Ackermann's Set Theory
Ackermann's Set Theory
Ackermann's Set Theory
1 8 9 - 2 4 9
William N,REINHARDT
Boulder. Colorado
Section 0
! ritroduction
* This paper contains a major part of the author's doctoral dissertation. 1 wish to thank the fol-
lowing people for helpful conversations eoncc'.ning this work: R.L.Vaught, my thesis advisor
(who also brougl~t to my attention most of fl~e y~ ~blems considered), J.Malitz, A.Levy, and
J.Silver. I also xvish to thank the Danforth Foundation for encouragement and support. Part
of this work was supported by NSF grants, including GP 12209, GP 7387.
190 A ct,'ermaml "s set thcorr equcls ZF
A1. (Extensionality)
Vz A t ( t ~ z * - - ~ t ~ V ^ ® ) ,
-* V z ~ V A t ( t E z ÷ ~ O ( x , y , t))
where the free variables of 0 are x, ~', t, and V does not occur in O.
x~V^Vu(u~x)
--, Vt~(u ~ x / x A t ( t ~ x -, t q~ , ) ) .
erty 't is a set such that ,;(,v, y, t)' is in a certain sense independent of
the (extension of t h e ) c o n c e p t of set, and may be regarded as giving a
sufficient condition for a collection to be sharply delimited. (A further
dis,,:ussion of these ideas is contained in Section 5.~
Tile intuitive ideas leading to Ackermann's theory are thus seen to
be quite different from those which lead to Zermelo-Fraenkel se~
theory (ZF). In that theory, of course, there are a number of set con-
struction principles, and there is an appeal to the intuitive principle
that a collection which is equivalent in power to a set must be a set.
Thus it is not obvious how the two theories compare.
It should bc remarked that the construction !~rinciples of ZF were
originally fornmlated to reflect the practice of mathematicians; rather
than starting from first principles and deriving set theory, one started
with set theory (a'- it had been developed historically) and tried to find
principles adequate to develop th,: theory which did not yield the
known paradoxes: no attempt was made to provide a philosophical
explanation of the source of the principles, or a clarification of their
intuitive basis (see E.Zemaelo 12! l P. 26t, 262). For a contemporary
discussion of intuitive ideas which, provide a basis for Zermelo's axiom's,
see Kreisel 122], pp. 100-105.
Much of the work that has been done on Ackermann's theory has
been directed toward comparing A and ZF.
thus showing that A* gives us no more information about the sets than
ZF does. These results were also proved (with appropriate modifications)
for Aoo. Levy proved a number of theorems within A, and in particular
showed that a strong reflection principle holds in A*. Thus Levy showed
that (the relativizations to V of) very strong theorems of ZF could be
proved in A*, and he raised the question whether the converse of (1)
holds.
(1II) Levy and Vaught [10l developed the theory of A* further, show-
ing that still larger classes of (the relativizations to V of) tt'eorems of
ZF could be proved in A*.
(IV) In his thesis [6], R.Grewe succeeded in obtaining a partial con-
verse to (1): he showed that in every natural model (R/3, c, Rc~>of A,
(R0~, e) ~ ZF (thus answering Levy's question for the case of natural
models of A*). This result is included in the paper [6a].
Grewe also introduced a methof of interpreting extensions of A within
A.
(V) Levy [ 10] showed that (the relativization to V of) the complete
reflection schema of ZF (which may be used instead of the replacement
schema in axiomatizing ZF) holds for A 1t formulas (in t.he hierarchy of
formulas developed in [ 101 .)
0.2. Results
The main result of this paper is t~le converse of (1):
This, in conjunction with (1), shows that A* and ZF give the same in-
formation about sets, and answer; the question of Levy mentioned
above. It should perhaps be remarked that the proofs of both ( l ) and
(2) are finitary, Recall that Ackermann originally stated that the re-
placement schema of ZF (relativized to V) can be proved in A. Notice
that (2) establishes this with A replaced by A*, i.e. assuming the axiom
In trod~tc tion 193
If F is any finite set of formulas involving only ~ and having one flee
variable x, and q, is one such formula, then
A /~ AXE V lO v ~ 0 v'] ).
~-~ E !:
r e t i c a l l y ) e q u i v a l e n t to y in case t h e r e is a f l m c t i o n ) " : x ~ .v w h i c h is
1 -- 1 and o n t o y . We say x is transitive iff y ~ z ~ x implies y ~ x. We
d e f i n e o r d i n a l s in t h e usual w a y as transitive sets w h i c h are well o r d e r e d
u n d e r t h e e r e l a t i o n : the n a t u r a l n u m b e r s are the o r d i n a l s w h i c h in addi-
t i o n are well o r d e r e d by t h e c o n v e r s e r e l a t i o n . We let w be t h e set o f all
n a t u r a l n u m b e r s : t h e e m p t y set 0 is t h e first n a t u r a l n u m b e r . If u, 13 are
ordinals, c~ +/3 is t h e o r d i n a l s u m o f u and/3, a n d we w r i t e a < / 3 for
~ ~, o~ </3 f o r o~ </3 o r ~ =/3. An o r d i n a l is called a c a r d i n a l in case it
is n o t e q u i v a l e n t to a n y smaller ordinal. A f u n c t i o n w h o s e d o m a i n is a
n a t u r a l n u m b e r is called a finite s e q u e n c e . I f / ' i s a f u n c t i o n , t h e n
.f()i> = ( . f ~ { (.x,.fx> } ) u {O,', .v> }. If a is an o r d i n a l a n d t h e r e is a f'anc-
tion .f s u c h t h a t for every/3 < a a n d an3 t, t ~ ,f/3 iff for s o m e 3' ~ 13.
t c .t7, t h e n we w r i t e Ro~ =/ix (= sets o f :~'ank < c~). We w r i t e R a + n = R ( a + n ) .
0 . 4 . 5 ) ' n t u c t i c a l n o ta tioll
We will be c o n c e r n e d w i t h first o r d e r language w i t h variables
v o, v I . . . . . t h e usual !ogical s y m b o l s =, ~ , A, a n d A, p r e d i c a t e s y m b o l s ,
o p e r a t i o n s y m b o l s , a n d individual c o n s t a n t s , t o g e t h e r w i t h t h e usual
rules o f f o r m a t i o n . O u r p r i m a r y c o n c e r n will be w i t h a l a n g u a g e w i t h
o n e b i n a r y p r e d i c a t e s y m b o l e (we w r i t e e~--e o r e = ~ if it will c a u s e
n o c o n f u s i o n ) , a n d o n e individual c o n s t a n t V. In t h e a b s e n c e o f indica-
tion to t h e c o n t r a r y , (9, ,,, q, will be f o r m u l a s , a n d ( t o simpli;'y n o t a -
t i o n ) ,c, y , z,/3 . . . . will be r e s p e c t i v e l y t h e variables v 0, v 1 , .... In t h e
usual w a y , we will w r i t e -(9/~ ~ f o r t h e c o n j u n c t i o n o f (9 w i t h ~', ~ (3
for t h e n e g a t i o n o f ®, etc. Also we will w r i t e A u E v(9 f o r A u ( u ~ v -~
0 ) , u. v ~ w for u ~ w A v e w, etc. I f O a . . . . , 0 . _ 1 are f o r m u l a s , t h e n
/Ik ~bn, will be t h e cot~iunction 0 0 A...A ( 9 , ~ : similarly f o r t h e dis-
m E n
t e r m , b,: O(,,
- " ) we u n d e r s t a n d t h e f o r m u l a o b t a i n e d f r o m O b y r e p l a c i n g
all free o c c u r r e n c e s o f it b y v, a n d c h a n g i n g t h e b o u n d variables o f ,I, t o
avoid collisions if n e c e s s a r y (all o c c u r r e n c e s o f an individual c o n s t a n t
are free o c c u r r e n c e s ) . We m a k e t h e c o n v e n t i o n t h a t if x 0, x l , -.., x n - l
are terms., O ( x 0, ..,, x , I ) will be t h e s i m u l t a n e o u s substittation o f
x 0 , •.... ~,z-l f o r v 0, ..., o , l r e s p e c t i v e l y (again c h a n g i n g b o u n d
variables if n e c e s s a r y ) . By t h e f o r m u l a O ~ we u n d e r s t a n d t h e f o r m u l a
196 Ackermann 's set theory equals ZF
O A Ao'(O(o°,) -* o = o')
VzAt(t~z ~ ; t~x^O)
A u V!t~o -* V z A t ( t E z ~ V u E x~o)
Introduction 19 7
A x V y V r ( R n O ' , r) Ax ~ r) ;
VzAt(t~z~-,t$,x AO y )
,.~( ~ o [x t i f f ,~, ~ ~ [ x l .
,Section 1
c. So(x) is
Cp(x) A ( A y , z ) ( z ~ y A v ~ x ~ z E x )
d. Ord(x) is
^ (Au, v ~ x ) ( V w C_ x ) A t ( t ~ w ~ t ~ u A t ~ v)
'X is an ordinal'.
e. Db(x, y, z) is
At(tEz ~ ~ t=xvt=y)
f. Oc(x, y, z) is
(Vv, w G z)(Db(x, x, o) A Db(x, y, w)A Db(v, w, z))
o Rl(x v , z ) is
V v(Oc(x, y, v,' ,, v E- z)
h. Rn(x, y )is
R n k ( x , y, z ) is
A u ( u ~ x ~ V ~ Rl(u, v, z)) A
i. lira(x) is
Ord(x) A A t ( t E x -~ V u ( t ~ u 6 x))
T I - U v 0A Uv I ^...A U ~ _ l - + l O + - - , O U] ,
Ax A t ( U x ^ (t c_ x v t ~ x) -~ U t ) .
T I-- A x A t ( U x A (t C_ X V t ~ X) -* U t ) .
Sc U I- Db(x, y, z) A Uz -* Ux A Uy
Sc U I- Rl(x, y, z) A Uz ~ Ux z U y ,
Corollary 1.4. The f o r m u l a s c_, Cp, Sc, Ord, Db, Oc, RI, Rnk, and lim
are absolute.
A b Vx Ux At(te x ~ t e VA O r d I t ) ) ;
A P Uc~ A t ( t ~ c~ ~ t e V ^ Ord(t)) .
T h e o r e m 1.6.
a. H Rn(x y ) - ~ S o ( y ) ,
b. k- Rn(x. y ) ^ x ' ex ~ u ' ( R n ( x ' , y ' ) ^ y' e y ) ,
c. A 2 i - R n ( x , y ) A x C- V - ~ x C _ y ,
d. A t-- Ord (c~),
e. A t - A x ( O r d ( ~ ) - * x e a v x = ~ v a e x ) ,
f. A I - - A x e ~ v v~VRn(x,y),
g. A ~- A x < a ( O r d ( x ) ~ V y C V U y R n ( x , y ) ) ,
O
A u , v c_ x V w c x A t ( t e w ~ t e u A t ( ~ ~)
in the d e f i n i t i o n o f Ord.
202 Ackermmm "s set theory equals ZF
T h e o r e m 1.7. (Levy).
a. (Non-definability o f ~)
AI--~[y~VAUs®(~,y)] ,
A O(~,y)A "" V X E ~ O ( x , y ) ] .
Vz V r [ R n ( x , r ) Az ~ rA O ( z , y ) ] ,
A* F- Rn(e~, V)
and
A t- A x ¢ c~ V y e V U y Rn(x, .v)).
Remark. One can easily see that replacing the schema A4 by the reflec-
tion principle for V yields an alternative axiomatization o f A* (see Levy-
Vaught [1 l l , p. 1057).
so evidently 1 ) follows.
Vz ~ V Ate V [ t ~ z ~-~ Vu ~ x ~ o ] .
Theorem 1.11. Let T be a theory (in the language with e) such that
A * I T v , (i.e., for every sentence o, T t- o implies A* I- o V ) a n d let 0 be
any e-formula who,~.e only free variable is x.
N o w if O isabsolute over A* and valid in T (i.e., A* I- A x
E v [ o V ( x ) ~ , O(x)] a n d T ~ A x ® ( x ) ) , d w n A* I- ®(cx).
which follows from (the contrapositive of) the reflection principle for
(l.7b).
Definition 1.13.
a. Ct(x, y, z) is
b. G(x, y, z, w) is
A t [ t E w ,--> ( O c ( y , z , t ) v
c. F ' ( x , y , z ) is
Vu(Ct(y, z, u)^ x ~ u) ^
d. Nn(x) is
e. Ffx, y ) is
Vz(Nn(z) ^ F'(x, z, y ) ) ,
Theorem 1.14.
a. The f o l l o w i n g are p r o v a b l e in A*:
1. x , y E V - ~ Vz~VUzCt(x,y,z),
2. x , y , z E V -+ V w -~ V U w G ( x , y , z, w ) ,
3. N n ( x ) ~ x ~ V ,
4. V z ~ V Uz A t ( t ~ z ~. ; N n ( t ) ) ,
5. y , z E V A F ' ( x , y , Z ) - > x E V ,
6. y c _ V A F ( x , y ) - - > x a V .
and
2) G ( x , y , z, w ) A G ( x , y , z , w')--> w = w' .
It is easy to check that the formula in 1) is absolute: F, Rn, and lira are
absolutc (by a3, 1.4, and 1.8), A* I--- Rn(/3, y) -~/3 ~ y, and (by a3, a5,
a~ad the definition of F) A* t-- F(x, y) Ay ~ V - 3- ~ V, so Lemma 1.3
applies. Thus Theorem 1.1 1 applies and we have
A* I- A t ( t ~ Co, , N n ( t ) ) ,
A*I-- A t ( t ~ A o ~ t ¢ t) ,
208 Ackermann 's set theory equals ZF
A* I- x , y ~ V ^ Uz RI(y, z, x)-* V a l ( x , y ) = z .
Section 2
(Sat(a. A , z) ~ soz )
210 A ckermann 's set theory c ( r~clt ZF
where F', ¢0, ~p, and ~1 are absolute. Now Sat is easily seen to be ab-
solute using Lemma 1.3 and the following fact:
4) A* H n , z ~ V A ~I,(s, n, z)-* s e V .
A * H n, z ~ V A q , ( s , n , z ) ~ s~ V,
As(q,(s, n, z) -~ s ~ V)
S a t ( x , y , z)A z 6 V ~ x , y 6 V .
Remark. This is the last vague definition, All remaining definitions are
given precisely in terms of Sat and ZF. In particular all that is needed in
Section 3 is that there are e-formulas Sat and ZF such that Theorem
2.12 holds.
2) (RT, e, Re) N A x , y ( x E y E V - - , x E V ) ,
3) x, y E V A Au ~ x V! t E V cv (u, t, y ) ,
where the free variables of ~p(tt, t, y) are anaong tl, t, y. Now we fix x, y
satisfyipg 3). Applying 1 ) to ¢, we see
SO
consequently
5) VuCxs0V(u,t,y)~ tE z E V .
Sketch of Proof. (See Grewe [61 for a detailed proof.) Assume tim
hypothesis and let 3' be chosen as in the theorem. Evidently the choice
of 3' assures that the schema
1) x 0 . . . . . Xn_ 1 E V A O r d ( f ) A U 6 0 ( 5 ) ~ 5 EV
V u 0 - ~ V6U~5[ Vu V r ( R n ( 6 , r ) A u ~ r A O ) A
D(x, y) formalizes "x is definable in (Ry, e> using paran ;ers from
Rx'.
Proof, To see that E, Modzv, S, UzS, and D are absolute, apply the
lemma on absoluteness of section I, making use of the tbllowing facts:
1. Sat, Rn, ZF, and G are absolute.
216 Ackermann's set theory equals ZF
2. A* I-- Z F ( x ) ~ x ~ V .
3. A* i - x ~ V v Sat(a, ~0, x ) ~ a , ¢ ~ V.
4. A* t-- Rn(x, r) ^ x E V --> r ~ V .
5. A* I-- S ( x , y , z , u ) ~ z ~ u .
Theorem 2.11.
a. Z + I- a ~ ~ ^ E(a, t3) --> Vr[ R n ( e , r) A MOdzF (r)l ;
Theorem 2.12.
a. A* t-- A x ( x ~ a A ~ D(x, a ) - V r I R n ( x , r ) A MOdzF(r)]) •
Section 3
The implication from right to left was proved by Levy [8] (for a
sketch of the proof see Theorem 4.18); we will prove the reverse impli-
cation. We begin with an important lemma. Recall that U/3O says tha t/3
is the unique/3 such that O. In other words, that/3 is defined by O (in
terms of the parameters of 0).
2) a, ~ e V ^ UaS(a, ¢, a, t3).
N o w the h y p o t h e s i s in L e m m a 3.2 is
3) x e V^ U~O(3, x).
4) x, a, ~0 e X, ^ Us Vt~(O(¢~, x) ^ S(a, ~, a, ~ ) ) ,
X O, . . . , Xn__ 1
e V ^ ,I, (t3) ^ Ord(13) A U~O(/3) ~ t3 e V ,
(U E o)Q = U ~ o , (~ o ) Q = ' ~ (O Q ) ,
Notice that the free variables o f ®Q are the same as those o f O, and
t h a t o Q is an e-formula.
A* 1-- q , ( ~ ) .
( R e c a l l t h a t ~ is an indn, i d u a l c o n s t a n t i n t r o d t t c e d so t,,~at
A* I- A x ( x ~ ~ ~ ~ O r d ( x ) A x e V).)
x~ V ^ Ut~O(t3, x ) - * a :~ ~ ,
where we make use o f the clause 'Ord(/3)' which appears in the defini-
tion o f D F * . ) E v i d e n t l y the Lemma 3.2 applies, so ~ D(0~,/3) and we
obtain the Corollary 3.7.
w I ( t
A x E x[ ~ D(x , x ) -~ V r ( R m x , r) A MOdzF(r))] . ,;
By Theoiem 2.12a, we see that A* i-- q'(a), so both lemmas (3.6, 3.7)
apply. The essential point here is that a is quite well behaved in the
e-part o f :~he theory A*, even though (fc, r example) Zennelo's theory Z
does not hold for the classes of A. Evidently by 3.7 and our choice of
q', for each instance o of DF* we have
A* + ~ o k- MOdzF (Ra)
1) A*+~o I-o~ .
On the other hand, using 3.6 and the weak replacement schema 1.1 O,
we see that for each axiom o 0 of ZF
3) x , y ~ VA A s ~ V V t ~ V[~oV (x, y , s, t) ^
-~ V z ~ V A ~ V ( t ~ z < . ~ Vs~x~oV(x,y,s,t)).
A* t- o v ,
w h i c h is the assertion o f T h e o r e m 3. !.
w h e r e x is the e-formula
A = {3 ~ o~ " ×(3)} .
N o w A ~ 0, so since O r d ( a ) t h e r e is a m i n i m a l m e m b e r ~ o f A . Using
basic p r o p e r t i e s o f ordinals, o n e easily sees t h a t this # satisfies
Evidently
~ V ^ Vr Vu[u ~ r ^ R n ( # , r ) ^ O l .
P r o o f o f L e m m a 3.6. L e m m a 3.6 is n o w i m m e d i a t e f r o m t h e s u b l e m m a
(3.8) by i n d u c t i o n o n f o r m u l a s . We discuss o n l y t h e case w h e r e
(9 = Vu,p. By i n d u c t i o n we m a y a s s u m e
-~ [ Vu ~ v ( ¢ Q ) , ,, Qu(¢Q)I
(by 3.8!, alld hence (by the definitions of 19v and O Q) we have
T + DF I- A x e V[6) v +--~-~9] .
This is because in T
v ~ V ,\ VxO(x, y) -~ Qx-O(x, y) ;
{/3' e ~3 : V r V x ( R n ( f J ' , r ) ^ x e r ^ ® ) } ) .
tn ~ ti
Proof. Since
A*P-VyEV W A x E V [ O v ~ >%nl ,
m E n
evidently
A'P- Vy~VVuEVAxEV(O v, ;
so if we take (9(x, z) to be
Vu, y ( O c ( u , Y , Z ) ^ W [u =A m ^ % n ( x , y ) ] )
m En
Section 3 227
1) A * + D F ve D A x ~ - V [ O v ~ - ~ ® e ] .
A*I--( W ~Om)V /~ om
m ~ n m ~ ~t
where the free variables o f O,n ([3, y ) are/3 and y. We will argue infor-
mally within A*. Assuming 1 ), e v i d e n t l y L e m m a 3.2 applies, se we have
o~ ~ ~ A ~ D(e~,/3). We c o n c l u d e using q~(~) that there are ¢, a, and "~
such that ~, a ,.=-V and either
or else
) = / 3 A A X E Ro~[® Ra ~ O R~t ] ,
so that eithe~-
or else
A* -t-~ o
m
t-- W V y ~ V A x E V [ O v , , e r ai 1
i
Corollary 3.11. Let F be a finite set o f e-Jbrmulas with one free variable
x, and q, one such formula. Then
Section 3 229
-~ V z A t ( t e z ~ O(t, x, y ) ) ,
Section 4
h e n c e as T t--- tg(V),
T t- AX ~ o~ ¢(RX) ;
Now by i),
Vz At(t ~t z ~ , t ~ V=,^ O)
x, y ~ V,, ^ A t ( ~ ( t . x. y ) ~ t ~ V,,)
Vz e V At(t e z ~ ¢ ( t , x . v'D
A6' Vn C
- V,~ +I c- Voo (fornEco).
T h e o r e m 4.4. Aoo m a y be a x i o m a t i z e d by
A ( V , ) all sentences ~(V,,) such that ¢ ( V ) is an a x i o m o f A (where
A6 Vn ~ V +1 EVoo (wherenEco).
Proof. Evidently A,,o yields AI(V,,)= AI, A3(V,:), A4(V,z), and (using
A6') A 2 ( V , ) for each n < o~. To see that A6 holds, in A4' take t ~ V m
for ~ and m + 1 for n. and conclude (using V ~ ~ V m + 1 ) that
V m E V m + j . By A3'. V m+l E V ~ also, so A-3 holds.
In the o t h e r direction, A I , A2', ~3' are assumed, and A6' follows
t ,
from A6 using A3'. Now it is easy to see that A4 ( V , ) yields A4 n ,
t
A6 assures that the parameters Vi, i E n may occur in the ¢ of A4 n .
P r o o f . E v i d e n t l y A* b o i m p l i e s A * I- o. Let ¢ be a f o r m u l a w i t h one
free variable x, and suppose that ~(V) is provable in A * . Then by the
preceding t h e o r e m , there is a formula O with one free variable x such
that A * b O ( V ) and
(where A* I-- O(V), and n ~ co). ( N o w o 0 plays the role o f V~o, % that
o f V 1.) The p r o o f is by i n d u c t i o n on n. Assume the result for m . and
let "4, be the existential closure o f 1) (taking n = m). Then the induction
hypothesis yields
A* I-- q,(V)
4.2. N a t u r a l m o d e l s o f A.
We now proceed to some rer.aarks on natural models o f A.
Definition 4.6. Let o~,/3 be ordinals, n ~ a ~/3. We write Ra -< R¢3 iff for
It
Remark. Ra -< R/3 iff Ra <: R/3, and Ra -< R/3 means that R/3 is a 2nd
0 1
order extension o f Ro~. We could as well write
(y,O) E Xn Ra iff ( R a + n , e ) p 0 [ y ]
iff (R~+n,e)~0[yl ,
(R/~ + n, e, R a ) ~ A .
1) xE Ra^O(x,a)-* Vy~aO(x,y)
x, y E a implies x + y E ot
2) ( R ~ + n , e ) l= A [ x , n ] iff x e ~ .
holds in <Rt3 + n, e> (here Xo, ..., x m_) exhaust the free variables of ~o).
Evidently (by 2))
so 2) yields
is a well ordering of A.
Proof. To simplify the discussion we assume n = 1 ; all the ideas are con-
tained in this case.
It is enough to see that for every e-formula O (with one free variable)
and every X c R~, we have
holds in (Re + 1, e> w h e n x takes the value X. (Here we use the defina-
bility oft3 in (P,43 + 1, e); in the general case e n e can use the definability
o f # in (Rt3 + n, e, n>.) Let ",I,( x ) b e the formula displayed in 2). Then
since ~, well orders Re + 1 in R/3 + 1,
holds in ( R/3 + 1, e), and hence (since Re -< R/3) in <Ra + 1, e> ,also. Let
1
X' be the subset o f Re defined by 3) in (Re + 1, e), and X be the subset
of R/3 defined by 3) in ( R~ + 1, e). Since Re -< R/3, for each x ~ Ra we
1
have
x ~ X' iff x ~ X .
Question 4.13. Let o~, fl be ordinals. Suppose that for every x ~ Ra, a is
not definable in (R~3 + 1, e, x). Is there a 7 <- # such that a ~ ~, and
Ro~ -< R3,?
l
Theorem 4.9 shows (assuming there are various indescribable cardi-
nals) that we can have a wide variety o f ordinals a, # such that
(R#, e, R~) ~ A but not Ra --- R~. The methods of proof do not seem
to answer the following question, however.
Question 4.14. Suppose that a,/3, ~, are ordinals,/3 ~ 7 and R/3 -< RT,
and for every x ~ Ra, o~ is not definable in ( R/3, e, x). Does it follow
that Ra -< R/3?
1) x ~ V 0 - , [O v o ~ e v~]
A I - x ~_v-* [O v ~ ~ 0 ]
Question 4.15. How large is the first ordir.al 3' such that there are
ordinals a i, i ~ ~ for which i < / - + ai < e / a n d
[ 161, p. 78), then it is easy to see that 7 satisfies 3). (Silver's condition
is satisfied if 3' is a measvrable cardinal.) But the condition 3) is prob-
ably quite weak.
4.4. Q u e s t i o n s a b o u t f i n i t e axio.matizability.
Next we consider some questions about ffinite axiomatizability.
In most cases where we have a proof that a theory T is not finitely
axiomatizable over a theory S, the methods of proof yield a stronger
result, namely that if S c_ T' c_ T and T' is finitely axiomatizable over S,
then the consistency of T' is provable in T. (Of course a precise formu-
lation of the stronger result is sensitive to the way ' I " is consistent' is
expressed.) I would like to mention some examples of theories T, S
such that the consistency of S is not provable in I-, but it appears likely
that T is not finitely axiomatizable over S.
Conjecture 4.16.
a. A + Z is not finitely axiomatizable over A.
b. A + ZF is not finitely axi~matizable over A.
The weak comprehension schema of' Z - was introduced and studied
by Tarski. He showed that Z is essentially not finitely axiomatizable
over Z - , and that Z- is finitely axiomatizable (unpublished). I do not
even know whether A + Z- I-- Z. Of course b implies a. We can make
some conjectures even stronger than b. For this we need some defini-
tions.
reflection:
x,y~V~[ov ,--~O]
Theorem 4.18.
a. F o r e-selztences o, ZA I-- o i l l Z F t- o.
b. Ac_ZA.
Conjecture 4.20.
ZA is not finitely axiomatizable over A + DF.
The last example seems in some sense more elementary. The theories
have infinite similarity type, but this defect may be removed by simply
considering the e-part of the theories.
Section 5
This section has two parts. The first part extends the main result o f
Section 3 to certain extensions of ZF and A. The second contains an
analysis of the intuitive ideas behind Ackermann's theory. This ana2ysis
suggests the introduction of an extension A + of A.
e0 x~VAAu~x Vo~VRl(u,o,r)-+
VyEVAu~x Vo~y Rl(u,v,r)
Theorem 5.2.
A~l--o v iff Z M | - o .
It is enough to show that for any finite set F of axioms of ZA, we can
show
Section 5 245
Now the axioms of ZA are A1, instances of the schema A2, A3, and in-
stances of the complete reflection schema
3) Ax E V(Ov , . , O)
But now Corollary 3.11 allows us tc :hoose V' so that V E V' and
Sc(V') and any finite number of instances of 4) hold. This establishes
2) and hence 1).
Now evidently A~ c ZA + e 0, so if A~ l- ov then ZM I-- o. If
ZM I- o, then ZA I- e 0 -~ ov . By 1), we then have
and since
A*t-V~V'ASc(V')-~[%-~e ]^[(ov) v ~o vl ,
3) At(~o(t) ~ t ~ V 0)
then
so that we have by 2)
K t ( ¢ ( t ) ~ t ~ V o) ~ Vz ~ V o A t ( t ~ z ~ ~ ~o(t)),
i) x, yC_ V ^ @(V,x,y)--~ V v ~ _ V O ( v , x N v , y N o ) ,
T h e o r e m 5.4.
a. A * ~ A + ,
b. A + t- V ~ V ' .
References
[ 16] J.Silver, Some applications of model theory in set theory, Doctoral dissertation, Univer-
sity of California, Berkeley, 1966.
[ 17] R.Solovay. Real-v~ued measurable cardinals, Am. Math. Soc. Notices.
[ 18] E.Specker, Typical ambiguity, Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Proceed-
ings of the 1960 International Congress (Stanford, 1962) pp. 116-124.
[ 19] A.Tarski and R.L.Vaught, Arithmetical extensions of relational systems, Compositio
Math. 13 (1957)
[ 20] R.L.Vaught, Inde~ribable cardinals, Am. Math. Soc. Notices 10 (1963) 126.
[ 21] E.Zermelo, Untersuchungen tiber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I., Mathematische
Annalen 65 (1907) 261-281.
[22] G.Kreisel, Mathematical logic, Lectures on Modern Mathematics, vol III, ed. E.Saaty
(Wiley, 1965).
[ 23] H.J.Keisler and A.Tarski, From accessible to inaccessible cardinals, Fund. Math. 53 (1964)
225--308.
[ 24] L.Tharp, On a set theory of Bernays, J. Symb. Logic 32 (1967) 319-321.