Peregrin - An Inferentialist Approach To Semantics
Peregrin - An Inferentialist Approach To Semantics
Peregrin - An Inferentialist Approach To Semantics
Abstract
The perennial question – What is meaning? – receives many answers. In this paper
I present and discuss inferentialism – a recent approach to semantics based on the
thesis that to have (such and such) a meaning is to be governed by (such and such) a
cluster of inferential rules. I point out that this thesis presupposes that looking
for meaning requires seeing language as a social institution (rather than, say, a
psychological reality). I also indicate that this approach may be seen as a new
embodiment of the old ideas of structuralism.
What is Meaning?
One of the most basic questions anybody who deals with language must
– sooner or later – face is the question: What is meaning? i.e., what is it
that makes some types of sounds or inscriptions meaningful? (It is therefore
somewhat surprising that a name for the ‘science of meaning’, semantics,
did not materialize until the late nineteenth century.)1 Moreover, even in
the twentieth century, investigation into the nature of meaning was held
as a more pressing task by philosophers than by linguists (particularly, of
course, following the linguistic turn which took place in the first half of
the twentieth century,2 and which stimulated the idea that to understand
meaning might be the task of philosophy).
Hence, what is meaning? It is helpful first to distinguish between various
senses this question may have. Let us start with the most obvious: taking
it to ask about the substance of which a meaning is made. What kind of
stuff makes up the chunk that must be glued to a type of sound or
inscription to make it meaningful?
The most exposed cases of such an alleged gluing are evidently the
events of baptism, through which a (proper) name becomes associated
with a tangible object (typically a human infant), and thus we may be
tempted to think that meanings are generally tangible things, elements of our
physical world. This answer, however, soon falls into disrepute; for the
physical world can not provide enough suitable entities to furnish all our
© 2008 The Author
Journal Compilation © 2008 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
An Inferentialist Approach to Semantics 1209
is not stated in exact terms; and yet we are asked to give an exact solution.
(Logical Foundations of Probability 3–4)
A B A∧B
T T T
T F F
F T F
F F F
(Disregard for now that the functioning of the English and has additional
complexities, that it, for example, often expresses temporal succession.
The point would remain the same even if and were taken to denote some
more complicated function, such as that proposed within various versions
of dynamic semantics.12)
The trouble is that this assumption could delude us into thinking that
and is the name of such a function in an analogous sense to which the
name Julius Caesar is the name of the historical person. And from this it
takes only a small step to wondering whether there is an act of baptizing
of the above truth-function by and, analogous to the act by which Julius
Caesar was baptized. (Not, of course, that anyone would be suggesting an
act quite analogous to Julius’s christening; but the usual wisdom is that
the interconnection of the word and the truth table is a matter of convention,
which does indicate some act of deliberate decision.)
The same may be the case if we move from merely logical words, like
and, to other parts of the vocabulary. Frege proposed explicating the
meaning of a predicative expression like (to be a) dog as a function mapping
individuals onto truth values, dogs on the truth and every other individual
on the falsity; a function that may obviously be identified with a set of
individuals, in the case of (to be a) dog with the set of all dogs. Carnap
urged that this would not yield us a feasible explication of meanings and
added possible worlds: the explication of the predicative expression became
a function mapping possible worlds onto their respective sets of dogs. And
then came others who have tried to further improve on this proposal.
In any case, Frege’s proposal clearly reflects the fact that a predicate like
(to be a) dog forms true sentences with some names (namely, names of
dogs), and false with others. Carnap’s improvement is then exposed as
reflecting the fact that what is and what is not a dog depends on the state
of the world; and further improvements may then reflect further semantic
aspects of predicates. Whatever the resulting function may be, it is not to
be seen as something that came to be named by the predicate, but rather
as something that tries to capture the functioning of the predicate.
Hence, asking how an expression has come to name the entity like the
truth function or the Carnapian intension is precisely the kind of misguided
question that might be engendered by not observing the distinction
between the explicatum, the explicating object, and the explicandum, the
explicated phenomenon. A function is a thing, and what comes naturally
when we consider the establishment of a relationship between an expression
© 2008 The Author Philosophy Compass 3/6 (2008): 1208–1223, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00179.x
Journal Compilation © 2008 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
1214 An Inferentialist Approach to Semantics
and a thing is some relation of the kind of naming. This may lead to the
idea that the whole language is simply a huge system of interconnected
names. And indeed this view has informed the notion of language held by
many theoreticians of language (originally more philosophers and logicians
than linguists, but recently probably mostly linguists influenced by logic).
A1, . . . , An A
in the sense of A is correctly assertible whenever A1, . . . , An are, we may
further rewrite this as
A and B A
A and B B
A, B A and B
Now the truth table above can be seen as summarizing these rules: the
first row says that if A and B are true, i.e., correctly assertible, then also
A and B is; whereas the other three say that if either A or B is false (not
correctly assertible), then also A and B is (not correctly assertible); in other
words that if A and B is correctly assertible, then both A and B are. Hence
the claim may be that seeing the connective as a name of the truth
function is misguided (though in many contexts it does not raise any
problems), for in fact the truth function is merely the explication of the
expression of the inferential role.
Considerations of this kind are well known from the philosophy of
logic, where we have been witnessing, for several decades, discussion
between those who are convinced that the semantics of logical constants
is essentially inferential (and is to be studied by proof theory) and those for
whom the constants must be seen as standing for something (and hence
must be accounted for by model theory).14 This, however, is not what
interests us now; our interest is whether the inferential paradigm can be
extended outside the boundaries of logical constants.
without a representation. For how could a word like dog come to express
the concept of dog without, at least inter alia, representing dogs? And
though there is undoubtedly some truth in this, the inferentialist answer
is that the concept of representing leads to a very odd way of capturing
what is going on between our empirical vocabulary and the world.
As it is only sentences that may be used to make a move in a language
game, any contact between a word and (a part of ) the world must be
mediated by sentences. Beside this, what matters is not what the speakers
really do with the sentences, but what they take to be correct to do – the
relation is normative. Thus, the link between the word dog and the world
is a matter of such facts as that it is correct to use the sentence This is a
dog in certain situations, and incorrect in others.
True, the usage of This is a dog may be ‘non-inferential’ in the sense
that its correctness is a matter of directly the extralinguistic circumstances,
and hence what is in question is not an inference in the standard sense
(from language to language), but an ‘inference’, as it were, from the world
to language. (Similarly, at the other ‘end’ of language, there are ‘inferences’
from language to action.) This means that if we want to extend the
inferentialist treatment of meaning from expressions like and to expressions
like dog, we have to generalize the concept of inference.
But talking about ‘generalized inferences’ may not be the best way of
seeing the situation. Imagine chess. The move I make responds exclusively
to the moves made by my opponents. It cannot respond to anything else,
for there is, in fact, nothing else to respond to. The pieces, board and
other equipment, strictly speaking, are not necessary – it is clear that we
can play chess completely without them. Thus, the rules of chess spell
out a pure, disembodied structure. However, as Lance pointed out,
language is more similar to a sport like football than to a game like chess.
Notice that football is less ‘disembodied’ than chess, in that its rules must
take into account the physical properties of the ball or the goalposts.
Similarly, the rules of language must reflect the fact that our language
games are not games in the sense of being self-contained; they are an
important way for us to interact with the world. Thus most of our language
games involve the world, and hence also the rules reflect the involvement.
As a result, even if you construe semantics in the inferentialist way, we
must keep in mind that the inferential rules governing it and conferring
meanings on expressions will involve the world. (Brandom stresses that
our linguistic practices cannot be seen as ‘hollow, waiting to be filled up
by things’, but rather as ‘as concrete as the practice of driving nails with
a hammer’ (332).) Hence, to understand dog, we must know not only how
the sentences containing dog (This is a dog, Every dog is a mammal and
others) can be correctly played within the game of giving of asking for
reasons in response to utterances of other players (that This bird is a dog
counts as a challenge to Every dog is a mammal, which than can be
defended by But this bird is not a dog), but, more broadly, how they are
© 2008 The Author Philosophy Compass 3/6 (2008): 1208–1223, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00179.x
Journal Compilation © 2008 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
1218 An Inferentialist Approach to Semantics
correctly used also vis-à-vis non-linguistic circumstances (that This bird is not
a dog is correctly played only when what one is pointing at is a bird etc.).
of eleven players etc.) has clearly something to do with human brains, but
nobody would pursue the idea that it is a mere imprint of a structure of
the brain we are born with. The question is why the case of language
should be any different.
Moreover, we must distinguish between syntax (which has to do with
the individuation of the potential vehicles of meaning) and semantics
(which is a matter of different vehicles carrying the same or different
meanings). And even if the former might be seen as closely connected to
the very structures of our brain (it is true that the individuation directly
rests on the wired up similarity standards), the situation is very different for
the latter. It may be inborn that we perceive two sounds as instances of
the same word, but surely not that we perceive two different types of
sounds as meaning the same.15 So what is the basis of the oppositions, or
of the structure, which make up semantics?
The answer the (neo)structuralists – who were also (neo)pragmatists,
like Quine or Sellars – were bound to give is that it is the sameness and
difference of usability, of the role that a word is able to play within our
language games, that any semantic structure must rest on.16 Two sentences
are semantically alike or synonymous if they can be employed to make
similar or the same moves within our language games. And then two words
can be said to be synonymous if their replacement within a sentence never
changes the way the sentence may be employed within the games.
Inferentialism, which gives the use-theory of meaning a normative
twist, is based on the assumption that the role of a word within our
language game is not a matter of the actual moves their players make, but
rather of the rules governing the permitted usage of these words. (Of
course, the rules are also a matter of what the players do; however, not
of the moves they choose to make, but of their ‘taking’ certain moves as
correct, whereas others as incorrect. In chess, the rules are also not a
matter of the moves the players tend to make, but rather of the fact that
they take some moves for legal and others for illegal.)
The notion of synonymy, which results from these considerations, is
vague, and hence also the resulting semantic structure, and consequently
its materialization into meanings, is vague. Therefore we must be aware
of the fact that making the step from the structure to an explication of
meaning is a non-trivial one – it amounts to drawing sharp boundaries
there where there are really none. However, this should not be read as
saying that explication is a dubious enterprise. Replacing fuzzy phenomena
by their non-fuzzy explications, using idealized models, is a standard part
of the methods we use to account and make sense of our world.
Thus the resulting picture is that our linguistic games, especially the central
game of giving and asking for reasons, are governed by certain rules which are
implicit in our practices and hence are not distinct in the way explicit rules
can be, but which are nevertheless essential. What we call meanings, then, are
the roles individual expressions of our language acquire vis-à-vis the rules.
© 2008 The Author Philosophy Compass 3/6 (2008): 1208–1223, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00179.x
Journal Compilation © 2008 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
1220 An Inferentialist Approach to Semantics
Many initiators of the pragmatic turn, notably Quine, were quite hostile
to the very concept of meaning – they praised the turn for ridding us of
the concept as an excessive baggage and for letting us concentrate directly
on our linguistic practices. In the same spirit, Sellars criticized Carnap for
his inclination towards ‘formal semantics’.17 However, in this paper I have
indicated that the two enterprises, inferentialism as one of the outcomes
of the pragmatic turn, and formal semantics as a project of a logico-
mathematical explication of meaning, need not be seen as incompatible.
Indeed I am convinced that the interconnection of the two projects may
help us make sense of many traditional ideas on the boundary between
linguistics and philosophy: it may throw new light on some of the ideas
of the classical and newer structuralism, it may provide for a new and
illuminating way of representing semantics yielded by normative use theories,
and it may lead us to a reinterpretation of the Frego-Tarskian formal
semantics such that it survives the pragmatic turn.
Acknowledgment
Work on this paper was supported by grant No. 401/06/0387 of the
Czech Science Foundation.
Short Biography
Jaroslav Peregrin’s research is located at the intersection of logic, analytic
philosophy, and semantics; he has authored papers in these areas for
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Erkenntnis, Journal of Philosophical Logic,
Pragmatic and Cognition, Semiotica, Studia Logica, and the Elsevier’s Handbook
of the Philosophy of Science (see his bibliography at <http://jarda.peregrin.cz/
mybibl/mybibl.php>). His book Meaning and Structure (Ashgate, 2001)
argues that recent and contemporary (post)analytic philosophy, as developed
by Quine, Davidson, Sellars, and Brandom, is largely structuralistic in the
very sense in which structuralism was originally tabled by de Saussure; it
also indicates that this view of language is not incompatible with formal
approaches to semantics. His current research focuses on both logical and
philosophical aspects of inferentialism, namely, the view that meaning is
essentially a matter of inference. He is a researcher at the Institute of
Philosophy of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic and a
professor of logic at the Faculty of Arts and Philosophy of the Charles
University in Prague. As a visiting scholar, he worked at the University
of Konstanz in Germany and the University of Pittsburgh in the USA.
Notes
* Correspondence address: Institute of Philosophy, Academy of Sciences of the Czech
Rebublic, Jilská 1, 110 00 Prague, Czech Republic. Email: peregrin@ff.cuni.cz.
Works Cited
Belnap, Nuel. ‘Tonk. Plonk and Plink’. Analysis 22 (1962): 130 – 4.
Brandom, Robert. Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1994.
Bréal, Michel. Essai de sémantique. Paris: Hachette, 1897.
Carnap, Rudolf. Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1942.
——. Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago, IL: U of Chicago P, 1950.
——. Meaning and Necessity. Chicago, IL: U of Chicago P, 1947.
Chomsky, Noam. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton, 1957.
Coffa, Alberto. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1991.
Davidson, Donald. The Structure and Content of Truth. Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990): 279 – 328.
Dekker, Paul. ‘The Semantics of Dynamic Conjunction’. Logic, Language and Computation III.
Eds. J. Seligman and P. Blackburn. Stanford, CA: CSLI, 2000. 105 –25.
Devitt, Michael. Designation. New York, NY: Columbia UP, 1981.
Egginton, William and Mike Sandbothe, eds. The Pragmatic Turn in Philosophy. New York, NY:
SUNY Press, 2004.
Fodor, Jerry. The Language of Thought. Scranton: Cromwell, 1975.
——. ‘Psychosemantics’. The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1987.
Frege, Gottlob. ‘Der Gedanke’. Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus 2 (1918/19):
58 –77.
——. Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Breslau: Koebner, 1884. English translation: Foundations of
Arithmetic. Oxford: Blackwell, 1953.
——. ‘Über Sinn und Bedeutung’. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100 (1892):
25 – 50.
Hacking, Ian. ‘What is Logic?’ Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979): 285 –319.
Kripke, Saul. ‘Naming and Necessity’. Semantics of Natural Language. Eds. D. Davidson and G.
Harman. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1972. 253 – 355. Subsequently published as Naming and Necessity.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1980.
Lance, Mark Norris. ‘Some Reflections on the Sport of Language’. Philosophical Perspectives 12
(1998): 219 – 40.
Lewis, David. ‘General Semantics’. Semantics of Natural Language. Eds. D. Davidson and G.
Harman. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1972. 169 –218.
Montague, Richard. Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague. New Haven, CT:
Yale UP, 1974.
Peregrin, Jaroslav. ‘Brandom and Davidson. What Do We Need to Account for Thinking and
Agency?’. Philosophica 76 (2006): 43–59.
——. ‘Is Compositionality an Empirical Matter?’. The Compositionality of Meaning and Content.
Eds. M. Werning, E. Machery, and G. Schurz. Frankfurt: Ontos, 2005. 135 – 50.
——. Meaning and Structure. Ashgate: Aldershot, 2001.
——. ‘The Nature of Meaning. Brandom vs. Chomsky’. Pragmatics and Cognition 13 (2005):
39 – 57.
——. ‘Semantics without Meaning?’. Prospects of Meaning. Ed. R. Schantz. Berlin: de Gruyter,
forthcoming 2008.
Prior, Arthur. N. ‘Conjunction and Contonktion Revisited’. Analysis 24 (1964): 191– 5.
——. ‘Runabout Inference Ticket’. Analysis 21 (1960/61): 38 – 9.
Putnam, Hilary. ‘The Meaning of “Meaning” ’. Language, Mind and Knowledge. Ed. K. Gunderson.
Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 1975. 131– 93.
Quine, Willard Van Orman. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York, NY: Columbia
UP, 1969.
——. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1960.
Rorty, Richard, ed. The Linguistic Turn. Chicago, IL: The U of Chicago P, 1967.
de Saussure, Ferdinand. Cours de linguistique générale. Paris: Payot, 1931. English translation:
Course in General Linguistics. New York, NY: Philosophical Library, 1959.
Schiffer, Stephen. Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.
Sellars, Wilfrid. ‘Language as Thought and as Communication’. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 29 (1969): 506 –27.
——. ‘Language, Rules and Behavior’. John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom. Ed. S.
Hook. New York, NY: Dial Press, 1949. 289 – 315.
——. ‘Some Reflections on Language Games’. Philosophy of Science 21 (1954): 204 –28.
Tarski, Alfred. ‘What are Logical Notions?’ History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (1986): 143 – 54.
Turing, Alan. ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’. Mind 59 (1950): 433 – 60.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Oxford: Blackwell, 1953. English translation:
Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell, 1953.
——. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge, 1922. English translation: London:
Routledge, 1961.