J PDF
J PDF
J PDF
SOCIOLOGICAL JURISPRUDENCE
As an initial explanation it is suggested that sociological jurisprudence
is the purposive evaluation of legal rules and/or legal systems. The
primacy of legal rules is presumed, or at least that legal rules are
the starting point for the consideration of law in society. Attempts
at evaluating or relating such rules to various social or sociological
phenomeha are developed. Attempts are made to understand laws in
terms of interests or conflicts of interests within society. Typical
examples of research employing this methodology are: (1) considera-
tion of the postulates/interests in society and hence the postulates/
interests to which law necessarily must refer/relate/ take account
(2) efficacy studies which consider the effectiveness of rules for which
they are intended, for what they are not intended, for what latent
effects can result 40; (3) law in action research, i.e. the evaluation of
88 G. Sawer, op. dt. p. 14.
89 e.g. R. Pound, " A Survey of Social Interests" (1943-44) 57 Harvard Law
Review 1.
,fI.
4 0 e.g. W. Jones, The Efficacy of Law, 1969. Concern with questions of
" efficacy entails a rejection of the " Jurisprudence of Concepts." '' A jurisprudenw
of concepts is one which attempts to treat the law as a closed system of definitions,
296 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [vol. 39
legal rules ,in accordance with the following study categories suggested
by Stone in Social Dimensions of Lao and Justice. The following
contrasts require study :
‘‘ (1) between what courts say and what they do; (2) between the
words of statutes and what courts do under them; (3) between
instructions to juries and what juries do; (4) between the formulae
for executive action and what executive officials actually do; (5)
between rules formulated for conduct on a matter by statute or
judicial decision or juristic writing, and the conduct of citizens
which actually occurs; (6) between the object assumed or expressed
by legislature or court in formulating a rule, and the actual
consequences which flow from observance of it; (7) between
‘facts’ as found by judges and juries on the issues raised in
adversary rocedures, which in the light of the applicable rule
determine %e results, and the ‘ true facts ’which do not emerge.” 4l
Additional, less general categories could .be added, but the preceding
suggested surveys should sufficea4*
All of these examples presuppose a basic knowledge of the law in
the area to be studied. Methodologically they aim at a study of law
from an assumption as to the distinct nature of legal phenomena in
contrast with other social phen~mena.’~ The rules and their presump-
tive nature must be known in order that their effectiveness can be
evaluated. Further all these approaches, utilitarian in essence, stem
from an “ apparent ” 44 view of the “ consequences ” of law,46rather
than a priori judgments about the law.‘O The idea of rule evaluation
is utilitarian in origin,47requiring data and research of a sociological
type. As with Bentham’s zeal for law reform, such research can be
seen to have played a paramount role in law reform movements,
based on the principal and characteristic ineffectiveness and mal-
adjustment of laws in Western dernocra~ies.‘~The basic idea of
purpose supports these approaches. Legal rules are seen as purposive
rules, not a-political, a-social, a-economic. Law, in Ihering’s words is
seen as “ a means to an end.”6o The concepts of evaluating and
engineering are relevant to law if social purposes are to be served,
and if certain ends are required.
rules of operation, and substantive major premises such that any specific legal
problem can be solved by deductive reasoning from the propositional system so
established.” G.Sawer, op. cir. p. 17.
4 1 Pp. 45-47.
42 See for index oP research, Stone, op. cir. Chap 1. s. 4, ‘‘Some main lines of
practical inquiry concerning law and society in common law countries,” pp. 41-71.
43 N.B. Ehrlfch would oppose this assumption-see analysis o P Ehrlich later.
4 4 ‘‘ Apparent,” e.g. Pound’s jural postulates, see h
is Jurisprudence (1959), Vol. 3.
4 6 Law being viewed as serving certain purposes or ends, sec particularly R. Von
Ihering, Law CIS a Means to an End, translated by I. Husik, 1913.
40 i.e. in terms of validity-natural law or positivist. See K. Olivecrona, Law CIS
Fact, 2nd ed.. 1971, Chaps. 1-3.
47 See J. Bentham, An In:roduction ro :he Principles of ‘Morals and Legislation,
Chaps. 1-5, ed. W. Harrison, 1948.
4s i.e. inability to cope with major problems such as slum nelghbourhoods,
ecology, delinquency, social disorganisation, etc.
4r1 Sea R. Von Ihering, op. cil.
60 ’‘ Der Zweck im Recht,” more literally translated as “ purpose in law.”
May 19761 SOCIO-LEGAL THEORY : SOCIAL.STRUCTURE AND LAW 297
It is more than a mere dispute over words that leads to the continued
reclassification and re-examination of the various approaches listed
above. As Karl Llewellyn remarked of Pound, the founding father
of sociological jurisprudence, his preference was “ for the study
of theory, verbalised theory, writer’s theory, over study of results,
or of how it gets done; over process and know-how either in the
concrete or in theory.” 61 The theory of this article, it is hoped, will
clarify the need for this preponderant concern with the theory and
method of law in society, being an area of study of developing
importance.
THEJURISPRUDENTIALBACKGROUND
In accordance with contemporary classification of the area of study
.of jurisprudence,62 inquiries into the law and legal phenomena are
threefold. Natural law philosophy searches for an Q priori legitimacy
for legal phenomena and involves studies into the ideas of justice.
nature, etc. Positivist legal philosophy involves the study of the identi-
fication of legal phenomena, their normative structure and validity
in human, if not empirical terms. Realist schools of legal philosophy
are concerned with the interpretation of laws in terms of social or
psychological facts, replacing the normative by the causal. Among
the realist developments is that of sociological jurisprudence. The
methodology of traditional jurisprudence in all its branches rests on
the existence of legal phenomena independent of their social contexts.
That is not to say that the realist arguments classify law as anything
more abstract than a set of social or psychological facts, but inasmuch
as their aim lies in enumerating those social and psychological facts
as equivalent to answering the question “ what is law? ” the answers
given are methodologically equivalent in many respects to the
answers of other schools of thought?s This might lead one to the
argument that the appropriate subject for study as jurisprudence is,
and only is, the manifest eccentricities of the question “what is
law? ” However, it must be pointed out that such an assessment is
highly arbitrary. The definition of jurisprudence, just as the defini-
tion of law knows no such illusory boundaries. Indeed, simple
relativist argument would defeat such a claim.
The principle which is expounded here is that an appropriate
question of jurisprudence is “what is society? ” just as much as
‘‘ what is law? ” The methodological differences emerge from this
starting point rather than any other as far as the differences between
sociological jurisprudence and sociology of law are concerned.
51 (1960) 28 University of Chicago L.R. 179.
52 N.B. the triology of books by J. Stone. Legal System and Lawyers’ Reasonings
.(1964), Human Law and Human Justice (1965), Social Dimensions of Law and
-Justice (1966).
5 3 “ Because of this divergence in methods, questions that are formulated as legal
questions cannot easily be dealt with in a social-scientific framework unless they nre
reformulated. The traditional jurisprudential question, * What Is law? ’ falls into this
category. To be answered in its own terms, it requires a plunge into ’ the illusion of
Teal essence’ (T. D. Weldon. The Vocabulary of Politics, 1955).” M . Barkun, Law
wfthout Sanctions, 1968, p. 3.
298 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39
A NEW JURISPRUDENCE
“ What is society? ” is an appropriate question for jurisprudence since
the essential characteristics of the phenomenon we call law require
explanation, not independent from, but explicitly within their social
context.
The distinction between the realist branches and the subject of
“ what is society? ” as a branch of jurisprudence, lies in the starting
. .
consist . in acts universally disapproved of by members of each
society.” O3 As such the relationship between law and common morals
is direct:
“. . . we must not say that an action shocks the common
conscience because it is criminal. but rather it is criminal because
it shocks the common conscience. We do not reprove it because it
is a crime, but it is a crime because we reprove it.”
The law which Durkheim shows arises from such mechanical solidarity
which he regarded as characteristic of pre-feudal societies, was penal
and repressive and “ consists in a passionate reaction of graduated
intensity.” O8 In consideration of the sentimentswhich the crime offends,
i.e. the common conscience “ a simple restitution of the troubled order
would not suffice for us; we must have a more violent satisfaction.”
The argument Durkheim expounds of relating the repressive or
penal law to a society structured by “ mechanical solidarity ” is
self-supporting. Mechanical solidarity is based on the common con-
science, on homogeneity. Crime itself implies that such homogeneity
is not absolute, as such it damages the source for the authority of
repression. But, if repressive action were not recognised as dependent
on moral sentiment, that society and its values would be disr~pted.~’
Repressive laws are functional for a society whose structure is based
on mechanical solidarity:
“ . . . there exists a social solidarity which comes from a certain
number of states of conscience which are common to all mcrnbers
of the same society. That is what repressive law materially
represents, at least in so far as it is essential.” O8
62 Ibid. p. 79.
0s Ibid. p. 73. 04 Ibid. p. 81. 0s Ibid. p. 90.
00 Ibid. p. 99. 87 Ibid. pp. 102-103. 08 Ibid. p. 109.
May 19761 SOCIO-LEGAL. THEORY: SOCIAL STRUCTURE AND LAW 301
The dependence of the law on the society and vice versa is expressed
by Durkheim when he says that ‘‘ In determining what fraction of the
juridical system penal law represents, we, at the same time, measure
the relative importance of this solidarity.” OD* 7 0
(b) Organic solidarity due to the division of labour. Organic
solidarity corresponds to the restitutive sanction type of law, rather
than the repressive sanction. It arises out of ditferentiation and
specialisation of functions in society rather than homogeneity. Such
differentiation and specialisation, varieties of experience and outlook
of the members of a given society, leads to an increase of the mutual
dependence of those members. It not being possible for individuals
in modern industrial societies to satisfy all their needs without
dependence on other members of society, the objective need for legal
regulation is great, due to necessary interdependence. But legal regu-
lation is required to play a different role, i.e. from repression to
restitution. Durkheim uses the example of the contract to demonstrate
the shift from repressive to restitutive law. “ I n effect, the contract
is, par excellence. the juridical expression of co-operation.” I1 ‘‘ . . .
the contract is the symbol of exchange,” which “exchange always
presupposes some division of labor more or less developed.” 7 2 The
movement is towards a law of positive co-operation. But it must not
be forgotten that society lies behind such co-operation “ Every contract
thus supposes that behind the parties implicated in it there is society
very ready to intervene in order to gain respect for the engagement
which has been made.” 73 Durkheim sums up that “ the relations
governed by co-operative law with restitutive sanctions and the soli-
darity they express. result from the division of social labor.” 74
Further, such restitutive law is not dependent upon the collective
conscience, but :
“This law definitely plays a role in society analogous to that
.
played by the nervous system in the organism . . we can equally
measure the degree of concentration at which a society has arrived
in accordance with the division of labor according to the develop-
ment of -operative law with restitute functions.” 76
Durkheim states quite succinctly the importance of the thesis which
he puts forward “ . . . law always varies as the social relations which
it governs.” To* 77
60 Ibid. p. 109.
70 Durkheim’s analysis of mechanical solidarity has been criticised by a number
of anthropologists, e.g. Bronislaw Malinowski-“ We may therefore finally dismiss
the view that ‘ group-sentiment ’ or ‘ collective responsibility * is the only or even
the main force which ensures adhesion to custom and which makes it binding or
legal.” Crime and Custom in Savage Society, 1926 (6th impression 1951), p. 55. See
Chap. l’l, an anthropological definition of law.
7 1 Durkheim, o p . dt. p. 123. 7 2 Ibid. p. 125.
7 8 Ibid. p. 114. 74 Ibid. p. 127.
7 5 Ibid. pp. 128-129. 70 Ibid. p. 132.
77 Ft; criticism of Durkheim’s Division of Lab:; see: R. D. Schwartz and J. C.
Miller Legal Evolution and Societal Complexity (1964) 70 American Journal of
Sociology, 159; J. Stone (1934) 47 Harvard L.R. 1448; Gurvitch, op. cir. pp. 83-96.
For use, sea M. Gluckman, The Idem in Borotse Jurisprudence, 1965, pp. 238-241.
For evaluation, see T. Parsons, The Structure of Social Action, 1937, pp. 308-324.
302 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39
It needs to be pointed out that Durkheim’s analysis has received
an over-rigid juristic account in the work of LRon Duguit, who
attempted studies of the transformation of French law under the
influence of industrialisation in the nineteenth century.78In the notion
of law and social solidarity expressed by Durkheim. Duguit finds
what was to him an “ objective law.” i.e. solidarity by the division
of labour, organic solidarity.’O Such an “ objective law ” he uses to
free positive law from its dependence on the sovereign and the state.
“. . . the ruling class has no subjective sovereignty. . . . The
state is no longer a sovereign power issuing its commands. It
is a group of individuals who must use the force they possess to
supply the public need. The idea of public service lies at the
very base of the theory of the modern state. No other notion
takes its roots so profoundly in the facts of social life.”8o
“ Thus there is produced in human society a vast division of labor,
rules are powerless, and the legal measures which they ordain
remain useless.” 8 o
The required determination of legal norms by social norms is the
explicit conclusion which can be drawn from this analysis for the
conceptual sociology of law. The theoretical and methodological
requirements for such study are that the question “ what is society? ”
is a prerequisite to “ what is law? ” There exists no secondary rela-
tionship between what law is and what society is, i.e. law is something
differentially applied to changing social conditions, there exists a
primary relationship, what law is is dependent on what society is, or
our understanding of it. An evaluation of the effectiveness of law
according to the theory developed is a secondary matter, as Duguit
shows.
EHRLICH
In the foreword to his major work, Fundamental Principles of the
Sociology of Ehrlich sums up his thesis in one sentence:
“ At the present as well as at any other time, the center of gravity
of legal development lies not in legislation, nor in juristic science,
nor in judicial decision, but in society itself.” O2
This often quoted and much misused statement has been taken to
classify Ehrlich, with Pound. as a lading figure of the sociological
80 Inquiries info the Nature of Law and Morals, p. 16 (translated by C. D. Broad,
1953).
87 Note how Duguit uses the same argument in criticism of “ subjective rights”
theories: “ In the affirmation of liberty there may be an act of religious belief,
of philosophic conviction, an aspiration, a hope, a drenm; but not an affirmation of
scientific value.” (1920) 20 Columbia L.R. p. 820. And at p. 821, “Man has always
felt the need of explaining the visible by the invisible, of placing behind the
phenomena he ascertains directly an invisible entity which he makes the basis and
the efficient cause of the phenomena which he ascertains.”
8 8 (1921) 21 Columbia L.R. p. 22.
80 Ibid. p. 21.
00 Austrian jurist, 1862-1922.
01 Translated by W. L. Moll, 1936. 92 1912.
304 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [vol. 39
jurisprudential school, rather than accepting the methodology of his
sociological leanings, and putting him in the forefront of a sociology
of iaw.93
In turning to his work, one finds an introduction by Roscoe Pound.
Pound puts forward his own jurisprudential conceptions in asserting
that:
“ T o the twentieth century, the problems seem to be first, not
what law is, but what law does, how it does it, what it can be
made to do and how; second, the canon of valuing the conflicting
and overlapping interests and claims which must be harmonised
or adjusted by the legal order; and, third, the limits of effective
legal action and the means of securing effectively the interests
which the legal order rmgnises and delimits.” 94
To utilise this framework to introduce Ehrlich is misleading. The three
problems brought forward by Pound, are questions of sociological
jurisprudence, the presumptive primacy of legal rules is accepted.
Xhis precludes some key points of Ehrlich’s analysis, which distinguish
his work as sociology of law. Maybe the contrast in starting points
can best be brought out by considering the terms of reference with
which Ehrlich looks at Montesquieu. by the side of Pound’s critique.
Ehrlich,B6having ignored Montesquieu in Fundamental Principles of
the Sociology of Law argues:
“ As law is essentially a form of social life, it cannot be explained
scientifically otherwise than by the working of social forces. . . .
Thus in order to discover the social foundation of law we must
seek the very form in which it is engendered by society.”
The symbolic difference between Pound’s analysis (of Ehrlich) and
Ehrlich‘s analysis (of Montesquieu) is that between the jurist’s interest
in the social relations of law and the sociologist’s interest in society
and law as an institution within society. Ehrlich’s structural analysis
of law in the latter terms needs to be examined. The only work of
his which can be used in his Fundamental Principles of the Sociology
of Law.97This work is, in fact, a series of essays, related to the theme
of the sociological study of law.
In Chapter I. “The Practical Concept of Law,” Ehrlich aligns
himself to the philosophical school exemplified by Rudolph von
93 It may well be argued that this is a juristic hypothesis, and that Ehrlich was
essentially a jurist, but the present writer believes that his methods were those of
the sociology of law and he is therefore classified as such. In Ehrlich’s own words:
“ Since the law is a socinl phenomena, every kind of legal science (Jurisprudenz) is
a socinl science; but legal science in the proper sense of the term is a part of the
theoretical science of society, of sociology. The sociology of law is the theoretical
science of law (die wissenschaftliche Lehre von Recht). Fundamentd Principles of
the Sociology of Law,p. 25.
94 Ibid. nix-xxx.
96 ‘‘ Montesqu1i:u and Sociological Jurisprudence ” (1916) 29 Harvard L.R. 582.
90 Ibid. p. 584.
9 7 See summary “Sociology of Law ” (1922) 36 Harvard L.R. 130. His other
major works remain untrnnslated, e.g. Die Iuristische Logik (1918). Freie Rechrsfin-
dung und freie Rechrswissenschoft (1903) is partly translated in Modem Legal
Philosophy Series Vol. IX.
May 19761 SOCIO-LEGALTHEORY: SOCIAL STRUCTURE AND LAW 305
Ihering O8 the German legal philosopher. Ihering’s book Der Zweck
im RechtoOis based on a grand theory of social action whereby he
asserts that it is purpose rather than causation which determines law.
To restate law in terms of its social purposes was the task which
Ihering anticipates in the above work, although which he never
completes. Ehrlich accepts the purposive nature of human thinking
and understanding.
“ Human thinking is necessarily dominated by the concept of
purpose, which determines its direction, the selection of its
materials, and its methods.”
This method, later developed in the writings of Roscoe Pound? did
not, however, distract Ehrlich from his sociological task. The method
of purpose is one of sociological jurisprudence. Ehrlich in a central
theme, later in the first chapter, develops his sociological model and
explicitly is able to show the limitations of purposive method.
‘‘ It is not an essential element of the concept of law that it be
created by the State. nor that it constitute the basis for the
decisions of the courts or other tribunals, nor that it be the basis
of a legal compulsion consequent upon such a decision. A fourth
element remains, and that will have to be the point of departure,
i.e. the law is an ordering.” *
Similarly Durkheim demonstrates the limitations of purposive thinking
in his The Rules ofSociological Method.
“ To show how a fact is useful is not to explain how it originated
or why it is what it ,is. The uses which it serves presuppose the
specific properties characterising it but do not create them. The
need we have of things cannot give them existence, nor can it
confer their specific nature upon them.” *
In following up this central theme, in Chapter 2 ‘‘ The inner order
of the social associations,” Ehrlich gives his definition of society. He
says :
“ Society is the sum total of the human associations that have
mutual relations with one another.”
Further, society, even today, is dependent on an “ inner order ” for
its maintained structure rather than a legal norm. It is social com-
pulsion which gives it such an “inner order” and the legal norm
and authority of the state are themselves based on this social com-
pulsion. In considering the development of society Ehrlich says :
“Even today, just as in primitive times. the fate of man is
determined to a much greater extent by the inner order of the
associations than by legal propositions.
98 1818-92.
99 Lau QP a Means to an End. translated by I. Husik. 1913.
1 Ehrlich, Fundarnenfd Principles of the Sodology of Law,p. 5.
a See particularly his ‘‘ Survey of Social Interests ” (1943) 57 Harvard L.R. 1.
3 Ehrlich, op. df. p. 24.
4 1938 at p. 90.
6 Ehrlich, op. c ff.p. 26.
VOL 39 (3) 3
306 THE MODERN LAW REVIEW [vol. 39
. . . The State existed before the constitution; the family is
older than the order of the family; possession antidates ownership;
there were contracts before there was a law of contracts. . . .”
Historically, Ehrlich argues, society is conceived of as pre-existing
laws about or related to that society. Social associations within that
society pre-exist and have an existence of their own, beyond
the legal propositions which refer to them. So, the inner order precedes
the legal regulation, and legal regulation is dependent on this inner
order.
“ The inner order of the associations of human beings is not only
the original, but also, down to the present time. the basic form
of law. The legal proposition not only comes into being at a
much later time, but is largely derived from the inner order of
the associations.” ’
This is the lesson which socio-legal research needs to learn, and
which Ehrlich has so bluntly stated. It is restated by the present
writer as : “ What is society? ” is a primary question of jurisprudence,
is a necessary point of departure for an understanding of law as a
dependent phenomenon, existing within the social context.
From a structural viewpoint Ehrlich maintains that the idea of law
is much wider than the notion of legal regulation. The legal norm is
the basis of living law. which is:
“ . . . not confined to its influence upon the norms for decision
which the courts apply or upon the content of statutes. The
knowledge of the living law has an independent value, and this
consists in the fact that it constitutes the foundation of the legal
order of human society.”
In chapter 21 ‘‘ The Methods of the Sociology of Law.” part 2, “ The
Study of the Living Law ” the themes so far illustrated are further
developed. Ehrlich says :
“ The reason why the dominant school of legal science so greatly
prefers the legal proposition to all other legal phenomena as an
object of investigation is that it tacitly assumes that the whole
law is to be found in the legal propositions.”
Ehrlich puts forward “ living law ” as a contrast to “ legal proposi-
tions,” the latter being that law which is enforced, or used as source
material, in courts or tribunals.
“ The living law is the law which dominates life itself even though
it has not been posited in legal propositions.” lo
The implications of this are that one must look to those matters which
underly the living law since the legal proposition in itself is insufficient
for the purposes of understanding law in its social context. Ehrlich
suggests that the sources of this “living law” are “. . . first, the
~ ~~
CONCLUSION
The discrepancy in methods between writers who attempt to develop
an analysis of law in society, is crucial to an understanding of and
development of such studies, both of a theoretical and practical
nature.28
The functional models of society postulated by writers such as
Durkheim, Ehrlich and Parsons, despite the criticisms which can be
made against functional analysis.2° demonstrate the value of consider-
ing law as a dependent social phenomena (or in Parsons’ language an
“ interdependent sub-system ”), demonstrate the misconceptions which