Civil Tpology

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Civil–military relations (Civ-Mil or CMR) describes the relationship between civil society as a whole and

the military organization or organizations established to protect it. CMR is an umbrella concept that
incorporates a diverse, often normative field, which moves within and across management, social
science and policy scales. [1] More narrowly, it describes the relationship between the civil authority of a
given society and its military authority. Studies of civil-military relations often rest on a normative
assumption that civilian control of the military is preferable to military control of the state, although
some analyses are more descriptive in nature.

A paradox lies at the center of traditional civil-military relations theory. The military, an institution
designed to protect the polity, must also be strong enough to threaten the society it serves. A military
take-over or coup is a worst-case example. Ultimately, the military must accept that civilian authorities
have the "right to be wrong".[2] In other words, they may be responsible for carrying out a policy decision
they disagree with. Civilian supremacy over the military is a complicated matter. The rightness or
wrongness of a policy or decision can be ambiguous. Civilian decision makers may be impervious to
corrective information. The relationship between civilian authorities and military leaders must be
worked out in practice.[3]

The principal problem they examine, however, is empirical: to explain how civilian control over the
military is established and maintained.[4] [5] In the broader sense it examines the ways society and
military intersect or interact and includes topics such as the integration of veterans into society,
methods used to recruit and retain service members, and the fairness and efficacy of these systems, the
integration of minorities, women, and the LGBT community into the military, the behavior and
consequences of private contractors, the role of culture in military organizations, voting behavior of
soldiers and veterans, and the gaps in policy preferences between civilians and soldiers. [6]

While generally not considered a separate academic area of study in and of itself, it involves scholars
and practitioners from many fields and specialties. Apart from political scienceand sociology, Civ-Mil
(CMR) draws upon such diverse fields as law, philosophy, area studies, psychology, cultural
studies, anthropology, economics, history, diplomatic history, journalism, and the military, among
others. It involves study and discussion of a diverse range of issues including but not limited to: civilian
control of the military, military professionalism, war, civil-military operations, military institutions, and
other related subjects. International in scope, civil-military relations involves discussion and research
from across the world. The theoretical discussion can include non-state actors[7][8] as well as more
traditional nation-states. Other research involves discerning the details of military political
attitudes, voting behavior,[9][10][11] and the potential impact on and interaction with democratic society[12]
[13]
as well as military families

Typology of CM

The term “civil–military relations” refers broadly to the interaction between the armed force
of a state as an institution, and the other sectors of the society in which the armed force is
embedded. It is an intensely interdisciplinary area of research, reflecting the work of political
scientists, military sociologists, and historians. Arguably, the field of civil–military relations
really took off – at least in the United States – as social scientists became part of the war
effort in World War II. Much of this early civil–military relations research focused on the
individual service member and small unit cohesion (Stouffer et al. 1949–50; Gray 1959).

Subsequently, there have been several “waves” of civil–military research (Desch 1999:2). In
the late 1950s and early 1960s, Samuel Huntington (1957), Morris Janowitz (1960), and
Samuel Finer (1962) reoriented research away from individuals and toward the relationships
among military institutions, societies, and governments in the post–World War II period. But
given the belief that military intervention in the United States was highly unlikely, the focus
of much postwar civil–military relations research was comparative, with special attention to
emerging states in Africa, Latin America, and the Middle East (Shils 1962).

A second wave emerged in the 1970s in response to the belief that US–Soviet détente
might create the conditions for international peace (Betts 1977; Perlmutter 1977;
Nordlinger 1977). A third wave broke with the end of the Cold War and continues to this
day. Much of this wave's research has focused on civilian control of the military in liberal
democracies (Dunlap 1992; Weigley 1993; Kohn 1994; 2002; Luttwak 1994; Foster 1997;
Holsti 2001) and the consequences of a possible “gap” between liberal society and a
possibly distinct military culture (Ricks 1999; Guttman 2000; Feaver and Kohn 2001). It has
not been unusual during this period to hear warnings about a “crisis” in civil–military
relations (Foster 1997; Kohn 1994; 2002; 2008).

For the most part, those who study civil–military relations take for granted that there are
significant differences between the leaders, institutions, values, prerogatives, attitudes, and
practices of a society at large, on the one hand, and those of that society's military
establishment, on the other (Welch 1993:507–11). Paradoxically, these differences apply
even to military governments, since the distinction has to do with functional roles, not
background. The functional role of the “political” leader, whether he wears a uniform or not,
is to address the whole array of domestic and foreign affairs that the state may face. The
functional role of the “military” leader is to run the military on a day-to-day basis
(Brooks 2008:3).

The basis of civil–military relations is a dilemma: what Peter Feaver has called the civil–
military problematique, which requires a given polity to balance two concerns. On the one
hand, it must create a military establishment strong enough to protect the state. On the
other, it must somehow ensure that this same military establishment does not turn on the
state that established it (Feaver 1996).

The response of a polity to the civil–military problematique can be seen as


a bargain negotiated among three parties: the citizens, the civilian governmental authorities,
and the uniformed military. The purpose of this bargain is to allocate prerogatives and
responsibilities among the parties.

Obviously, the terms of the bargain and the bargain itself will vary from state to state and,
even within a single polity, may vary across time. For instance, in liberal democracies, the
playing field is relatively balanced: all three parties have more or less of a say in negotiating
the terms of the bargain. Although the citizenry may not be directly involved in drawing up
the bargain, the bargain cannot be sustained without their acquiescence. For instance,
during the period of the Early US Republic, important political and military leaders would
have preferred a larger regular establishment, but strong opposition to the idea of a
standing army rendered such a preference moot (Cress 1982).

This is not to say that in a liberal democracy, the parties to the bargain are equal. The
liberal democratic civil–military bargain is the outcome of an “unequal dialogue.” It is “a
dialogue, in that both [the civilian and military] sides expressed their views bluntly, indeed,
sometimes offensively, and not once but repeatedly – and unequal, in that the final authority
of the civilian leader was unambiguous and unquestioned” (E.A. Cohen 2002:247). In liberal
democracies, the military, despite having a monopoly on coercive power, generally accepts
its position relative to the other parties.

In authoritarian states, conversely, the role of the people at large is greatly curtailed. In the
extreme case, the military may be coeval with the government, subject to the distinction
made above. As has been said about Prussia, most states have an army but, in the case of
Prussia, the army had a state.

From time to time throughout the history of a polity, certain circumstances – political,
strategic, social, technological, etc. – change to such a degree that the terms of the existing
civil–military bargain become obsolete. The resulting disequilibrium and tension lead the
parties to renegotiate the bargain in order to restore equilibrium.

There are five sets of questions that lie at the heart of the civil–military bargain at a given
time (Owens forthcoming). The first category concerns the issue of who controls the
military, and how. In authoritarian or praetorian states, the question is largely moot. On the
other hand, liberal societies often take civilian control for granted, but doing so begs several
further questions: does civilian control refer simply to the dominance of civilians within the
executive branch – the president/prime minister or the secretary/minister of defense? What
is the role of the legislative branch in controlling the military instrument? Is the military
establishment “unified,” that is, does it speak with anything like a single voice vis-à-vis the
civil government? What is the nature of military advice? Should military leaders “insist” that
their advice be heeded? What courses of action are available to military leaders who
believe the civilian authorities are making bad decisions?

The second question is closely related to the first. What degree of military influence is
appropriate for a given society? To what extent does or should the military intervene in
domestic affairs? The extreme form of military influence is a coup d’état. Another form of
military intervention in domestic politics is praetorianism. How does the government avoid or
limit military intervention? For the most part, advanced liberal societies have avoided these
forms of military intervention. But even in the case of a liberal society, it is appropriate to
ascertain the proper scope of military affairs. To what extent should the military influence
domestic or foreign policy? Should active duty officers lobby for programs and policies?

The third question concerns the appropriate role of the military in a given polity. Is it to fight
and win the nation's wars or engage in constabulary actions? What kind of wars should the
military be preparing to fight? Should the focus of the military be foreign or domestic? States
have answered this question differently at different times and under different circumstances.
For example, throughout most of its history, the United States Army was a constabulary
force. It oriented itself toward large-scale conflicts against foreign enemies only in the
1930s. The end of the Cold War and the attacks of 9/11 have suggested new answers, e.g.
a focus on “irregular warfare” (counterinsurgency and counterterrorism) as well as an
openness to the use of the military in domestic affairs. What impact do such issues have on
civil–military relations?

Fourth, who serves? Is military service an obligation of citizenship or something else? How
are officers accessed and promoted? Is the accession and promotion of officers based on
merit and achievement or political affiliation, social class, ethnicity, or religion? Obviously,
such questions have been answered differently from state to state and even differently
within a state at different times under different circumstances. Through most of its early
history, the United States maintained a small regular peacetime establishment that mostly
conducted limited constabulary operations. During wartime, the several states were
responsible for raising soldiers for federal service, either as militia or volunteers.
Conscription was the norm in the United States from World War II until the 1970s. Today
the US military is a volunteer professional force. But even this force continues to evolve, as
debates over such issues as women in combat and service by open homosexuals make
clear (Moskos et al. 2000; Miller and Williams 2001). Other states pursue different
approaches.

Finally, how effective is the military instrument that a given pattern of civil–military relations
produces? All of the other questions mean little if the military instrument is unable to ensure
the survival of the state. If there is no constitution, the question of constitutional balance
doesn't matter. Does effectiveness require a military culture distinct in some ways from the
society it serves? What impact does societal structure have on military effectiveness? What
impact does political structure exert? Is the effectiveness of militaries in some developing
states degraded as a result of their primary role in ensuring domestic security and regime
survival? What impact does a given pattern of civil–military relations have on the
effectiveness of strategic decision making processes (Brooks 2008; Desch 2008)?

In general, there are two lenses through which to examine these questions. The first is
the institutional lens, which focuses on how the actors in a polity, including the military as an
organization, interact within the institutional framework of a given polity's government. The
most influential institutional theory of civil–military relations was advanced fifty years ago by
Samuel Huntington in his seminal work, The Soldier and the State (1957). The primary
concerns of institutional theorists are control of the military, the proper sphere of the military,
and the ability of the military to maintain its effectiveness in protecting the interests of the
state – in the face of a “social imperative” that may be hostile to the military “way.”

The second lens is sociological or cultural. This lens focuses on the broad question of
military culture vs. liberal society; the role of individuals and groups, e.g. women, minorities,
enlisted servicemen and women within the military and the relationships among them; the
effectiveness of individual service members in combat; small unit cohesion; the relationship
between military service and citizenship (to include the civic republican tradition); the nature
of military service (occupation, profession, etc.); and the relationship of militaries and the
societies from which they stem. The origins of the sociological perspective on military affairs
can be traced to Morris Janowitz’s 1960 book, The Professional Soldier (Burke 1993; 1998).

A variation of this perspective is “concordance theory,” which rejects the idea that “healthy”
civil–military relations necessarily require a distinct separation between the civilian and
military realm. Israel, for instance, has little separation between the two and yet civil–military
relations seem stable (Schiff 1995; 2009).

Questions of civil–military relations are complex. It is unlikely that one analytical approach
will provide anything close to the whole picture. A “central task of the political sociology of
the military is to look at both the military institution and the political system and to determine
how the special institutional characteristics of a particular military establishment shape its
response to influences coming from the political system” (Stepan 1971:55).

Of course, an important reason for studying civil–military relations is to determine what


constitutes “good” and “bad” relations. Such a determination is of more than merely
academic interest. It has implications for the very survival of a polity. As the civil–
military problematique would suggest, the worst-case consequences of dysfunctional civil–
military relations would include catastrophic failure on the battlefield leading to the defeat of
the state in a war or the seizure of the government by the military itself.

But dysfunctional civil–military relations may generate other adverse outcomes short of the
catastrophic ones. For example, poor civil–military relations may lead to failures in strategic
assessment (Brooks 2008). This is true during both war and peacetime. In the case of war,
poor strategic assessment may contribute directly or indirectly to defeat on the battlefield
because strategic leaders, both political and military, fail to share information or cooperate
in other ways (Snyder 1984; Brooks 2008). A case in point is the US war in Iraq. Many
observers have contended that most of the problems the United States faced in this conflict
were the result of Secretary of Defense Rumsfeld's management style (Herspring 2008), the
insulated nature of the Bush administration, or Rumsfeld's penchant for simply overruling
advice that did not support his preferences. However, Brooks argues persuasively that
these problems, especially with regard to post-conflict planning, resulted from civil–military
pathologies created by earlier debates over “transformation” in the Pentagon between
Rumsfeld and the uniformed military. These pathologies resulted in oversight mechanisms
that weakened strategic coordination (Brooks 2008:226–55).

In the case of peacetime, poor strategic assessment may lead to an overestimation of an


adversary's capabilities, resulting in the wasting of resources on defense. On the other
hand, underestimating adversaries’ capabilities leads to the allocation of too few resources
to defense.

Criteria for judging the health of civil–military relations might include: (1) relative harmony
between civilians and the military; (2) the effectiveness of the armed forces in executing
their missions; and (3) constitutional balance. “Good” civil–military relations would seem to
exhibit some combination of the following: (1) comity and a low number of disagreements
between civilian and military decision makers; (2) success in war and peace and the
absence of policy–strategy “mismatches”; and (3) a lack of encroachment by either party on
to civil–military decisions on the “turf” of the other.

Some authors dispute the notion that harmony and comity necessarily make for “good”
civil–military relations, arguing that tension between civilian authorities and the military is
healthy. For instance, a low number of disagreements between civilian and military decision
makers may simply mean that the civilians have appointed “yes men” who can always be
expected not to “rock the boat” (E.A. Cohen 2002). This charge was frequently leveled
against former US Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld.

Unfortunately, “except for the most obvious cases, there is no consensus in the recent
literature as to what constitutes ‘good’ civil–military relations or ‘effective’ civilian control of
the military” (Snider and Carlton-Carew 1995:16). In the case of liberal democracies, the
absence of coups would seem to set the bar too low. Most scholars focus on the extent to
which civilian preferences prevail when there are differences between the civilians and the
military (Huntington 1957:83–5; Feaver 1996; Desch 1999:4–5; Kohn 2002). Others equate
healthy civil–military relations with the maintenance of civilian values and the lack of military
domination of society (Millett 1979). Of course, a critical measure of good civil–military
relations is success in war. Paradoxically, this may require civilian intervention in military
affairs, generating significant civilian–military friction (E.A. Cohen 2001).

Determining “bad” civil–military relations is less difficult. The two polar extremes of bad
relations are militarismand de-bellicization. The former is the dominance of military
institutions, values, prerogatives, attitudes and practices, etc. within society (Ekirch 1956;
Vagts 1959). The latter is the denigration or even complete extirpation of military virtues
from a society (Huntington 1957; Guttman 2000; Sheehan 2008), the most dangerous
consequence of which is defeat in war. While some have suggested that the United States
is moving toward one extreme or the other (Lasswell 1941; Ekirch 1956; Bacevich 2005),
the evidence to support such claims is weak. The real civil–military relations issues for most
polities, including developing states, concern the mutual influence of the civilian and military
sectors of society. “The problem of the modern state is not armed revolt but the relation of
the [military] expert and the politician” (Huntington 1957:20; Welch 1992).

Influences on Civil–Military Relations


A number of factors influence the civil–military relations of a state. The first of these are its
history and culture. All too often, students of civil–military relations treat history and culture
as peripheral issues, “intervening variables” that lie between the “real” factor to be studied –
the independent variable, whatever it may be – and the dependent variable, the state or
pattern of civil–military relations (Desch 1999:11). But the substantial differences in patterns
of civil–military relations between Prussia and Great Britain in the nineteenth century and
between the United States and Israel today are directly attributable to differences in culture
and history (Craig 1955; Strachan 1997; Schiff 2009).

The political institutions of a state also exert a strong influence on its civil–military relations
by allocating relative power to civilian and military leaders. Clearly, different regime types
will exhibit different patterns of civil–military relations (Janowitz 1964: Perlmutter 1970; S.P.
Cohen 1984; 2002; Avant 1994; Millett and Maslowski 1994; Bland 2000; Peri 2003;
Lewis 2006; Schiff 2009). The military may be dominant, subordinate to civilian control, or
share power (Brooks 2008:33–4). Even in highly militarized regimes, the military may only
be one constituent part. For example, in the Soviet Union, the military had to compete
against the Communist Party apparatus and the state security system, the KGB, for
influence (Nichols 1993). The People's Liberation Army (PLA) faces similar challenges in
China.
In liberal democracies, civil–military relations are affected by the constitution of the state
and the statutes and practices arising therefrom. In such polities, civil–military relations are
complicated by the vast array of players in both the civilian and military realms.

The former consists of the executive and legislative branches of government, both of which
are further divided. The executive branch includes the president or prime minister, the
appropriate cabinet officers, especially the secretary/minister of defense, advisory
committees, e.g. the National Security Council in the United States, and non-cabinet civilian
appointees such as the service secretaries. The fact that the interests of political appointees
and career civil servants are not always the same and that the interests of both may differ
from those of the uniformed military has an important impact on civil–military relations. Nor
are legislatures monolithic, consisting as they do of members from a number of political
parties. Structure matters as well. The national legislature of the United States is bicameral.
In the United States, as in most liberal regimes, the legislative branch does most of its
business in committees.

The same goes for the military realm, which usually includes a number of uniformed
services. For many years in the United States, the services were the main players on the
military side. The result was often a high degree of interservice rivalry, which reached its
peak in the United States during the “defense unification” debates after World War II. This
extreme manifestation of interservice rivalry played out not only within the newly formed
Department of Defense, but also in Congress and the press (Caraley 1965; Keiser 1982;
Boettcher 1992). While competition among separate services for mission and resources
may contribute to civil–military pathologies, such competition may also have some
beneficial effects, e.g. division of labor, a prudent focus on planning future forces, and
innovation (Sapolsky 1997; Owens 2006). But since the passage of the Goldwater-Nichols
Defense Act in 1987, power has flowed from the services to the commanders of the “unified
commands,” the joint regional and functional organizations that are tasked with the actual
conduct of operations and deployments.

Nonetheless, the individual services still exert a great deal of influence on US policy. As
Huntington observed, each military service is built around a particular “strategic concept […]
which defines the role of the service in national policy, public support which furnishes it with
the resources to perform this role, and organizational structure which groups the resources
so as to implement most effectively the strategic concept” (1954:483). These paradigms,
which the late Carl Builder called “masks of war” (Builder 1989), have shaped the services’
institutional approaches to influencing policy, especially in Congress.

The power of the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff (CJCS) was also enhanced by
Goldwater-Nichols (Locher 2002). Previously, CJCS was merely the spokesman for the
Joint Chiefs of Staff, a corporate body consisting of the four service chiefs, who in their
collective capacity were the source of military advice to the president. But Goldwater-
Nichols made the Chairman, not the Joint Chiefs of Staff as a whole, the primary military
adviser to the president and the secretary of defense. Along with the large Joint Staff, the
Chairman per se has become a major player in civil–military affairs, despite the fact that he
is not in the chain of command. Precedent is also important. In the case of the United
States, the principle of military subordination to civilian authority seems to have been
internalized by each generation of officers based on the precedent set by George
Washington at the end of the American Revolution. Most analysts agree that the likelihood
of a coup d’état in the United States is low, but others wonder if the power of this precedent
has been weakened over the past few years. But the low likelihood of a coup in the United
States does not mean that military actors cannot still find other ways to undermine balanced
civil–military relations.

However, precedent is not always determinate. The military establishments of India and
Pakistan were both shaped by the British military tradition, but the civil–military relations of
the two countries are vastly different (Schiff 2009).

Changes in the international security environment also influence civil–military relations,


although writers have disagreed about the direction of that influence. Harold Lasswell
contended that a greater level of external threat would move civil–military relations in the
direction of a “garrison state” (Lasswell 1941). Michael Desch, on the other hand, has
argued that states facing high external threats and low internal threats have the most stable
civil–military relations (Desch 1999).

Technology has an impact on patterns of civil–military relations. For instance, the


destructive power of nuclear weapons not only increased the role of civilians in the
development of strategy, but also reduced the leeway of the military in operational and even
tactical matters (Feaver 1992). The proliferation of information technology increases the
potential for civilian involvement in operational details. Social forces play an important role
as well in shaping civil–military relations, as illustrated by debates over racial integration,
women in combat, and open homosexuals serving in the military (Moskos et al. 2000; Miller
and Williams 2001; Williams 2008).

The character of conflict affects civil–military relations. Changes in the kinds of war the
military is expected to fight have potential implications for the process of strategic decision-
making, the composition and operations of military organizations, and the interagency
cooperation process during the course of a conflict. Patterns of civil–military relations during
traditional interstate war may well differ from those during the conduct of a
counterinsurgency. Heavy reliance on special operations forces has implications for
congressional oversight and the increasing reliance on contractors will continue to
complicate civil–military relations.

Finally, there is the changing concept of “soldier-hood.” In the case of the United States, the
idealized model for military service throughout most of American history was the “citizen-
soldier.” A civilian most of the time, he answered his country's call in times of emergency,
returning to civilian pursuits once the emergency had passed. Since the end of the draft in
1973, the citizen-soldier has given way to the long-term professional, a soldier akin to the
Roman legionnaire (Abrams and Bacevich 2001; E.A. Cohen 2001). Other countries face
similar issues (S.P. Cohen 1984; 2002; Gal 1986; Haqqani 2005).

Theories of Civil–Military Relations


As the Prussian “philosopher of war,” Carl von Clausewitz, observed: “theory exists so that
one need not start afresh each time sorting out the material and plowing through it, but will
find it readily to hand and in good order” (Clausewitz 1976:141). A theory seeks to illuminate
comprehensively and systematically the link between cause and effect.
At a minimum, a theory must be able to describe usefully the phenomenon or phenomena
under investigation and explain it. This is the empirical function of theory. But theories often
are employed to do two other things. First, based on its description and explanation of the
phenomenon under examination, a theory may be used to predict, at least in a general way,
what might happen under similar conditions in the future. A theory may also serve as the
basis for prescribing policy, for translating “is” to “ought.” This normative function links the
descriptive and predictive qualities of the theory to the policy of the state.

Applied to civil–military relations, a workable theory would meet the minimum requirement
to describe and explain the nature and characteristics of different patterns of civil–military
relations. But most theories of civil–military relations are also used to specify general
conditions either conducive or detrimental to healthy relations (Desch 1999:11). Finally, a
theory of civil–military relations may prescribe what steps a state must take in order to
achieve or maintain healthy relations.

Clearly this meaning of theory is less formal than that found in the physical sciences. It is
more based on intuition, experience, and an understanding of the rules arising out of
practice. What Michael Handel observed with regard to theory in war applies with equal
force to theories of civil–military relations: “the development of the study and theory of war
is (and probably will remain) in a pre-Newtonian, pre-scientific, or non-formal stage”
(Handel 2001:xvii).

The need for a theory of civil–military relations is driven by the aforementioned civil–
military problematique(Feaver 1996). In order to ensure its security, society delegates the
authority for the use of force to a subgroup within society. How does society ensure that this
subgroup does what it is supposed to – protect society from its enemies, both foreign and
domestic – without turning on society itself?

The problematique implies that there are two polar dangers for a society when it comes to
civil–military relations. If the military is weakened in order to ensure that it will not turn on
society itself, it may face defeat on the battlefield. But if the military is given everything it
needs to ensure that it will prevail on the battlefield, it may be in a position of political
dominance, able to dictate policy to the civilians. These correspond to de-bellicization and
militarism.

The extreme case of military dominance is a coup. But even short of a coup, there is always
the possibility that the military will not do what civilian authorities want it to do. For instance,
in the United States the uniformed military has often employed such techniques as leaks to
the press, lobbying the public and Congress, “foot-dragging,” and “slow-rolling” to thwart the
policy goals of civilian authorities (Feaver 2003; Owens forthcoming).

Samuel Huntington: An Institutional Theory of


Civil–Military Relations
The theory of civil–military affairs prevalent in most Western liberal polities is based on a
distinction between the civil and military realms. This approach can be traced to the practice
of eighteenth and nineteenth century European states and to the theory of war advanced by
Clausewitz. Rebecca Schiff calls this approach “separation” theory (Schiff 2009).
Although the Prussian state that Clausewitz served is often seen as the exemplar of
militarism, his formulation of war as a continuation of politics or policy (politik) by other
means (Clausewitz 1976:87) implies a distinction between political decision makers and the
military. “No one starts a war – or rather no one in his senses ought to do so – without first
being clear in his mind what he intends to achieve by that war and how he intends to
conduct it. The former is its political purpose; the latter its operational objective” (1976:579).

Actual war as opposed to war in theory (absolute war) “is only a branch of political activity”
that “is in no sense autonomous” (Clausewitz 1976:605). “The character and general shape
of any war should mainly be assessed in light of political factors and conditions” (1976:607).
Since “absolute” war is theoretically unlimited, driven by its own logic to the extreme of
violence and exhaustion, it is the political purpose of war that makes war “rational,”
providing war with a purpose beyond its own logic.

The most influential theory of civil–military relations in the West in general and the United
States in particular is the institutional theory advanced half a century ago by the eminent
political scientist Samuel Huntington in his book, The Soldier and the State (1957). The
Soldier and the State has had a great and lasting effect on American thinking about the way
the military interacts with civilian society, especially within the uniformed military. Indeed,
the US military has come to endorse many of its general conclusions and has made it
central to its civil–military relations education.

Huntington's main descriptive or empirical claim was that American civil–military relations
were shaped by three variables: first, the external threat, which he called the functional
imperative; and two components of what he called the societal imperative, i.e. “the social
forces, ideologies and institutions dominant within the society” (Huntington 1957:2–3).

The first component of the societal imperative is the constitutional structure of the United
States, the legal-institutional framework that guides political affairs generally and civil–
military affairs specifically. The second is ideology, the prevailing worldview of a state.
Huntington identified four ideologies: conservative pro-military, fascist pro-military, Marxist
antimilitary, and liberal antimilitary (1957:89–94). He argued that the fourth was the
dominant ideology of the United States (1957:143).

Huntington contended that both components of the societal imperative – the constitutional
structure and the American ideology of antimilitary liberalism – had remained constant
throughout American history. Accordingly, the entire burden of explaining any change in
civilian control or level of military armament would have to rest with the functional
imperative, i.e. the external threat (1957:2, 156).

Huntington further contended that liberalism was “the gravest domestic threat to American
military security” (1957:457). “The tension between the demands of military security and the
values of American liberalism,” Huntington continued, “can, in the long run, be relieved only
by the weakening of the security threat or the weakening of liberalism” (1957:456). Thus the
requisite for military security is a shift in basic American values from liberalism to
conservatism. Only an environment that is sympathetically conservative will permit
American military leaders to combine the political power which society thrusts upon them
with the military professionalism without which society cannot endure (1957:464).
According to Huntington, America's antimilitary liberal ideology produces “extirpation” – the
virtual elimination of military forces – when the external threat is low, and “transmutation” –
the refashioning of the military in accordance with liberalism, which leads to the loss of
“peculiarly military characteristics” – when the external threat is high. In Huntington's view,
the problem for the United States in a protracted contest such as the Cold War was that
while transmutation may work for short periods of time during which concentrated military
effort is required, e.g. a world war, it would not assure adequate military capability over the
long term.

In the context of the Cold War, Huntington argued that the ideological component of
America's societal imperative – liberal antimilitary ideology – would make it impossible to
build the forces necessary to confront the functional imperative in the form of the Soviet
threat to the United States and to permit US military leaders to take the steps necessary to
provide national security. Thus the predictive element of Huntington's theory held that
without a change in the societal imperative, the United States would never be able to build
the military forces necessary to confront the USSR.

The prescriptive or normative element of Huntington's theory was to suggest a way for the
United States to deal with the dilemma raised by Feaver's civil–military problematique: how
to minimize the power of the military and thus make civilian control more certain without
sacrificing protection against external enemies. His prescription, which he called “objective
civilian control,” has the virtue of simultaneously maximizing military subordination and
military fighting power. Objective control guarantees the protection of civilian society from
external enemies and from the military themselves.

In Huntington's prescriptive or normative theory, the key to objective control is “the


recognition of autonomous military professionalism,” i.e., respect for an independent military
sphere of action. Interference or meddling in military affairs undermines military
professionalism and so undermines objective control (1957:83).

This constitutes a bargain between civilians and soldiers. On the one hand, civilian
authorities grant a professional officer corps autonomy in the realm of military affairs. On the
other, “a highly professional officer corps stands ready to carry out the wishes of any civilian
group which secures legitimate authority within the state” (Huntington 1957:84). In other
words, if the military is granted autonomy in its sphere, the result is a professional military
that is politically neutral and voluntarily subordinate to civilian control. Of course, autonomy
is not absolute. Huntington argues that while the military has responsibility for operational
and tactical decisions, civilians must decide matters of policy and grand strategy.

While objective control weakens the military politically, rendering it politically sterile or
neutral, it actually strengthens the military's ability to defend society. A professional military
obeys civilian authority. A military that does not obey is not professional.

At the opposite pole from objective control lay Huntington's worst-case situation, “subjective
control,” which constituted a systematic violation of the autonomy necessary for a
professional military and produced transmutation. Huntington argued that subjective control
was detrimental to military effectiveness and would lead to failure on the battlefield by
forcing the military to defer to civilians in the military realm (1957:80–3).
Morris Janowitz: The Sociological Response to
Huntington
Morris Janowitz offered an early critique of Huntington from the standpoint of sociology
(Janowitz 1960). The sociological perspective does not ignore the central civil–military
relations question of institutional theory: civilian control. However, it focuses most of its
attention on the relationship between individuals in the military and civilian society. With
regard to Huntington's civilian–military divide, Janowitz argued that the distinction between
the civilian and military roles that lay at the heart of Huntington's theory had been blurred by
the emergence of nuclear weapons and limited war. For Janowitz, this state of affairs was
only the latest manifestation of the way in which emerging technologies and the political
interaction between civilian and military elites were causing the two spheres to converge.

Like Huntington, Janowitz focused on the meaning of a professional officer corps. But while
Huntington saw military professionalism as a fixed standard, an “ideal-type” based on a
strict division of labor between the uniformed military and civilians, Janowitz conceived
professionalism as dynamic, changing in response to new sociological conditions. Janowitz
argued that, given the central place of the US–Soviet rivalry in both international and
domestic politics, even a professional military could not avoid some degree of politicization.

With regard to Huntington's functional imperative, Janowitz contended that in the nuclear
age the military needed to adopt a new military role and military selfconception – that of a
constabulary force. According to Janowitz, “the military establishment becomes a
constabulary force when it is continuously prepared to act, committed to the minimum use
of force, and seeks viable international relations, rather than victory” (1960:418). Obviously,
the constabulary concept blurs the distinctions between peace and war. Accordingly, the
soldier comes to resemble a police officer instead of a warrior. This leads to politicization of
the military and raises a challenge to civilian supremacy, as the military attempts to use the
political system to resist unwelcome policy direction.

Janowitz's solution to the new problems created by the constabulary concept was to reject
Huntington's concept of objective control of the military. Instead of autonomy, he prescribed
greater civilian oversight of the military at all levels. He pointed out that civilians possess
three main mechanisms for controlling the uniformed military: the budget process; the
allocation of roles and missions; and advice to the president concerning the use of the
military to advance US interests in the international realm. But the military, Janowitz argued,
had found ways to undermine civilian control (1960:363–7).

Although Janowitz proposed a number of external mechanisms for strengthening civilian


control, he, like Huntington, ultimately fell back on professionalism. But unlike Huntington's
professional officer who eschewed politics altogether, Janowitz's officer corps would be
politically aware and possess functions and expertise that overlapped with those of its
civilian counterpart.

Janowitz's heirs have taken military sociology far beyond his own conclusions, generating a
vast and rich literature that examines how the military and civil society have shaped each
other. But when it comes to the critical issue of ensuring civilian control of the military,
Janowitz did not really go much beyond Huntington. He merely concluded that to ensure
civilian control, Huntington's “self-imposed professional standards,” the basis of objective
control, needed to be supplemented by a “meaningful integration” of military and civilian
values (Janowitz 1960:420).

Despite Janowitz's sociological challenge to Huntington's institutional theory of civil–military


relations, the latter still dominates the field. The reason for this continued dominance is its
elegance as an ambitious treatment of civil–military relations and the fact that his
prescriptions for how best to structure civil–military relations continue to find a very
receptive ear within the American officer corps (Feaver 2003:7).

Most recent attempts to reconstruct the theoretical edifice of civil–military relations


constitute refinements of Huntington and Janowitz rather than providing a new theoretical
alternative (Avant 1994; Desch 1999). Exceptions include Peter Feaver, who has offered a
civil–military relations theory based on a “principal–agent” framework; Rebecca Schiff, who
argues on behalf of a theory of concordance that takes issue with the “separation” theory
that she attributes to both Huntington and Feaver (Schiff 2009); and Risa Brooks, who,
while maintaining the civil–military distinction, has usefully modified aspects of existing
theories to create a “distributional approach” that aids in understanding how various
patterns of civil–military relations influence strategic assessment (Brooks 2008).

Peter Feaver: Agency Theory and Civil–Military


Relations
Feaver argues that although Huntington's theory is “elegant,” it doesn't fit the evidence of
the Cold War. For instance, one of Huntington's testable hypotheses was that a liberal
society (such as the United States) would not produce sufficient military might to survive the
Cold War. But in fact, the United States did prevail during the Cold War despite the fact that
the country did not abandon liberalism (Feaver 2003:27). The continued divergence
between civilian and military preferences during the Cold War casts doubt on the predictive
power of Huntington's empirical theory.

The same problems affect Huntington's prescriptive theory. During the Cold War, the
military became more “civilianized,” the officer corps more politicized, and civilians
habitually intruded into the military realm (Feaver 2003:37). Feaver concludes that the
disjunction between Huntington's theory and the available evidence requires another theory.
To provide such an alternative, Feaver turns to “agency theory.”

The problem that agency theory seeks to analyze is this: given different incentives, how
does a principal ensure that the agent is doing what the principal wants him to do? Is the
agent “working” or “shirking”? The major question for the principal is the extent to which he
will monitor the agent. Will monitoring be intrusive or non-intrusive? This decision is affected
by the cost of monitoring. The higher the cost of monitoring, the less intrusive the monitoring
is likely to be.

The agent's incentives for working or shirking are affected by the likelihood that shirking will
be detected by the principal and that the agent will then be punished for it. The less
intrusive the principal's monitoring, the less likely that the agent's shirking will be detected.
Feaver argues that shirking by the military takes many forms: the most obvious is
disobedience, but it also includes “foot-dragging” and leaks to the press designed to
undercut policy or individual policy makers.

Feaver posits four general patterns of civil–military relations: (1) civilians monitor intrusively,
the military works; (2) civilians monitor intrusively, the military shirks; (3) civilians monitor
unintrusively, the military works; and (4) civilians monitor unintrusively, the military shirks.
He then shows that Huntington's postulated outcomes are in fact special cases of his own
more general agency theory of civil–military relations: Huntington's “objective control”
corresponds to pattern (3); his “subjective control” corresponds to pattern (1)
(Feaver 2003:119).

Feaver uses the Cold War to test Huntington's prescriptive theory. Huntington had argued
that the best way to ensure both military effectiveness and subordination to civilian control
was through pattern (3) – objective control (Feaver 1996:33). However, it turns out that the
civil–military relations pattern during the Cold War that most corresponds to the evidence is
pattern (1) – Huntington's nightmare civil–military scenario – subjective control
(Feaver 2003:178). Indeed, agency theory predicts that pattern (1) will prevail when there is
a wide gap between the preferences of the civilians and the military, when the costs of
intrusive monitoring are relatively low, and when the military thinks the likelihood of
punishment for shirking are fairly high. Feaver argues persuasively that the evidence from
this period supports these hypotheses. Yet according to Huntington's own criteria for
professionalism – expertise, responsibility, and corporateness (Huntington 1957:8–10) – the
US military remained highly professional despite extensive civilian intervention.

Of critical importance in establishing Cold War civil–military relations was the firing of a
popular military hero (MacArthur) by an unpopular president (Truman). This dramatic action
shaped the expectations of the military concerning the likelihood of punishment for shirking
during the Cold War period (Feaver 2003:129).

Feaver explains the post–Cold War “crisis” in civil–military relations in a way that integrates
a number of features that arose in the 1990s – the end of the Cold War, a growing gap
between civilian and military elites, the personal history of President Clinton, the creation of
a powerful chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff by the Goldwater-Nichols Defense Act of
1986, and the occupation of this office by a popular, politically savvy general – Colin Powell
(Feaver 2003:180–233).

Feaver argues that civil–military relations pattern (2) prevailed during the 1990s: civilians
monitored intrusively, the military “shirked.” The cost of intrusive monitoring went down. The
preferences of civilian and military elites diverged in many important ways, increasing
incentives for the military to pursue its own preferences. Finally, the expectation of
punishment for shirking decreased as a result of the election of Bill Clinton, whose
equivocal relationship with the military made punishment unlikely. Combined with a powerful
and popular military leader and an absence of consensus regarding security affairs across
the executive and legislative branches, the civilian principals were in a relatively weakened
position vis-à-vis the military agents (Feaver 2003:190–210).

Feaver observes that civil–military relations are obviously better when there are good
civilian leaders and worse when civilian leadership is bad. One issue is how to hold civilians
accountable to the same or greater degree than the military is held accountable. Bad policy,
after all, presumably comes from civilian principals.

But Feaver's focus is on the military institution in a democratic polity.

[E]ven when the military is right, democratic theory intervenes and insists that it submit to
the civilian leadership that the polity has chosen. Let civilian voters punish civilian leaders
for wrong decisions. Let the military advise against foolish adventures, even advising
strenuously when circumstances demand. But let the military execute those orders faithfully.
The republic would be better served even by foolish working than by enlightened shirking.

(Feaver 2003:302)

After all, the claim that the military should not do what civilians want because what they
want is bad for the country shapes the rhetoric of every coup leader who justifies his seizure
of power as the rescue of a state from the consequences of an inept government.

Concordance Theory
Rebecca Schiff has argued on behalf of a theory that questions the assumptions that
underlie both Huntington and Feaver: that a theory of civil–military relations should be
based on the physical and ideological separation of the military from the political institutions
of a state (Schiff 2009:32). Concordance theory is concerned with predicting and preventing
military intervention in the domestic affairs of a state. Schiff contends that the best way to
avoid such an occurrence is to achieve concordance among three “partners” within a polity
– the military, the political elites, and the citizenry – on four issues: the social composition of
the officer corps; the political decision-making process; the method of recruiting soldiers;
and “military style.” Such a cooperative relationship may involve separation but does not
require it.

According to Schiff, concordance theory resolves two problems associated with separation
theory, as explicated by Huntington and Feaver. The first is the tendency of separation
theorists to treat the particular institutional arrangements arising from the experience of the
post–World War II United States as universal, applicable to all states regardless of their
particular historical conditions and culture. This is especially relevant to the cases of
developing states because it means that they “need not adopt the traditional Western model
of civil–military relations in order to achieve greater political maturity (Schiff 2009:33).

The second problem is methodological. Separation theory's institutional analysis alone “fails
to take into account the cultural and historical conditions that may encourage or discourage
civil–military separation. We can see this deficit, for example, in the post-revolutionary US
example – a stark contrast to the post–World War II United States from which separation
theory is derived” (Schiff 2009:33).

Criticism of concordance theory includes the charge that it is merely a variation of


Huntington's concept of “fusion,” the demand “that military leaders incorporate political,
economic, and social factors into their thinking” (Huntington 1957:351) and that “military
leaders assume non-military responsibilities” (1957:353). Critics also claim that the
predictive aspect of concordance theory falls short with regard to the correlation between
agreement among the three partners and military intervention on the one hand and to the
likelihood of coup d’état on the other (Wells 1996).

But, according to Schiff, these objections ask concordance theory to be something it is not:
a theory capable of analyzing all facets and problems in the realm of civil–military relations.
Its causal objective is more limited: to predict the likelihood of military intervention in
domestic affairs, which, Schiff claims, it does successfully (Schiff 1996:42–3).

Civil–Military Relations and Strategic Assessment


Risa Brooks argues that patterns of civil–military relations affect national security because
of their impact on strategic assessment. Brooks identifies two variables that determine the
pattern of civil–military relations: (1) the intensity of preference divergence between political
and military leaders with regard to corporate, professional, and security issues; and (2) the
balance of power between political and military leaders (political dominance, shared power,
military dominance). These two variables interact, generating “logics” that affect the
institutional features of strategic assessment (Brooks 2008:2–34).

Next she identifies four sets of institutional processes that constitute the element of strategic
assessment. The first is the routine for information sharing. The second is strategic
coordination regarding the assessment of strategic alternatives, risk and cost, and the
integration of political and military policies and strategies. The third is the military's structural
competence in conducting sound net assessment. The fourth is the authorization process
for approving or vetoing political-military actions (Brooks 2008:34–42).

Brooks then hypothesizes how the various configurations of power and preference
divergence affect the quality of strategic assessment, using case studies to illustrate the
relation between various patterns and strategic assessment. She hypothesizes that the
combination of political dominance and low preference divergence leads to the “best”
strategic assessment. The combination of shared power and high preference divergence
leads to the “worst” strategic assessment. Other combinations lead to “poor” or “fair”
strategic assessment (Brooks 2008:42–54).

Of course, the quality of a state's strategic assessment is not the only determinant of a
state's success or failure in the international arena. The competing strategies of other states
and other exogenous factors may well trump even the best strategic assessment. Michael
Desch has employed a similar methodology to show that the alleged military advantage of
democratic states in international relations is overstated (Desch 2008).

Problems with the Contending Theories and


Suggestions for Further Research
There is no more important question facing a state than the place of its military relative to
civil society and the roles that the military exercises. The coercive power that a military
institution possesses always makes it, at least theoretically, a threat to the regime. Clearly,
there are many possible patterns of civil–military relations that provide different answers to
the five questions posed at the beginning of this essay.
As the survey of contending theories of civil–military relations suggests, there is no
“general” or “unified field” theory that successfully explains all of these patterns
(Bland 1999). Nor, given the variety and complexity of civil–military patterns is one likely or
desirable.

Institutional theory and agency theory focus on control of the military and the military's role.
Sociology usefully investigates the question of who serves. For a variety of reasons,
Huntington's institutional theory remains the dominant paradigm for examining civil–military
relations. First, it deals with the central problem of such relations: the relation of the military
as an institution to civilian society. Huntington was the first to attempt a systematic analysis
of the civil–military problematique. Second, despite the claims of many of those who look at
US civil–military relations through the lens of sociology, analytically distinct military and
civilian spheres do appear to exist.

But as the discussion above of Feaver's critique of Huntington makes clear, there are many
problems with Huntington's argument. In 1962, S.E. Finer argued that Huntington had
severely understated the problem of civilian control (Finer 1962:7–10). He contended that a
professional military does not necessarily keep officers out of politics, but indeed might
incline them to engage in politics (1962:207 ff.). He also observed that differences in
national experience limit the applicability of Huntington's theory.

Schiff agrees, arguing that Huntington's theory is particular to the American experience and
is therefore not applicable to other countries (Schiff 2009: chs. 5–7). Indeed, she argues
that it does not even apply to the United States during all historical periods (2009: ch. 4).

In addition, empirical studies have not confirmed some of Huntington's key assertions or
predictions. It is also the case that some of Huntington's historical arguments are
questionable. For instance, the US Army in the late nineteenth century was not nearly as
isolated as Huntington contended it was (Gates 1980; Owens 2007). This particular problem
illustrates the importance of keeping historical context in mind when examining civil–military
relations. Historians such as Russell Weigley, Richard Kohn, and Lawrence Cress have
made significant contributions to the study of civil–military relations (Kohn 1975;
Cress 1982; Weigley 1993). Finally as Eliot Cohen, perhaps Huntington's most
accomplished student, has pointed out, some of the most successful democratic war
leaders have paid very little attention to the divide that Huntington's objective control
demands (E.A. Cohen 2002).

When it comes to the question of civilian control of the military, Feaver's agency theory
corrects some of the flaws in Huntington's theory. Agency theory seems to do a better job
of describing the problem of civilian control than Huntington's theory. It is also does better
with regard to the predictive aspect of the theory. One reason for this is that agency theory
does not depend on the non-rigorous and therefore problematic concepts of professionalism
and autonomy to predict how and under what circumstances civilians will best be able to
control the military instrument.

Finally, it follows that if agency theory fulfills both the descriptive and predictive functions of
a theory better than Huntington's institutional theory, its prescriptive element will also be
more useful than what Huntington laid down. Nonetheless, critics argue that as applied to
civil–military relations, agency theory achieves analytical rigor by severely limiting its scope.
The theory is too parsimonious; it fails to explain enough in the world.

Janowitz and the military sociologists also provide useful insights, especially regarding the
question of “who serves?” and related issues. The writers who take their bearings from
Janowitz have indeed moved the question of demographics, ethnicity, and recruitment to
center stage in a way that transcends the American experience (Moskos et al. 2000;
Williams 2008; Schiff 2009). But even as they argue that the concept of separation between
the two spheres is theoretically and empirically flawed, these writers still maintain the
analytical distinction between the military and civilians.

In the case of concordance theory, critics charge that the definition of military intervention
sets the bar too low to be meaningful. The cooperative relationships that are necessary to
avoid military intervention themselves look like intervention unless the standard for civilian
control is merely the absence of a military coup. The utility of the idea of “concordance” is
somewhat in question as it is not clear that the degree of harmony among civilian and
military leaders is a “good” or “bad” thing in terms of either political control or military
effectiveness.

In many respects, the current state of theorizing about civil–military relations brings to mind
the story of the three blind men examining an elephant. Since each can only sense what he
is touching (the trunk, a leg, and the tail) and has no concept of the elephant as a whole,
each concludes that the beast is something different from what it really is. Despite the lack
of an overarching framework for analyzing civil–military relations, the various areas of the
field offer many rich “pastures” in which researchers may graze.

Research agendas might well include: additional examination of the emerging civil–military
patterns of such emerging powers as China, Russia, and Iran; ascertaining a theory of civil–
military relations of Muslim states; follow-up work to Risa Brooks’s excellent study of the
impact of civil–military relations on strategic assessment; the civil–military implications of
the expanded roles of contractors on the battlefield and increased reliance on special
operations forces; the civil–military implications of the increased utilization of airstrikes by
unmanned aircraft; the impact of popular will on effectiveness in various sorts of warfare,
e.g. counterinsurgency; and further research into the impact of an increasing “civilianization”
of the military on military effectiveness.

You might also like