Pricedisc080808 0
Pricedisc080808 0
Pricedisc080808 0
1 Introduction
Whenever we take a trip by train or by plane, we are often well aware that the
price we paid was quite different from that paid by our fellow passengers with
whom we are sharing the carriage or cabin. We can bemoan this situation, if
we booked late and do not qualify for an age discount and our ticket was one of
the more expensive ones or perhaps be pleased at having gotten a good price.
The different prices are illustrations of what economists call discriminatory pric-
ing. This seems to be a textbook case where a service which is identical (same
journey, same date, same time, same comfort class) is sold at different prices1 .
∗ We gratefully acknowledge travel funding from the CNRS and NSF under grants INT-
9815703 and GA10273, and research funding under grant SES 0452864 . We thank Anita
Anderson, Alain Béraud, Catherine de Fontenay, Robin Lindsey, André de Palma, Emile
Quinet, and Sarah Tulman for their comments and suggestions. We would also like to thank
Melbourne Business School and the Autoridade da Concorrencia in Lisbon for their hospitality.
and air travel. Odlyzko (2004) provides examples from maritime transport, inland waterways,
1
Looking closer, it is a little oversimpliÞed to claim that all travelers have
actually received the same level of service. Less expensive tickets are often
service. It is often necessary to buy the ticket a long time in advance, with
enjoy the same service as she would have had if she had paid full price — unless,
of course, her plans change at the last minute. However, to get the cheap fare
she has to accept some risk, had she been obliged to change or cancel her ticket,
or indeed she might have had to put up with some inconvenience due to having
not changed her ticket in order to not lose money. There are also reduced fares
On May 5, for May 18, 2007 the prices for one-way second class travel be-
tween Charleroi Sud (Belgium) and Paris Nord (France), proposed on the inter-
32.5 E; and Smilys 20.5 E. The rates for Mezzo+, Mezzo, and Smilys can
be reserved only if sufficient seats are still available, and only if one buys a
round trip ticket. It is less expensive to buy a round-trip Smilys ticket than
to buy a one-way Librys ticket. However, Smilys can only be bought when
reserving two weeks before the departure date and it is the only fare which is
2
date. The only difference between the two tickets is that the quota for Mezzo+
is sold out quicker than for Mezzo. It is also possible to get a Lys fare for 26
tariff.
For these examples, the menu of prices that are proposed must take into
account the fact that travelers can personally arbitrage (or choose between) the
different options. There are also fare categories which are not subject to such
arbitrage, such as: Kid (15 E), for children under 12 years old; Kid & Co. (29.5
E), for adults accompanying a child under 12; Youth (29.5 E) for travelers under
26; and Senior (41.5 E) for travelers over 59. All of these classes, except for
Smilys, are also available in Þrst class — Librys, for example, costs 100 E.
Price discrimination arises when a Þrm sells different units of the same good
nonlinear pricing where the price per unit depends on the number of units
brought (such as the price of a French Metro ticket when bought singly or in a
pack of ten).2
for example, Lott and Roberts, 1991). To address this concern, some writers
2 Price discrimination is often also based on time of travel, such as evening or summer tariffs.
The simplest analysis assumes that the demands in each period are independent (see also the
analysis of peak-load pricing in the Backhaul section below). Gerstner (1986) formulates a
peak-load pricing model in which Þrms account for intertemporal demand shifting.
3
have proposed deÞnitions based on the comparison of price differences relative
to cost differences. Stigler (1987) proposed comparing the ratio of the prices
of two services with the ratio of their marginal production costs. By this
(1983) on the other hand proposes comparing absolute differences. Then prices
are discriminatory if the difference in marginal costs is not equal to the difference
in prices.
It is difficult to Þnd a decisive argument for one deÞnition over the other.3
Both deÞnitions indicate that prices can be discriminatory even if price differ-
ences are small, just as it can be discriminatory if price differences are large.
Suppose an airline brings passengers to a Parisian airport from which its in-
ternational ßights leave, and has everyone pay the same price for a ßight to
New York. This pricing discriminates against travelers living near Paris (see
Tirole, 1988, 1993, for a similar example).4 The deÞnitions do not say whether
such discrimination harms economic efficiency: the airline’s pricing scheme al-
lows it to more effectively exploit its market power by bringing its transatlantic
travelers to Paris.
A Þrm with some market power and proposing different services can set its
prices to get the greatest proÞt, and its prices will not bear any simple relation
through the ability to price above marginal cost. Offering diverse services
4
the service proposed and its pricing to a demand that differs from customer to
customer.5
ability of the Þrm to distinguish between buyers who are prepared to pay a higher
price and those inclined to pay less. Pigou deÞnes Þrst-degree discrimination
as when consumers pay their maximal willingness to pay for each unit. This is
Pigou recognized that this Þrst form of price discrimination might not have
great practical relevance. He notes that the Þrm is better able to segment the
market between different groups of buyers who have different demands. Ideally,
the Þrm would like to segment the market into groups with similar willingness
to pay; such segments could be ranked from highest to lowest willingness to pay.
talize consumers according to their willingness to pay. The Þrm must use
characteristics which it can directly monitor, such as the type of good that is
being transported (for example, livestock or pig iron6 ) for a railroad that trans-
ports freight, or the location of the buyer. This latter practice is third-degree
price discrimination.
5
for the Þrm to exercise its market power as well as possible. Rather than
and Phlips, Pigou deÞned the benchmark where the ultimate objective of dis-
crimination is attained, that is, where each unit is sold at the highest possible
price.
observable characteristics such as age, departure location, and time and date of
the journey.
to a situation which is particularly favorable for the Þrm, where the veriÞable
willingness to pay (for example, if older people are willing to pay more).
pricing or offering different comfort classes within a train or plane do not rely
on a veriÞable criterion and allow the user to choose her preferred option. Such
economists have gotten into the habit of calling such practices second-degree
price discrimination (see Phlips, 1983, Tirole, 1988, 1993, chapter 3, Varian,
1989, Mougeot and Naegelen, 1994). This term is therefore currently used to
cover practices that are quite different from those originally envisaged by Pigou.
6
The discussion above suggests that discriminatory pricing is tightly tied to
the exercise of market power.7 Under perfect competition, Þrms are constrained
to sell their output at the price that is imposed by the market. It is then
try to affect prices by proposing a range of different services (at least as long
as such services are sold in a competitive market). Even if the Þrm has some
market power, its ability to discriminate between different buyers can be undone
proposed.8
This arbitrage can take two forms, depending on whether one or several
buyers are involved. If it is possible to transfer the good, buyers can exchange
the good or service between themselves and the Þrm cannot charge different
prices, because those buyers who beneÞt from the lowest price will be able to
buy in order to resell to those who would otherwise have to pay more. For
example, if someone has a membership card which allows her to obtain her
tickets at a cheaper price, she could buy a large number of them and resell them
the condition that the ticket should be bought sufficiently far in advance, then
in order to sell them just before the date when the tickets are valid. Even
show that the extent of price discrimination has no theoretical connection to the extent of
market power.
8 One other limit on the ability to price discriminate is that Þrms cannot effectively propose
a price menu that is too complex. See Levinson and Odlyzko (2007) for a recent treatment.
7
represents a signiÞcant constraint on Þrms’ pricing strategies, so much so that
Þrms often put in place several techniques to stop it. They often require one
to present the membership card during the trip, or, for airlines, present a piece
of identiÞcation which has on it the name matching that of the ticket holder.
This type of rule also allows the Þrm to circumvent the second type of arbitrage,
in which one customer with several options does not choose the one which was
designed for her. For example, if a Þrm wants to discriminate on the basis
of age, by presenting a driver’s license the customer veriÞes that she is paying
the price that she should. When buyers can practice such arbitrage between
the different pricing options that are offered, Pigou (1938) says that demand is
transferrable.
trage. The Þrm then has to explicitly worry about potential arbitrage when it
is setting up a discriminatory tariff structure. While the Þrm cannot force its
customers to not arbitrage, it has to set up the right incentives in its pricing
plan.
that transactions costs are high enough to render it impossible. We, too, will
implicitly invoke this assumption throughout the paper.9 On the other hand,
so-called personal arbitrage— by which a user can choose an option which is not
intended for her purchase— has been the subject of numerous studies, especially
9 See Alger (1999) for an analysis of the constraints that are imposed by the potential of
8
over the last three decades.
ples which are needed to understand the rest of the paper.10 In Section 3
we will show how a Þrm can exploit information about customer demand in
between several categories of buyers who are purchasing the same good (3.2),
and market segmentation where the Þrm offers different services for which it can
perfectly determine the buyers who are prone to buying each service. Section
4 looks at strategies which allow the Þrm to motivate buyers to not engage in
personal arbitrage when the Þrm cannot stop it by using veriÞable information.
We Þrst consider using nonlinear tariffs (4.1 and 4.2), and then the possibility
clude and also discuss the link between discriminatory pricing and competition.
This discussion allows us to evaluate the robustness of the results obtained for
monopolies.
We start with the simplest pricing structure, uniform pricing, where all units of
the same good are sold at the same price, such as a given journey where there
is only one comfort class and all travelers pay the same price.
Let D (p) be the quantity demanded at the price p. The simplest inter-
1 0 For a simple and broader treatment of this subject, see Varian (2000)
9
pretation is to suppose that D describes the distribution of willingness to pay
over different travelers. Each traveler only wants a single trip, and D (p) then
It is also useful to deÞne the inverse demand for each quantity q. This is
the maximum price at which this number of trips can be sold, P (q). When
each traveler only wants a single trip, P (q) is the willingness to pay of the
marginal consumer: the individual who would not travel if the price were slightly
higher. In order to simplify the analysis, suppose that the marginal cost of
production is constant at rate c per unit, which is also therefore the average
variable production cost (and is the cost generated by each traveler). Under
perfect competition, the price would be given by this marginal cost, and the
a
q = D (p) = a − bp, a > 0, b > 0, and > c.
b
wants to carry q travelers, the highest uniform price that it could charge is:
a−q
p = P (q) = .
b
10
Figure 1: Uniform Monopoly Pricing
by the rectangle above marginal cost (i.e. the mark-up per traveler), p − c,
multiplied by the number of travelers q.11 The optimal quantity must therefore
maximize:
∙ ¸
a−q
− c q,
b
and the Þrst order conditions for an optimal quantity can be written as:
a − 2q
= c.
b
The left hand side of this expression is marginal revenue, M R. This is a straight
line with the same price intercept as inverse demand D, but its slope is twice as
steep. It is easy to see from Figure 1 that the condition for equality between
D (c) a − bc
qm = = ,
2 2
which is therefore half the quantity produced under perfect competition. The
a + bc
pm = P (q m ) = ,
2b
1 1 See Anderson and Engers (2007b) for further discussion of the concept of producer surplus.
11
and this generates a producer surplus, P S, equal to:
2
(a − bc)
(pm − c) q m = ,
4b
In the general case, the equality of marginal revenue and marginal cost al-
pricing, we will often use Þrst order conditions for prices (rather than quanti-
ties). Under uniform pricing, the Þrm chooses a uniform price pm in order to
maximize D (pm ) (pm − c) . The Þrst order necessary condition for a maximum
pm − c 1 D0 (pm )
m
= m
, where η (pm ) = pm < 0,
p |η (p )| D (pm )
where η (pm ) < 0 is the elasticity of demand. The left hand side is the mark-
up rate, also known as the Lerner Index. it is therefore higher when demand
demand at the uniform price chosen by the monopolist is always less than -1.
We have just seen that a private Þrm which maximizes its proÞt will choose a
price that is higher than the perfectly competitive price, and can thus increase
its proÞt. Obviously, this is done at the expense of the consumers (travelers),
who face higher prices. We now show how this loss of consumer well-being can
1 2 This quantity is strictly positive and unique if marginal revenue at zero is superior to
marginal cost, and if the slope of marginal revenue is always less than that of marginal cost.
12
be measured in monetary terms in a way that can be compared with the extra
price that the consumer is willing to pay for a trip and the price that she
to pay in decreasing order, so that the q trips are sold to the q travelers willing to
pay most. Aggregate consumer surplus, CS, generated by the sale of quantity
D (p) at price p, therefore corresponds to the area between inverse demand and
the quantity from 0 to D (p).13 For the solution described in Figure 1, this
resulting from a change from pricing at marginal cost to pricing at the monopoly
level is given by the monopoly producer surplus plus the area DW L in Figure 2.
This loss of consumer surplus can be interpreted as the sum of what travelers
would have been willing to pay, collectively, in order to be able to access tickets
priced at marginal cost as opposed to the monopoly price. Insofar as this total
possibility for all market participants which has not been realized (the Þrm
would be ready to cut its price down to marginal cost if, in exchange, it could
by that part of the loss of consumer surplus which is not offset by an increase
13
understand this inefficiency more concisely, it is convenient to introduce the
concept of social surplus. This is the sum of producer surplus and consumer
price.14
satisfactory. When there are increasing returns to scale, such pricing will not
cover production costs. For example, when marginal cost is constant, marginal
cost pricing will generate zero producer surplus, so the Þrm will not cover its
Þxed costs.
It follows that the Þrm must be partly Þnanced by taxpayers. It may then be
desirable to suffer some deadweight loss in order to avoid an overly large deÞcit.
that the Þrm just covers its costs. Nevertheless, it seems rather arbitrary to
impose the condition that the Þrm should not make losses. An alternative
in the allocation of resources (see Meade, 1944). Optimal pricing must therefore
strike a balance between maximizing social surplus in the markets served by the
Þrm and the efficiency cost of raising tax revenue in the rest of the economy.
The latter cost can be measured by the deadweight losses caused by the taxes in
1 4 Any price below marginal cost causes a deadweight loss because it leads to the sale of
some units for which consumers are willing to pay less than the extra social cost that their
production would engender.
14
the markets where they are levied.15 Under such circumstances, the Þrm will
only be fully Þnanced by its users if the cost of raising public funds is too large.
This reasoning also implies that if the cost of raising public funds is too large,
and if the government can appropriate the Þrm’s proÞts (which is effectively
the case if the Þrm is public), it may be desirable to earn a return exceeding
production costs. This extra revenue will enable the government to reduce Þscal
We can now address the pricing problem of a public or regulated Þrm. Fol-
marginal deadweight loss of raising public funds: an extra euro raised means a
cost of 1 + λ euros.16 The Þrm’s objective function can then be written as:
CS + (1 + λ) P S.
When λ becomes large, the Þrm pays no heed to consumer surplus. This case
correspond to a private Þrm maximizing its proÞts. Otherwise, the Þrm chooses
p to maximize:
CS (p) + (1 + λ) D (p) (p − c) .
Using the relationship CS 0 (p) = −D (p)17 gives the Þrst order necessary
condition of :
1 5 For example, income taxes cause deadweight losses in the labor market.
1 6 The size of λ has been the topic of several studies. One reasonable estimate for the US
is 0.3 (see Ballard, Shoven, and Whalley, 1985, and Hausman and Poterba, 1987).
1 7 Consumer surplus at price p is the integral of the demand for prices larger than p.
15
p−c λ 1
= .
p 1 + λ |η (p)|
The price thus obtained is a special case of what are called Ramsey-Boîteux
prices, which ensure maximization of social surplus under the constraint that
the Þrm returns a particular level of proÞts, for example to cover its Þxed costs.
Under this interpretation, λ therefore indicates the severity of the budget con-
straint and is the marginal social surplus gain that could be obtained by reducing
the proÞt level to be earned by one euro (see Ramsey, 1927, and Boîteux, 1956).
wish for public policy to respond not only to economic efficiency but also to
redistribution. The current analysis does not need to take a stand on these
issues.
Thus, if a higher price (of a train ticket) allows the government to efficiently
collect revenues, these could be used to give lump sum transfers to consumers.
of the perverse incentives it may induce, as well as perhaps for reasons of polit-
ical viability. If indeed transfers are not to be made directly from Government
revenues because it is intrinsically costly to do so, then the pricing scheme may
be used directly for transfers, and it may therefore be reasonable to put a larger
1 8 This follows from applying the Implicit Function Theorem to the Þrst order condition to
16
weight on consumer surplus than on producer surplus. This translates in our
formal analysis to −1 < λ < 0.19 This allows us to understand why we might
pricing below marginal cost. Finally, there may be other reasons for pricing
have not taken into account the possibility of positive or negative externalities
placing, in our analysis, marginal private cost with marginal social cost, which
or positive.
We Þrst consider the case which is most advantageous to the seller. This arises
when the seller has perfect information about the demand from each possible
buyer. Perfect discrimination arises when the Þrm can use this information
information, the seller must be able to control the price and the characteristics
of each unit sold to each buyer. For example, if an airline perfectly knew the
needs and desires of all of its customers it could choose the price at which each
1 9 A negative lambda might also be applied in a welfare analysis used to evaluate different
market outcomes, and where the Þrms’ losses do not contribute to (or need to be Þnanced
from) the public purse. Private Þrms’ surplus would usually be weighted (much) less than
consumer surplus. For example, a consumer surplus standard, as is arguably used in some
antitrust circumstances, would put a weight on producer surplus of zero (λ = −1).
17
client would take the price, and dictate the date, time, and comfort class.
This principle can be illustrated very simply by supposing that the good sold
is perfectly homogeneous, and that each buyer only wants a single unit. In this
case, the tastes of the buyer are completely described by her willingness to pay.
A proÞt-maximizing monopolist will then have each buyer pay her maximum
willingness to pay, leaving the consumer no surplus. The Þrm will therefore
want to sell to all those whose valuations exceed marginal cost. This situation
is shown in Figure 1 for constant marginal cost and linear demand. We see here
that this pricing policy leads to maximal social surplus, all of which is captured
by the Þrm.
The above approach can easily be extended to deal with elastic individual
demand (so the quantity demanded decreases as the price rises). For illustra-
tion, suppose that the demand curve in Figure 1 represented a single consumer.
The inverse demand would then indicate the highest price that she would pay
to consume one extra unit. If the quantity q were sold at the uniform price
P (q), the net consumer surplus would be CS (P (q)); we can then deÞne the
Optimal discriminatory pricing would then mean paying the willingness to pay
for each unit, and selling units as long as this willingness to pay exceeds mar-
ginal cost. This then induces the quantity q ∗ = D (c) sold at a tariff equal to
the corresponding gross consumer surplus, V (q ∗ ) which is the surplus that the
consumer would enjoy if she could consume the quantity q ∗ for free.
2 0 The corresponding aggregate concept simply sums the surpluses over individuals.
18
Another method for getting to the same result would be to use a two-part
tariff (see also Oi, 1971). Such a tariff would specify an entry, or membership,
fee A that the consumer must pay in order to consume the good at all. If
she joins, then she can buy as much as she wants at a price p. Setting p = c
ensures that the consumer will therefore choose q ∗ , and she will therefore enjoy
a surplus of V (q ∗ ) − cq ∗ . She will join as long as the entry fee is not larger
than this, and so the seller will set a fee as large as possible subject to this
her full surplus is extracted by the Þrm. The outcome is thus just the same as
for the preceding pricing system. Even though a two-part tariff seems simpler,
marginal cost, calculating the entry fee means knowing the consumer’s surplus,
The pricing solution for a public Þrm under the similar assumption of per-
exactly the same tariff structure. This is because all surplus is extracted from
the consumer and earned by the Þrm for the public purse.
2 1 Nofurther complication is introduced for the preceding analysis when marginal costs are
not constant. The optimal quantity, q∗ , equates the demand price with marginal cost, and all
consumer surplus is extracted. A single (all-or-nothing) tariff equal to gross consumer surplus
at this quantity is optimal, and is equivalent to a two-part tariff with a per-unit price equal
to the demand price P (q∗ ) and an entry fee of A = V (q ∗ ) − P (q∗ ) q ∗ (= CS (q ∗ )).
19
3.2 One good and several groups of buyers
these characteristics allows the Þrm to infer something about demand. The Þrm
can exploit some correlation between the observed variable and the individual
The Þrm can then choose a price that depends on the observed character-
istic, and the individual who does not have this characteristic can be excluded
from prices not meant for her. However, discrimination is imperfect insofar as
consumers are bundled together onto the same characteristics (e.g. the same age
group), and individuals still may differ by willingness to pay within the group
ing differentiation can be used to get potential buyers to reveal their tastes: see
Section 4). The Þrm is therefore obliged to set a uniform price for each category
(or group). Suppose, for example, there are two classes of buyers: youths under
26 and the rest of the population. Asking for identiÞcation (in the absence of
fake IDs), the Þrm can know which category the buyer is in. It can therefore
exclude arbitrage by which people in one group buy the good or service in or-
der to sell it to people in the other group (for example, airline tickets with the
traveler’s name on them). In the absence of such arbitrage, demand from each
Consider the case of a public Þrm: the specialization to a private Þrm will
20
simply be given by letting λ become arbitrarily large. Let pi be the price applied
to group i, and let Di (pi ) be the resulting demand curve, and CSi (pi ) be the
at rate c, so that the Þrm can choose prices for groups independently of each
This leads to a Þrst order condition which simply generalizes that, for a single
market:
pi − c λ 1
= .
pi 1 + λ ηi (pi )
This type of discrimination beneÞts the Þrm because it faces groups of con-
sumers whose elasticities differ. The less elastic demand is (the closer η is to
zero), the higher the price charged to the group. Thus, youths enjoy lower train
fares and airfares because they are more likely to reduce their demand if prices
were higher. Clearly the Þrm beneÞts from discrimination because it can always
opt to charge the same price across groups. However, only consumers for whom
marginal revenues across groups for any given total production level, and then choosing the
total quantity which equalizes marginal cost with this common revenue.
2 3 This discussion assumes that two demands are comparable in the sense that one is more
elastic than the other for all prices. It is possible to construct examples for which prices under
discrimination are higher or lower than under uniform pricing (see Nahata, Ostaszewski, and
Sahoo, 1990)
21
is simply the sum of consumer surplus and producer surplus. Note Þrst that,
this quantity between two groups. The price paid by the consumers in a group
reßects what they are willing to pay in order to buy one extra unit. Social
surplus can be increased by shifting consumption from those willing to pay less
at the margin to those willing to pay more. Furthermore, since the output of
a monopolist under uniform pricing is too low, discrimination can only improve
duced is ambiguous. For example, suppose that the demand in each group i is
Di (p) = ai − bi p.
Applying the earlier analysis of linear demand, if both groups are served under
a1 + a2 − (b1 + b2 ) c
,
2
while the quantities allocated to each group of buyers under discrimination are,
respectively:
(a1 − b1 c) (a2 − b2 c)
and .
2 2
22
The total output is therefore identical24 , and discrimination is necessarily
harmful to social welfare. This conclusion is invalid if only one group is served
served. In this case, the group which is served under both pricing schemes is
not worse off because it pays the same price under both, while the other group
pay the same price. Nevertheless, this reasoning is only valid in the short
run, because in the longer run the possibility of discrimination can motivate the
envisaged by Pigou (1938) can be seen as a special case of the above analysis of
istic used by the Þrm to discriminate can allow it to perfectly separate buyers
into groups that can be ordered according to willingness to pay, then it can
(2003b). Suppose that a traveler wishes to take a train trip and her willingness
2 4 This is a special property of linear demand, that marginal revenue corresponding to the
sum of demands is equal to the sum of the marginal revenues to the demands for each group.
23
to pay is perfectly positively correlated with age. Even though this would
seem to allow the Þrm to practice perfect discrimination (because the client’s
age perfectly reveals her demand), it might in practice be costly to specify too
many different prices. For example, it may be only possible to offer two prices.
The railroad company must then set a threshold age above which people cannot
With zero marginal cost, the monopoly price and output are both one-half. It
is then easy to see that the Þrm’s optimal strategy is to charge full fare of 2/3
for the oldest third of the population, and to set a reduced fare of 1/3 for the
younger ones. In this context, we can also determine the second best policy of
choosing the critical age with the objective of maximizing social surplus, subject
to the Þrm choosing its prices given this critical age. The second best solution is
that the Þrm only offers the reduced fare to the younger half of the population.
The Þrm would then choose a full fare of 1/2 for the older half of the population
and a half-priced fare of 1/4 for the younger travelers. In this sense, the critical
3.3 Backhauling
cost. In the case of transportation, services are provided and these depend
upon the capacity offered. While it is out of our scope to cover the full range of
issues associated with proper cost attribution, scheduling of service, and route
24
simple example of capacity that is provided on an outbound trip: the train has
to get back to the origin to make the next trip to the destination.
see Rietveld and Roson (2002) for a recent application in this vein. Many
commuters might wish to make the trip to the Central Business District in the
morning rush-hour commute, but few people want to go in the reverse direction
soon afterwards.25
goods in the opposite direction. However, the trucks, ships, or freight trips must
still make the return trip to pick up another load. This is termed the “backhaul
the classic fronthaul and backhaul context (e.g., Mohring, 1976). This is well
outbound trip to the Þnal market is created (fronthaul), then a return trip is
well understood. Suppose, as above, that the round trip costs c, and that the
25
D (p). Suppose too that the demand for trips back from the Þnal market
is Db (p). Denote the inverses of these demand curves as P (Q) and Pb (Q)
respectively. For simplicity we assume that the incremental cost when carrying
passengers for the trip back is zero. The relevant demand price for round
trips is, therefore, the sum of the demand prices for the outbound and inbound
back empty). That is, if Q is quantity, the demand price for the round trip is
P (Q) + Pb (Q) (where it is understood the demand prices are non-negative) and
this sum is equal to p in equilibrium. Denote the solution as Q̂: transport prices
³ ´ ³ ´
for each leg are then P Q̂ and Pb Q̂ . Clearly, if the backhaul demand is
³ ´
weak then Pb Q̂ can very well be zero. Some passengers can be carried, but
backhaul demand is not contributing anything to reducing the price on the front
haul, and effectively Q̂b < Q̂ where Q̂b is the number of travelers transported
on the backhaul.
It is now simple enough to see how to introduce incremental costs for back-
haul: they can be netted off the demand price for the backhaul. The same
principle applies in what follows: it suffices to net the incremental costs off the
demand price.
For a monopolist, say the commuter train where it has a large cost advantage
carry (and the corresponding prices) is that the sum of the marginal revenues
equal the marginal cost. Here again, the monopolist is not obligated to carry
26
zero. Then the solution for the fronthaul quantity, Q∗ , is given as the solu-
marginal revenue to the outbound demand curve (and M Rb (Q) for the back-
haul demand). In this case, with a weak backhaul demand the price charged
will not be zero but rather the revenue maximizing point on the (net) backhaul
demand curve. This “zero-cost monopoly price” (which is equivalently the rev-
enue maximizing price) will prevail when some backhauls carry no passengers.
Equivalently, any solution with Q∗b < Q∗ involves Q∗b = M Rb−1 (0). For any
solution to the monopoly problem, the prices on the two legs are given from the
In the preceding analysis, the discriminating Þrm behaves just like a Þrm
To set the stage, assume that a transportation vehicle (such as a train) has
a single seat to Þll.27 The operator knows that one traveler will purchase
the ticket, and that the traveler’s reservation price for the trip is uniformly
distributed on [0, 1] (think linear demand curve, as in Section 2.1 and Figure
1). There is no cost associated with selling the ticket or Þlling the seat. The
2 7 For references in this area, see Anderson and Schneider (2008), which also contains more
analysis of competitive cases. See also Sinsou (1999) for a detailed presentation of the algo-
rithmic methods Þrms can use for Yield and Revenue Management.
27
operator is to set a price to maximize its expected proÞt. Given that the
associated demand curve is linear, the price the operator should set solves the
Now consider the case where two travelers will arrive, one after the other, and
their reservation prices are independently distributed on [0, 1]. The operator
sets a single price for both. What price should it set? To Þnd the answer, we
Þrst determine its proÞt. It is more transparent to write out the more general
that the Þrst traveler buys, plus the probability that she does not (F (p)) times
the probability that the second one does (1 − F (p)). In the case of linear
demand, F (p) = p for p [0, 1] and the Þrst-order condition implies that:
1 1
p= √ >
3 2
The second order condition is readily seen to be satisÞed; and proÞt is ap-
proximately 0.385. This is more proÞt because the operator can take a shot at
a higher price given that the second customer provides some insurance in case
the Þrst one refuses. This logic is Þne-tuned in the next example. Note that
the price charged (in the current case of a single price for all) is increasing in
the number of consumers, and the proÞt is too. As the number of travelers
gets large, retaining a single seat, the price goes to the highest possible in the
population (1) and the proÞt goes to 1 too since the probability of acceptance
also tends to 1.
28
ProÞt is even higher if the operator can choose a separate price for each
arriving guest. Suppose there are again two travelers, and they arrive sequen-
tially. We want to Þnd what price will the operator will set for the Þrst one to
arrive, and what it will charge the second one if the Þrst traveler declines the
seat. To Þnd these prices, we work backwards. If the Þrst traveler does not
buy, we can simply use the answer from the monopoly case with one seat.
This gives the expected proÞt of 1/4 if the room is not Þlled on the Þrst
shot. We can now determine the proÞt for the choice of a price p1 to the
Þrst traveler. Noting that the probability that the Þrst traveler does not buy
a single price must be set for both travelers, since the discriminatory problem
We next consider the case of three travelers and two places. Recall Þrst that
1
with simple linear demand, the monopoly price is 2 and proÞt is 14 . These are
indeed the price and expected proÞt that are earned on the last traveler if one
place has already been sold. Likewise, if the very Þrst sale is a failure, there
1
are two places left and two travelers, so then the price is again 2 in each period
and the expected proÞt coming out of the failed Þrst sale is 12 . If the Þrst sale
was a success, there is one place left and there are two remaining consumers.
25
The continuation proÞt is then that derived just above, i.e., π = 64 .
We are now in a position to analyze the Þrst period’s price. This is given
29
by the solution to
∙ ¸
25 1
maxπ = (1 − F (p)) p + + F (p) .
p 64 2
£ 25
¤
With a uniform distribution, the proÞt expression is π = (1 − p) p + 64 + p 12 ,
7
which generated a Þrst order condition (1 − 2p) + 64 = 0, and hence the solution
71 71 5
p= 128 . The corresponding sequence of prices is then 128 , followed by 8 (an
1
increase) if the sale was a success or 2 (a decrease) if it was a failure. The last
The type of exercise above can be applied to various other different pricing
practices observed in transportation. For example, the SNCF sells a Þrst batch
of tickets at a lower price than a second tranche, which in turn is lower than the
third tranche. The simplest set-up to analyze this practice is to assume that
there are three travelers, and two seats. In contrast to what was just described,
the pricing is now per seat, instead of the operator being able to condition per
traveler. This implies that this is a special (constrained) case of the earlier
The analysis can also be expanded to deal with uncertainty in the number
Þrst price), correlation in traveler values, etc. We pick up on this last topic
early demand response to gauge later demand strength (for example, airlines
2 8 The proÞt associated to the pricing© per¡ seat ¢ª busi-
ness model is π = (1 − F (p1 )) p1 + p2 1 − F 2 (p2 ) +
F (p1 ) {(1 − F (p1 )) [p1 + p2 (1 − F (p2 ))] + F (p1 ) (1 − F (p1 )) p1 } .
The Þrst term corresponds to the Þrst traveler buying the Þrst (lower-priced) seat, and then
one of the other two buys the second seat. The second term corresponds to the Þrst traveler
declining the Þrst seat, and then either the second buys it (and the third might buy the second
seat), or else only the third might buy the Þrst seat.
30
or passenger trains judging demand for special events like Olympic Games or
Suppose then an operator has a single seat to Þll, and there are two potential
travellers. Both have the same valuation for traveling (perfect correlation), and
this valuation is uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. If the operator charges p to the
Þrst traveler, it expects to sell the seat with probability 1−p. If the Þrst traveler
does not buy, the operator knows the seat is worth less than p to the second.
The updated valuation for the second traveler is uniformly distributed on [0, p],
and so the optimal price to set, conditional on a Þrst refusal, is p/2. The second
Þrst refusal, is p/4. This means the operator’s proÞt problem as a function of
This proÞt is maximized at p = 2/3. If the Þrst traveler refuses, the price
is dropped to 1/3. The case of uncorrelated demand, given earlier, has less
price dispersion, starting with a lower price (5/8) and ending with a higher one
(1/2). With correlated demand, the operator starts with a higher price that
includes an experimentation motive to Þnd out more about the second traveler’s
valuation.
31
3.5 Discriminating with several products
When a Þrm sells several goods with perfectly independent demands, the sit-
uation is formally very similar to the one we have just discussed. The main
difference is that marginal costs generally differ across products. With several
at the same price or at prices that are close to each other. As we pointed out in
is discriminatory.
over time and tied sales. In all cases that we consider, the client group which
might buy one of the goods is clearly identiÞable and there is no possibility of
is possible will be studied in the next section. We Þrst develop the optimal
pricing strategy for a Þrm which sells to consumers located at different distances
from its production point. We then show how this theory is relevant to a Þrm
which must transport travelers over different distances, and we suggest other
applications in transportation.
at a competitive price, and they can use this service to transport the good from
its production point. Using this service, a consumer then pays for each unit
of the good, an f.o.b. price set by the Þrm at its production point plus the
32
transport cost.29
if the Þrm can take care of delivery itself and if it can circumvent consumers’
access to competing delivery services, it can extract more proÞt even though
the delivery point does not reveal information about the demand of the buyers
in question.
For illustration, suppose that demand is the same at every point in space. If
the Þrm charges a price px to buyers located at a distance x away, the demand
is D (px ) and the consumer surplus is CS (px ). Transport costs are linear and
it costs tx to transport one unit a distance x, with t > 0. The Þrm chooses px
to maximize
The price chosen will then be similar to that derived earlier, where we now
simply use the full marginal cost c + tx. It can be shown that as long as the
in the Þrm’s price is less than t per unit distance (see Anderson, 1989). This
means that the Þrm does not pass on all of the transportation costs into the
price (“freight absorption”). In other words, the implicit f.o.b. price— the
price net of transportation costs— is smaller the farther that buyers are from the
2 9 The term f.o.b. stands for “free on board” or “freight on board” and means that the
buyer must pay transportation costs for delivery. In spatial economics, the term f.o.b. price
is synonymous with the term “mill price” to indicate the factory price (or the store price).
3 0 See Anderson and Renault (2003a) for a precise deÞnition of this concept. The condition
33
production point.
Freight absorption is often used in practice31 . Tirole (1988) notes that there
are good reasons why there should be freight absorption even if demand curves
do not satisfy the condition above. First, any pricing policy which over-bills
transport costs might provoke arbitrage between consumers, with those who are
closer to the factory perhaps buying the good and transporting it themselves,
and reselling it to those farther away. Second, buyers far from the production
site might also be more likely to be closer to a rival’s production site, and
this might render their demand more elastic. The Þrm may consequently be
The social beneÞts from forcing a private Þrm to set a uniform price are
per se, improves social welfare) but it does so while imposing higher prices
on nearby consumers. For linear demand, the social welfare is highest under
is highest when λ > 0 because the producer surplus is always higher when the
selling long-distance ßights between Paris and New York. Customers’ points
of origin differ: they start out from different regional French airports. Our
3 1 Greenhut (1981) presents survey results on spatial pricing by Þrms.
3 2 See Lederer and Hurter (1986) for a model of competitive spatial discrimination and
Anderson, de Palma, and Thisse (1992, Chapters 8 and 9) for a review of the literature on
spatial economics.
3 3 The case of uniform pricing is a special case of discriminatory pricing. See Greenhut,
Norman, and Hung (1987) for other developments with monopoly, and Anderson, de Palma,
and Thisse (1989 and 1992b) for competition. Quinet (1998) describes in detail competition
between two airports.
34
benchmark is when ßights between different regional airports and Paris are sold
on a competitive market and are therefore sold at marginal cost. Suppose that
the airline can provide exclusive service to Paris, and that the demand for a
trip to New York is the same irrespective of the starting point of the travelers
(Paris, Bordeaux, Nice...), and that this demand is not “too convex”. The
who originate farther from Paris (because of the higher cost of service), but
price differences are less than the extra cost of serving these customers. In this
sense, the more distant customers are subsidized by those closer to Paris.
tion network. Consider two trips of different length, which therefore involve
the price difference between two trips is not the same as the cost difference. If
the demand for the two trips is the same (so that we eliminate any price differ-
ences due to demand differences), and if the demand curve is not “too convex”,
then optimal prices will be closer than costs. In other words, the price should
than the sketch presented above. Demand typically depends on the distance
traveled and the other transport modes available. Pricing should take conges-
tion into account, etc., but this simpliÞed framework at least serves to indicate
There are numerous dimensions other than space over which buyers can be
35
sorted. Time is one obvious example. Airlines often offer lower prices for
return trips that include a Saturday night stay. This practice allows them to
prices which differ according to the time and date of departure can allow account
but it can also be used to discriminate between clients with differing demand
elasticities.34
discrimination is that of bundling or tying. Sales which combine two goods were
sales allow the Þrm to distinguish buyers interested in both goods from those
plus hotel, allow tourists to pay less for both services than if they were bought
individually.
more subtle than just verifying IDs. However, strategies that do not rely on
viduals or “within” the individual. The limits that personal arbitrage impose
on discriminatory pricing were laid out in the 19th century by the French Ponts
paper. De Palma and Lindsey (2000) treat the problem of two competing toll roads, and de
Palma and Lindsey (1998) study the role of information acquisition in this context.
36
that many workers would like to use the bridge, but that a universal price of 1
In an attempt to impose a special workers’ price that would be less than that
based on clothing: “for a crosser with a cap or a smock or jacket, the toll is
reduced to 1 c.” (p. 220) instead of 5 c. for the other travelers. However, he
also notes that “it is quite likely that revenues will be reduced because some 5
c. crossers will beneÞt, by dint of their tenue, from the price reduction that was
not meant for them” (p. 220). To staunch this potential arbitrage, he proposed
only applying the price reduction at certain times of day (when workers were
more likely to be present) or to require that worker present their pay stubs. In
the next section we give a systematic analysis of strategies that allow the Þrm
4 Personal arbitrage
tion revelation problem. The Þrm knows that there is heterogeneity in the
willingness to pay among buyers, but it doesn’t have a means of knowing this
are willing to pay only one centime to cross may be relatively poor people who
are not workers with a pay stub, or indeed they may be people who do not truly
37
need to cross the bridge and who will not bother if it costs too much.
demand varies with price, or if the Þrm can vary some characteristics of its
In the example of the footbridge, Dupuit noted that the second possibility
could be to price differently according to the time of day. To see how the sale
of different quantities can be exploited in the same example, suppose that the
workers were sold a coupon, valid for six return trips per week, at a price of 12
c. If the other users only want, at most, one return trip, they will only pay 5
c. per trip rather than buying the ticket tailored for the workers. This type
As we saw above, a two-part tariff speciÞes an entry fee A and a marginal price
p, at which those who paid the entry fee can get the good. When the Þrm
perfectly knows consumer tastes it can use this type of pricing to appropriate
practice, transportation Þrms do not have such perfect information, they often
use this type of pricing. The SNCF uses different passes for various periods of
time. The French Metro (RATP) has the unlimited-ride Orange Card, which
has a marginal price of zero. As we shall now see, such a two-part tariff can be
useful when the Þrm does not know the consumers’ tastes. (see also Oi, 1971)
38
sumers, whose demand at price p is D1 (p) while the rest of the consumers
demand D2 (p). Suppose that D1 (p) < D2 (p) for all p ≥ 0 (the demand
curves are shown in Figure 3), so that Type 1 consumers are low-demand and
When the Þrm has full information it would choose a marginal price p = c
and have Type 1 consumers pay an access fee A1 = CS1 (c), and A2 = CS2 (c)
for the others. The number of trips would be q1∗ = D1 (c) and q2∗ = D2 (c)
for consumers of Types 1 and 2, respectively. These are the Þrst-best opti-
mal quantities.35 Under incomplete information, if the Þrm offered these two
choices, clearly Type 2 consumers would pay the lower entry fee A1 , which would
give them access to the same price per trip, and there would thus be personal
arbitrage.
two-part tariff. If the Þrm offered the full-information prices tailored for Type
2 buyers, the consumers with the lower willingness to pay would not buy.
If there are enough Type 1 consumers (if α is large enough), this will not
be the best solution. Instead, offering the Þrst-best optimal price tailored for
the Type 1 consumers, the Þrm can put in place an allocation which maximizes
total surplus (because marginal price equals marginal cost and both types of
This will be an optimal solution for a public Þrm when there is no marginal
3 5 Theyare the socially optimal quantities if the Þscal system allows lump-sum redistribution
with a zero marginal cost of public funds.
39
cost of public funds (λ = 0). If λ > 0, the Þrm is also concerned with its proÞts.
Even though the Þrm can extract the full surplus of Type 1 consumers, it must
The Þrm’s objective can be split into two parts, the social surplus associated
plus the entry fee, which has a value of λ per euro because it is a transfer from
full consumer surplus from Type 1 consumers when λ > 0. If A < CS1 (p) <
CS2 (p), a small increase in the entry fee will have no impact on the quantities
consumed and will raise revenues, so the Þrm is better off. It will therefore
choose, as with full information, to set A = CS1 (p), so that consumers with
a low willingness to pay are just indifferent between joining and not joining.
Nevertheless, in contrast to the solution with full information, the Þrm now
wants to price above marginal cost. Even though the Þrm would maximize its
objective over the Type 1 consumers by choosing p = c, this does not maximize
social surplus with regard to the Type 2 consumers. The objective can then be
40
written as:
where the last term takes into account that an increase in marginal price must
The Þrm can thus improve surplus by increasing the marginal price. As
the effect of such an increase on social surplus for Type 1 buyers is negligible
optimal marginal price pmar is strictly between marginal cost and the price
which maximizes social surplus for Type 2 consumers. This latter price is
striction that the second price be linear in quantity, performs better. Figure
3 shows that consumers with a high willingness to pay get a surplus (a rent)
measured by area KN LM J.
Suppose that instead of offering a two-part tariff, the Þrm gives each con-
41
pmar q2 + CS2 (pmar ), plus the area KN J. Type 1 consumers will then prefer
of JN LM if they chose (q1 , T1 ), and they would get at least as much paying T2
for quantity q2 . The Þrm then wants to leave the Type 2 consumers with as
As we shall see, the pricing scheme that we have just described dominates
the simple two-part tariff, but it is not generally the optimal tariff. It has a
zero surplus, and consume less than their Þrst-best optimal quantity (which
positive surplus and are indifferent between the two choices offered. This latter
Continuing the theme from above, suppose that there is a choice between two
considered the problems with personal arbitrage from buyers with weak demand.
Taking into account the possibility of such arbitrage can greatly complicate the
prices, it will be more useful to write gross surplus as a function of the quantity
3 6 Forfurther advances on this topic, see Brown and Sibley (1986) and Wilson (1992).
3 7 It
is straightforward to show that the solution we shall describe is not subject to arbi-
trage by Type 1 buyers, insofar as it remains the optimal solution when we include an extra
constraint to take such arbitrage into account.
42
consumed. To this end, let Vi (q) denote the gross surplus of a buyer of type i
consuming quantity q. If personal arbitrage only arises from buyers with high
demand, it is clear that there should be no surplus left for consumers with low
demand. If their surplus was positive, raising the tariff T1 would raise revenues
without affecting quantities because this would render Package 1 ((q1 , T1 )) less
attractive to Type 2 consumers. This condition for zero surplus for Type 1
T1 = V1 (q1 ) .
On the other hand, a strictly positive surplus must be left to Type 2 buyers,
because if the combination (q1 , T1 ) is acceptable for Type 1 buyers then the
Type 2 buyers would get a strictly positive surplus from this combination. To
get them to buy Package 2 ((q2 , T2 )), they must be enticed with at least as
V2 (q2 ) − T2 = V2 (q1 ) − T1 ,
The term in brackets is the “informational rent” which the high demand buy-
ers must be guaranteed under personal arbitrage. If λ > 0, this rent represents
43
a cost for the Þrm.
buyers. For the choice of q2 , it can be seen from Figure 4 that if q2 < q2∗ , an
increase of this quantity will raise social surplus for a Type 2 buyer as well as
raising the Þrm’s proÞts (with the informational rent unchanged) and it is not
argument, if q2 > q2∗ , the Þrm can improve surplus by reducing the quantity
addressed to Type 2 buyers.38 The Þrm thus chooses to produce the Þrst-
best socially optimal quantity (obtained by ignoring the marginal cost of public
funds) for buyers whose demand is high. This is also true for λ > 0. ProÞts
that can be earned by selling to Type 2 buyers depend on social surplus and
informational rent. Because the latter only depends on the quantities sold
to Type 1 buyers, it is optimal to choose for Type 2 buyers the quantity that
If the Þrm could extract the full surplus of a Type 1 consumer, it would
like this consumer to buy q1∗ = D1 (c), because this would extract the maximal
surplus. This would also yield the greatest Þscal revenue, which coincides with
the social surplus. Because the Þrm is uncertain about the buyer type, it must
take into account the impact the quantity q1 has on the rent that would accrue
Taking into account this possibility leads the Þrm to choose a quantity below
3 8 Recall that the area between marginal cost and demand entails a negative surplus when
the latter is below the former.
44
the Þrst-best optimal one, q1∗ . At q1∗ the effect of a quantity reduction on social
surplus for a Type 1 consumer is negligible, while it allows the surplus to a Type
with Type 1 consumers and a decrease in the informational rents to Type 2 con-
sumers. Figure 5 shows that the reduction in social surplus would be P1 (q1 )−c,
which has a social value of (1 + λ) per euro, because this amount is entirely ap-
propriated by the Þrm. The reduction in informational rent, which from the
Þgure is P2 (q1 ) − P1 (q1 ), is a transfer from Type 2 consumers to the Þrm and
whose social value per euro is therefore λ. The optimal quantity can thus be
seen from the Þgure: it is the value of q1 for which the ratio of the vertical
distance between the lower demand and marginal cost to the vertical distance
λ 1−α
.
1+λ α
where the last term measures the impact of informational rent on the Þrm’s
objective when the buyer is of Type 2 (and a constant term involving V2 (q2 ) is
45
λ 1−α 0
V10 (q1 ) = c + [V2 (q1 ) − V10 (q1 )] .
1+λ α
useful to rewrite it using the fact that the gross surplus derivative of type i is
the price Pi (q), given by the inverse demand curve, which is the demand price
This latter pricing induces consumers to buy less than the Þrst-best optimal
cost. The possibility of generating such a surplus depends inversely on the price
elasticity of demand: the more elastic demand is, the less feasible it is to raise
price without causing too large of a drop in quantity. With nonlinear pricing,
reduced, while still motivating them to reveal their demand. The distortion is
larger when the impact on rent is higher, as measured by P2 (q1 ) − P1 (q1 ), and
1−α
the relative share of high-demanders is higher, as measured by α . Because
46
Although it is clear that the price per unit will differ between groups of
often see that those who buy more beneÞt from larger discounts. For example,
membership programs or frequent traveler programs allow those who travel more
to pay less.
The current analysis does not immediately apply to this type of rebate, in
part because we have not explicitly considered the possibility that large buyers
could buy up several packages targeted to small buyers (see Alger, 1999, for more
merit a deeper study (recent work includes Cohen, 2002, Ivaldi and Martimort,
frequent practice is to offer several classes of service on the same voyage. This
practice goes back a long way, and Jules Dupuit gives an extremely perceptive
consumers could be made to pay all of the utility that they get from
make them voluntarily sort themselves into one or another price cat-
47
host of measures which are generally quite poorly understood by the
public.
they denounce the barbarity of the railways. It would cost very little,
they say, to put some meters of leather and kilos of horse-hair [on
benches; it would happily sacriÞce this for the sake of its popularity.
Its goal is to stop the traveler who can pay for the second class
trip from going third class. It hurts the poor not because it wants
them to personally suffer, but to scare the rich. The proof is that
if today the State were to say to this railroad: here are one hundred
Thus, it is for the same reason that companies, after being cruel
prodigious for those in Þrst class. After having refused the poor
48
Walras (1875/1897) had a similar view of the logic which guided the pricing
in second class, and 5.5 c. in third class; but they put 24 travelers
average price of 7.66 c., which is close enough to the 7.5 c. which is
the second class fare, as being the price of maximal proÞt; but they
who are prepared to pay more, nor to refuse to get less from travelers
the companies to put windows in third class, and when today they
second class travelers and some of the Þrst class ones would go there,
out on a large number of travelers who, rather than pay the Þrst or
49
Following Dupuit and Walras, the choice of the level of comfort in the differ-
ent seating classes is effectively driven by the desire to make people pay a price
those from whom the company wants to extract a high fare. Such arbitrage is
our results for nonlinear pricing. We have shown that potential personal ar-
fect discrimination. Dupuit and Walras suggest that railways use a similar
logic when they choose the level of comfort. We now show that there is a
pricing of a homogeneous good, consider the following model due to Mussa and
Suppose that there are two types of users, l and h, differing in their willing-
ness to pay for quality. Assume that their willingness to pay for an extra unit of
quality is θh and θl , respectively, where θh > θl . Now let q be the quality level
of the service proposed rather than the quantity sold, as it was under nonlinear
is then given by Vi (q) = θi q. Each customer only wants one unit of the good,
and her willingness to pay is her gross surplus. Her net surplus for a price T is
50
θi q − T . The marginal cost of service c (q) is increasing and strictly convex.
The combinations of quality q and tariff T that give an equal level of utility
lines with slope θi (with quality on the horizontal axis and euro price on the
vertical). The indifference curve through the origin corresponds to zero surplus
indifference curves farther to the right. The producer surplus for one unit of
service (one trip) from quality q sold at tariff T is given by T − c (q). If the Þrm
knew the value of θi for each traveler, it could perfectly discriminate and leave
the Þrm will therefore choose the quality qi∗ that maximizes this (with social
Figure 6 shows the indifference curve for zero surplus and the marginal cost
curve as a function of quality. The optimal quality is that which maximizes the
distance between the indifference curve and marginal cost, which gives a value
qi∗ where the curves have the same slope: formally, θi = c0 (qi∗ ) (the vertical
distance between the two curves is always less than that between the indifference
curve and the tangent to marginal cost at qi∗ ). With perfect discrimination,
the optimal quality will then optimize the willingness to pay for quality with
If the Þrm does not know the consumers’ willingness to pay for quality then,
if it were to offer the two Þrst-best optimal qualities, it would necessarily leave
some surplus to the high consumer type. Figure 7 shows that the combination
51
(qh∗ , Th∗ ) is to the left of the high-type user’s indifference curve, denoted by ICh,l ,
which goes through (ql∗ , Tl∗ ), and she therefore prefers this latter combination.
In order to motivate her not to choose the low quality, the Þrm must quote
her a price such that she is on the indifference curve ICh,l . Just as under
constitutes the constraint for the Þrm. Again, because the Þrm is not concerned
with arbitrage by the low-demanders, it can extract their full surplus so that the
between the indifference curve ICh,0 and the indifference curve ICh,l (which is
the difference between the perfectly discriminatory tariff and what they actually
have to pay).
The social surplus associated with high-demanders is then the Þrst-best so-
cial surplus. Although this rent does not depend on the high quality, the
optimal high quality is qh∗ , as with perfect discrimination. On the other hand,
as is seen from Figure 7, the Þrm wants to decrease the low quality below ql∗ .
This permits the Þrm to reduce the informational rent because the indifference
curve ICh,l shifts left while, for a small change, the loss of social surplus as-
This model thus conÞrms Dupuit’s (1849) intuition. The comfort in third class
is deliberately reduced to dissuade travelers who are ready to pay for higher
levels of comfort from traveling at the cheaper fares. Today’s economy class
air travelers might sympathize. As Tirole (1988, 1993) points out, the comfort
52
offered to the Þrst class travelers actually is not “superßuous” because it is the
level chosen under perfect discrimination; contrary to what Dupuit and Walras
thought, it is only by adjusting the lower quality that the Þrm discourages per-
sonal arbitrage. There is therefore a perfect analogy between this model and
that of nonlinear pricing, and the results are the same (under reinterpretation).
Only passengers whose willingness to pay is high can retain some surplus, and
One variant of this model explored by Chander and Leruth (1989), and
class decreases in the number of users as it becomes more congested. The Þrm
then chooses two different prices, with the cheaper class having a lower quality
just because it attracts more travelers. The two classes in the Parisian Metro
until the 1980s give a striking illustration of this type of strategy.39 Second class
carriages only differed from Þrst class by their color, but fares were lower.40
The modern day counterpart to the insights of Dupuit and Walras can be
found without much difficulty in air travel. What was true in nineteenth century
train carriages sometimes seems to be not very far off from what is found on
modern economy class ßights. Airlines could scarcely charge such premiums
for Þrst and business class travel if economy class were more comfortable.41
3 9 Another illustration is that of a toll road with a parallel freeway to the same destination
(see de Palma and Lindsey, 2000).
4 0 This system was abolished by Charles Fiterman, Communist Transportation Minister in
that it has about passengers is very sparse and evolves over time. See the sub-section on
Yield Revenue Management above.
53
5 Conclusion
We have focused on discriminatory pricing for a single Þrm (without rivals) and
Þrm under the assumption that public funds are valued more than consumer
pricing problem of a public Þrm and that of a private Þrm. However, restricting
this analysis to monopolies is more restrictive for the private sector. Although
several transport modes are effectively monopolies, such as the railways and
most notably the airlines. We now give a brief review of oligopoly competition42 .
For the discussion that follows, we consider private proÞt maximizing Þrms
and we let λ = 0, so that consumer surplus and producer surplus are equally
weighted.43
ory fairly quickly delivers some main conclusions. For one good sold to several
groups the model most directly comparable with monopoly is Cournot’s frame-
work, where Þrms choose outputs and price equates aggregate output with the
quantity demanded. If each Þrm has the same marginal costs ci for serving
4 2 Fora review of the state of the art
on price discrimination under oligopoly, see Stole (2007), and Armstrong and Vickers (2001).
4 3 The Competition Authority of the European Union seems to put more weight on consumer
surplus.
54
market i, Lerner’s formula becomes:
pi − ci 1 1
= ,
pi ni |η i (pi )|
where ni is the number of active Þrms in market i. If Þrms have different costs,
pi − cm 1 1
= ,
pi ni |ηi (pi )|
where
ni
1 X
cm = cj
ni j=1
is the average cost for serving market i. This formula is directly comparable to
the monopoly one. If two groups differ by elasticity of demand, we again Þnd
that the price is higher for inelastic demand. However, all prices go to marginal
cost when the number of Þrms becomes large, and competition eliminates price
differences. These results can also be applied when Þrms discriminate with
different products, in which case the marginal cost differs from one market to
differentiation within each market. One common formulation for demand for
in greater detail in other chapters of this book. One interesting feature of these
congestion, into the consumer preferences which are at the heart of the model.44
4 4 Anderson, de Palma, and Thisse (1992a) provides background for this model.
55
The multinomial logit model is a particularly useful formulation. If prices
µi
pij = cij + ,
1 − Dij
where Dij is the equilibrium demand addressed to Þrm j in market i and depends
on prices set by all active Þrms in market i. Anderson and de Palma (2001)
show that this price equilibrium has several intuitive properties. For example, if
consumers have a higher tendency to buy the product, then prices will be high
and the differences will be large across variants. Furthermore, the more Þrms
there are, or the more similar they are (from the point of view of a group of
consumers), the lower prices will be and the more similar they will be across
Þrms.
differences across different services. Borenstein and Rose (1994) note that fol-
lowing airline deregulation in the United States, price differences increased. The
theoretical explanation that they propose is that those travelers who are willing
to pay more for a trip (hence, those for whom the reservation value is high) are
also those who are the most loyal to a particular airline, which translates to a
duced into the marketplace, the difference between the high business class fare
and the low economy class fare is ampliÞed by the differential intensity of com-
petition at the two service levels. Competition is more intense for the economy
56
segment.45 However, more recent work by Gerardi and Shapiro (2007) Þnds
York market, aimed at different consumer types. He Þnds that fares targeted to
business ßiers differ across airlines, while fares targeted to leisure ßiers do not.
petition concerns the level of producer surplus when discrimination is not always
possible (it could, for example, be illegal). Several authors came to the same
conclusion: in contrast to monopoly, it may be that proÞts are lower when Þrms
can discriminate. Hoover (1948, p. 57) anticipated this result in the context of
spatial discrimination.
guerrilla warfare. In the former case all the Þghting takes place
along a deÞnite battle line; in the second case the opposing forces are
This indicates that the implications of discrimination for proÞts can be very
4 5 Borenstein and Rose base their theoretical arguments on Borenstein (1985) and Holmes
(1989).
57
different, depending on the degree of competition. However, it remains true
and Rochet (1989), Ivaldi and Martimort (1994), Stole (1995), Armstrong and
Vickers (2001), and Rochet and Stole (2001). The latter two articles show
that if duopolists offer relatively close services, nonlinear pricing can lead to
two-part tariff with zero proÞts for each Þrm (an extension of the Bertrand
Paradox). Rochet and Stole (2001) also show that if the services offered are
continue to develop the theoretical framework which will allow empirical studies
References
[1] Alger, Ingela (1999). Consumer Strategies Limiting the Monopolist’s Power:
[2] Anderson, Simon P. (1989). Socially Optimal Spatial Pricing. Regional Sci-
58
[3] Anderson, Simon P. and André de Palma (1989). Spatial Price Discrimina-
592.
[5] Anderson, Simon P., André de Palma and Brent Kreider (2001). Tax Inci-
81, 173-192.
[6] Anderson, Simon P., André de Palma and Brent Kreider (2001). Efficiency
[7] Anderson, Simon P., André de Palma and Jacques-François Thisse (1989).
1-18.
[8] Anderson, Simon P., André de Palma and Jacques-François Thisse (1992a).
Mass.
[9] Anderson, Simon P., André de Palma and Jacques-François Thisse (1992b).
59
[10] Anderson, Simon P. and Maxim Engers (2007a). Consumer Surplus, Article
[11] Anderson, Simon P. and Maxim Engers (2007b). Producer Surplus, Article
126-139.
[13] Anderson, Simon P. and Luc Leruth (1993). Why Firms May Prefer not to
[14] Anderson, Simon P. and Régis Renault (2003a). Efficiency and Surplus
264.
[15] Anderson, Simon P. and Régis Renault (2003b). Second degree price dis-
[16] Anderson, Simon P. and Yves Schneider (2008) Price Competition with
Virginia.
578-590.
60
[18] Anderson, Simon P. and Wesley W. Wilson [2008]. Spatial Competition,
[19] Armstrong, Mark and John Vickers (2001). Competitive price discrimina-
[21] Ballard, Charles L., John B. Shoven and John Whalley (1985). General
[23] Boîteux, Marcel (1956). Sur la gestion des monopoles publics astreints à
[25] Borenstein, Severin (1991). Selling costs and switching costs: explaining
61
[26] Borenstein, Severin and Nancy Rose (1994) Competition and price disper-
sion in the U.S. airline industry. Journal of Political Economy, 102, 653-683.
[27] Brander, J. A. and A. Zhang (1990). “Market Conduct in the Airline In-
[28] Brown S. and Sibley, David (1986). The theory of public utility pricing.
[30] Chander, Parkash and Luc Leruth (1989). The Optimal Product Mix for
[32] Cohen, Andrew (2002) Package Size and Price Discrimination in the Paper
62
[34] Cournot, Augustin (1838). Recherches sur les principes mathématiques de
[35] De Palma, André and Robin Lindsey (1998). Information and Usage of Con-
[36] De Palma, André and Robin Lindsey (2000). Private toll roads : competi-
tion under various ownership regimes. The Annals of Regional Science, 34,
13-35.
[37] Dupuit, Jules (1849). De l’inßuence des péages sur l’utilité des voies de com-
207.
[38] Gerardi, Kristopher and Shapiro, Adam Hale (2007). The Effects of Com-
[39] Gerstner, Eitan (1986). Peak Load Pricing in Competitive Markets. Eco-
[40] Hausman, Jerry A. and James Poterba (1987). Household Behavior and
[41] Holahan, William L. (1975). The welfare effects of spatial price discrimina-
63
[42] Holmes, Thomas J. (1989). The effects of third degree price discrimination
Studies, 4, 182-191.
McGraw-Hill.
[46] Ivaldi, Marc and David Martimort (1994). Competition under Nonlinear
http://rational.ce.umn.edu.
[51] Lott, John R. and R. D. Roberts (1991). A guide to the pitfalls of identifying
64
[52] McAfee, R. Preston, Hugo M. Mialon, and Sue H. Mialon (2006). Does
360-367.
[54] Meade, James (1944). Price and output policy of state enterprise. Economic
Ballinger.
[56] Mougeot, Michel and Florence Naegelen, (1994) La discrimination par les
[57] Mussa, Michael, and Sherwin Rosen, (1978). Monopoly and product qual-
[59] Oi, Walter, (1971). A Disneyland dilemma: Two-part tariffs for a Mickey
65
[61] Pigou, Arthur Cecil (1938). The economics of welfare. Macmillan and Co.,
[63] Rietveld, Piet, and Roberto Roson [2002] Direction dependent prices in
public transport: A good idea? The back haul pricing problem for a mo-
[64] Rochet, Jean-Charles and Lars A. Stole (2001). Nonlinear pricing with
242-247.
[66] Seade, J. E. (1985). ProÞtable cost increases and the shifting of taxation:
66
[69] Stigler, George (1963). A note on block booking. Supreme Court Review.
[70] Stole, Lars A. (1995). Nonlinear pricing and oligopoly. Journal of Eco-
[72] Tirole, Jean (1988). The Theory of Industrial Organization. MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
[74] Thisse, Jacques-François and Xavier Vives (1988). On the strategic choice
zation, Vol. 1, Chapter 10. Eds. Richard Schmalensee and Robert Willig,
North-Holland, Amsterdam.
[78] Walras, Léon (1897). L’Etat et les chemins de fer. Manuscript written 1875.
67
[79] Wilson, Robert (1992). Non-linear pricing. Oxford University Press, Ox-
ford, England.
[80] Yin, Xiangkang (2004). Two part tariff competition in duopoly. Interna-
68