighbor as well as it
can. Prudence and love are not just partners, they are one
and the same. That is to say. Christian love and Christian
* "Morals of the Catholic Church," 26:25, in Philip
SchaflF, ed., Nicene and Ante-Nicene Fathers (Buffalo: Chris-
tian Literature Co., 1887), Vol. IV, p. 55.
88 SITUATION ETHICS
prudence are one and the same, since they both go out to
others. (Self-centered love and prudence are something
else altogether!)
This is a side of love that businessmen can appreciate,
as w^hen a production engineer tries to balance product
quality against price in a low^-income market; or a per-
sonnel manager has to choose between letting an illness-
weakened supply clerk keep his job, on the one hand, and
on the other, playing fair with hne workers whose output
and piece-rate pay are being cut down by the clerk's delays.
Love as prudence helps a field commander who has to
decide whether a platoon or company, or even a regiment,
is expendable. And if so, which one. Prudence, careful
unto the day is the evil thereof!" "Future love does not
exist," he said. "Love is a present activity only."^ A love
that casts aside breadth of vision and imaginative fore-
sight in this fashion is ethically crippled. Sad to say, it is
not at all rare the name for it is sentimentality.
:
A Proposed Reunion
However, the main thing to emphasize is that only
a misdirected conscience has to wrestle with the "justice
versus love" problem. It is seen to be a pseudoproblem at
once when we drop the traditional systematic habit of
separating them as "virtues." There is an interesting
parallel between the love-justice and faith-works syn-
dromes. Some theologies treat faith-works as faith versus
works, some as faith or works, some as faith and works.
^ Leo Tolstoy, On Life, tr. by Aylmer Maude (Oxford
University Press, 1934), p. 98.
Love and Justice Are the Same 93
^5 The Theology
of Culture (Oxford University Press,
1959), pp. 133-145.
1^ Love, Power and Justice (Oxford University Press,
1954), p. 79,
17
Wright, The Biblical Doctrine of Man in Society (Lon-
don: SCM Press, Ltd., 1954), p. 168; O. C. Quick, Chris-
tianity and Justice (London: Sheldon Press, 1940), p. 25.
18
Basic Christian Ethics, p. 243.
—
Love and Justice Are the Same 95
from intergroup). But Christianly speaking, we know that
this iswrong; that agape is what is due to all others, to
our various and many neighbors whether we "know" them
or not. Justice is nothing other than love working out its
problems. This viewpoint has existed potentially for a
long time. Now we state it flatly and starkly so that there
is no mistaking what is said. Love = justice; justice=love.
is perhaps the best they can do, given their initial mistake
of separating love and justice as "virtues" — as properties
to be "infused" rather than predicates of action. Actually,
our only choice is between sentimentality and discern-
ment, not between love and justice. Love and justice are
the same, for justice is love distributed, nothing else.
Addendum
We have been speaking of justice as a moral principle,
not as something settled and static, transfixed in laws. The
root jus means many things: law, both written and un-
written; rights; and standards or ideals. But the basic
distinction to be grasped is between moral justice and legal
justice. The two, of course, are not antithetical, but it
must be fully recognized that legal justice (law) always
threatens to suffocate and cheat moral justice. Statutory
laws, both civil and criminal, and the common law or
custom, as in the Anglo-American tradition and most
cultures, are in the situationist's view a necessary danger
— but not, note, necessarily evil.
It is the task of jurisprudence, the philosophy and
ethics of law and legislation, to keep legal justice as close
as possible to moral justice. Most judicial systems even
include, as a court of last resort, a procedure called equity
in which it is sometimes admitted that although "the law
was broken," the wrongdoer in the situation could not
have acted otherwise without betraying moral justice too
grossly to let even legalists close their eyes to it. This task
of equity and jurisprudence is all bound up in, when it is
not tied down by, the conflicting attitudes and tempers
of jurists who are agapeic about justice and those who are
legahsts. The latter say with unction and every appearance
100 SITUATION ETHICS
25 Shorter Novels
of Herman Melville (Liveright Publish-
ing Corporation, 1928).
VI
our neighbors not for our own sakes nor for theirs, really,
but for God's. We can say quite plainly and colloquially
that Christian love is the business of loving the unlovable,
i.e., the unlikable.
This love is as radical as it is because of its non-
reciprocal, noncongenial outreach. It is for the deserving
and the undeserving alike. God makes his sun rise on the
eviland on the good, and sends rain on the just and the
unjust. To suppose that we are required by any Christian
imperative to hke everybody is a cheap hypocrisy ethically
and an impossibility psychologically. People often point
out, quite reasonably and properly, that "it is impossible to
love in obedience to a command" and that to ask it of us
only encourages hypocrisy, "since all men are not lov-
able. "^^ Both objections are correct. But only if we senti-
mentalize love, taking it to be a matter of feeling or
emotion, could they be true objections to agape. Loving
and liking are not the same thing.
Kant observed that love cannot be commanded, and
discussed the question at some length. ^^ In his own way
and in his own language he recognized that romantic love
(and, for that matter, friendship love) cannot be ordered
at all. But agape can. He concluded that in Jesus' Sum-
mary, in the second part, "it is only practical love that is
meant in that pith of all laws." There is nothing senti-
mental about Christian love or Christian ethics.
Admittedly, there can be no command, no obligation,
no duty, it most assuredly
to love if love is affection, as
is in friendship love Genuine emotion what
Cphilia'). —
psychologists call "affect" to mark it off from conation or
will —
cannot be turned on and off like water from a
faucet, simply by an act of will or willing obedience to a
command. But the works of will, of love, cani
Kindness, generosity, mercy, patience, concern, righ-
teous indignation, high resolve —
these things are "virtues"
or dispositions of the will, attitudes or leanings, and there-
fore they are, psychologically speaking, perfectly possible
requirements of covenant and command. (A typical hst-
10 The Forgiveness of Sins (Edinburgh:
Cf. E. B. Redlich,
T. &T. Clark, 1937), pp. 294-295.
11
Critique of Practical Reason, tr. by T. K. Abbott (Long-
mans, Green & Co., Inc., 1923), p. 176.
—
Love Is Not Liking 107
you love those w^ho love you, v^^hat rew^ard have you?"
What more, that is to say, do you accomplish with philic
love than anybody else? Friendship, romance, self-realiza-
tion —all these loves are reciprocal. Agape is not. It seeks
start, at least, with love. Given the will, philia finds a way,
discovers a reason to follow love. But when and if this
happens, the feeling side is secondary —
one of love's
dividends.
Where were there ever more unlovable men than those
who stood around the cross of Jesus, yet he said, "Forgive
them"? Paul gave this its cosmic statement: "While we
were yet sinners Christ died for us" (Rom. 5:8). Non-
reciprocity and nondesert apply even to affection-love:
Reuel Howe explains why "my child, your child, needs
love most when he is most unlovable. "^^ Good medical
care prescribes "t.l.c." (tender loving care) every hour
on the hour, whether doctors and nurses like the patient
or not.
An egoistic ethic (erotic) says in efiEect, "My first and
last consideration is myself." This is the essence of an
exploitive stance; it is "what makes Sammy run." A
mutualistic ethic (philic) says, "I will give as long as I
1953), p. 87.
110 SITUATION ETHICS
^^ The Works
of Love, tr. by D. F. and L. M. Swenson
(Princeton University Press, 1946), p. 17.
^^Ibid., p. 19.
19
"Morals of the Catholic Church," 26:49, loo cit.
20
"The Freedom of the Christian," in Luther's Works,
Vol. 31, tr. by Harold J. Grimm (Concordia-Muhlenberg
Press, 1957), pp. 367, 371.
21
The Mind and Heart of Love, p. 29 et seq.
112 SITUATION ETHICS
from (1) love of self for self's sake, to (2) love of God,
yet still for self's sake, to ( 3 ) love of God for God's sake,
to (4) love of self, once more, but this time for God's
sake and not one's own.^^ In the same way, surely, we
can see how it is possible, by a parallel, to ascend the
ladder of neighbor-love: from (1) love of ourself for
our own sake, to (2) love of our neighbor for our own
sake, to (3) love of neighbor for the neighbor's sake, to
(4) love of ourself again, but now for the right reason,
i.e., for the neighbor's sake.
The meaning of this is, in a real way, that the Christian
takes Aristotle's ideal of self-realization (self-nurture)
seriously, but for the sake of his neighbors whom he will
thereby be more fully able to serve, to whose welfare he
may more solidly contribute. Better a trained man than a
dolt, better for everybody.
But the problem of tragedy still haunts us, even if we
(reader and author) are still together after the last flight
22 On the Love of God (De diligendo Deo} newly tr. by a
Religious of C.S.M.V. (Morehouse-Gorham, Inc., 1950),
pp. 56-69.
Love Is Not Liking 113
hate the sinner but it hates the sin, to use an old but
fundamentally true bromide. This is w^hy Augustine said,
right after his reduction of Christian ethics to a loving
will: "Love can be angry, charity can be angry, with a
kind of anger in which there is no gall, like the dove's and
not the raven's. "^^
Again, to love is not necessarily to please. Agape is not
gratification. It has often been remarked that the golden
rule should read, "Do unto others as they would have you
do unto them" —that its classic form, "as you would have
them do unto you" is self -centered, cutting its cloth
according to what you want rather than what the neighbor
wants. But to accept this revision would be too close to
"disinterested" love; it would be neutral love, which is too
close to indifference. For agape is concerned for the neigh-
bor, ultimately, for God's sake; certainly not for the self's,
but not even for the neighbor's ovm sake only. Christian
love, for example, cannot give heroin to an addict just
because he wants it. Or, at least, if the heroin is given,
it will be given as part of a cure. And the same with
all pleas —
sex, alms, food, anything. All parents know
this.
With the development of computers all sorts of analyt-
ical ethical possibilitiesopen up. Legalism could find little
of interest in it but situation ethics does. Once we laughed
at Raimon Lull's medieval Ars major, an arithmetic, sure-
fire device for getting answers to theological questions.
It is said that followers of his in the "Lullian Science"
contrived a barrel device to revolve after fixing clock
pointers, so that a whirl of the barrel, like the spin of a
26 "Seventh Homily on the First Epistle General of St.
VII
old end will justify any old means. We all assume that
some ends justify some means; no situationist would make
a universal of it! Being pragmatic, he always asks the
price and supposes that in theory and practice everything
has its price. Everything, please note. Even a "pearl of
great price" —whatever it is — might be sold for love's
sake if the situation calls for it.
If our loyalty goes more fully to the end we seek than
to the means we use, as it should, then the means must be
appropriate and faithful to the end. We ought not to
forget Thomas Aquinas' warning that means are proximate
ends, and that therefore the means we employ will enter
into theend sought and reached, just as the flour and
milk and raisins we use enter into the cake we bake.
Means are ingredients, not merely neutral tools, and we
122 SITUATION ETHICS
(1) A
Scottish woman saw that her suckling baby, ill and
crying, was betraying her and her three other children,
and the whole company, to the Indians. But she clung to
her child, and they were caught and killed. (2) A Negro
woman, seeing how her crying baby endangered another
trail party, killed it with her own hands, to keep silence
and reach the fort. Which woman made the right
decision?
We have already seen, in the discussion of our first
proposition, that love only is always good, and that the
neighbor-love!)
Therefore, in the relativities of this world where con-
science labors to do the right thing, we may always do
what would be evil in some contexts if in this circumstance
love gains the balance. It is love's business to calculate
gains and losses, and to act for the sake of its success.
On this ground, then, we must
oppose the classical
flatly
means-ends rule in Christian ethics and moral theology.
12 The Theology
of Emil Brunner, ed. by C. W. Kegley
(The Macmillan Company, 1962), p. 255.
12 F. J. Connell, in American Ecclesiastical Review, Vol.
CXLII (1960), pp. 132-133.
Love Justifies Its Means 133
does not exist ante rem, before or apart from the facts as
lived, but in rebus —
in the lived event itself. And so with
the good! Several years ago Congress passed a special
bill giving citizenship to a Roumanian Jewish doctor, a
woman, who had aborted three thousand Jewish women
brought to the concentration camp. If pregnant, they were
to be incinerated. Even accepting the view that the
embryos were "human lives" (which many of us do not),
by "kilhng" three thousand the doctor saved three thousand
and prevented the murder of six thousand!
If, for example, the emotional and spiritual welfare of
the parents and children in a particular family could best
be served by a divorce, then, wrong and cheap-jack as
divorce often is, love justifies a divorce. Love's method is
to judge by particularity, not to lay down laws and uni-
versals. It does not preach pretty propositions; it asks
concrete questions, situation questions. Getting a divorce
is sometimes like David's eating the reserved Sacrament;
Wanted: A System
Too many people an ethical system of
at heart long for
prefabricated, pretailored morality. They want
to lean on
strong, unyielding rules. It was all very well, they com-
plain, for Paul to say that living by law is like slavery
(Gal. 4:21-26), "but after all, we aren't St. Pauls."
Even he did say that those who stick to the law are no
if
1 Ethics,
pp. 84 fF.
136 SITUATION ETHICS
because they are too petty or too rigid to fit the facts of
hfe. Many people prefer to fit reahty to rules rather than
to fit rules to reality. Legalism always bears down hard
on the need for order, putting its premium on obedience
to law, even statutory law. It would, if it could, immobihze
Martin Luther King and the sit-in demonstrators or civil
rights protesters, whereas situation ethics gives high-order
value to freedom, and to that responsibility for free de-
cision which is the obverse side of the coin of freedom.
In ethics as in pohtics we can see that ideology has come
to a dead end. Doctrinaire by-the-book theory and practice
is too confining, too narrow. "The point is," says Daniel
Fanatic Virtue
As the old adage has it, "Virtue never goes out of style,"
i.e., the disposition toward honor, chastity, loyalty, pa-
tience, humility, and all the rest. But situations change.
There another old saying, Semper sed non ad semper
is
and the moral order, with love in the driver's seat, always
takes first place whenever the fit is lacking. Love can
even love law, if law knows its place and takes the back
seat. Legal rights are subordinate, and so are legal prohibi-
Love Decides There and Then 145
Postscriptum: Why?
thinks not.
A Neocasuistry
The Situations-ethik more and more openly wins a
place in nonfundamentalist Protestant ethics. It is sparking
or cultivating a kind of neocasuistry. Occasionally leading
Protestant writers take issue with the relativism of the
method, but this appears to be a mood objection rather
than genuinely critical. Two such moralists in America,
John Bennett and Daniel Williams, have made the mistake
of thinking that the situational method procedurally is
tragedy is that we
often find ourselves in situations of
ethical inscrutahilia and imponderahilia, like the destroyer
commander in Monsarrat's novel The Cruel Sea, when he
had whether to drop a depth charge that would
to decide
be sure hundreds of desperate seamen struggling
to kill
in the icy waters of the North Atlantic. He had a hope but
no certainty that he would also destroy the U-boat on the
sea floor, waiting there to destroy other ships and men
in the convoy. As the CO. said, there are times when aU
we can do is guess our best, and then get down on our
knees and ask God's mercy. Monsarrat draws us a perfect
picture of Luther's pecca fortiter!
Allergic to Law
chology, for example, got its start and growth this way.
The same is true in many other sectors of the growing
Sacrificial Adultery
three years, maybe less, that only a miracle can save me.
They can only give me some stuff that will keep me ahve
a while. can leave here tomorrow but can't do any work,
I
just rest and take
pills." After a pause he added: 'The
pills cost $40 about every three days. Who can afford
that? They say if I stop them, then six months and I've
had it."
170 INDEX
64, 70, 71-74, 77-78, Christ. See Jesus
85, 91, 107, 125, 134 Christians, 20, 31, 33, 88
Birth control, 34, 122, 126, Chrysostom, 129
131, 139 Churchill, Winston, 167
Bitter Choice, The, 116 Cicero, 77
Black, Max, 48 Clarke, Samuel, 28
Bonhoeffer, Dietrich, 28, 33, Cobb, John B., 46
38, 42, 58, 74-75, 80, CofiFee, T. P., 35
98, 149, 157-158 Coggan, F. D., 104
Bornkamm, Giinther, 74 Cohen, Morris, 41
Bretall,R. W., 61 Commandment, the Great,
Brightman, Edgar S., 58 27, 38, 45, 55, 74, 77,
Brothers Karamazov, The, 81 96, 110 fF., 125
Bruckberger, Raymond, 141 Commandments, the Ten, 22,
Brunner, Emil, 27, 33, 45, 31 ff., 146
55, 58, 66, 70, 77, 93- Communists, 74, 115
94, 103, 131, 142, 148- Community (society), 50,
149 83, 89 ff.
172 INDEX
Goethe, J. W. von, 52 Huxley, Thomas, 138
Golden rule, the, 117 Hypocrisy, 106
Good (right), the, 13, 27,
32-33, 50, 54, 59, 65, Ibsen, Henrik, 141
133, 144 Ideology, 24, 137
Good Samaritan laws, 82 Idolatry, 25, 31, 72, 160
Goodwill, 63, 105 Importance of Being Earnest,
Grace, 48, 52, 84, 152 The, 118
Greeks, the, 42, 52, 68, 107 Indifference, 63, 82
Green, T. H., 49 Individualism, 50, 91, 160
'
INDEX 173