FDFHFDH
FDFHFDH
FDFHFDH
Cordelia Fine
Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics, Department of Philosophy,
University of Melbourne, Victoria, Australia
Mark Gardner
Department of Psychology, University of Westminster, London, UK
Jillian Craigie
School of Philosophy and Bioethics, Monash University, Clayton, Victoria,
Australia
Ian Gold
School of Philosophy and Bioethics, Monash University, Clayton, Victoria,
Australia, and Departments of Philosophy & Psychiatry, McGill University,
Montreal, Quebec, Canada
Correspondence should be addressed to Cordelia Fine, Centre for Applied Philosophy and
Public Ethics, Department of Philosophy, University of Melbourne, Victoria 3010, Australia.
E-mail: cfine@unimelb.edu.au
This work was supported by an Australian Research Council Large Grant (no. A00103679), an
Australian Research Council Discovery-Projects Grant (no. 0343348), and a Senior Fellowship to
IG in the McDonnell Project in Philosophy and the Neurosciences, Simon Fraser University. We
would also like to thank our reviewers *in particular, Emmanuelle Peters *for many helpful
comments on earlier versions of the paper.
# 2007 Psychology Press, an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
http://www.psypress.com/cogneuropsychiatry DOI: 10.1080/13546800600750597
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 47
Results. We found that only one of four measures of the JTC bias *‘‘draws to
decision’’ *reached significance. The JTC bias exhibited by delusional subjects *
as measured by draws to decision *did not appear to be solely an epiphenomenal
effect of schizophrenic symptomatology, and was not amplified by emotionally
salient material.
Conclusions. A tendency to gather less evidence in the Beads task is reliably
associated with the presence of delusional symptomatology. In contrast, certainty
on the task, and responses to contradictory evidence, do not discriminate well
between those with and without delusions. The implications for the underlying basis
of the JTC bias, and its role in the formation and maintenance of delusions, are
discussed.
1998; McGuire, Junginger, Adams, Burright, & Donovick, 2001; Peters &
Garety, 2006; van Dael, Vermissen, Janssen, Myin-Germeys, van Os, &
Krabbendam, 2006). A JTC bias has also been suggested as a possible
contributory factor in several well-known multifactorial accounts of the
formation of specific categories of delusion, for example, persecutory
delusions (e.g., Bentall, Corcoran, Howard, Blackwood, & Kinderman,
2001) and the Capgras delusion (e.g., Young, 2000). The claim that a
reasoning bias contributes to the formation of delusions has also had an
impact on the development of cognitive therapies for delusions, some of
which now target the reasoning processes thought to be involved in
delusional belief formation and the maintenance of those beliefs (see Rector
& Beck, 2002).
certainty on the early trials of the task. A variant of this procedure is the
‘‘graded estimates’’ approach. Here, after each trial the participant is asked
whether the bead is definitely, almost certainly, or probably from jar A or B,
or whether there is currently no preference.
The ‘‘draws to certainty’’ methodology is also used to assess a second
prediction of the JTC hypothesis, that patients with delusions will be more
likely than controls to reject hypotheses in response to contradictory
evidence (Garety & Hemsley, 1994). In what we refer to as ‘‘response to
potentially disconfirmatory evidence’’, the dependent variable is the change
in certainty in response to a single bead that potentially disconfirms the
participant’s likely hypothesis. For example, Garety et al. (1991) calculated
participants’ certainty after Bead 3 (the third of three pink beads) minus
certainty after Bead 4 (the first green bead), as a measure of ‘‘response to
potentially disconfirmatory evidence’’.
Some researchers have also examined participants’ change in certainty
when, in the latter half of the experiment, the evidence is genuinely
disconfirmatory. Participants are presented with a sequence of beads such
as the one below:
AAABAAAABABBBABBBBAB
In this sequence, the first 10 beads suggest that beads are being drawn from
the ‘‘mostly As’’ jar, while the second 10 beads suggest that the beads are
being drawn from the ‘‘mostly Bs’’ jar. It is then assessed whether patients
with delusion are the same as, or different from, control groups in the way
they lose confidence in their initial hypothesis. We refer to this dependent
variable as ‘‘response to reversal’’.
The range of dependent variables used to tap JTC reflects uncertainty in
the literature regarding what, precisely, are useful and valid measures of
‘‘jumping to conclusions’’. There appears to be consensus that hastiness in
decision making derives from a lower threshold for amount of information
required (measured by the dependent variable ‘‘draws to decision’’), rather
than a bias in reasoning about probabilities per se (e.g., Dudley, John,
Young, & Over, 1997b; Garety & Freeman, 1999; Moritz, Woodward, &
Hausmann, 2006; Peters, Thornton, Siksou, Linney, & MacCabe, 2005).
However, ‘‘draws to certainty’’ has been used as a measure of JTC bias in
several recent studies (e.g., Moritz & Woodward, 2005; Peters & Garety,
2006; Peters et al., 2005). The issue of whether or not ‘‘draws to certainty’’
predicts the presence of delusions is an important one, since the answer
could constrain in significant ways our understanding of the JTC
phenomenon. Finally, it is not clear whether the JTC phenomenon should
also be taken to include a tendency to ‘‘jump to new conclusions’’, indexed
by the dependent variables ‘‘response to potentially disconfirmatory
50 FINE ET AL.
Summary
Theoretical understanding of the JTC bias currently lacks precision.
Different studies have used different dependent measures to tap a JTC
bias and it is not yet clear which measure(s) best discriminate between
subjects with and without delusions. Reflecting this uncertainty, current
accounts of the cause underlying the tendency to jump to conclusions differ
in the predictions they make regarding how the JTC bias should manifest in
patients with delusions. An investigation into which of these measures best
discriminates the reasoning style of delusional patients from controls is
needed therefore to clarify the nature of the putative JTC bias in delusion,
and to indicate viable accounts of an underlying mechanism.
52 FINE ET AL.
1
However, no significant differences were found in comparison with a nondelusional group
with schizophrenia.
2
No psychiatric control group was used.
3
For the harder 60:40 ratio. However, no significant differences were observed in comparison
with a nondelusional group with schizophrenia, or when a memory aid was provided.
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 53
group (see Pélissier & O’Connor, 2002; Volans, 1976; also Dudley & Over,
2003), rather than a reduction in the delusional group, relative to normal
nonpsychiatric performance. The only unambiguous support for reduced
‘‘draws to certainty’’ in patients with delusions comes from Peters and
Garety (2006), who found that their delusional group showed a significantly
greater mean certainty over the first three trials than did both psychiatric
and nonpsychiatric controls.
Overall, it appears that ‘‘draws to certainty’’ does not discriminate well
between the presence or absence of delusions once the confounding effects of
psychiatric symptomatology are taken into account. From this it has been
inferred that patients with delusions have a tendency to seek less information
prior to reaching a decision (and thus have a reduced ‘‘draws to decision’’),
rather than a tendency to differ with respect to certainty (Dudley et al.,
1997b; Garety & Freeman, 1999). In line with this conclusion, a number of
studies have demonstrated that patients with delusions show normal
sensitivity to variations in the ratio of beads in the Beads task. Thus when
the ratio of different coloured beads in the jar is changed (for example,
reduced to 60:40) patients with delusions, like controls, appropriately change
the number of beads they require for a decision or for certainty (e.g., Dudley
et al., 1997b; Young & Bentall, 1997).
Five studies have used ‘‘responses to potentially disconfirmatory evi-
dence’’ as a dependent variable. The majority of these found that individuals
with delusions become significantly less certain about their hypotheses
following potentially disconfirmatory evidence in comparison with non-
psychiatric, but not psychiatric, control groups (Fear & Healy, 1997; Garety
et al., 1991; Peters & Garety, 2006; Young & Bentall, 1997). One exception is
Moritz and Woodward (2005), who found that this dependent variable
distinguished between delusional patients with schizophrenia and nondelu-
sional patients with schizophrenia, as well as psychiatric and healthy
controls.
A fourth variable, ‘‘responses to reversal’’, has also been used as a
measure of a JTC style. Overall, the evidence from studies using this variable
also offers little support for the idea that patients with delusions ‘‘jump to
new conclusions’’. Three studies using this measure found no significant
differences between patients with delusions and control groups (Dudley et
al., 1997b; Fear & Healy, 1997; Young & Bentall, 1997). Moritz and
Woodward (2005) found some evidence of greater adjustment of certainty
responses in delusional patients with schizophrenia compared with psychia-
tric and nonpsychiatric controls. However, significant effects were not
observed for all disconfirmatory beads (only two of the eight beads in the
latter half of the experiment that disconfirmed the original hypothesis), and
no significant differences were seen when these patients were compared with
nondelusional patients with schizophrenia. Brankovic and Paunovic (1999)
54 FINE ET AL.
Method
Studies to be included in the meta-analysis were identified by carrying out an
electronic search using the Medline and PsycInfo databases. Search terms
used included: delusion, jumping to conclusions, reasoning. In addition, the
review of Garety and Freeman (1999), and the reference lists of other more
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 55
FINE ET AL.
the meta-analyses
Effect sizes (g) are reported by study design and dependent variable. The studies included are marked in the reference section with an asterisk.
Pot.Disc. /Response to potentially disconfirmatory evidence.
a
Mortimer et al. (1996) employed a correlational design to examine the relationship between draws to decision and delusional items of the CASH.
b
Psychiatric controls had OCD.
c
The delusional group had predominately a diagnosis of schizophrenia (58%). The remainder had delusional disorder.
d
The ‘‘graded estimates’’ procedure was used. Effect sizes are for ‘‘definitely the bag with...’’ judgements, unless insufficient data was available in which
case ‘‘almost certainly the bag with . . .’’ was used (Young & Bentall, 1997, Exp. 2).
e
39% of the psychiatric control group had OCD.
f
A symptom-based approach was employed in these studies. The delusional group had mixed diagnoses, containing at least 50% patients with
schizophrenia.
g
Insufficient data were reported to compute an effect size. However, this study was included in tests in which p values were meta-analytically pooled.
Control Group
1.50 psychiatric
non psychiatric
Effect size, g
1.00
0.50
0.00
Figure 1. The distribution of effect sizes (g) by type of control group and dependent variable.
4
This pattern of significance and nonsignificance also remained after Bonferroni correction for
multiple comparisons (n /6).
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 59
5
Bonferroni correction for repeated significance testing (n /8) did not affect this pattern of
results other than to confirm the nonsignificance of ‘‘response to potentially disconfirmatory
evidence’’ for comparisons with psychiatric controls.
60 FINE ET AL.
et al. gave the Beads task to a group of patients with schizophrenia whose
delusion scores ranged from 0 to 22 on delusional items of the Compre-
hensive Assessment of Symptoms and History (CASH; Andreasen, Flaum,
& Arndt, 1992). This scale assesses range of delusional beliefs as well as
degree of conviction, preoccupation, and extent to which the belief is acted
upon. Despite the wide range of delusional symptomatology reported in
their sample (from 0 to 22 on the CASH), Mortimer et al. found that 42% of
patients required only one draw to decision, a proportion similar to that
observed by Garety and colleagues. Moreover, number of draws to decision
did not correlate with the CASH delusion score. As Mortimer et al. (1996;
p. 301) noted, ‘‘[t]his suggests that abnormal probabilistic reasoning is a
consequence of having schizophrenia rather than having the particular
schizophrenic symptom of delusions’’. By contrast, however, van Dael et al.
(2006) explored the association between JTC (indexed by ‘‘extreme
responding’’) and the presence of delusions, and found evidence for a
significant link between the two in their patient group.
Menon et al. (2006) compared the performance of delusional and
nondelusional patients with schizophrenia on variants of the Beads task.
In their first experiment they found no differences on ‘‘draws to decision’’
between delusional and nondelusional patients with schizophrenia nor
indeed between any groups. There were slight procedural differences between
the Menon et al. task and that used by Huq et al. (1988) and Garety et al.
(1991). For example, in the original studies the beads, once drawn, were then
hidden from view. However, in the Menon et al. study the beads remained in
sight, thus providing a memory aid. In follow-up experiments, Menon et al.
found significant differences between the groups with schizophrenia and
nonpsychiatric controls when the original procedure was used. However,
they found no significant differences between the delusional and nondelu-
sional patients with schizophrenia. Furthermore, when the beads were left in
sight (the memory aid condition), the differences between the groups
disappeared. Menon et al. (2006; p. 533) thus suggested that ‘‘a key
component of the ‘jumping to conclusions’ (JTC) effect relates to the
memory demands imposed by the task’’. This study therefore supports the
epiphenomenon view and, in particular, identifies memory demands as a
possible contributory factor to the JTC effect observed in patients with
schizophrenia (but see Dudley et al., 1997b, who found that the addition of a
memory aid had no effect on the performance of patients with delusions).
A second recent study conducted by Moritz and Woodward (2005) also
compared the performance of delusional and nondelusional patients with
schizophrenia on the Beads task. The presence of delusional symptomatol-
ogy did not distinguish between patients with schizophrenia on ‘‘draws to
decision’’. Although Moritz and Woodward did find that delusional patients
with schizophrenia were significantly more likely than nondelusional
62 FINE ET AL.
6
This study employed a symptom-based approach involving clinical groups including a high
proportion of patients with schizophrenia.
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 65
1.50
1.25
Effect Size, g
1.00
0.75
0.50
0.25
0.00
Figure 2. The distribution of ‘‘draws to decision’’ effect sizes (g) for studies comparing a group with
schizophrenia and delusions with three types of control group. Data for the nondelusional
schizophrenia control group also includes one study that employed a correlational design (Mortimer
et al., 1996).
7
Peters et al. (2005) was not included in this comparison because insufficient data was reported
in this study to compute an effect size.
66 FINE ET AL.
Effect Size, g
1.00
0.75
0.50
0.25
Figure 3. The distribution of ‘‘draws to decision’’ effect sizes (g) by type of clinical group with
delusions and type of control group.
GENERAL DISCUSSION
Three conclusions are supported by the current findings. First, ‘‘draws to
decision’’ is the most reliable measure of JTC bias. This offers some
important constraints on our theoretical understanding of the JTC reason-
ing style. Second, the JTC bias, as represented by ‘‘draws to decision’’,
appears to make a genuine contribution to delusional symptomatology, and
is not solely an epiphenomenal effect. This provides evidence for the
possibility of a causal role for a JTC reasoning style in the formation and/
or retention of delusional belief. Third, emotional salience does not increase
the hastiness of decision-making in patients with delusions. This finding
suggests that the particular delusional beliefs adopted by a patient cannot be
explained by the emotional nature of those types of belief. Rather, delusional
patients may be hasty with respect to all types of material.
In the following sections we consider two questions about the JTC bias.
First, what are the implications of our findings for the underlying basis of
the JTC bias? And, second, what role does the JTC bias play in the
70 FINE ET AL.
to come into play after a delusional hypothesis has already been formulated.
Sequential information does not seem to play any role in the development of
a hypothesis but only in the evaluation of evidence for or against it. Thus, on
Bentall and colleagues’ account, a delusional hypothesis must already be
present before a JTC bias would be manifested in delusional cognition.
Similarly, a confirmatory reasoning style can make an appearance only after
a hypothesis has been formulated and is available to be confirmed or
rejected. Thus, on Dudley and Over’s account as well, a JTC bias could only
play a role in delusion development once a delusional hypothesis occurs to
the patient.
In particular, on Dudley and Over’s (2003) account, while people without
delusions apply a confirmatory reasoning style to danger-related conditional
statements, delusional patients apply such a style even to neutral situations
because they perceive danger and threat in them. It is a normal reasoning
strategy applied to situations in which only the delusional individual
erroneously perceives threat. Thus the patient must presumably first develop
a delusional sense of threat or danger prior to extending their confirmatory
reasoning style to neutral situations. This position is supported by our
finding that the JTC effect is not disproportionately enhanced by emotion-
ally salient material. Thus it cannot be that a JTC bias, applied to an
emotionally salient domain, can ‘‘boot-strap’’ the development of a
delusional belief. The situation being reasoned about must first gain a
delusional significance before the JTC bias can get a purchase.
A delusional thought must therefore be present before a JTC bias can
have an effect on the development of delusion. A JTC bias may, however,
lead to a premature acceptance of such a thought. Evidence for this view
comes from Garety et al. (2005) who have recently found evidence that a
JTC style of reasoning is associated with delusional conviction. Their
analysis supported a model in which ‘‘belief inflexibility’’ *a reluctance to
consider the possibility that one might be wrong about one’s delusional
belief*largely mediates the contribution of a JTC reasoning style to
delusional conviction. The role of JTC in this account appears to be one
of facilitating the precipitous acceptance of the delusional hypothesis, and
‘‘precluding reflection on past learning to consider whether the information
fits with previous knowledge, with the result that the possibility that one
might be mistaken is not considered’’ (p. 381). In line with this position,
Freeman et al. (2004) found that patients who did not report any alternative
explanations for the experiences on which their delusions were based were
more likely to jump to conclusions than were patients who could come up
with alternative explanations.
There is another reason for limiting the role of the JTC bias in this way,
and this is the strikingly small number of forms of delusion that exist. Yager
and Gitlin (2000, p. 801) list only 14 ‘‘classic’’ forms, and over 85% of
72 FINE ET AL.
Overview
Taken together, our findings suggest that a causal role for a JTC bias should
be hypothesised to lie in that stage of delusion development in which a
patient is considering whether or not to accept or reject a thought with a
delusional content. The JTC bias does not seem to play any role in either the
production of a delusional thought or in its maintenance once it has been
accepted. We conclude that further research on the processes of delusion
acceptance may illuminate the role of a JTC bias in delusion.
8
We are grateful to one of our reviewers for this point.
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 73
Conclusions
The results of our meta-analyses provide support for the view that patients
with delusions exhibit a genuine difference in the amount of evidence they
require to embrace a hypothesis, and that this difference is not entirely a
consequence of the presence of schizophrenia. The JTC bias does not extend
to the processing of contradictory information following the formation of a
hypothesis, and it is not disproportionately increased when the content of
material being reasoned about is emotionally salient.
Overall, consideration of our findings and the possible role the JTC bias
could take in delusion, suggests that the JTC bias is not relevant to the
formulation of delusional hypotheses. In particular, it does not appear to be
relevant to the question of why delusional forms are so small in number. Nor
is the JTC bias likely to play a role either in an explanation of why patients
take these implausible hypotheses seriously or in the explanation of how
delusional patients identify putative evidence for the hypotheses. Finally, the
JTC bias seems to have no role to play in the maintenance of delusion in the
face of disconfirmatory evidence. Further investigation into the processes of
belief acceptance *both pathological and nonpathological *may prove
fruitful in illuminating the way in which the JTC bias exerts its effect in
delusional patients.
Manuscript received 12 November 2003
Revised manuscript received 29 March 2006
REFERENCES
(Studies included in the meta-analysis are preceded by an asterisk.)
American Psychiatric Association (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (4th
ed.). Washington, DC: Author.
Andreasen, N. C., Flaum, M., & Arndt, S. (1992). The Comprehensive Assessment of Symptoms
and History (CASH): An instrument for assessing diagnosis and psychopathology. Archives of
General Psychiatry, 49 , 615 623.
JTC BIAS AND DELUSIONS 75
Bentall, R. P., Corcoran, R., Howard, R., Blackwood, N., & Kinderman, P. (2001). Persecutory
delusions: A review and theoretical integration. Clinical Psychology Review, 21 , 1143 1192.
Brankovic, S. B., & Paunovic, V. R. (1999). Reasoning under uncertainty in deluded schizophrenic
patients: A longitudinal study. European Psychiatry, 14 , 76 83.
*Broome, M., Brett, C., Johns, L., Woolley, J., Peters, E., Garety, P., & McGuire, P. K. (2003).
Reasoning styles and delusions in early psychosis. Schizophrenia Research , 60 (Suppl. 1), 12.
*Colbert, S. M., & Peters, E. R. (2002). Need for closure and jumping-to-conclusions in delusion-
prone individuals. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 190 , 27 31.
*Conway, C. R., Bollini, A. M., Graham, B. G., Keefe, R. S., Schiffman, S. S., & McEvoy, J. P.
(2002). Sensory acuity and reasoning in delusional disorder. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 43 ,
175 178.
*Dudley, R. E., John, C. H., Young, A. W., & Over, D. E. (1997a). The effect of self-referent
material on the reasoning of people with delusions. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 36 ,
575 584.
*Dudley, R. E., John, C. H., Young, A. W., & Over, D. E. (1997b). Normal and abnormal
reasoning in people with delusions. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 36 , 243 258.
Dudley, R. E. J., & Over, D. E. (2003). People with delusions jump to conclusions: A theoretical
account of research findings on the reasoning of people with delusions. Clinical Psychology and
Psychotherapy, 10 , 263 274.
*Fear, C. F., & Healy, D. (1997). Probabilistic reasoning in obsessive-compulsive and delusional
disorders. Psychological Medicine, 27 , 199 208.
Freeman, D., Garety, P. A., Fowler, D., Kuipers, E., Bebbington, P. E., & Dunn, G. (2004). Why do
people with delusions fail to choose more realistic explanations for their experiences? An
empirical investigation. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 72 , 671 680.
Freeman, D., Garety, P. A., Kuipers, E., Fowler, D., & Bebbington, P. E. (2002). A cognitive model
of persecutory delusions. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 41 , 331 347.
Garety, P., Kuipers, E., Fowler, D., Freeman, D., & Bebbington, P. (2001). A cognitive model of the
positive symptoms of psychosis. Psychological Medicine, 31 , 189 195.
Garety, P. A., & Freeman, D. (1999). Cognitive approaches to delusions: A critical review of
theories and evidence. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 38 , 113 154.
Garety, P. A., Freeman, D., Jolley, S., Dunn, G., Bebbington, P. E., Fowler, D. G., et al. (2005).
Reasoning, emotions, and delusional conviction in psychosis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology,
114 , 373 384.
Garety, P. A., & Hemsley, D. R. (1994). Delusions: Investigations into the psychology of delusional
reasoning . Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
*Garety, P. A., Hemsley, D. R., & Wessely, S. (1991). Reasoning in deluded schizophrenic and
paranoid patients: Biases in performance on a probabilistic inference task. Journal of Nervous
and Mental Disease, 179 , 194 201.
Gray, J. A., Feldon, J., Rawlins, J. N. P., Hemsley, D. R., & Smith, A. D. (1991). The
neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14 , 1 84.
Gutiérrez-Lobos, K., Schmid-Siegel, B., Bankier, B., & Walter, H. (2001). Delusions in first-
admitted patients: Gender, themes and diagnoses. Psychopathology, 34 , 1 7.
Hedges, L. V. (1981). Distribution theory for Glass’s estimator of effect size and related estimators.
Journal of Educational Statistics, 6 , 107 128.
*Huq, S. F., Garety, P. A., & Hemsley, D. R. (1988). Probabilistic judgements in deluded and non-
deluded subjects. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 40A , 801 812.
Jørgensen, P. (1995). Recovery and insight in schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica , 92 ,
436 440.
Jørgensen, P., & Jensen, J. (1994). Delusional beliefs in first admitters: A clinical description.
Psychopathology, 27 , 100 112.
76 FINE ET AL.