Text 2 Erotism
Text 2 Erotism
Text 2 Erotism
MATT GEORGE
Kyungsung University
The American tradition of action theory failed to produce a useful theory of the
possible existence of trans-individual consistencies in sexual desirability. Instead,
most sociological theorists have relied on market metaphors to account for the logic
of sexual action. Through a critical survey of sociological attempts to explain the
social organization of sexual desiring, this article demonstrates that the market
approach is inadequate, and that its inadequacies can be remedied by studying sexual
action as occurring within a specifically sexual field (in Bourdieu’s sense), with a
correlative sexual capital. Such a conception allows for historical and comparative
analysis of changes in the organization of sexual action that are impeded by the use of
a market metaphor, and also points to difficulties in Bourdieu’s own treatment of the
body qua body.
Though group sex has certain attractions, its serving as a primary symbolization,
even of wider solidarities, seems to be severely limited.
Talcott Parsons (1971)
In this work, Parsons took up theoretical arms against the prescription of the
Aquarian Age that universal love would conquer all, which he took as a worrisome
sign of de-differentiation. Even more, this vision undermined the edifice with which
his theory began, namely, his solution to the Hobbesian problem of order, which was
assumed to stem from scarcity of things desired. The vision of solidarity through
group sex Parsons criticized not only violated the religious legitimacy of dyadic love,
it was also based on a ‘‘non-zero-sum’’ vision of erotic abundance, which undermined
the very need for a normatively structured solution of the Hobbesian problem in the
first place. Yet that had been Parsons’s (1968) fundamental point: while specific
interests might in fact conflict, this does not mean they are idiosyncratic and
un-organizable, for individual passions and desires (what we now call ‘‘interests’’1)
are systematically related to overarching value commitments (Parsons [1940]
1949:211). It was this argument of Parsons—that competing material interests must
*Address correspondence to: John Levi Martin, Department of Sociology, University of Wisconsin,
Madison, 8128 Social Sciences Bldg., 1180 Observatory Dr., Madison WI 53706-1393. E-mail: jlmartin@
ssc.wisc.edu. An earlier version of this article was presented at the 1997 meetings of the American
Sociological Association, Toronto; we thank Paul DiMaggio and Bonnie Erickson, as well as the reviewers
and editors, for comments and criticism.
1
On the development of ‘‘passion’’ to interest, see the wonderful account of Hirschman (1977).
2
In seeming contradiction to this last claim, Turner (1982) has argued that Foucault’s work ‘‘has to be
located within a well-established tradition in social philosophy which recognized the problem of human
passions as the critical factor in social order,’’ and in his own work explicitly begins, as do we, with the
relevance of the body for the Hobbesian problem of order. However, in linking Foucault’s concerns to the
Hobbesian problem of order, Turner has confused the functionalist problem of governance (a problem for
sovereigns) with Hobbes’s problem of insecurity in the state of nature (a problem for desiring individuals).
Because he does not begin from conflicting and intrinsically unlimited desires, Turner’s (1984:39) notion of
the centrality of the body amounts to seeing the body as an internal environment with physiological needs;
what then results is a set of wholly universal statements, as opposed to a theoretical framework that can
begin an investigation of the social differentiation of bodies.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 109
(cf. Tiryakian 1981). Furthermore, while they are few, there have been a number of
explicit and noteworthy attempts in sociological theory to discuss this social organ-
ization of sexual desiring. We undertake an analytic review of these attempts, arguing
that they tend to founder on market metaphors. We return to Weber, who also
discussed (in different terms) the organization of a specifically sexual sphere of life,
and then follow the alternate elaboration of Weber’s action theory recently pursued
by Pierre Bourdieu, arguing that an analytics of the sexual field allows us to rephrase
the question asked by the authors we survey in a noncontradictory manner amenable
to empirical exploration.
This issue is clearly of relevance to general questions regarding the relation between
the sexes and prestige orders in feminist theory (e.g., Ortner and Whitehead 1981),
and more specific questions regarding to what extent sexual resources or rankings are
tied to or exchangable for resources or rankings in other spheres, such as the
economic (see Zelizer 1996).3 Further, our extension of Bourdieu is relevant for
theorists seeking to study how bodily capital is formed (Wacquant 1995) or how the
emotional aspects of social life treated as residual by Bourdieu may be related to
stratification (Illouz 1997; Reay 2004); it also suggests limitations to Bourdieu’s
treatment of the body.
Parsons’s insight in the opening quotation was that despite the potential for social
integration through unrestricted sexual contact, social life may require restricted and
organized pairing (see also Parsons [1940] 1949a: 171–75); this was understood by the
writers we will survey as implying a social consensus regarding a hierarchy of desir-
ability or attractiveness in sexual pairing. We will begin our analysis of 20th-century
sociological approaches to the social ordering of sexual desiring with Davis; this is
fitting for two reasons. The first is that, as stated, Davis most clearly understood the
relevance of sexual desire for the Hobbesian problem of order,4 and attempted to
demonstrate a normative organization of desiring. But he—like the other theorists we
will survey—never actually found such a normative basis. Instead, as we shall see, he
relied on market analogies. The second reason is that Davis was the first to focus on a
stratification of sexual attractiveness as the fundamental basis of the social organiza-
tion of sexual desiring, as opposed to simple mechanisms of heterophily (opposites
attract) (e.g., Forel [1906] 1929:84) or social homophily (see Laumann et al.
(1994:231ff) and England and Farkas (1986:34) for good discussions). This latter
approach assumes that choices are made on nonsexual grounds, and hence that a
structural analysis of pairing could dispense with the super-structural phenomenon of
desiring. Arguments from homophily also deny the possibility of one stable ranking,
since there are structured disagreements in taste. In contrast, the theories of sexual
stratification put forward by Davis and the others we survey maintain that there is a
specifically sexual ranking and that it is the subject of social consensus: hence those
matched with ‘‘lows’’ have been so matched as the result of a market-like process in
which they desired higher-ranking partners but could not attain them. We now turn to
the specifics of Davis’s theory.
3
Some feminist appraisals of the sexual revolutions of the 1920s and 1960s have divided over whether it is
liberatory for the sexual sphere to be divorced from the economic, or whether the divorce weakens women’s
positions by ‘‘increasing and legitimating male right of sexual access to women’’ (Jackson 1987:52). For a
further discussion, see George (1996).
4
‘‘Unless there is some kind of social order in the distribution of sexual favors, a war of all against all will
tend to result’’ (K. Davis 1966:350).
110 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
5
It is worth noting that Murray Davis (1983) also begins from this premise of absolute scarcity of
‘‘lovables’’; see Hume ([1777] 1985) and Levi-Strauss ([1949] 1969:38) for a critique of this premise.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 111
In order to have Class A rating [men] must belong to one of the better frater-
nities, be prominent in activities, have a copious supply of spending money, be
well-dressed, be ‘‘smooth’’ in manners and appearance, have a ‘‘good line,’’ dance
well, and have access to an automobile. . . . The factors which appear to be
important for girls are good clothes, a smooth line, ability to dance well, and
popularity as a date. The most important of these factors is the last, for the girl’s
prestige depends upon dating more than anything else; here as nowhere else
nothing succeeds like success.
Hence, women would manipulate their perceived scarcity in order to inflate their
rank, which would then be a self-fulfilling prophecy (1937:730).
Scarcity is the key to relative power in this system, not only on the individual level
(the scarcer woman is the more valuable) but also on the level of the sexes. When
women are scarce (e.g., during the winter term in one school described by Waller), the
coeds have ‘‘a relatively high bargaining power,’’ but when school teachers come for
the summer term, the balance of power reverses, and men get easy sexual access
(1937:732). At the same time, one’s dating scarcity is not the only factor contributing
to one’s rank—indeed, for men, it is not even the primary one. It is quite interesting
that beyond the fact that men paid for dates, and that various institutions arose (such
as the corsage6) to allow the man to publicly demonstrate the money spent on the date
(and therefore the equilibrium of her worth and his supply), the system does not
involve an exchange of economic support (which the college woman has) for sexual
access. The logic of Davis’s sexual market is unnecessary. Yet again, men’s ranks seem
to be closely aligned with ranks in other spheres, while women’s ranks are more
autonomously generated within the system. Finally, Waller clearly saw the ranking as
taking into account a number of different attributes—such that we might conceive of
a woman’s overall dating rank as being a combination of her endogenous dating rank
(her popularity, proportional to her scarcity), and her exogenous rank (e.g., clothes,
‘‘line’’).
Thus Waller, like Davis, perceived there to be a system of exchange between men
and women, and a system that implies the ranking of men and women according to
their dating attractiveness. But in contrast to Davis’s reliance on a preexisting degree
of attractiveness in everybody, Waller proposed that, to a certain degree, attractive-
ness is a result of the ranking system itself. Thus, scarcity becomes not simply a way of
increasing the price of a good that one may happen to hold, but the very good itself.
A man wishes to go out with a scarce woman because she is scarce—it is not that
attractive women are scarce, or that the attractive woman, by withholding sex (as in
Davis’s account), increases her bargain. The idea that one’s value within the ranking
system might be different from one’s visible attractiveness is amplified in the argu-
ments of Zetterberg, to which we now turn.
carries ‘‘that he can induce an emotional overcomeness among persons of the opposite
sex.’’ This probability is actualized—and changed—in erotic contests. ‘‘The steps up
and down [the erotic ranking] are not necessarily signalled in the form of sexual
relations between the principles . . . but as events when someone no longer is master
of his feelings’’ (Zetterberg 1966:135).7
Zetterberg suggested that erotic rank entered into rating and dating courtship à la
Waller,8 but he emphasized its independence from other forms of stratification,
including dating popularity. Despite its secret existential basis, Zetterberg believed
that the effects of the erotic ranking could be manifested in social disruption, espe-
cially when there was a disjunction between one’s erotic rank and one’s other ranks.
The tournament of erotic contests that gives rise to this rank seems quite divorced
from the stable pairings associated with marriage; however, Zetterberg believed the
erotic stratification to be relevant for such pairings. ‘‘We may take it as a worthwhile
assumption that equals in erotic rank get along best.’’ At the same time, Zetterberg,
like K. Davis (1966), claimed that persons of low erotic ranks may have offsetting
characteristics that lead to stable unions. This led Zetterberg (1966:136, 138, 139) to
ask ‘‘in what settings this ranking becomes dominant,’’ a key question he never
answered.
The story Collins told was a historical one of the development of a free market in this
property, culminating in the ‘‘personal sexual market’’ of the modern era.
There are, of course, rankings of men and women in terms of attractiveness in this
market, as discussed by Davis. But this ranking, for women at least, preceded the
emergence of this market, although at the dawn of modernity, sexual rank was well
synchronized with social rank. But with the emergence of market society, the middle
classes, the smaller household, and the state’s restriction on the use of violence against
women, women become ‘‘at least potentially free to negotiate their sexual relation-
ships.’’ This is done through the marriage market, in which the man trades ‘‘economic
and status resources for possession of a woman’’ whose ‘‘main resource’’ is her
sexuality. With the emergence of this market, women try to manipulate their scarcity:
‘‘The most favorable female strategy, in a situation in which men control the economic
world, is to maximize her bargaining power by appearing both as attractive and as
inaccessible as possible,’’ and to promote monogamy and stigmatize the promiscuous.
But with the entry of women into the paid labor force, they became more ‘‘free to
strike their bargains without economic compulsion’’ (1971:13f, 16).
Collins recognized that this was only a partial change, but that ‘‘it is now at least
possible for a number of different things to be bargained: income resources as well as
sexual attractiveness, social status, personal compatibility, deference, and emotional
support. . . . Where women bring economic resources of their own, they may concen-
trate on bargaining for sexual attractiveness on the part of men,’’ which leads to the
rise of the ideal of male sexual attractiveness. ‘‘A pure market based on rankings in
terms of sexuality, in the sense discussed by Zetterberg, thus becomes more prominent
for both men and women, but as only one of the many sexual markets in existence’’
(1971:17, 19).
Thus Collins integrated the timeless idea that women’s sexual scarcity is the key to
what power they have with a general and theoretically consistent approach to social
action as a combination of conflict and exchange. He discussed both the system of
exchange of male support for female sex à la Davis and the more autonomous sexual
ranking à la Zetterberg as being different, though overlapping, historical types. We
might therefore assume that such a market perspective is the most general and
reasonable one for the subject in question. But surely it seems somewhat odd to
begin by looking for a social organization of sexual desiring akin to the organization
of values of sociological theory, and end up with the apparently anomic world of the
market—in other words, the very historical circumstance of atomized action that
prompted the question! In fact, this tension was perceived by some of the authors.
We go on to demonstrate the weaknesses of the market approach.
that the others recognize the superiority of these, quit struggling, and turn their
attention elsewhere.’’ Similarly, Zetterberg (1966:141) argued that ‘‘[i]t is known that
society regulates whatever places persons in any one of its dimensions of
stratification. . . . If sexual relations produce ranks, that fact in itself will generate a
set of social norms,’’ but the only norms he brought into play were those stemming
from the fact that the ranking was to be kept secret.
This paradox of beginning with strong talk about the importance of norms and
ending up without any indicates the ambiguous nature of a sociological reliance on
anomic market metaphors to explain the social regulation of action. Although the
current work in economic sociology finds markets—real economic markets, even the
stock market—to be social institutions, not incarnated economic abstractions (Lie
1997; classic examples are White (1981), Baker (1984), and Fligstein (2001)), the
understanding of market behavior used to discuss sexuality tends to assume an
abstract and perfect market.
As Swedberg (1994) has stressed, classic economic treatments of markets have been
surprisingly undertheorized—what was meant by ‘‘market’’ was generally more
implicit than explicit. We may say that an efficient market exists when the following
conditions are met (see Stigler 1968:5–12): there are a large number of buyers and
sellers, none of whom commands a large proportion of the market, and all of whom
are free to decline any offered trade.11 Trades are made in money prices, and the costs
of making any transaction are negligible. Goods traded are divisible and comparable,
and their quality can be determined easily, or at least any information about their
quality not accessible to buyers would not alter buyers’ offered prices. Information
about the transactions made by others is public, and people rationally attempt to
maximize their own subjective utility. These assumptions lead to powerful results—
items carry prices that allow all individuals to increase their subjective utility and that
efficiently distribute supplies and direct production. Most relevant to us, the marginal
cost of a good to a buyer is the same as the marginal cost to a seller, and so we may
say that these prices bring ‘‘equality.’’
If the market approach made analytical sense, it would be rather unscientific to
reject it merely on the grounds of a disciplinary prejudice for stronger social factors.
But when we seek to uncover the social logic of sexual desiring, the market approach
fails us in two important ways. The first has to do with the oft-mentioned point that a
market approach dissolves into tautology when there are unobservable utility func-
tions (not to mention unobservable supply schedules, as in this case), as any outcome
can be explained by crafting appropriate utilities (see, e.g., Etzioni 1988). More
importantly, to ask why there is consensus regarding a principle of stratification in
sexual desirability is to ask a question about the basis of one of these utilities, that is,
the utility of one body as opposed to another. To make all utilities exogenous to the
analysis is then—as noted by Collins (1993:204) and Kanazawa (2001:1133)—to fail
to answer the question. Instead of having a useful framework in which to ask an
empirical question, we have a one-size-fits-all story that tells us nothing in particular.
The second failure is more particular to the case of a ‘‘sexual’’ market, in which no
objects are exchanged that carry prices. This drowns whatever tautological virtues the
market approach might have when utilities are unobservable in a sea of confusion, as
analysts cannot separate the price of an object, its utility for a purchaser, its intrinsic
value, and the object itself. As England and Farkas (1986:53) point out in their
11
This last point is generally forgotten by rational choice theorists, such as Coleman (1990), who consider
any fight an exchange and any meleé a market.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 115
The first component of this utility, xj, is the ‘‘attractiveness’’ of the potential partner,
however defined, while the various zjk are all those factors affecting the utility of the
partner that are not perceived as ‘‘attractiveness’’ per se. For example, in Davis’s
model, one such z might be wealth. The weights ai and bi indicate that various factors
are weighed differently by different persons; if we wanted to fully replicate Davis’s
analysis, these would be functions of the marginal utility of person j’s contribution of
some factor to person i’s existing stock. The social organization here is found in the
fact that the factors only have j subscripts, not i’s—there is no disagreement among
persons as to how others ‘‘rate’’ on various attributes. None of the authors we
reviewed introduced such disagreement.
If we are to give the market model fullest flexibility, the ‘‘attractiveness’’ component
x must be potentially decomposable into two portions: one x* that has to do with
some specific bodily attractiveness, and others w that are not directly bodily yet are
immediately perceived in the form of greater attractiveness.13 To illustrate: if women
follow Davis’s logic or Parsons’s ([1942] 1949c:225) ‘‘female glamour pattern’’ and
prefer ‘‘rich and powerful men’’ because they are willing to give up some attractiveness
in a potential partner to gain riches and power, then ‘‘riches’’ and ‘‘power’’ enter into
this model as zs. If, however, women perceive rich and powerful men as attractive,
then riches and power enter this model as ws. The distinction between these two types
of elements is clearly central for any sociological investigation of the organization of
desiring.
The market approach we analyze not only defines the utility of one person for
another as above, it also makes the substantive claim that as a market, the sexual
12
The Laumann et al. volume, being the result of collaboration between researchers of different back-
grounds, has overlapping and at times frankly competing explanatory strategies; here, we focus only on the
market approach. But we wish to note that two of the authors, in recent theoretical work (Laumann and
Gagnon 1995, esp. at p. 204), have called for a study of the social structuring of sexual pairing in terms
compatible with our approach below. Further, we must acknowledge that our general approach has been
greatly influenced by the earlier work of Laumann on networks and Gagnon on scripting. Once again, we
subject this work to critical attention precisely because we believe that it is exemplary, and hence any
analytic problems can be traced back to the use of market metaphors.
13
Because of this immediacy, we refrain from assigning weights to the different components.
116 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
substantively empty, since this utility is totally invisible, and one is free to postulate an
equally plausible, and equally invisible, utility pulling in the opposite direction. In
other words, the addition of a utility to partner specificity can explain why there is less
changing of partners than might otherwise be expected—if this is observed. But, of
course, were people to change partners more often than might be expected, this can be
explained with equal ease—the utility coming from novelty outweighs that coming
from asset specificity. The same theoretical apparatus can be invoked to account for
totally opposite findings.
A reasonable response would be that one should not fault theory for missing
observations; it is in principle possible to measure the acquisition of partner-specific
skills, in which case this becomes a testable claim. But—and here is the key point—
given the market assumption, any such data only force us to repeat the cycle of
inventing new utilities to balance the equation. That is, we may compute new pre-
dicted utilities that take into account this new factor we have measured, but still find
some difference e’ between them. Indeed, such an e’ is certainly expected if, like
Collins, one posits an infinite number of other possible factors that go into the general
utility. We see Laumann et al. (1994:11) inexorably drawn along in this direction: they
continue their analysis by reasonably suggesting that ‘‘[a]nother type of human capital
used to secure sexual activity is the skills necessary for maintaining an existing
relationship. These might include . . . the ability to accommodate his or her personality
and interests, to get along with his or her family and friends and so forth.’’
There are two things to note here, in addition to the fundamental point that this is
indeed a logically sound extension of the market approach. The first is that we are
clearly moving away from the identification of factors that are components of ‘‘attrac-
tiveness’’ per se (ws in the model above), and moving toward ones that are theoreti-
cally opposing, namely, factors that can compensate for a lack of attractiveness (zs).
Yet there is nothing in the market model that can distinguish between the utility
gained by that portion of one’s partner’s human capital that is realized in the form of
one’s increased sexual pleasure, and that which is realized in the form of easier
relations with one’s parents. Accordingly, while this may have relevance for issues
of choice (Laumann et al.’s primary concern), this seems unlikely to be a fruitful way
to understand desiring.
The second thing to note is that not only does such an approach seem to miss the
‘‘desiring’’ aspect of the organization of desiring, it also misses the organization.
Laumann et al. clearly consider this sexual human capital as something that should
be stable in terms of its differential distribution—accordingly, they attempt to discuss
those who ‘‘possess more of the traits most valued.’’ Yet their definition of such
resources resists any such definition. The analogous situation in economics to
Laumann et al.’s ‘‘human capital’’ for dates (which includes the ability to get along
with one’s partner’s family) would be to attempt to construct a theory in which
human capital included being the same height as one’s boss. It would be impossible
then to speak of people who had ‘‘more’’ human capital than others. In other words,
we logically must abandon the constraints on those weights (b) that would allow us to
use the assumption of equal exchange to identify factors (z) contributing to increased
utility.
Thus the market approach’s strength—its ability to consistently find creative terms
to justify its assumption of equal exchange—is its weakness. But imagine that the
market analyst is eventually faced with evidence of stubborn differences in utilities
that will not go away. What can be done? In a brilliant move, the analyst can
postulate that the very disutility of the less attractive partner is a utility. Collins
118 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
(1975:253) writes: ‘‘A highly secure and (erotically or economically) attractive person
can profit from a ‘mismatch’ to a less attractive person, by demanding greater
subservience from him or her as the price of staying.’’ But if one’s disutility is one’s
very utility (the more attractive chooses the less attractive in order to get the sub-
servience), then it seems that any pairing is matched in terms of price by fiat.
The only response to the charge of tautology is to admit that there could be
situations in which the more attractive partner refuses to exact any surplus subser-
vience from the less attractive. But it is hard to imagine that a market theorist would
need to accept this as a falsification of the postulate of equal exchange; one simply
brings in the well-known egoistic utility of altruism, and hence the pleasure taken in
refraining from obtaining subservience, and the equation is again balanced. Indeed, it
is not hard to imagine the most rarified utility of all being the second-order pleasure
taken in not taking pleasure in refraining from exacting subservience. The point is not
that such utilities are impossible, it is that this line of theorizing is necessarily flawed if
any disproof is handled by the creation of a utility that only serves to cancel the
disproof. It is as if the error term in an equation were instantly made into a theoretical
term, leading a model to fit perfectly. We go from a model of rational action to a model
rationalizing action; we can come up with a seemingly good excuse for any observation.14
16
On the connection between orthodox economics and the rise of the idea of desire as fundamentally
idiosyncratic, see Birken (1988).
17
It is worth speculatively amplifying this contrast. An analysis along these lines might then suggest that in
such a system women are the currency that gives the price for men, who have an indexically formed value
from other systems (fraternity, sports). Although the idea of an ‘‘exchange of women’’ underlying the
general ‘‘political economy’’ of the sex/gender system à la Rubin (1985) is historically untenable, in such
cases as the rating-dating game, to the extent that women’s dating value is only a function of their scarcity
(and not, as is also the case, a function of their sorority, looks, dancing, etc.), then women may approximate
the free-floating significance function of money in ordering male prestige. Evidence of this in college dating
is given by Holland and Eisenhart (1990:96, 99, 105, 212; also see Irigaray 1985:170–91). It is perhaps not
without significance that Levi-Strauss’s own preemptive critique of Rubin’s approach holds that ‘‘women
are not primarily a sign of social value, but a natural stimulant’’—not simply a sign of value but the value
itself (Levi-Strauss [1949] 1969:62, 496), thus corroborating the implication of the above analysis that the
dissociation of the sexual field from sexual satisfaction allows the function of social valuation to become
primary.
120 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
In sum, whatever virtues the market approach has in constructing a ‘‘just-so story’’
for whatever is observed, these vanish in the situations where the attractiveness of any
person for another is shaped by the opinions of third parties. What, then, is left? Most
important is the assumption that if persons i and j successfully pair, then uij ¼ uji. In
other words, each person’s utility is a sufficient measure of the ‘‘price’’ of the other.
Indeed, were there a sexual market, this is what it would accomplish, for a market—as
opposed to just any conjunction of individuals pursuing their ends—is a place where
efficient prices are made. But as noted above, the sexual market produces no prices,
and if it is any kind of market, the sexual market must be a barter market (also see
Collins (1993:213f) regarding the more general case of symbolic interactions), which
unfortunately possesses none of the qualities that most endear markets to social
theorists (e.g., utility maximization).
As we have seen above, Laumann et al. recognized this difficulty due to an absence
of prices, but maintained that the pairing is sufficiently market-like to ensure the
matching of persons of equal value. ‘‘Anyone who has participated in the market for
sex partners knows that those possessing more of the traits most valued in a particular
culture have more opportunities for exchange than those possessing fewer. The
majority of these opportunities are likely to involve similarly or less attractive poten-
tial partners, from among whom each individual is expected to choose the ‘best deal’
that he or she can get. This mechanism of competition generates partnerships in which
the two partners are likely to have similar ‘values’ on the partner market’’ (1994:12),
since a partner will withdraw from a relationship where the costs outweighs the
benefits (1994:21).
However, this is to confuse a Panglossian comparison to an alternative road not
taken (you chose this person as opposed to not choosing, so the benefit must outweigh
the cost) with a wholly different issue of equal exchanges (your net gain is the same as
your partner’s net gain). Analysts seem to make the unreasonable assumption that the
cost to oneself of consenting to the pairing is the same as one’s utility for the other,
again a result of the confusion between value-in-oneself and value-for-another; it is
this assumption that leads to the belief that consent implies equality. But this is not
necessarily so. If we imagine a population divided into two subgroups A and B, with
identical preferences, and similar distributions in terms of ‘‘attractiveness’’ (x) differ-
ing only in mean ‘‘quality’’ (say the mean for group A is greater than that for B, i.e.,
E[xA] > E[xB]), then all persons might pair according to rank in their respective
subgroup (A1 matched with B1, A2 with B2, etc.), while every single A comes off
worse than the corresponding B. That is, for person i from group A and person j from
group B, (uij ¼ axj) < (uji ¼ axi) where a is some positive scaling constant; this can be true
even if the net gain for the member of group A is positive, that is, uij > 0. In short, the fact
that one has consented to an exchange does not imply that the exchange is equal.
Indeed, the most rigorous economic approach to this issue has taken the form of
what is called a two-sided matching game, where we assume that all unions are serially
monogamous, that each man has a partial order of preferences for female partners,
and that each woman has a partial order of preferences for male partners. (Here, we
rely on Roth and Sotomayor (1990).) Several important conclusions have been drawn
from such modeling, but they are not at all those derived on the basis of the market
metaphor. First, while it can be proved that such games have stable equilibria closely
analogous to a Nash equilibrium (there is no M1 matched to W1 and W2 matched to
M2 such that W1 prefers M2 to M1, and M2 prefers W1 to M2), it is not true that just
any process of social interaction will actually reach such an equilibrium—indeed, the
more plausible mechanisms do not.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 121
Second, such equilibria are not guaranteed to exist for single-sided matching
(e.g., homosexual fields). None of the authors we reviewed would have been likely
to propose that the dynamics of heterosexual fields were integrally dependent on
the twoness of the choice process. (The extent to which homosexual pairing may
have a two-sided nature is of great importance and has been explored by Wiley and
Herschkorn (1989).) Third, the matching process does not allow us to conclude that
the utility contributed by the partners is equal; indeed, it necessarily follows that the
interests of men as a whole run counter to those of women. The matching that is best
for the men is worst for the women. And certainly, one cannot make any conclusions
as to the tradeoffs between different utilities that might enter the matching process—
all of this is folded into each individual’s ranking, which is treated as given and
nonproblematic.
Thus the simple claim of equal exchange does not follow from the axiom of rational
and free actors, nor, accepted as an postulate, does it have any theoretically produc-
tive consequences.18 What is left of the market approach, then, is only the cost-benefit
rationality of the actors. But in the absence of a true market, we can derive nothing
from this; furthermore, this is the one thing we know not to be generally the case: to
the extent that persons adopt a cost-benefit subjectivity to ensure their happiness in
sexual relationships, they are more likely to be unhappy (see Sprecher 1998). The only
recourse left is to claim the rationality of choosing not to be rational; we leave it to
others to determine what explanatory power such a formulation has.19
In sum, we must accept the fundamental poverty of the market approach in the
analyses reviewed; far from simply being tautological, it is an approach that aspires to
tautology and only reaches paradox. We emphasize that our claim is not that a
market analysis cannot treat sexual decision making; indeed, it may be empirically
testable, but only when attractiveness is exogenously given (e.g., some people are
beautiful). To the extent that trans-individual consistencies in sexual desiring are more
complex that this, and we seek to explain them, the market approach fails us
spectacularly. Further, we do not object to the particular assumptions that often go
into the market metaphor (e.g., high agreement on attractiveness, compensating
utilities, self-interested behavior). Our point is that even if these assumptions are
empirically justified, the social organization of pairing is not such as to lead to the
strong conclusions made by analysts. Finally, we do not claim that sexual decision
making cannot be rigorously modeled using approaches pioneered in economics, but
such modeling does not rehabilitate the conclusions that have been drawn from the
market metaphor.
Be that as it may, a market model of anything generates a tremendous degree of face
plausibility in 21st-century America. Accordingly, sympathetic readers often note that
modifications to the classical market model that allow for a more realistic application
to actual economic markets also produce models that do not necessarily suffer the
18
Analyses of mate choice that take seriously the process involved propose that information on the
distribution of possible partners’ quality is so costly that rational individuals do not try to maximize the
quality of their partner, but ‘‘satisfice,’’ or take the first one over a ‘‘reservation threshold.’’ See England and
Farkas (1986:39f) and Todd and Miller (1999).
19
Posner (1992:85) finally throws out this one substantive element of the rational choice approach, namely,
the assumption of rationality: ‘‘Responding appropriately to incentives, whether consciously or not, is
rational; so animals are rational as well as people.’’ Now it may be true that much of animal behavior
can be profitably studied in terms of rational action, such as foraging behavior (see, e.g., Drent 1982), but
one can be sure that Posner means to include all animal action—the lemming hurling itself off a cliff is, in a
sense, rational, and it is this sense that is a dead end for sociology. It is not necessary that respecting the
exogenous and idiosyncratic nature of preferences structures necessarily leads to abandoning a substantively
meaningful definition of rationality: for example, see von Magnus (1984:640).
122 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
deficits we have outlined here. Exactly—for these modifications entail the systematic
unraveling of the very constraints that give the market model any general explanatory
power, and simply replace ‘‘market’’ with ‘‘interpersonal interactions.’’ Since we know
already that sexual behavior falls into this category, the use of such weakened market
terminology clearly adds nothing.20 Put another way, everyone agrees that sexual
pairing is not a strict price-making market, but that it is like a market. But the
possibility of metaphor is not itself a sufficient justification for an analytic approach
devoid of explanatory power.
What happens, then, when we cast aside the market metaphor? We need not only
follow Waller in examining the principle whereby differential evaluation is assigned to
prospective partners, but also to problematize the goal of sexual action. In what
follows we go on to use field theory to discuss how such a problematization can be
made; we argue that this extends Weberian action theory in a more satisfactory
manner than the market approach. Indeed, the question of the organization of sexual
value comes directly out of Weber’s own work, but his approach relies on surprisingly
a-sociological premises that are remedied by attention to the sexual field.
Weber argued, then, that modernization has led to the creation of a distinct value
sphere of eroticism, with its own goal that is necessarily distinct from ‘‘organic’’ sex
per se. It possesses its own laws of action and development, and correspondingly
appears in distinct unions (extramarital affairs). Although it is a sphere of opposition
to the rationalization of life in general, its existence is negatively defined by this very
rationalization, and while it claims to transcend other conflicting values on the
grounds of a destined conjunction of two souls, it is unavoidably a contest à la
Zetterberg of ‘‘the most intimate coercion of the soul of the less brutal partner’’
(1946:348).
Weber thus proceeded beyond the others in suggesting that the sexual system can
have goals somewhat detached from the simple satisfaction of a biological impulse,
but he nowhere explained how he had deduced that such eroticism is a necessarily
fundamental value sphere (as opposed to, say, a Wallerian sphere of popularity). As
mentioned above (note 22), Weber drew this idea of value spheres from Rickert
(1913), but Rickert’s system of values was constructed on trans-historical principles
unappealing to sociologists. Weber’s formulation of an erotic value sphere also
contained something profoundly asocial—while its pairings have a distinct institu-
tional form (the affair), the laws of the erotic value sphere are unrelated to concrete
institutions.
Contemporary Weberians tend to ignore this sexual aspect of Weber’s understand-
ing of the effects of rationalization;23 however, we see it as a significant precedent for
theorizing the formation of an autonomous sphere of specifically sexual action with
its own logic—but a precedent with a philosophical grounding untenable for a flexible
sociological theory. This leads us to the field theory of Pierre Bourdieu, which, we
hope to show, can generalize and position both the market-based approaches to
sexual stratification found in Davis et al., and the value-spheres-based approach to
the goal of sexual action of Weber. To summarize our review, the American tradition
of action theory understood ‘‘value’’ to imply both an integrative function, and a
correspondence to price; hence discussions slipped from analyzing the social construc-
tion of sexual desiring to analyzing the sexual construction of social desiring—allow-
ing theorists to uncovered their usual suspects for explaining macro order (rationality
and integration) applied to a new domain. While the American tradition built on one
portion of Weber’s work, it ignored what Roth has called Weber’s sociology of
domination. Bourdieu begins with this portion of Weber, but integrates it with the
conception of fields, preserving the distinct laws (eigengesetzlichkeit) that Weber saw
as characteristic of value spheres (Bourdieu 1990a:389, [1989] 1996:433, n. 2), but
without making transcendent philosophical assumptions.
23
It is interesting that Habermas (1987:326) excises eroticism as one of the value spheres when discussing
the above work of Weber (he also excises power as a value sphere in its own right), so as to make it
compatible with his own trinitarian formula of self/other/thing. But he then must include sexual stratifica-
tion in an entirely different form: in his explication of the sources of prestige, he divides attributes from
resources, and both are in turn divided into empirical versus rational (a division that corresponds roughly to
whether they motivate via systemic media or via communication oriented to mutual understanding). Among
the empirical attributes are strength (which allows reward or punishment), know-how (which produces
expectations of success), and physical attractiveness (which produces emotional ties) (Habermas 1987:182).
He then not only ignores erotic know-how and makes it a merely physical attribute, but because of his
refusal to consider sex a fundamental ‘‘moment,’’ he links this physical attribute to emotional ties that the
body somehow inspires. Parsons (1979:2), however, did not make this excision—instead, he proposed a triad
of erotic/economic/intellectual spheres for explaining social evolution.
124 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
24
For example, despite the looseness of Bourdieu’s equation of capital with ‘‘that which can be the basis of
power,’’ we still prefer ‘‘capital’’ over the seemingly more neutral ‘‘resources’’ of James Coleman (1990), since
from Marx sociologists are likely to understand capital not as a thing, but as a relation, and it is such a
relation that underlies the ‘‘sexual capital’’ that is equivalent to a consensus regarding desirability.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 125
We propose that what all the authors reviewed above have been discussing is the
sexual field, that is, the field in which the ‘‘libido’’ as discussed by Bourdieu is socially
identical to the specifically sexual libido; the riddle on which the market metaphors
foundered was determining the nature of specifically sexual capital and its degrees of
convertibility.25
Bourdieu himself does not see sexuality as being institutionalized in a particular
field; we argue that this is related to certain inconsistencies and loosenesses in his
usage. First of all, being mainly concerned with class exclusion and taste in Distinction
(which contains his most developed theory of attraction), he emphasizes homogamy
as the principle not only of marriage but also of love: ‘‘Love is also a way of loving
one’s own destiny in someone else and so feeling loved in one’s own destiny’’
(Bourdieu [1979] 1984:243). Intentionally or not, Bourdieu ironically echoes the
romantic definition of love as destiny—also discussed by Weber ([1915] 1946:348)—
but replaces the romantic’s vision of a supra-mundane order of souls and sensibilities
with predictable trajectories through social space.
When it comes to sexual attraction, as opposed to love, Bourdieu has not been
wholly consistent (also see McNay 1999:96). At some points, he suggests that class
homogamy operates: thus Bourdieu ([1989] 1996:180, 182) argues that as different
schoolings inculcate differences in bodily hexis ‘‘and even sexual habits’’ as well as
differences in habitus, there will be a tendency for like to like like (at least within the
dominant class that he is here examining). ‘‘As social positions embodied in bodily
dispositions, habitus contribute to determining whether (biological) bodies come
together or stay apart by inscribing between two bodies the attractions and repulsions
that correspond to the relationship between the positions of which they are the
embodiment.’’ But in other places, he parses sexual desirability into one element
coming from what the body signifies about the agent’s trajectory through social
space, and a second element, exogenous beauty, which is an accident of birth. Thus
Bourdieu ([1979] 1984:91) admits that ‘‘[e]ducationally equivalent individuals . . . may
differ radically as regards bodily hexis,’’ and that the latter can be used to accumulate
social capital.26 Bourdieu assumes that what is specific to sexual attractiveness (as
opposed to the valorization of class bodies) is ‘‘natural,’’ which is clearly incompatible
with a notion of sexual capital.
Bourdieu ([1979] 1984:152f) recognizes ‘‘the constitution of a socially recognized
corps of experts specializing in advice on sexuality,’’ but he does not take this to imply
25
Chancer has also proposed that ‘‘looks’’ can function ‘‘as a form of capital, as Bourdieu depicts’’
(1998:117f); while there are clear convergences between her approach and ours, there are important
differences. Most important, she defines capital in nonautonomous terms: because of her interest in the
use of women as a status signal among men (1998:114ff), sexual capital becomes something that women
possess but is used by men as a form of symbolic capital. Because she sees this system as at the heart of
sexism, Chancer then views sexual capital as a resource that disempowers those who hold it (1998:261). This
definition of sexual capital as something women are forced to have means that rather than formulate a
specifically sexual field, with its own mode of domination, Chancer posits a synchronization with other
forms of domination (e.g., race, sex, class) (1998:120). Although not using the term ‘‘sexual capital,’’
Holland and Eisenhart (1990:102f, 212, 218) make analogies to Bourdieu’s work on symbolic capital
when analyzing the logic of attractiveness.
26
‘‘One can begin to map out a universe of class bodies, which (biological accidents apart) tends to
reproduce in its specific logic the universe of the social structure. It is no accident that bodily properties
are perceived through social systems of classification which are not independent of the distribution of these
properties among the social classes. . . . Thus, bodies would have every likelihood of receiving a value strictly
corresponding to the positions of their owners in the distribution of the other fundamental properties—but
for the fact that the logic of social heredity sometimes endows those least endowed in all other respects with
the rarest bodily properties, such as beauty (sometimes ‘fatally’ attractive, because it threatens the other
hierarchies), and, conversely, sometimes denies the ‘high and mighty’ the bodily attributes of their positions,
such as height and beauty’’ (Bourdieu [1979] 1984:193).
126 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
the autonomy of the sexual field and hence a sexual capital; rather, attractiveness is
merely a form of ‘‘physical charm’’ that is, oddly, part of ‘‘cultural capital.’’ And
finally, while Bourdieu has occasionally (e.g., Bourdieu 1978:832) discussed sexual
attractiveness as a convertible resource, it has only been in the form of a general
physical capital available to the dominated classes, and it is gendered female, as
opposed to male, physical capital that leads to the sporting field (Wacquant 2003;
cf. Shilling 1993:127–47).
To some extent, these ambiguities come from his trying to discuss a form of
convertible capital that is not generated by a specific field, but they also seem related
to a more general ambiguity in Bourdieu’s notion of the habitus. Since the habitus, as
a set of classifying practices, is not conscious, Bourdieu (as any good Cartesian) tends
to assimilate it to the ‘‘body’’; further, the connotations of the Latin ‘‘habitus’’ include
‘‘bearing’’ or ‘‘deportment.’’ Thus Bourdieu tends to assume an inseparability between
the unconscious disposition that classifies bodies and the socially shaped bodily hexis
that is classified. Logic leads Bourdieu then to look for the homogamous attraction
due to the naturalizing process whereby the body classifying and the body classified
are shaped by the same social environment. But Bourdieu recognizes the insufficiency
of such an explanation, and so (not wholly unlike the market theorists we criticized)
he relies on an ‘‘accident of birth’’ to explain the rest.
These contradictions can be eliminated by considering the possibility of a specifi-
cally sexual field with a bodily capital that is not wholly indexical (i.e., that has no
value in itself, but merely points to the value of the person in some other social space),
but—to the extent that the field is autonomous—has its own genetic logic. Indeed,
other theorists have pointed to what may be seen as the creation of an autonomous
sexual field in the West during the past century.27 But the virtue of the vocabulary of
field is not its parsimony, nor the ability to retell the analyses of other theorists.
Instead, it directs us to certain empirical and historical questions that are difficult to
frame within the market perspective, and that also seem to us to be reasonable
avenues of investigation. We conclude by outlining three.
release per se)? Certainly, we must be able to specify some such organizing principle
that is distinct from marriage or nonsexual leisure activities (e.g., ballroom dancing).
Further, we can ask several questions about the nature of sexual capital. First, we
attempt to specify not only what set of properties—or, perhaps better, what set of
relations—functions as sexual capital (as, e.g., in the empirical work of Holland and
Skinner (1987)), but also what field conditions allow this set of properties to function
as capital (Bourdieu [1989] 1996:264). Although researchers have repeatedly demon-
strated that there is a reasonably high agreement as to personal ‘‘attractiveness’’ (see
Feingold’s (1988) meta-analysis), little has been done to explore the logic of this
ranking, let alone its sociogenesis. But as Collins (1975:281) noted: ‘‘Attractiveness
is a social role as much as a state of appearance; learning to play it with self-
confidence results in a self-fulfilling prophecy, while the opposite process leads to
cumulative failure through awkwardness of posture, complexion, and the like.’’
Although Collins (1993) has pointed to the possible cumulative nature of success in
interaction ritual chains, and other researchers have noted that relative status position
affects how people hold their bodies (see the review in Henley 1977:82–93), we
propose that to understand the production of sexual capital, we must investigate
not only what properties are conventionally labeled as ‘‘attractive,’’ but how they
index a trajectory through the sexual field.
Second, we can attempt to determine the position of this capital on a general
dimension. Bourdieu ([1980] 1990b:57, 130; cf. 1986:243) speaks of two states of
capital, as objectified in institutions (the field) and as incorporated in the body as
habitus; he then suggests that the degree of the objectification of capital—its position
in the dialectic of the internalization of field as habitus and the externalization of
habitus as trajectory—is the most important difference between modes of domina-
tion.28 When fully exteriorized as in Waller’s endogenous dating rank, sexual capital,
we hazard, is akin to Coleman’s social capital: it is a network property of a node, as
opposed to an attribute of an isolated unit. When fully interiorized, sexual capital is
wholly a matter of the body and its ‘‘bearing’’ or ‘‘hexis.’’
There is reason not only to think that it is possible for sexual capital to vary in
degree of objectification (with implications as to the volatility and ‘‘naturalization’’ of
the sexual field), but also for this degree of objectification to differ for men and
women. Indeed, it is possible that ‘‘gender’’—that is, our cultural understandings of
sexual difference—is a kind of folk-sociological attempt to reference the differences
between the strategies of sexual capitalization of men and women, heterosexuals and
homosexuals, normal and deviant (see also McNay 1999:112). Once again, such
investigation is impossible from within the market perspective, where all desires are
unfathomable, idiosyncratic, exogenous, and yet absolutely comparable. The market
approach must posit a trans-historical attractiveness, as opposed to studying how
concrete institutions of the sexual field—for example, the barn dance as opposed to
the frat party—lead to different constitutions of sexual capital.
The third direction is to describe objectively the degree of autonomy of the sexual
field. Previously, analysts have focused on the disorganizing potential of sexual desire,
at least when this is joined with romantic love: it is that which messes up stratification
systems (Goode 1959). But if this is because the sexual field has its own logic (as
claimed by Weitman (1998:75)), and its own dictates, then the absence of one type of
organization is due to the presence of another. Are there concrete institutions that are
28
Interestingly, Laumann and Pappi (1976:188) also classified resources in terms of the degree to which
they were network or individual phenomena, as well as their degree of convertibility.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 129
29
It is perhaps worth pointing out that, as noted by Kent (1983:312), the one example Weber ([1920]
1976:263, n. 22) provided of ‘‘[s]pecialists without spirit, sensualists without heart’’ was the new medicalized
sexual expert wresting evaluation of sexual propriety from the puritan divine.
30
It is interesting that this understanding of price is not that of the economists of DeBeauvoir’s days: it is
that of Hobbes ([1651] 1909:67): ‘‘The value, or WORTH of a man, is . . . his Price. . . . And as in other things,
so in men, not the seller, but the buyer determines the Price.’’
130 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
explanations. We may hope that attention to the sexual field will allow us to empiri-
cally investigate these questions, if not to begin a critique of sexual judgment.
REFERENCES
Adler, P. A. and P. Adler. 1998. Peer Power: Preadolescent Culture and Identity. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press.
Altman, D. 1983. The Homosexualization of America. New York: Beacon Press.
Bailey, B. L. 1988. From Front Porch to Back Seat. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Baker, W. E. 1984. ‘‘The Social Structure of a National Securities Market.’’ American Journal of Sociology
89:775–811.
Batten, M. 1992. Sexual Strategies. New York: Putnam.
Birken, L. 1988. Consuming Desire: Sexual Science and the Emergence of a Culture of Abundance 1871–1914.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Bourdieu, P. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice, translated by R. Nice. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
———. 1978. ‘‘Sport and Social Class,’’ translated by R. Nice. Social Science Information 17:819–40.
———. [1979] 1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste, translated by R. Nice.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
———. [1983] 1986. ‘‘The Forms of Capital.’’ Pp. 241–58 in Handbook of Theory and Research for the
Sociology of Education, edited by J. G. Richardson. New York: Greenwood Press.
———. 1990a. ‘‘The Scholastic Point of View.’’ Cultural Anthropology 5:380–91.
———. [1980] 1990b. The Logic of Practice. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
———. 1990c. In Other Words, translated by M. Adamson. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
———. [1989] 1996. The State Nobility, translated by L. C. Clough. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Burgess, E. W. and H. J. Locke. [1945] 1950. The Family: From Institution to Companionship. New York:
American Book Company.
Butler, J. 2004. Undoing Gender. London: Routledge.
Chancer, L. S. 1998. Reconcilable Differences: Confronting Beauty, Pornography, and the Future of
Feminism. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Coleman, J. S. 1984. ‘‘Introducing Social Structure into Economic Analyses.’’ American Economic Review
74:84–88.
———. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Collins, R. 1971. ‘‘A Conflict Theory of Sexual Stratification.’’ Social Problems 19:3–21.
———. 1975. Conflict Sociology: Toward an Explanatory Science. New York: Academic Press.
———. 1993. ‘‘Emotional Energy as the Common Denominator of Rational Action.’’ Rationality and
Society 5:203–30.
———. 2004. Interaction Ritual Chains. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Davis, K. 1936. ‘‘Jealousy and Sexual Property.’’ Social Forces 14:395–405.
———. 1966. ‘‘Sexual Behavior.’’ Pp. 322–72 in Contemporary Social Problems, 2nd ed., edited by R. K.
Merton and R. A. Nisbet. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.
Davis, K. and W. E. Moore. 1945. ‘‘Some Principles of Stratification.’’ American Sociological Review
10:242–49.
Davis, M. 1983. Smut: Erotic Reality/Obscene Ideology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
de Beauvoir, S. [1949] 1989. The Second Sex, translated and edited by H. M. Parshley. New York: Vintage
Books.
DiMaggio, P. J. and W. W. Powell. 1983. ‘‘The Iron Cage Revisited: Institutional Isomorphism and
Collective Rationality in Organizational Fields.’’ American Sociological Review 48:147–60.
Drent, R. H. 1982. ‘‘Risk-Benefit Assessment in Animals.’’ Pp. 75–94 in Animal Mind—Human Mind, edited
by D. R. Griffin. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Elder, G. H., Jr. 1969. ‘‘Appearance and Education in Marriage Mobility.’’ American Sociological Review
34:519–33.
England, P. and G. Farkas. 1986. Households, Employment and Gender: A Social, Economic and
Demographic View. New York: Aldine.
Etzioni, A. 1988. The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. New York: Free Press.
Feingold, A. 1988. ‘‘Matching for Attractiveness in Romantic Partners and Same-Sex Friends: A Meta-
Analysis and Theoretical Critique.’’ Psychological Bulletin 104:226–35.
SEXUAL STRATIFICATION 131
Fligstein, N. 2001. The Architecture of Markets. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Forel, A. [1906] 1929. The Sexual Question, translated and edited by C. F. Marshall. New York: Physicians
and Surgeons Book Company.
Foucault, M. [1976] 1980. The History of Sexuality. Volume I: An Introduction, translated by R. Hurley.
New York: Vintage.
———. [1984] 1986. The History of Sexuality. Volume III: The Care of the Self, translated by R. Hurley.
New York: Pantheon.
Freud, S. 1938. ‘‘Three Contributions to the Theory of Sex.’’ In The Basic Writings of Sigmund Freud,
translated and edited by A. A. Brill. New York: Modern Library.
Frey, B. S. and R. Eichenberger. 1996. ‘‘Marriage Paradoxes.’’ Rationality and Society 8:187–206.
George, M. C. 1996. ‘‘The Critique of Sexual Reason.’’ Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation. University of
California, Berkeley, CA.
Giddens, A. 1991. Modernity and Self Identity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
———. 1992. The Transformation of Intimacy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Goode, W. J. 1959. ‘‘The Theoretical Importance of Love.’’ American Sociological Review 24:38–47.
Habermas, J. 1987. The Theory of Communicative Action. Volume 2: Lifeworld and System: A Critique of
Functionalist Reason, translated by T. McCarthy. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Henley, N. M. 1977. Body Politics. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Hirschman, A. O. 1977. The Passions and the Interests. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hobbes, T. [1651] 1909. Leviathan. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Holland, D. and M. A. Eisenhart. 1990. Educated in Romance: Women, Achievement and College Culture.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Holland, D. and D. Skinner. 1987. ‘‘Prestige and Intimacy: The Cultural Models Behind Americans’ Talk
about Gender Types.’’ Pp. 78–111 in Cultural Models in Language and Thought, edited by D. Holland and
N. Quinn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holmes, S. J. and C. E. Hatch. 1938. ‘‘Personal Appearance as Related to Scholastic Records and Marriage
Selection in College Women.’’ Human Biology 10:65–76.
Hume, D. [1777] 1985. Essays, Moral, Political and Literary. Indianapolis, IN: Literary Fund.
Illouz, E. 1997. Consuming the Romantic Utopia: Love and the Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Irigaray, L. 1985. The Sex Which is Not One. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Jackson, M. 1987. ‘‘‘Facts of Life’ or the Eroticization of Women’s Oppression? Sexology and the Social
Construction of Heterosexuality.’’ Pp. 52–81 in The Cultural Construction of Sexuality, edited by
P. Caplan. London: Tavistock Publications.
Kanazawa, S. 2001. ‘‘De Gustibus Est Disputandum.’’ Social Forces 79:1131–63.
Kent, S. A. 1983. ‘‘Weber, Goethe, and the Nietzschean Allusion: Capturing the Source of the ‘Iron Cage’
Metaphor.’’ Sociological Analysis 44:297–320.
Laumann, E. O. and J. H. Gagnon. 1995. ‘‘A Sociological Perspective on Sexual Action.’’ Pp. 183–213 in
Conceiving Sexuality, edited by R. G. Parker and J. H. Gagnon. New York: Routledge.
Laumann, E. O., J. H. Gagnon, R. T. Michael, and S. Michaels. 1994. The Social Organization of Sexuality:
Sexual Practices in the United States. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Laumann, E. O and F. U Pappi. 1976. Networks of Collective Action: A Perspective on Community Influence
Systems. New York: Academic Press.
Levi-Strauss, C. [1949] 1969. The Elementary Structures of Kinship, translated by J. H. Bell, J. R. von
Sturmer, and R. Needham. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Lie, J. 1997. ‘‘Sociology of Markets.’’ Annual Review of Sociology 23:341–60.
Loewenstein, G. 1996. ‘‘Out of Control: Visceral Influences on Behavior.’’ Organizational Behavior and
Human Decision Processes 65:272–92.
Martin, J. L. 1996. ‘‘Structuring the Sexual Revolution.’’ Theory and Society 25:105–51.
———. 2003. ‘‘What is Field Theory?’’ American Journal of Sociology 109:1–49.
McNay, L. 1999. ‘‘Gender, Habitus and the Field: Pierre Bourdieu and the Limits of Reflexivity.’’ Theory,
Culture and Society 16:95–117.
Orléan, André. 1988. ‘‘Money and Mimetic Speculation,’’ translated by M. R. Anspach. Pp. 101–12 in
Violence and Truth, edited by P. Dumouchel. London: Athlone Press.
Ortner, S. B. and H. Whitehead. 1981. Sexual Meanings, The Cultural Construction of Gender and Sexuality.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Parsons, T. [1940] 1949a. ‘‘An Analytical Approach to the Theory of Social Stratification.’’ Pp. 166–84 in
Essays in Sociological Theory, Pure and Applied. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
132 SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
———. [1940] 1949b. ‘‘The Motivation of Economic Activities.’’ Pp. 200–17 in Essays in Sociological
Theory, Pure and Applied. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
———. [1942] 1949c. ‘‘Age and Sex in the Social Structure of the United States.’’ Pp. 217–32 in Essays in
Sociological Theory, Pure and Applied. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
———. 1968. The Structure of Social Action (2 vols.). New York: Free Press.
———. 1971. ‘‘Belief, Unbelief, and Disbelief.’’ Pp. 207–45 in The Culture of Unbelief, edited by R. Caporale
and A. Grumelli. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
———. 1979. ‘‘Religious and Economic Symbolism in the Western World.’’ Sociological Inquiry 49:1–48.
Posner, R. A. 1992. Sex and Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Reay, D. 2004. ‘‘Gendering Bourdieu’s Concepts of Capitals? Emotional Capital, Women and Social Class.’’
Pp. 57–74 in Feminism After Bourdieu, edited by L. Adkins and B. Skeggs. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing
Rickert, H. 1913. ‘‘Vom System der Werte.’’ Logos 4:295–327.
Roth, A. E. and M. A. O. Sotomayor. 1990. Two-Sided Matching: A Study in Game-Theoretic Modeling and
Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rubin, G. 1985. ‘‘The Traffic in Women: Notes on the ‘Political Economy’ of Sex.’’ Pp. 157–210 in Toward
an Anthropology of Women, edited by R. Reiter. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Schluchter, W. 1996. Paradoxes of Modernity: Culture and Conduct in the Theory of Max Weber, translated
by N. Solomon. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Shilling, C. 1993. The Body and Social Theory. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Sprecher, S. 1998. ‘‘The Effect of Exchange Orientation on Close Relationships.’’ Social Psychology
Quarterly 61:220–31.
Stein, E. 1992. Forms of Desire: Sexual Orientation and the Social Constructionist Controversy. New York:
Routledge.
Stigler, G. J. 1968. The Organization of Industry. Homewood, IL: R. D. Irwin.
Swedberg, R. 1994. ‘‘Markets as Social Structures.’’ Pp. 255–82 in The Handbook of Economic Sociology,
edited by N. J. Smelser and R. Swedberg. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Tiryakian, E. A. 1981. ‘‘Sexual Anomie, Social Structure, Societal Change.’’ Social Forces 59:1025–53.
Todd, P. M. and G. F. Miller. 1999. ‘‘From Pride and Prejudice to Persuasion: Satisficing in Mate Search.’’
Pp. 287–308 in Simple Heuristics that Make Us Smart, edited by G. Gigerenzer and P. M. Todd. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Turner, B. S. 1982. ‘‘The Discourse of Diet.’’ Theory, Culture and Society 1:23–32.
———. 1984. The Body and Society. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Udry, J. R. 1966. The Social Context of Marriage. Philadelphia, PA: J. B. Lippincott Company.
Von Magnus, E. 1984. ‘‘Preference, Rationality, and Risk Taking.’’ Ethics 94:637–48.
Wacquant, L. J. D. 1993. ‘‘On the Tracks of Symbolic Power: Prefatory Notes to Bourdieu’s ‘State
Nobility’.’’ Theory, Culture and Society 10:1–17.
———. 1995. ‘‘Pugs at Work: Bodily Capital and Bodily Labor Among Professional Boxers.’’ Body and
Society 1:65–94.
———. 2003. Body and Soul: Notebooks of an Apprentice Boxer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Waller, W. 1937. ‘‘The Rating and Dating Complex.’’ American Sociological Review 2:727–34.
Weber, M. [1915] 1946. ‘‘Religious Rejections of the World and Their Directions.’’ Pp. 323–59 in From Max
Weber: Essays in Sociology, translated and edited by H. H. Gerth and C. W. Mills. New York: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1958. The Religion of India, translated and edited by H. H. Gerth and D. Martindale. Glencoe, IL:
Free Press.
———. [1920] 1976. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, translated by T. Parsons. New York:
Scribners.
White, H. 1981. ‘‘Where Do Markets Come From?’’ American Journal of Sociology 87:517–47.
Whittier, D. K. and W. Simon. 2001. ‘‘The Fuzzy Matrix of ‘My Type’ in Intrapsychic Sexual Scripting.’’
Sexualities 4:139–65.
Wiley, J. A. and S. J. Herschkorn. 1989. ‘‘Homosexual Role Separation and AIDS Epidemics—Insights
from Elementary Models.’’ Journal of Sex Research 26:434–49.
Zahavi, A. 1975. ‘‘Mate Selection—A Selection for a Handicap.’’ Journal of Theoretical Biology 53:205–14.
Zelizer, V. A. 1996. ‘‘Payments and Social Ties.’’ Sociological Forum 11:481–95.
Zetterberg, H. L. 1954. On Theory and Verification in Sociology. New York: Tressler Press.
———. 1966. ‘‘The Secret Ranking.’’ Journal of Marriage and the Family 27:134–42.