Xenology As Phenomenological Semiotics

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 22

Xenology as phenomenological semiotics

ALEXANDER KOZIN

Abstract

In this article I examine the science of the alien, or xenology for its contri-
bution to semiotics. As a subfield of phenomenology, xenology emerged in
the Husserlian theory of intersubjectivity when, in his late period, Husserl
performed a transition from the other as an analogue of the self to the alien
as a non-analogical structure. The transition came with singling out four
alien modalities — children, animals, foreigners, and the insane — as the
Limit-Subjects in possession of their own liminal worlds. Following the ar-
gument for the continuous relationship between phenomenology and semiot-
ics, I examine the possibility of enriching the phenomenological theory of
the alien through a semiotic intervention. I arrange for the latter with Gilles
Deleuze who, owing to his association to both disciplines, helps me create a
semiotic theory of the alien. In this model, the original alien modalities op-
erate on the level of signification, thus building on the Husserlian investiga-
tions of how we experience alien-worlds with an elaboration of their signify-
ing e¤ects.

Keywords: Husserl; alien; rationality; liminality; Deleuze; becoming-


Alien.

1. Introduction

The influence of Edmund Husserl and his phenomenology on the semiotic


field has been widely acknowledged. Umberto Eco names Husserl as the
key figure whose phenomenology helped semiotics achieve the status of
an independent discipline. According to Eco, Husserl’s phenomenology
was the basic drive that generated the field and the object of semiotic
inquiry: ‘phenomenology undertakes to rebuild from the beginning the
conditions necessary for the formation of cultural units which semiotics

Semiotica 171–1/4 (2008), 171–192 0037–1998/08/0171–0171


DOI 10.1515/SEMI.2008.073 6 Walter de Gruyter
Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries
Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
172 A. Kozin

instead accept as data because communication functions on the basis of


them’ (Eco 1979: 167). From this definition it appears that phenomenol-
ogy provides the first foundation for the study of the sign and sign sys-
tems. Julia Kristeva renders an equally strong endorsement: ‘Husserlian
phenomenology . . . became the basis for this century’s theory of significa-
tion to which, consciously or not, explicitly or not, all linguistic theories
refer’ (1989: 223). Both Eco and Kristeva agree that the key source of the
phenomenological influence was the timely appearance of Logical Investi-
gations, Husserl’s main texts on the constitutive properties of language.
Roman Jakobson, one of the founders of formalism, found this text in-
spirational enough as to extend phenomenology into the structuralist
thought, instigating the subsequent conquest of linguistics by structural-
ism.1 In the course of this transition — from phenomenology to linguis-
tics, and from linguistics to structuralism — emerged a special strand of
semiotics, phenomenological semiotics. The presence of phenomenologi-
cal semiotics can be traced in the works of such phenomenological figures
as Martin Heidegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Emmanuel Levinas, Mi-
chel Foucault, and Jacques Derrida.2
At the same time, the acknowledgment of the phenomenological influ-
ence on semiotics implies a certain finality of the phenomenological con-
tribution. The latter should not be surprising: when referencing Husserl,
semioticians tend to lean on the early period of his work, following his
preoccupation with the formal/logical side of transcendental phenomen-
ology. Understandably appealing to the linguistic scholarship of the first
half of the twentieth century, the original definition of phenomenology
ended up defining its main contribution to semiotics as well. After semiot-
ics broke o¤ from linguistics completely in the early nineteen seventies,
the e¤ects of the original phenomenology have subsided, turning Husserl
into a largely historical figure. In the meantime, continuous advances in
phenomenology, together with the diversification of the phenomenolog-
ical agenda, opened widely a space for interdisciplinary cooperation,
and it is in this spirit that I would like to introduce and explore xenolog-
ical phenomenology as a way into an experience-based communication-
centered semiotic theory. In the next section, I o¤er a brief account of
xenological phenomenology, also known as the science of the alien.3

2. From the other to the alien

In section 52 of the Fifth Cartesian Meditation, Husserl states: ‘The char-


acter of the existent ‘‘other’’ has its basis in this kind of verifiable accessi-
bility of what is not originally accessible’ (1977: 144). The statement is

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 173

enigmatic, paradoxical, and, in this way, revealing. When commenting on


the revelatory significance of paradox for philosophy, Gilles Deleuze
writes, ‘Paradox is the pathos or the passion of philosophy’ (1994: 227,
italics added). In the context of the Fifth Cartesian Meditation, the para-
dox finds its pathos in Husserl’s theory of intersubjectivity in general and
the relationship to the other in particular. I call the status of the other to
be the key problem in this text for two reasons: first, phenomenologically,
I position myself next to David Carr (1973) who pointed out that the core
problem for phenomenology in Cartesian Meditations is not the problem
of the ‘I’ or solipsism but the problem of understanding of the world as
objective and the accompanying understanding of the subject not as an-
other object but as precisely a subject whose experience cannot be re-
duced to that of the object, for the consciousness of the subject is a self-
reflective consciousness that parallels mine. Second, from the semiotic
standpoint, I side with Yuri Lotman who names the ‘I-Other relation’ to
be the most basic semiotic structure.4
From the latter perspective, in the Cartesian Meditations Husserl seeks
to explain how the other ego is apperceived within my sphere of ownness
(Eigenheit), or ‘the Ego in whom the center is the one identical I-myself ’
(1977: 145). The other ego is then defined as both everything alien (allem
Fremden) and yet apperceptively accessible (zugänglich) (1977: 145). Here,
the paradox is still applied reductively: Cartesian Meditations o¤ers a for-
mal and not a descriptive phenomenology, which views the I-Other rela-
tionship as apophantic. The implications of this position for the semiotics
at this point are purely structural: communication never features an unin-
terrupted flow of parallel expressions; on the contrary, it is always asym-
metrical, with the foundation for this asymmetry always residing wit the
‘I,’ or the source of signifying intentionality. It is on the basis of this thesis
that Lotman first critiques and then modifies the semiotic square of Grei-
mas. By reversing the relationship of opposition and apposition he shows
how collective consciousness transforms individual experiences into limit
phenomena, or limit-signs. The latter help extend the universe of signs ‘by
showing its borders’ (Lotman 1996: 175). Lotman distinguishes not only
between inner and outer borders, but recognizes that their juncture can be
meaningful in itself: there are also liminal borders or the borders that in-
corporate the elements of the outside and the inside. For an example, he
evokes the so-called ‘strange familiars,’ or those liminal groups of people
who inhabited the outer boundaries of the growing Russian empire under
Ivan the Terrible.
In his later works, Husserl anticipated the emergence of liminality as
a semiotic theme by expanding his theory of intersubjectivity to the phe-
nomenology of the alien. In the manuscripts on intersubjectivity that

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
174 A. Kozin

embrace the period from 1929 to 1935 he takes great care in both posing
and reformulating the problem of the inaccessibly accessible other. The
new formulation, albeit nearly identical to the previous one, is given
with an entirely di¤erent emphasis. Husserl writes: ‘In mediate horizons
there are heterogeneous communities and cultures, they belong to them
as alien and heterogeneous, but alienness means accessibility in genuine in-
accessibility, in the mode of incomprehensibility’ (1973b: 631, italics added,
my translation). The content of the above quote clearly situates the en-
counter with the other in the broad socio-cultural context — the connec-
tion that prompted Ludwig Landgrebe to suggest that the development of
Husserl’s thought since Cartesian Meditations had been progressively
tending toward ‘the social plurality within the life-world’ (Landgrebe
1981: 133). The acknowledgment of this plurality for Husserl meant a re-
turn to the concept of the alien. Upon numerous deliberations, the alien
was no longer conceived as everything alien to the ego constituted within
this ego’s sphere of ownness, but as a community whose experience could
simultaneously engage several spheres and dimensions. To put this insight
in the semiotic terms, Husserl presumed the possibility that there were
many di¤erent ‘systems of experience,’ or, to borrow from Lotman,
‘semiospheres.’ Some of these spheres coalesce, while others do not. In ei-
ther case, liminal systems are generative because they ‘possess transfor-
mative potential’ (Lotman 1996: 183).
The transition to an examination of alien-worlds implied moving away
from considering inaccessible accessibility on the conceptual level as the
formal prerequisite for communication to the level of proximally interact-
ing heterogeneous beings whose experiences of the shared world are de-
limited from each other by respective generative terrains. The move from
the other to the alien implied neither a loss, nor a substitution. Within the
specificity of the Fifth Cartesian Mediation, the other was employed to-
ward finding the solution of the ‘solipsism’ question. In his subsequent
investigations Husserl introduced the alien on the strength of a di¤erent
question: ‘There are problems emerging here of creating concrete under-
standing and mutual understanding; at issue is to somehow accomplish a
making home of the alien, as if it were home. Of course, there is also the
question of the limits of such knowledge and the question of justifying the
idea of complete understanding’ (1973b: 625, my translation). It is this
line of thinking that allowed some contemporary phenomenologists to
propose that in the last period of work Husserl had turned to a particular
kind of phenomenology that aspired to provide a connection between two
phenomenological realms, transcendental and empirical.5 The latter im-
plied an interrelation between two phenomenological methods, transcen-
dental and eidetic. In The Crisis, the last manuscript that Husserl saw

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 175

published while still alive, he explains that ‘through an eidetic method we


investigate the essential form of transcendental accomplishments in all
their individual and transcendental types, that is, the total essential form
of transcendentally accomplishing subjectivity in all its social forms’
(1970: 178). As a result of this merger, transcendental phenomenology
was expected to extend the theory of intersubjectivity based on the expe-
rience of the other into the theory of interculturality based on the encoun-
ter with the alien. In this essay, I would like to examine the implications
of this development for the semiotic theory. For my starting point, I sug-
gest that we review the Husserlian concept of the alien.

3. Two senses of the alien

When Husserl refers to the alien in various later manuscripts, he gives it


two senses: a) as the transcendental structure ‘home-world/alien-world’
(Heimwelt/Fremdwelt); and b) as the empirical modality ‘the Alien’ (das
Fremde).6 Concerning the former, the structure ‘home-world/alien-world’
is singled out as one of the two most basic or elementary transcendental
structures which participate in the foundational constitution of experi-
ence. The other one is defined as ‘earth-as-ground/world-as-horizon.’
Both structures are essential for the experience of the life-world. How-
ever, due to my emphasis and the space restrictions of this essay, I would
like to entertain only the first structure. The structure consists of two un-
equally distributed components: ‘home-world’ and ‘alien-world.’ The re-
lationship between the home-world and the alien-world is a relationship
between what belongs to the recognizable ‘home’ and the experience of
the unrecognizable ‘alien’ that encompasses everything that is consti-
tuted by a world other than my home-world. The primacy in this relation-
ship belongs to the ‘home.’ It is only from the ‘home’ that I can observe
and thus experience the alien. At the same time, the alien-experience is
inaccessible to me. We can say, at this point, that the alien-world co-
constitutes the home-world. Simultaneously transcendental and non-
foundational, the co-determinate structure alien-world/home-world
presents the relationship between the home and the alien as the su‰cient
and necessary condition for understanding the genesis of all, but espe-
cially social experience.
At this juncture, I would like to suggest that we take the relationship
between the home and the alien as a particular kind of semiosis that takes
place, according to Lotman, in a certain symbolic space. In phenomeno-
logical terms, this space can be defined as a liminal space which consists
of limits, borders, and boundaries that prevent complete experience of the

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
176 A. Kozin

world. The relationship between the home and the alien is conducted in
the liminal realm. The question that arises in this regard is, How shall we
understand this realm? Most generally, liminality is what delimits us from
the outside and therefore reaches inside. Waldenfels calls liminality ‘in-
between’ (Zwischen), or new logos: ‘We encounter the alien as something
that can not be said or done within our order. The extraordinary makes
its appearance as an order existing elsewhere’ (Waldenfels 1996: 115).
This extraordinary order resides in the twilight and feeds on ambiguity.
This is the reason why limit-phenomena cannot be appropriated, assimi-
lated, brought home, made united: ‘Alienness then does not proceed from
a division but consists in a division’ (Waldenfels 1990: 21). At the same
time, the alien cannot be ignored: as a generative phenomenon, it gives
rise to ‘those mythical narratives which give an account of a ‘‘genesis’’
that is genetically impossible to know, but generatively possible to experi-
ence in the generative density of a cultural tradition’ (Steinbock 1995:
219). Hence, the ethical dimension that stimulates the encounter with the
alien; one meets the alien by crossing over from within, and that means,
from within your own order. In this formulation, both terms, ‘within’ and
‘over’ are essential: when crossing, one must carry their world with them
‘from within,’ and, at the same time, must separate from the home at
large by ‘moving over.’ In short, it is the liminal realm that features both
transcendental and ontological structures.
Detailed investigations of this sphere led Husserl to propose that the
liminal sphere di¤ered from the normative one because it was founded
on abnormality which signified itself through their subjects, or ‘allon.’
Consequently, Husserl entertained four types of alien-subjects (Fremde-
Subjecte): animals, children, foreigners, and the insane. He was explicit
about their common genealogy: when discussing the correlation between
the world and transcendental subjectivity in The Crisis, Husserl asked
himself

. . . are the insane also objectifications of the subjects being discussed in connection
with the accomplishment of world-constitution? . . . And what about children who
already have a certain amount of world-consciousness? . . . And what about ani-
mals? There arise problems of intentional modifications through which we can
and must attribute to all these conscious subjects — those that do not co-function
in respect to the world understood in the hitherto accepted (and always funda-
mental) sense, that is, the world which has truth through ‘reason’ — their manner
of transcendentality, precisely as ‘analogues’ to ourselves. (Husserl 1970: 187)

Husserl’s inquiry as well as his solution have far-fetching implications for


all human studies: first, he discovered a sphere of experience that came
pre-separated from the normal and therefore acceptably foundational

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 177

sphere. Second, he discovered that this liminal sphere houses fundamen-


tally di¤erent social worlds. Third, he chose to associate these worlds
with specific empirical modalities, namely, children, animals, foreigners,
and the insane. For Husserl, the four alien modalities are predicated on
abnormality which is a constitutional category, in accordance with which
the alien is conceived as abnormal, i.e., ‘discordant, non-optimal, atypi-
cal, and unfamiliar’ (Husserl 1973a: 225, my translation). In the phenom-
enological context, abnormality is a neutral term; it means an experience
of the Alien as a being, who is completely on its own, reflectively outside
of our constitutive comprehension, in other words, radically di¤erent.
Coming from and with a world of their own that is delimited from our
own world, the Alien types are shadowy or, to put it in phenomenological
terms, liminal phenomena. Husserl calls them Limes-Subjekte. All limit-
subjects reside in the liminal sphere. Like all other subjects, let it be nor-
mal or abnormal, limit-subjects are social subjects. At the same time, they
possess their own worlds. These worlds di¤er from the normative worlds
because their communities act in accordance with the modified rational-
ity. It is through their worlds that we access the liminal sphere.7
In the next sections I would like to build on this deliberation by exam-
ining the alien subjects in terms of a) their specific communities and b) the
relationships between and among these communities, and c) the composi-
tion of the liminal sphere as a relational network that engages contribu-
tions from all the alien-worlds. In other words, I expect that by following
Limit-Subjects to their alien-worlds, one can penetrate the liminal sphere
within a particular configuration of its experience at the limits of its pos-
sibilities. A semiotic analysis would examine the limits to experience as
signifying limits. By addressing the signifying potential of liminality, one
could disclose the workings of intersemiosis, or complex coding. There-
fore, in the remainder of this article I o¤er two parallel interpretations of
the children, animals, foreigners, and the insane. In the beginning I show
how Husserl treated each individual alien; then I make an attempt to sys-
tematize his insights. Next, I give a semiotic reading of the alien modal-
ities. For the main semiotic figure that guides me in this project I choose
Gilles Deleuze. The choice of Deleuze is stipulated by several reasons. I
present those in the next section.

4. The semiotic phenomenology of Gilles Deleuze

Situated at the crossroads of several philosophical traditions, Gilles Dele-


uze’s philosophy is way too complex to be referenced in a single defini-
tion. However, in his early overview of French philosophy Bernhard

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
178 A. Kozin

Waldenfels describes Deleuze as a second-generation phenomenologist,


who is no longer attached to the phenomenological foundation directly
but is attached to it via numerous associations and dissociations.8 More
specifically, Waldenfels grounds his view of Deleuze in the fact that the
latter was highly influenced by the radical turn in phenomenology in the
late 1960’s and followed that turn toward ‘transformation of phenomen-
ology’ (Waldenfels 1983: 488). Initiated by Derrida, this turn retains the
elements of both the empirical world and its modes of constitution, or
transcendentals, neither of which can be fully accessible to philosophical
inquiry on their own. This position zeroes in on the notion of radical dif-
ference, or di¤érance, which is essentially a Kantian legacy. Unlike Der-
rida, who coins the term and so incorporates it in his philosophy explicitly,
Deleuze has never acknowledged the impact of di¤érance on his thought
beyond a mere motivation past Kant. However, it is precisely in the mo-
tivation that we find a continuous association with phenomenology.
The latter comes about in two ways: by way of his on-going argument
vis-à-vis Bergson with the key phenomenological figures, such as Husserl,
Merleau-Ponty, Heidegger, and Derrida, and by his philosophical por-
traits, that is, ‘analyses of concept-making’ (Deleuze 1990: 177). In Dele-
uze’s own words, ‘Husserl thought a decisive step forward when he
discovered a region of vague and material essences (in other words, es-
sences that are vagabond, anexact and yet rigorous), distinguishing them
from fixed, metric and formal essences’ (Deleuze 1994: 78). In his most
technical treatise, Di¤erence and Repetition, Deleuze makes one step fur-
ther as he conducts his argument in an implicitly phenomenological vein
that can be traced in both the set-up and the trajectory of his delibera-
tions: he begins with the analysis of representation (phenomenon) as it
was introduced by Plato and ends in the realm of social phenomenology
with the question of the Other and the third. He is more explicit about
his commitments in the more recent Logic of Sensation, whose aim and
purpose is at the core transcendental and phenomenological; an examina-
tion of how Bacon could paint ‘the scream more than the horror’ situates
Deleuze alongside with Merleau-Ponty, Sartre, and Levinas, who discuss
the possibility of givenness being a phenomenon in itself rather than a
mode of constitution for what is being given.
The emphasis on threshold phenomena leads Deleuze to a philosophi-
cal method that Slavoj Žižek calls dialectical materialism in its fullest
sense. With Marx, explains Žižek, Deleuze understands philosophy as
necessarily critical, an inquiry that seeks to subvert sedentiary thinking
via nomadic interventions. The latter presupposes a di¤erent kind of dia-
lectical intervention. This intervention engages other than traditional du-
alities o¤ered by Hegel, for example, abstract/concrete, or by Husserl, to

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 179

that matter, such as eidos and hyle, but introduces dual liminal categories
as the Sense-Event, which express themselves di¤erently when engaged in
either the empirical or the transcendental realms. According to Žižek,
these categories have two faces: ‘one face is turned toward things — that
is, it is the pure, non-substantial surface of Becoming, of Events heteroge-
neous with regard to substantial things with regard to which these Events
happen; the other face is turned toward Language — that is, the pure flux
of Sense in contrast to representational Signification, to the referring of a
sign to bodily object’ (Žižek 1993: 123).
It is from the dialectical perspective that Deleuze asks himself the most
basic phenomenological question: What makes the appearance of various
phenomena possible if one accepts the possibility that their phenomenologi-
cal field exceeds the sensual, and extends directly into the transcendental?
The answer to this question is sought out in the liminal realm, on the
surface of the matter. Thus, for the object of his phenomenologically-
oriented philosophy Deleuze takes a liminal phenomenon, or what fol-
lows from the collision between matter and force, inserting the thread
that marks the division between the organic and the non-organic, image
and e¤ect to the point of their indistinguishibility, or, in Leibniz’s words,
incompossibility that proceeds from the possible without denying it, al-
lowing for the actual and the virtual to co-exist. Deleuze describes this di-
alectical relation in the body without organs, which subsists and consists
of ‘nothing but flesh and meat’ (Deleuze 2004: 22). As a common zone
for man and beast, the body without organs circumvents the human cog-
ito, making it fall back on the pre-reflective way of dwelling in this world.
Regardless of the kinds of phenomena Deleuze examines in his work, his
focus inevitably falls on those phenomena that belong to liminal fields,
whether it is aesthetic cinematography, or Francis Bacon’s art, or the his-
torical period of Baroque. The importance of these fields is not in them-
selves but in that they are capable of revealing liminality, which eventual-
izes itself in nomadic event-objects.
It is therefore as a semiotic phenomenologist whose thought developed
on the edge and in-between the two disciplines, phenomenology and semi-
otics, that I engage Deleuze in this study. Since what is at stake here is
an understanding of the social world at the limit of its comprehension,
I suspect that Deleuze’s phenomenological semiotics would double the
strength of penetrating the liminal sphere, exposing, or shall we say, dis-
closing its limits in both phenomenological and semiotic terms. In this re-
lationship, phenomenology will be guiding semiotics. In what follows I
examine the four Alien modalities first with Husserl and then with Dele-
uze. My aim is to connect the two approaches and their respective models
in a xenological theory of the alien.

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
180 A. Kozin

5. Husserl: Experiencing the alien

In his writings on intersubjective constitution, Husserl does not o¤er a


systematic theory of the alien. However, there are three concepts that
make consistent appearance throughout his investigations: abnormality,
rationality, and community. The relations between and among the three
concepts is systemic. For Husserl, the Alien modality is abnormal on the
level of community which is defined by a particular kind of rationality. In
other words, we experience the Alien beings as strange because their com-
munities are rational but in an odd manner. The degree of strangeness de-
pends on the distance of a particular normal world from the threshold
that separates the liminal sphere from the normative one. When de-
scribing the alien-world, Landgrebe, with Husserl, establishes the con-
tinuum for their inaccessibility by distinguishing between ‘far-worlds’
and ‘near-worlds’ (Landgrebe 1981: 132). Furthering this distinction,
Waldenfels notes that if one is to take the experience of the alien as
the experience of the own in the process of its transformation, two
types of experiencing the alien would be possible. One is the experience
of the alien from within. The other is the experience on the outskirts.
Close alien-worlds evolve from within, while far alien-worlds dwell on
the outskirts. In other words, the far-world is the world most removed
from our familiar experience, while the near-world borders on compre-
hensibility. The operations of inner borders and outer borders as well as
far and near worlds will serve as the static grid for the subsequent genetic
analysis.
The farthest of the alien-worlds known to humans is possessed by the
animal. This might explain why Husserl consistently refers to the animal
as ‘dark.’ In several texts that specifically address the issue of monadic
constitution of the animal Husserl posits two theses aimed at explaining
how the experience of the animal can be understood as communal. First,
he states that the animal di¤ers from the human because it ‘appears to be
irrational, not making sense’ (Husserl 1973b: 622, my translation). In
fact, argues Husserl, rationality of the animal being develops on the plane
that is not operational for the human. Husserl calls this plane Instinct. The
normalizing force of the Instinct optimalizes the animal’s behaviour, ‘gives
the animal a purpose that directs its ego-acts’ (1970: 227). Importantly,
emphasizes Husserl, no individual animal exists separately from it species.
The collective of a particular species forms a community, a form of so-
ciality. The animal must have relations to subsist and traditions to uphold
if it means to survive as a species within a specific environment of its own.
Husserl forewarns against hasty distinctions based on sheer appearances.
In comparison to the human body, a di¤erent bodily comportment of the

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 181

animal does not su‰ce as a primal distinction simply because a rational


animal would be a di¤erent kind of being, which would not be experi-
enced as an animal but as a foreigner. For an illustration, Husserl refers
to the Horse People from Jonathan Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels (Husserl
1973b: 625, my translation). If we encounter dressed up horses who can
speak and reason, we cannot help but accept them as our analogues.
Thus, and this is Husserl’s second thesis, the animal is a social being in
the same way as a human, that is, it has a community; and if it has a
community, it has a ‘home.’ In this home, the foundational structure is
Instinct-rationality.
The nearest world on the ‘far-near’ alien continuum and simultane-
ously the deepest alien-world belongs to the child. The child too is experi-
enced as irrational. Following the psychology of his times, Husserl defines
the experience of the infant (child) as that of ‘the non-recognition of tem-
porality and spatiality and a unique mode of connecting to the others
through fulfillment’ (Husserl 1973b: 605, my translation). The object of
fulfillment for this primordial mode is the mother, the first relation. For
the infant, the mother constitutes the entire world. At the times of Hus-
serl, it was customary to associate the primary caretaker with the mother;
for the contemporary sensibilities, the Husserlian mother would be any
primary caretaker. This way to the social, through the Other, situates the
child firmly inside the other’s sphere of ownness, makes it a cultural being
par excellence, for the child symbolizes the beginning of the social. There-
fore, in contrast to the animal, the inaccessible child poses the limit not at
the point of rationality but at the point of origin. The child’s corporeality
contributes to the experience of originarity: the child is not a miniature
adult, its originary ways of constituting its world resist an analogy with
the adult body; its motility is optimal for the relation with the ‘world’
that defines the child as child. This world is the first world; constantly
growing into the world of the adults, the child does not perform a quali-
tative leap of any kind but remains connected to the first world by adher-
ing to the originary experiences. These experiences are di¤erent from the
adult experiences in that they serve as the conditions for them. The Other
is no longer just the mother; however, the mother continues to retain the
primordial status. According to Zahavi, the first experiences do not only
‘make the constitution of the objectivity, reality, and transcendence pos-
sible, thus permanently transforming our categories of experience,’ more
importantly, ‘they continue to participate in the ongoing transformation
of all subsequent experiences’ (Zahavi 2003: 116). They are therefore the
primers for the experience of the experiencing subject. The limit posed by
the child and its experiences is the limit of conditions and consequences:
the child’s experiences are the primers for the subsequent experiences. We

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
182 A. Kozin

thus may define the foundational structure of the child’s alien-word as


Ur-rationality.
Husserl’s writings on madness are scattered in a variety of texts, most
notably, in Husserliana Volume 13 as well as The Analyses Concerning
Passive and Active Synthesis. In the latter text Husserl writes, ‘Isn’t it pos-
sible that we all become insane and that many subjects live without rely-
ing on a life-world, without any communal experience’ (Husserl 2003:
32). As the quote indicates, for Husserl, madness is a paradoxical form
of sociality. The madman is without community at the same time as he
remains within the community. One can say that, in comparison to the
other three Alien modalities, the madman resides on the margins of a
community. Not properly communal, the madman is an alien other, who
is inaccessible in the familiar constitutive order; yet, she is formerly famil-
iar. Attentive to the familiar culture, albeit to an extent, and speaking a
familiar language, albeit in an incomprehensible fashion, the madman is
an inaccessible deviant. He is a homeless ex-patriot. Constituting the
moral order in ab-normal ways, the madman nonetheless constitutes its
rupture, something that is always in need of repair. Experienced on the
side of their former home, the insane are properly liminal beings since
their own abnormalities are not of the reparable order. At the same
time, the insane constitute an order of their own, the order of unmaking,
which cuts across the other three categories: an insane child or a mad an-
imal are mad in the same way: by no longer adhering to the familiar ways
of constitution any longer. The non-adherence or Ir-rationality is the pri-
mary mode in which the insane constitute their communal world.
For Husserl, the foreigner is a special kind of subject because she epit-
omizes community as a human sociality. In addition to natural sciences
and psychology, Husserl’s other non-philosophical academic interest was
anthropology. In line with the anthropological thinking of the time, he
often models his alien on the exotic alien, the savage (das Wilde). The co-
incident use of the two terms (das Fremde and das Wilde) is significant as
it points to the extreme end of the position that Husserl assumes toward
the foreigner. The foreigner is someone whose home is founded on myths
and rituals, in other words, special social activities that engage an entire
community of people identifying it not just as a form of sociality, but as
a culture, meaning that this community is not homogenous but is seg-
mented into multiple parallel worlds. As long as a foreigner is separated
from another foreigner by language, territory and customs, she may em-
brace a wide range of manifestations, from another European to a pre-
historical humanoid. The unifying principle for these manifestations is
rationality predicated on the logical schema of language. Husserl writes,
‘The world of humans is fundamentally and essentially determined by

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 183

language’ (Husserl 1973b: 224–225, my translation). Our experiences


with foreign languages and travels to foreign countries strongly testify to
the generative powers of language. Speaking in a foreign tongue or par-
ticipating in a foreign custom often feels like an actual limit being im-
posed on the self. No matter how advanced we may be in communicating
our original selves otherwise than in our home language; no matter how
much at home we feel in a foreign country; when abroad, we are savages
crippled by the force that continuously pulls us back to the primordial
home, that terrain which constituted the beginning and continues to do
so even after we physically place ourselves in a foreign world. The for-
eigner is the paradigmatic Alien other who is always in a relationship
with other alien Others. In comparison to the animal and the child, Alien
foreigner designates multiplicity within the species, forwarding language
as the mediating type of rationality, Language-rationality.
In the beginning of this article, I argued that after Cartesian Medita-
tions, in his late period, Husserl continued his work on the intersubjective
dimension of the other. One of the results of this work was an extension
of the original definition of the I-other relation into the home-alien rela-
tion. The latter prompted Husserl to state that the encounter with the
alien-world takes place in the liminal sphere, on the border of experience.
For the guiding figures into that world, Husserl singled out the child, the
animal, the madman, and the foreigner. He identified them as regional
beings, that is, those beings who possess their unique worlds, alien-
worlds, all of which belong to the liminal sphere of experience. Husserl
further indicated that by constituting their specific alien communities the
above Limit-Subjects emerge as rational subjects; yet, to the normal sub-
ject, their specific type of rationality — Instinct-Rationality for the ani-
mal, Ur-Rationality for the child, Language-Rationality for the foreigner,
and Ir-Rationality for the insane — will appear as abnormal. Normal
communities consist of fully-rational adults who are rational in the moral
sense. According to Husserl, a normal adult behaves and experiences in
the manner of consequentionality, which is but an awareness of certain
societal prohibitions. Most often, the latter come under the theme of
moral values.
In contrast, the liminal sphere which accommodates di¤erent Alien
types and their respective worlds di¤er from the normative sphere not by
giving its opposite but rather by varying its foundation, which, for Hus-
serl, happens to be rationality. We can therefore claim that, in the Hus-
serlian interpretation, rationality is the su‰cient and necessary condition
for any form of sociality. In the case of the four Alien modalities ratio-
nality manifests itself in di¤erent modes. The animal’s Instinct-rationality
is completely inaccessible to the fully-rational human, who sees animal

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
184 A. Kozin

behavior as chaotic and irregular. In fact, according to Husserl, the ani-


mal proves its sociality by pursuing a communal purpose albeit it in a
primitive, for the fully-rational human, fashion. The Instinct-rationality
is engaged entirely in the name of survival, showing it as an every day
drive. Unlike normal human communities, animal communities persist
by completely attending to surviving. It is easy to imagine how a human
becomes an animal if only she starts dedicating herself to nothing else
but survival. A more comprehensible alien experience the fully-rational
adult find in the child, who provides a historical connection to those ex-
periences that once formed the basis for further experiences. The Ur-
rationality creates the ground, so to speak, for the development of moral
rationality. Yet, as the foundation, it is completely covered by the sub-
sequent structures.
The breaking of those structures characterizes the experience of the in-
sane. Those do not go outside of themselves in committing irrational acts,
as our mundane experiences often intuit. As an Alien-species they do so
by systematically and thus rationally un-making the super-structures of
their fully-rational self. The end result of this process is sedimentation
of irrational rationality in its consistent performance. In contrast to the
above three Alien-modalities, the foreigner is delimited from the fully-
rational human by being its subcategory that made it to the liminal side
by virtue of a technicality. This technicality is the tradition which is up-
held by the language and its use for narrating a specific history. Called
Language-rationality, this kind of rationality is also moral. That is why
various foreigner communities comprise the fully-rational normative
world, or, from a di¤erent perspective, as liminal communities, they over-
lap with it. At the same time, the other three liminal communities are lo-
cated in di¤erent degrees of proximity from the world of the fully-rational
adult, without creating as much as some form of parallelism. From this,
we can deduce the componential make-up of the liminal sphere; however,
its relational necessity remains unclear. I therefore suggest that we take
the Husserlian model as provisional and, on its basis, attempt a semiotic
theory of the alien which would endow this model with the density and
texture of signification.

6. Deleuze: The signifying alien

In the previous section, I presented Gilles Deleuze as a semiotic phenom-


enologist. I also defined the di¤erence between traditional Husserlian phe-
nomenology and semiotic phenomenology in terms of the phenomenolog-
ical focus. In the case of Husserl, the focus is on the alien-experience. The

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 185

level on which Husserl conducts his xenological investigation is therefore


transcendental-ontological. Deleuze, on the other hand, approaches the
alien-experience and the experience of the Alien on the plane of significa-
tion. This means attending to the conditions that allow certain Alien
modalities to appear as significant, that is, meaningful-in-themselves and
also as the conditions for the meaningfulness of the liminal sphere. The
shift of focus redefines the liminal sphere as a signifying terrain. The limits
of signification di¤er from those of experience for they are located on the
surface, or the skin of the matter which blurs the distinction ‘between the
container and the contained’ (Deleuze 1990: 100). In turn, the Alien mod-
alities are addressed as signifying modalities, or ‘surface e¤ects’ (Deleuze
1990: 83). Although they can be easily taken for ideal entities, and Dele-
uze even calls them incorporeal entities, the Alien modalities are firmly
connected to the empirical sphere: ‘Only the empiricism knows how to
transcend experiential dimensions of the visible without falling into Ideas,
and how to track down, invoke, and perhaps produce a phantom at the
limit of a lengthened or unfolded experience’ (Deleuze 1990: 22).
The first alien modality, the animal, is approached by Deleuze in terms
of the line of flight. For Deleuze, the line of flight does not signify the es-
cape path. The animal does not just run away; nor does it run around
without purpose or determination. The animal rather runs to disappear.
Its path is thus the path of disappearance. The animal disappearing signi-
fies the spatial distribution of the liminal sphere. According to Deleuze,
the line of flight has a special logic determined by the relationship be-
tween code and territorialization: ‘populations that are deterrioriolized
and reterritorialized and also coded and decoded’ (Deleuze and Guattari
1987: 54). This is to say that the animal makes the space, ‘which is consti-
tuted, marked o¤ by signs that divide it into zones, mobilizes special or-
gans, and corresponds to fragments of code’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:
55). The line of flight bestows meaning by producing the division as a re-
sult of which the limit-world becomes divided into the inner and the outer
structure. The inner structure is coded in an emotional state of the anxiety
before the open; the outer boundary or the associated milieu are deter-
mined by the maintenance of what is own, in the most primitive sense of
possession, the one that signifies nothing more than belonging. The super
nomad, the animal belongs to the world in a loose fashion; as loosely dis-
persed are its constitutive e¤ects because animal territorialities are formed
by incessant wandering: ‘their epistrata are constantly shifting, moving,
and sliding, creating cracking and rupture’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987:
55). The only stable, the only prominent feature about the animal itself
is its belonging. Deleuze characterizes the nomadic structure as ‘without
property, enclosure or measure’ (Deleuze 1994: 36). Nomads are the

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
186 A. Kozin

ones who distribute nothing but themselves. This distribution creates the
space for becoming: by having the previously drawn boundaries con-
stantly redrawn, ‘thereby confounding these boundaries’ (Deleuze 1994:
37). In short, the animal is the becoming-animal, who signifies space.
According to Deleuze, Alfred Hitchcock endows the line of flight with
the specificity of an overlap between the animal world and the human
world (Deleuze 1989: 34). In his film, The Birds, the most innocuous ani-
mal creature, who also happens to be the one most removed from the hu-
man reach, turns against the human being and begins falling on the heads
of hysterical humans like the Biblical plague. The birds attack in mass, as
a population. The explicitly stated conflict between the animal world and
the human world gives Hitchcock an opportunity of disclosing both the
hysterical condition of the human and the nomadic (becoming) nature of
the animal. The attack of the humans by the birds makes nomadism ac-
cessible to the humans as a liminal structure, shows it in its line of flight,
as it were. The image of the birds pursuing the running people in flight
forms the backdrop for the erratic movements of the humans and, simul-
taneously, shows the birds being united by a common purpose, however
unknown this purpose would be. Like with any other animal, you cannot
reason with the birds, even if reason is just a rational form of emotional
response. As a genre, the horror film has a history of capitalizing on that
property by having the shark, or the snake to be the ultimate horror ani-
mal. By appearing rationally motivated, the birds appear mad. They are
animals only when they are becoming-animals, that is, the nomads of the
liminal sphere.
Deleuze chooses to define the mode of signification for the child in the
Freudian terms as a relation of the body to its organs. It seems that the
connection to Husserl at this point is particularly strong. If we assume
the body for the world and the organs for its constituents, we would
have to admit that the child indeed does not experience the world as a
combination of things. Coming in close proximity to Lacan, Deleuze
claims that the child experiences the world as a plurality of possible and
seemingly incommensurable attributes that nonetheless form meaningful
assemblages, except that their meaning would always escape an adult be-
cause it would be given in the mode of appearing for the first time. These
assemblages are not Freudian displaced signifieds but beginnings. Incapa-
ble of separating the components from each other, whether in perception
or in expression, the child is equally incapable of conceiving of the world
as finite. From the temporal perspective, the child is closer to the animal
than it is to the adult. Its original experiences are inaccessible because
they are continuously interrupted by the world and its a¤ects. Deleuze
writes, ‘These a¤ects circulate and are transformed within the assemblage

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 187

. . . they indeed have an optimal limit’ (Deleuze 1986: 257). Through


his perception of the world as an endless gathering, the child is the
becoming-of the world. If consciousness is always the consciousness of
something, as Husserl taught us, an experience of the child allows the
adult to perceive the becoming-of the world as that very something;
hence, the modification to the child’s consciousness in the future, and,
through this modification, a particular signification for the world. Ac-
cording to Deleuze, Freud missed this very point: ‘psychoanalysis has
no feeling for unnatural participations, nor for the assemblages a child
can mount in order to solve a problem from which all exits are barred
him: a plan(e), not a phantasy’ (Deleuze 1986: 259–260). From the inter-
semiotic perspective, with its experiences, the child compliments the expe-
rience of the animal by associating the limits of comprehension as a spa-
tial structure with the structure of time. The child discloses the time of the
liminal sphere as experiential primordiality.
In his discussing the child, Deleuze often references Marcel Proust who
shows the significance of childhood for the experience of the world. In
Search of Lost Time is permeated by the ‘presence of madness’ (2006:
30). The notion of time as it is linked to madness is of course a well tread-
ed philosophical theme: Plato discusses it in his dialogue Phaedrus, St.
Augustine examines this connection in his Confessions, Nietzsche elabo-
rates on time and insanity in Ecce Homo; finally Foucault gives this
theme a new and inspiring spin in Madness and Civilization. Each of these
interpretations, although very di¤erent in both methodology and empha-
sis, yields the third, connecting, relation between time and madness: pro-
phetic vision for Plato; divinity for St. Augustine; politics for Nietzsche;
power for Foucault. For Deleuze, the theme of madness as a category of
time dovetails into the pre-original experience of the child. He therefore
particularly appreciates Proust’s descriptions of childhood because they
show original primordiality as the perception of time. In Swann’s Way,
this perception is described as collapsing the world to a singularity,
whether it is the original sexual desire, or, more primordially, the experi-
ence of the world in its original mode. Deleuze calls this mode ‘haecceity,’
or the becoming-one: ‘Individuation proceeds by haecceity, pure haecce-
ity’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 271). The haecceic experience presup-
poses nothing ‘but the relations of movement’ (Deleuze and Guattari
1987: 266). Children are thus fugitive beings, nomads in a similar way as
the animals. ‘Note,’ writes Deleuze, ‘how children talk to the animals
and are moved by them’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 257). Semiotically
speaking, the animals and children form a relational pair, a dual Alien
structure. Their signifying liminal space and time, respectively, makes
this pair precede, as it were, the modalities of the insane and the foreigner

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
188 A. Kozin

because both of them signify a di¤erent aspect of the Limit-world expres-


sion. In the next section I examine the two remaining Alien modalities.
I have already mentioned Deleuze’s use of the term ‘madness’ as the
‘becoming-mad.’ Madness is an indispensable component of his organic
theory designed to show the instability of the self-contained system by
exposing its organic flow which is but ‘the desire itself: non-figurative ab-
stract lines of escape, that is, deterritorialization; lines of segmentaries,
whether supple or hard, in which one gets entangled, or which one
evades, moving beneath the horizon of one’s abstract line; and how con-
versions happen from one line to the others’ (Deleuze 2006: 13). Here, we
see the same emphases: the line of flight, plan(e) of consistency, haecceity,
and stratification. It is therefore in this capacity, as a mode of significa-
tion for the liminal sphere, madness emerges as a unifying theme for the
other two modalities. However, it might be worth reminding ourselves
that, for Deleuze, madness is much more than just a theme. It is the mat-
ter that Deleuze chose to use for his challenge to psychoanalysis. In the
Anti-Oedipus, he is explicit about this connection. The schizophrenia is a
result of self alienation but not in the inward, rather in the outward sense.
The Marxist take on madness by Deleuze shows the outward area as pol-
itics: the madman is alienated not from the self but from the other in the
self. The natural outcome of this condition is madness or doubling, or
fold; hence, Deleuze’s second correction for Freud: the desire for the
Other does not find the Other but runs into the other self, alter ego, over
and over again (Deleuze and Guattari 1983: 298). The correction leads us
back to Husserl: the madman provides the limit to any self-generating
community by way of separating the content from expression.
The foreigner comes into play for the final round. It is with the for-
eigner that the concept of liminal expression receives its definition. As
with Husserl, the foreigner constitutes a separate category. Despite his
strong interest in structural anthropology and especially Levi-Strauss,
Deleuze never addresses the foreigner as an empirical modality but ap-
proaches him through the question of the Other. This de-emphasis does
not signify the lack of attention but rather a special overreaching status
of the Alien who surpasses the Other by going beyond both its structure
and its experience. This explains the frame which serves as the foundation
for the Deleuzian elaboration: Michel Tournier’s Robinson. The novel is
significant in its key question: What kind of the world is the world without
Others? Following the plot of the novel, Deleuze begins with a critique
of the Other: first, the Other ‘organizes a marginal world, a mantle, or a
background’ (Deleuze 1990: 344). The limits posed by the Other are
therefore structural: they allow for the objective world to appear as objec-
tive. As a result of this structural position, the Other becomes the cause of

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 189

our desire for the objects. The second e¤ect of the Other comes from the
same direction: the Other as the condition for the possibility of the objec-
tive world can also be desired. This prompts Deleuze to state that ‘the
Other as a structure is the expression of a possible world; it is the ex-
pressed, grasped as not yet existing outside of that which expresses it’
(Deleuze 1990: 347).
According to Deleuze, the Other becomes a tool for psychiatry which
implicates the Other in the works of perversion. The desire of an object
qua the Other turns into a perversion when the Other becomes an object
of desire. It is only if one is to imagine the world without the Other that
perversion finds its object elsewhere. However, what the structure of de-
sire shows and rea‰rms is not that the Other can be objectified, but,
more importantly, that if the Other disappears, the desire will fail to di-
rect itself to the world of objects. The latter will simply collapse under
the weight of the elementals which are going to replace the Other with a
di¤erent set of the conditions for the possibility of experiencing the world:
earth, air, fire, water, they all are going to take over: ‘the Other fabricates
bodies out of the elements, without the Other, the world returns to what
is properly own’ (Deleuze 1990: 351). In this world, the Alien replaces the
Other as one of the elemental forces; hence, the importance of Friday. In
Tournier’s interpretation of the encounter between Robinson and Friday,
the latter is not conceived as the Other. By the time Friday arrives, Rob-
inson had already lost the Other. The main role of Friday-the-savage,
who is untamed by the Other, is to complete the metamorphosis that
Robinson began and to reveal to him its sense and its aim. This function
determines his status: ‘Friday is not another, but something wholly other
than the Other; not a replica, but a Double: one who reveals pure ele-
ments and dissolves objects, bodies, and the earth’ (Deleuze 1990: 355).
For Robinson, the savage is just a being; his language, customs, are irrel-
evant for he belongs to a totally di¤erent regime which knows no consti-
tutive limits, only constitutive conditions.
The Alien who is not the Other opens the transcendental dimension of
a di¤erent order, that of the divine. In that dimension, the Alien has a dif-
ferent face. Not that of savage, but that of angel. It is the face of angel
that calls to me and thus binds me to the world in the absolute welcome.
According to Deleuze, the angel is ‘a Double without resemblance, an ele-
ment without constraint: it is a phantasm’ (Deleuze 1990: 354). As a mo-
dality of its own, the angelic stranger tops the quartet formed by the ani-
mal, the child, the insane, and the foreigner. At the same time, it has the
intrinsic connection to the child and the animal since, like them, it is un-
able to express itself by human means; it can only express itself by the
means which are liminal.9 The angel’s speech is not hearable; it is pure

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
190 A. Kozin

signified, the message without the expression. The angel is the body of the
message. The messenger is the message. The angel is all expression. This is
why, according to Dionisius Areopagus, the angel cannot be experienced
by the human in any other way but divine madness. Possessing nothing of
the human world and belonging to the heavenly world, ‘the angel is light,
wisdom and essence’ (Areopagus 2005: 122). This is how the angel comes
to serve as the paradigm for the entire Alien world.
The quasi-empirical figure of the angel situates the four empirical
Alien-modalities in a three-dimensional space. In this space, the angel
sets the direction for reading the relations between and among the modal-
ities. Its role is testifying to the code which explains the Alien modal-
ities as elementals whose language is that of divination. For the ‘silent’
angel to speak the language of the divine means to reveal the transcenden-
tal structures of the alien (divine) world in their signifying expressions. The
becoming-of-expression that characterizes the angel institutes ‘becoming’
as the primary mode of existence for liminality, an analogue of the Hus-
serlian limits to rationality. Under the transcendental guise of the angel,
becoming as a signifying structure manifests its temporality in the figure
of the child and spatiality in the figure of the animal. Between the animal
whose line of flight territorializes being and the child whose primordiality
contains all beginnings, stands the madman whose being is pluralized by
way of singularity. On the very surface of this structure one finds the for-
eigner, whose ‘normality’ conceals the alien in the exotic Other. Outside
of the analytical reflection, only when it gets compromised by the experi-
ence of profound traumatism, the liminal sphere reveals one of its elemen-
tals or unconceals itself as itself. In itself the sphere does not have any
limits and is not dependent on limit subjects. Its sole purpose is to gener-
ate limit-worlds and limit-subjects, of which the Alien modalities are but
nomads. Unlike the Husserlian view of the liminal sphere that holds the
alien modalities, Deleuze makes sure as to leave the system open. The
limit-less, subject-less liminality allow us to see the Other as a pure possi-
bility, a phantasm, an enigma, and xenos.
On the basis of these findings, I would like to rea‰rm the productive
union of phenomenology and semiotics and suggest that it should see fur-
ther expansions and refinements of the Husserlian theory of the alien, or
xenology.

Notes

1. For an expose about the influence of Husserl’s phenomenology on Jakobson, see Holen-
stein (1974).

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
Xenology 191

2. Lanigan (1989, 1992) makes a strong case for the semiotic allegiances of Merleau-Ponty
and Foucault. For an argument about the influence of semiotics on Levinas, see Kozin
(2004).
3. The term ‘science of the alien’ was coined by Waldenfels (2006).
4. In this article, Lotman functions as a guiding figure, a semiotic interpreter of Husserl.
5. Zahavi (2003) is particularly convincing in showing that the movement of Husserl’s
thought allowed for both realms to form a symbiotic relationship.
6. Following the conventions that concern the distinction between the ‘other’ and the
‘Other,’ I use the small case ‘alien’ when referring to alienness more generally,
while the capital case ‘Alien’ refers to the Alien being, which is a psychophysical
entity.
7. An example of a phenomenology of Limit-Subjects is o¤ered by Natalie Depraz who
adopts the Alien modalities — the animal, the child, the foreigner, and the insane —
toward arguing for the ability of all alien modalities to elicit from other human
beings hyper empathetic response, providing access to the liminal sphere (Depraz 2001:
171).

References

Areopagus, Dionisius (2005). On the hierarchy of heavens. In The Book of Angels, 117–170.
St. Petersburg: Amfora.
Carr, David (1973). The ‘Fifth Mediation’ and Husserl’s Cartesianism. Philosophy and Phe-
nomenological Research 34 (1), 14–35.
Deleuze, Gilles (1986). Cinema 1: The Time-Image, H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta (trans.).
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
Deleuze, Gilles (1989). Cinema 2: The Time-Image, H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta (trans.).
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
Deleuze, Gilles (1990). The Logic of Sense, M. Lester (trans.). London: Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles (1994). Di¤erence and Repetition, P. Patton (trans.). New York: Columbia
University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles (2004). Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, D. W. Smith (trans.). Lon-
don: Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles (2006). Two Regimes of Madness, A. Hodges and M. Taormina (trans.).
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix (1983). Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, R.
Hurley et al. (trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix (1987). A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophre-
nia, B. Massumi (trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Depraz, Natalie (2001). The Husserlian theory of intersubjectivity as alterology. Journal of
Consciousness Studies 8 (5–7), 169–178.
Eco, Umberto (1979). A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Holenstein, Elmar (1974). Roman Jakobson’s Approach to Language: Phenomenological
Structuralism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Husserl, Edmund (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenol-
ogy, D. Carr (trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Husserl, Edmund (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Na-
chlass, Erster Teil, 1905–1920 (¼ Husserliana 13), I. Kern (ed.). The Hague: Martinus
Nijho¤.

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM
192 A. Kozin

Husserl, Edmund (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Na-
chlass, Dritter Teil, 1929–1935 (¼ Husserliana 15), I. Kern (ed.). The Hague: Martinus
Nijho¤.
Husserl, Edmund (1977). Cartesian Meditations, D. Cairns (trans.). London: Springer.
Husserl, Edmund (2003). The Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis, A. Stein-
bock (trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Kozin, Alexander (2004). The sign of the other: On the semiotic of Emmanuel Levinas’s
phenomenology. Semiotica 152 (1/4), 235–249.
Kristeva, Julia (1989). Language: The Unknown, A. M. Menke (trans.). New York: Colum-
bia University Press.
Landgrebe, Ludwig (1981). The Phenomenology of Edmund Husserl: Six Essays. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Lanigan, Richard (1989). Phenomenology of Communication. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne
University Press.
Lanigan, Richard (1992). The Human Science of Communicology: A Phenomenology of Dis-
course in Foucault and Merleau-Ponty. Pittsburgh, PA: Dusquesne Univeristy Press.
Lotman, Yuri (1996). Inside Thinking Worlds. Tartu: University of Tartu Press.
Steinbock, Anthony (1995). Home and Beyond: On the Generative Phenomenology After
Husserl. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Waldenfels, Bernhard (1983). Phänomenologie in Frankreich. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard (1990). Experience of the alien in Husserl’s phenomenology, A. J.
Steinbock (trans.). Research in Phenomenology 20, 19–33.
Waldenfels, Bernhard (1996). Order in the Twilight, D. Parent (trans.). Athens: Ohio Univer-
sity Press.
Waldenfels, Bernhard (2006). Grundmotive einer Phänomenologie des Fremden. Munich:
Suhrkamp.
Zahavi, Dan (2003). Husserl’s Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Žižek, Slavoj (1993). The Metastases of Enjoyment. London: Verso.

Alexander Kozin (b. 1964) is a post-doctoral research fellow at Freie Universität Berlin
3kozinal@yahoo.com4. His research interests include phenomenology, semiotics, and trans-
lation theory. His recent publications include ‘Crossing over with the angel. A visual semi-
otic analysis of Genesis 32: 22–32’ (2005); ‘Subversive neutrality. An interactional phenom-
enon of translation-in-talk’ (2006); ‘The legal file. Folding law: Folded law’ (2007); and
‘Unsettled facts. On the transformational dynamism of an object in legal discourse’ (2008).

Brought to you by | University of Iowa Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 5/23/15 4:03 PM

You might also like