slime-mould-and-philosophy
slime-mould-and-philosophy
slime-mould-and-philosophy
Slime Mould
Matthew Sims
all of the central topics in the philosophy Michael Ruse
of biology. Contributors to the series Florida State
are cutting-edge researchers who offer University
balanced, comprehensive coverage
of multiple perspectives, while also
developing new ideas and arguments
from a unique viewpoint.
Matthew Sims
Ruhr-Universität Bochum
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009488624
DOI: 10.1017/9781009488648
© Matthew Sims 2024
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009488648
First published 2024
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 978-1-009-48862-4 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-009-48861-7 Paperback
ISSN 2515-1126 (online)
ISSN 2515-1118 (print)
Additional resources for this publication at www.cambridge.org/Sims
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence
or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this
publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will
remain, accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy
DOI: 10.1017/9781009488648
First published online: December 2024
Matthew Sims
Ruhr-Universität Bochum
Author for correspondence: Matthew Sims,
matthew.sims-m4e@ruhr-uni-bochum.de
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Contents
1 Introduction 1
6 Conclusion 72
References 75
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 1
1 Introduction
Physarum polycephalum (henceforth Physarum), also known more colloquially as
‘the blob’, ‘acellular slime mould’, or simply ‘slime mould’, is a unicellular protist
that has continued to attract the interest of biologists over the past century because
of its complex life cycle, unique physiology, morphology, and behaviour. It has
been used as a model organism for numerous studies, some of which include the
investigation of various mechanisms that underpin synchronous nuclear division,
the development of drugs for the treatment of cancerous tumours, and the investi-
gation of putative cognitive capacities such as decision making, learning, and
memory in organisms that lack nervous systems. More recently, biologists have
even used Physarum to study the effects of microgravity on growth and behaviour
in outer space.
Although Physarum has much to offer in terms of being a model organism
for biological research, as the non-exhaustive list of uses above should make
apparent, the aim of this Element is to illustrate how Physarum can be
a valuable tool for approaching various issues in the philosophy of biology.
Physarum’s unique features not only pose a challenge to some of the received
views of biological processes but also, I shall argue, provide an opportunity to
clarify and appropriately sharpen the concepts underlying such received
views. For example, the notion of ‘niche construction’ has become an important –
yet not fully agreed upon – concept within the context of evolutionary biology.
Roughly, niche construction refers to the idea that evolution is influenced not
only by how (genetic) variation allows organisms to differentially adapt to the
challenges of their environment but also by how organisms modify their
environments and thus alter which selection pressures they are exposed to.
By looking closely at Physarum’s complex life cycle, an opportunity arises to
understand how different kinds of niche construction are exemplified and,
more generally, how those different kinds of niche construction often dynamically
interact.
Each section of this Element is organised around a distinct philosophical issue
as contextualised by Physarum. Using Physarum’s life cycle as a concrete
example, Section 2 focuses on the issue of how attention to complex life cycles
can provide insights into the intricacies of niche construction. Section 3 addresses
the tension between the idea that metabolic exchange is a necessary feature of all
known life and the fact that biologists classify spores as a form of life despite their
being metabolically inert for long periods of time. Section 4 turns to a central
concept in biology – ‘biological individuality’ – and how Physarum’s fragmenta-
tion and fusion behaviour forces us to rethink at least one way of understanding
that concept. Lastly, Section 5 turns to the issue of whether to understand
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
2 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 3
unnecessary details for fear of not seeing the forest for the trees. There are also
a fair number of figures throughout the Element. These are intended to supplement
some of the more abstract concepts and descriptions that are introduced in each
section. They are by no means intended as replacements for the text.
I have personally been fascinated – unabashedly so – by Physarum and its
behaviour for some years now and I hope this Element can also serve to awaken
a level of fascination for Physarum in both readers who are familiar and those
who are unfamiliar with this organism that is at least on par with my own.
Domain Eukaryota
Kingdom Protista
Phylum Amoebozoa
Class Myxomycetes
Order Physarales
Family Physaraceae
Genus Physarum
Species P. polycephalum
1
Acellular slime moulds should not be confused with cellular slime moulds of the class
Dictyostelia (e.g., Dictyostelium discoideum). The latter are social amoeba that aggregate at
a stage in their life cycle, forming a multicellular vegetative slug.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
4 Philosophy of Biology
bacteria, yeast, amoeba, and also decomposing organic matter. Small spore-eating
beetle species, woodlice, land slugs, and other myxomycetes species are among
Physarum’s predators (and more broadly, the predators of myxomycetes).
Physarum – in its plasmodial stage – has proven to be easy to culture in labs
under conditions roughly mimicking those in which it thrives in the wild. This
entails being kept in a humid and dark enclosure and having a steady food supply –
usually store-bought dried oats. In addition to its unique features, the ease with
which Physarum is cultured has added to its popularity as a model organism.
Having a basic understanding of what Physarum is, let us without further ado
put this fascinating organism to work.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 5
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
6 Philosophy of Biology
2
I will continue to use the term ‘fitness’ to refer to the combination of viability and fecundity,
following the convention of how the term is understood in life history.
3
Some of the key figures in biology and ecology that laid the groundwork for the development of
niche construction theory were Darwin (1881), Clements (1916), Schrödinger (1944), and
Waddington (1969).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 7
4
Also see (Sultan, 2015) and (Chiu, 2019) for similar efforts to expand the categories of canonical
niche construction theory.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
8 Philosophy of Biology
this is just to say that a niche consists of the sum of factors faced by a population
that select for organismal features. If something like this is assumed correct,
which it is by canonical niche construction theory, then organisms can alter their
niche in three ways: (1) modifying factors (i.e., perturbation), (2) modifying the
relation between factors and features (e.g., relocation), and (3) modifying their
own features. Thus, for niche construction to be consistent with the factor–feature
interactions conception of niche, constitutive modifications to the features of the
organism must be taken on as a third category of niche construction.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 9
compensate for exposure to excess light (Sultan, 2015). Importantly, such differ-
ences in leaf shape amongst members of the same species are not due to genetic
differences; they are different environmentally induced forms that genetically
identical plants (or the same plant) may take over the course of their (its)
development.
Some proponents of niche construction have expressed scepticism regarding
such an expansion (see Godfrey-Smith, 1996, 2001; Baedke et al., 2021;
Trappes et al., 2022). Part of such scepticism may be seen as stemming from
a general worry concerning the ubiquity of niche construction, namely: if every
selection-relevant biotic or environmental modification that an organism makes
is a form of niche construction, then the concept becomes trivial and of no
explanatory use. Discussing and responding to this criticism, Abby and Ramsey
remind us that both selection and genetic drift are equally ubiquitous phenom-
ena and that this case does not make them any less useful. Their usefulness in
evolutionary theory stems from recognising that not every instance of selection
or drift is equally important in every evolutionary process. That is, there are
explanatory contexts in which specific forms of selection or drift should be
foregrounded, whilst others are backgrounded and this differential importance
across different contexts allows selection and drift to remain useful notions.
According to Abby and Ramsey, niche construction is similar in this manner.
Despite niche construction’s ubiquity, the differential importance of different
types of niche construction relative to a particular explanatory context can help
us to understand and model evolutionary processes. In one particular stage that
makes up Physarum’s complex life cycle (or transitions to and/or from that
stage), a number of different types of niche construction are possibly at play.
However, understanding the differential importance of ENC, RNC, CNC, or
any combination thereof relative to that stage can be useful in understanding
(and informing models of) the evolutionary dynamics that have stabilised that
stage within the sequence of stages that make up Physarum’s life cycle.7
Another worry that some sceptics have raised has to do with the idea that
describing a plastic response in terms of something like CNC fails to provide
any additional information about that response and, thus, to do so is unwar-
ranted. This worry, however, overlooks the fact that although phenotypic
plasticity is a mechanism that underwrites niche construction, considering the
evolutionary consequences of plastic responses is extrinsic to any accurate
description of a response as such. Describing some variable response as
a form of phenotypic plasticity is to acknowledge that it is a change in pheno-
type in response to an environmental or internal cue without any accompanying
7
I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify this point.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
10 Philosophy of Biology
genetic change. Although there have been various suggestions that such
responses can have evolutionary impacts on the subsequent genetic fixation of
those phenotypes (West-Eberhard, 2003; Bateson and Gluckman, 2011; Levis
and Pfennig, 2016), that this is the case is above and beyond describing some
response as an instance of phenotypic plasticity. The notion of niche construc-
tion, on the other hand, was formulated in the context of evolutionary theory.
Thus, describing some plastic response as niche construction embeds it in
a broader evolutionary context in which the historical, ongoing, or future
consequences of that response upon evolutionary dynamics is central.
In what follows, I will assume expanding niche construction to include more
than perturbance and relocation is theoretically warranted, enough so to justify
the further exploration of Aaby and Ramsey’s tripartite niche construction
taxonomy. One manner of examining the details of each of the three kinds of
niche construction is to look at how they occur within a life cycle of one
organism. Looking at particular complex life cycles in which all three kinds
of niche construction are present, I shall argue, provides a broad perspective for
examining the details of ENC, RNC, and CNC and the part that each plays in
altering the selective environment of a focal organism. This of course raises the
question of what a complex life cycle is, a topic to which we will now turn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 11
refers to a life cycle pattern in which there is an alternation between at least two
different organisational forms with different ploidy levels (haploid or diploid),
each of which also often displays notable differences in morphology, behaviour,
and physiology. Within such a multigenerational life cycle, one generation
produces another with a distinct organisational form, which in turn produces
the next generation of the first type again, marking a return to the beginning of the
life cycle of a different token organism. In this context, production can be
understood as a causal relation (Godfrey-Smith, 2016) in which one entity brings
another entity into existence. This can be contrasted with developing, which is
a continuation or progression from an existing stage, rather than a causal relation.
Alternation of generations is clearly exemplified by plants such as ferns,
mosses, and some algae whose complex life cycles alternate generationally
between two organisational forms: one being a sex cell-producing plant that has
a single set of chromosomes (a haploid gametophyte) and the other a spore-
producing plant with two sets of chromosomes (a diploid sporophyte).8 Each of
these forms represents a distinct generation with its own development and each
organisational form produces the other. In contrast, more recently evolved
animal lineages, including humans and other mammals, exhibit simple, mono-
generational life cycles. Although mammalian reproduction involves haploid
and diploid stages, the haploid stage is limited to gametes (egg or sperm cells)
and does not have its own ontogeny. Thus, neither egg nor sperm qualify as
a separate generation. Through sexual reproduction – more specifically fertil-
isation – adult mammals give rise to a diploid zygote, marking a new gener-
ation. This zygote develops into a diploid adult, resembling its parents. To
stress, haploid mammalian sex cells do not produce the zygote; rather, the
reproducing parents produce the zygote. Nor does the zygote produce the
adult; it develops into an adult.9 In a mammalian life cycle, there is only one
organisational form that develops and gives rise to the same organisational form
of a distinct generation, starting the life cycle anew.
One fascinating example of a complex life cycle, which offers valuable
insights into understanding ENC, RNC, and CNC, and also exemplifies the
potential value of investigating complex life cycles for the purposes of under-
standing niche construction, is that of P. polycephalum. The life cycle of
Physarum involves two vegetative stages, or periods in which there is feeding,
growth, and cellular repair. These stages are the uninucleate ‘ameboflagellate
stage’ and the multinucleate ‘plasmodial stage’. Both stages exhibit distinct
organisational forms and have different ploidy levels (haploid or diploid).
8
For numerous examples, see Fusco and Minelli (2019).
9
The same can be said of complete metamorphosing beetles and sea urchins; a larva in such a case
does not produce an adult but develops into one.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
12 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 13
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
14 Philosophy of Biology
into a swimming, biflagellate cell. Biflagellates may feed but cannot undergo binary
fission (Clark and Haskins, 2015). Upon encountering drier conditions, the bifla-
gellate will rapidly revert into a myxamoeba again. This highly plastic cell trans-
formation can occur multiple times in either direction, depending upon the
availability of free water (Pagh and Adelman, 1988).
Under unfavourable conditions such as starvation, drought, overabundance
of water, and overcrowding, the ameboflagellate may convert into a dormant
microcyst. This resistant structure, a suspension of vegetative growth, can
remain viable for long periods of time. Encysting of the ameboflagellate
involves the synthesis of a resistant wall around the cell, in addition to various
other intracellular changes (Gorman and Wilkins, 1980). In contrast to the
spore, the microcyst is a reversable dormant stage; when environmental
conditions improve, it reverts into ameboflagellate again.
Upon encountering another mating competent cell of a compatible mating
type, two haploid myxamoebae (or two biflagellate cells) may sexually fuse.
This leads to the initiation of the plasmodium stage, in which nuclear fusion
and the subsequent formation of a diploid zygote cell occur. As the diploid
nucleus undergoes multiple rounds of division without cell division, the cell
grows and develops into a multinucleate plasmodium, the other vegetative stage
of Physarum’s life cycle. It is during this stage that Physarum becomes visible to
the naked eye as a mass of bright yellow, slimy protoplasm. It may reach a size
of up to 900 cm2 and can crawl across surfaces at a speed of up to 5 cm/h
(Kessler, 1982).
As it grows, the plasmodium migrates across decaying organic substrates,
feeding and avoiding any environmental conditions that may challenge its
viability. Plasmodia consume bacteria, fungi, and other microbes (including
other myxomycete amoebae), but can also feed on non-living organic matter.
Feeding occurs in this stage via both phagocytosis and the excretion of enzymes
that break down organic matter which is then absorbed into the cell (Bailey,
1997). The cell’s shape is plastically reorganised on the go via the restructuring
of an internal, vein-like tubular network, through which protoplasm is rhyth-
mically shuttled. Such shuttling pushes the edges of the cell towards food or
away from potentially harmful substances. As it migrates, a trail of extracellular
slime (i.e., a non-living, cytoplasmic casing) is secreted which, amongst other
things, functions as a lubricating surface upon which to crawl more easily
(Patino-Ramirez et al., 2019). Upon encountering a patch where nutrient condi-
tions are adequate, plasmodium may remain sedentary, growing steadily at that
location (Dussutour et al., 2010).
When encountering adverse conditions such as prolonged periods of drought,
starvation, and/or low temperatures, a plasmodium may transform into a dried,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 15
hard, resistant mass called the ‘sclerotium’ (plural: sclerotia). Like the micro-
cyst, the sclerotium represents a reversible dormant structure, the formation of
which allows a plasmodium to withstand unfavourable growth and metabolic
conditions until those conditions subside. A plasmodium can remain dormant as
sclerotium anywhere from months to years (Sperry et al., 2022). When condi-
tions improve, the sclerotium may revert back into a plasmodium and continue
living as a large diploid vegetative cell. Like the microcyst, the sclerotium is
also an optional developmental stage; whether it occurs in an individual
Physarum’s life cycle will depend upon the kinds of environmental conditions
which are encountered by the individual plasmodium.
Within a period of extended starvation, a mature plasmodium will migrate from
its usual shaded microhabitat into the light, where various biochemical events
lead to the differentiation of the cell protoplasm into multiple fruiting bodies or
‘sporangia’ (singular: sporangium) (Gorman and Wilkins, 1980). Physarum’s
sporangia consist of long, thin, twisted stalks upon which multiheaded spore
enclosures are attached: hence the species name ‘polycephalum’ (many-headed).
Once the process of fruiting has begun, it is irreversible. During spore develop-
ment, meiotic cell division occurs, resulting in the formation of multiple uni-
nucleate spores within the spore enclosure. After a period in which fruiting bodies
and their spore contents dry, spores are released and dispersed by wind or also
sometimes via surface contact with spore-eating arthropods (Blackwell, 1984;
Sugiura et al., 2019). This completes Physarum’s complex life cycle.
How might the various stages of Physarum’s life cycle provide concrete
examples of either ENC, RNC, or CNC, and how might these forms of niche
construction work in tandem? This is the topic to which we will now turn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
16 Philosophy of Biology
ENC, RNC, and CNC interact across development. The examples of niche
construction that I identify here are not meant in any way to be exhaustive;
within the various stages of Physarum’s life cycle there are undoubtedly many
more instances of niche construction that occur. For reasons of space, I cannot
deal with all of them here.
Starting with the reversible and optional transformation from myxamoeba to
biflagellate, I would like to argue that this transformation provides an example of
both CNC and RNC. To see this, consider that a myxamoeba is limited to the use
of pseudopods for locomotion and hence cannot swim (or at least cannot swim
effectively). As such, the presence of free water introduces a fitness-relevant
challenge: assuming that capturing food in water requires effective locomotion,
a submerged myxamoeba may be less successful at capturing food than it would
be in a non-water microhabitat. The ability to transform into a biflagellate medi-
ates this challenge. Although the degree that a biflagellate cell can direct its
movement is very limited and the distance that it can swim is typically short,
being able to swim can improve feeding in some situations (Clark and Haskins,
2015). In morphologically transforming from a myxamoeba to a swimming
biflagellate, the ameboflagellate increases the amount of food available to it
while it is in its water microhabitat. Moreover, because biflagellate cells cannot
undergo binary fission, and feeding cannot occur at the same time as binary
fission, a biflagellate may continue to feed without interruption as long as food is
available. In short, the water-induced transformation from myxamoeba to bifla-
gellate is an active modification of the ameboflagellate’s features that change its
causal relation(s) to environmental factors. This is a clear instance of CNC, one
that albeit occurs in a motile organism.
The transformation into a biflagellate, however, comes with a potential
fitness cost since of the two ameboflagellate forms only the myxamoeba can
undergo binary fission and produce daughter cells. As such, a sustained exist-
ence as a biflagellate means low ameboflagellate fecundity. Transforming into
a biflagellate thus seems to mediate one kind of selection pressure but in turn
introduces another: the inability to reproduce as a biflagellate cell. One manner
of accommodating this morphology-related decline in fitness is for the amebo-
flagellate to swim to a dry surface (if the surface is not too far away), thus
changing its spatial relation to the water microhabitat that induced its current
form. This active change in location on the part of the ameboflagellate repre-
sents an instance of RNC, which in addition to the subsequent reversion to the
myxamoeba form – an instance of CNC – re-establishes the ameboflagellate’s
ability to undergo binary fission again.
The transformation from myxamoeba to biflagellate and back exemplifies not
only CNC and RNC but also an interesting way that these two kinds of niche
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 17
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
18 Philosophy of Biology
10
If the timing of encysting and excysting is influenced by genetic variation, and either encysting
or excysting too early or too late can have negative fitness effects, then selection for those
variations on timing mechanisms that are tuned to the onset and termination of unfavourable
environmental conditions may occur. As such, variation in timing mechanisms underwriting
when CNC-mediated RNC occurs can have effects on subsequent evolution.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 19
to exercise this capacity would be outcompeted and (b) that any heritable
genetic variations that would allow Physarum to exercise this capacity would
be maintained in the population.
The production and use of extracellular slime may also provide a possible
example of how ENC and RNC occur in tandem. Whether a plasmodium avoids
slime trails will be dependent upon things like the presence and quality of food
that can be reached by migrating across extracellular slime (Reid et al., 2013)
and/or the nature of biochemical cues reflecting the stressed or well-nourished
condition of the plasmodium that left the slime trail (Briard et al., 2020). If
a well-nourished plasmodium leaves behind a carbohydrate-rich slime trail and
such trails provide nutrients for the growth of red yeast, then a well-nourished
plasmodium may also eventually revisit its own slime trail to consume the red
yeast that have since grown there (Epstein et al., 2021). This plasmodial fungal
farming – if it is indeed a robust phenomenon – seems to be both an instance of
ENC and RNC;11 it is both an active modification of environmental factors (i.e.,
leaving slime trails) that impact selection pressures (i.e., the availability of food)
because it influences the spatio-temporal relation between the slime-secreting
plasmodium and the growing red yeast. In other words, ENC has the fitness
effects that it does because it brings about RNC. The fact that a plasmodium will
choose to consume higher quality food over lower quality food (Latty and
Beekman, 2010) when there is an option may thus allow it to modify its physical
environment with extracellular slime trails in a way that, over time, systematic-
ally alters its relationship to the fungi which it consumes; a well-nourished
plasmodium brings yeast to it (locally), rather than having to relocate to yeast
elsewhere.
When a plasmodium migrates from a food-depleted to a food-abundant site in
the same habitat, such migration depends upon its ability to plastically modify its
features. During the plasmodial stage, a Physarum is able to change its shape by
altering its internal tubular network structure in a matter of hours in response to
changes in external conditions (Nakagaki et al., 2004). This structural reconfig-
uration that alters the way plasmodia experience their heterogeneous resource
environment as more homogeneous is analogous to how plants modify their root
structure according to changing soil nutrient patch availability (one exception
being that plants are sessile and operating at a much slower timescale than
plasmodia). And like such plant root reconfiguration may be viewed as an
11
I make this qualification because the oscillatory successional dynamics that Epstein et al. (2021)
discovered were based upon an analysis of only five Petri dish ‘ecosystems’, each of which
differed in experimental light exposure conditions. To show that plasmodial yeast farming is
a robust phenomenon, this experiment requires replication using many more samples of each
ecosystem condition.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
20 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 21
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
22 Philosophy of Biology
Taking stock: I have illustrated how some of the stages that P. polycephalum
completes over the course of its complex life cycle exemplify at least one of the
three kinds of niche construction included in Aaby and Ramsey’s (2022)
tripartite niche construction taxonomy. Moreover, I have shown how some of
these stages and the transitions between them reveal different ways that ENC,
RNC, and CNC causally interact and occur in tandem. Lastly, I have shown how
some of the (reversible and non-reversible) transitions between Physarum’s life
cycle stages associated with CNC and ENC can be viewed in terms of fitness
trade-offs (see Table 2). I will now offer a few considerations regarding the
value of looking at complex life cycles for niche construction approaches.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
Table 2 Life cycle stages of P. polycephalum (excluding the spore stage), some of the kinds of niche construction
arising within and/or between them, and the resulting fitness trade-offs. If there are relations between kinds of niche construction
exhibited in the sclerotium stage and/or whether there are fitness trade-offs in the plasmodium stage have not been
addressed in the analysis above and remain open questions for future research
Table 2 (cont.)
Plasmodium External: depositing and using extracellular Cyclical niche construction: constitutive ?
slime for improved navigation and niche construction brings about external
efficient foraging in complex niche construction, which results in
environments relational niche construction that in turn
Relational: allowing red yeast to grow on brings about further constitutive niche
deposited carbohydrate-rich extracellular construction and more of the same
slime for later consumption
Constitutive: structural reconfiguration of
the internal network of tubes in response to
resource fluctuation
Sclerotium Constitutive: optional and reversible ? Temporarily
transformation from plasmodium to suspending
resistant, dormant unit in response to fecundity to
drought, light, and/or starvation maintain viability
Fruiting Body External: plasmodial transformation into External mediated relational niche Permanently
partially non-living environmental construction: external niche construction suspending viability
structures that support the development as a means of bringing about relational for fitness of next
and dispersal of spores niche construction in next generation generation
Slime Mould and Philosophy 25
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
26 Philosophy of Biology
Such explicit recognition is clear, for instance, on NASA’s Office of Safety &
Mission Assurance (OSMS) webpage, where they write on bacterial spores:
‘Spores are the most likely form of terrestrial life to be able to survive on
another planet’ https://sma.nasa.gov/sma-disciplines/planetary-protection/
explore/explore-item/what-are-spores.
That biologists also view spores as exemplifying life is evidenced by the fact
that they are regarded as stages in life cycles of spore-forming organisms
(Section 2.2). It would be truly odd if spores were considered devoid of life
and yet featured as a developmental stage within a life cycle.
The claims that dormant spores are an example of life and that a living system
must necessarily engage in metabolic processes, however, pull in different
directions when assuming life-living equivalence. For if spores are an example
of life, then, deploying life-living equivalence, they are also living systems.
However, in taking the assumption onboard that metabolic activity is necessary
for life, spores also turn out to be non-living systems because they do not engage
in metabolic activity. Taken together, we arrive at the conclusion that dormant
spores are both living systems and non-living systems. Two ways of avoiding
this reductio ad absurdum that make sense of the fact that biologists regard
dormant spores as an example of life are to: (1) maintain life-living equivalence
and relax the condition that metabolic exchange is necessary for being a living
system or (2) keep the condition that metabolic exchange is necessary for being
a living system and abandon life-living equivalence.
In this section, I will build a case for the second option, arguing that the relevant
equivalence is between life and being alive (rather than life and living), and that
living is a way of being alive. To illustrate and develop this position I will articulate
a taxonomical analysis of the biotic status of Physarum spores – an analysis that can
be generalised to other spore-forming taxa given the shared biotic features of
spores. This section will have the following organisation: firstly, I will survey
some examples of metabolic definitions of life that have been introduced in biology
(and biology-related fields), highlighting how these definitions deploy life-living
equivalence and, hence, assume that engaging in metabolic exchange is not only
necessary for being a living system but also necessary for life. Turning to Physarum
spores, I will briefly look at their metabolic inert (dormant) state and then articulate
one reason why biologists consider ametabolic dormant spores an example of life.
Nick Lane’s (2016) distinction between ‘living’ and ‘being alive’ will then be
elucidated and used as the basis for taxonomising the biotic status of Physarum’s
spores (and spores of other taxa) in support of option (2). Lastly, I will deploy the
proposed taxonomy to consider spore ageing and its relation to senescence in
vegetative entities, illustrating one of the wider implications of this taxonomy.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 27
12
ATP is an energy-supplying molecule that is often referred to as the cellular ‘energy currency’
because its breakdown via catabolism supplies a source of energy that is used for the vast
majority of cellular functions.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
28 Philosophy of Biology
[L]ife is a cyclic process that produces the components that in turn self-
organise in the process itself, and all within a boundary of its own making.
(Bitbol and Luigi, 2004: 99).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 29
[W]e shall first characterise the kind of machines that living systems are and
then show how peculiar properties of living systems may arise as
a consequence of the organisation of this kind of machines [sic]. (1973: 78)
and then:
13
The idea that life requires metabolism (and reproduction) goes at least as far back as Aristotle,
who is often considered the father of biology.
14
Although Sagan was an astronomer, not a biologist, I think it’s fair to say that his deployment of
life-living equivalence is representative of a general attitude adopted by many of the biologists
that he attributes his standard metabolic definition to.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
30 Philosophy of Biology
Maturana and Varela are careful to focus upon living systems as their intended
objects of analysis and do not, as Bitbol and Luisi’s interpretation suggests,
equate definitions of living systems with definitions of life.15 Bitbol and Luisi’s
interpretation of Maturana and Varela’s autopoietic definition of living system
exemplifies life-living equivalence and how readily it is assumed even by the
likes of careful biologists and philosophers.
Gánti’s definition also assumes life-living equivalence. His real- (absolute)
life criteria turn out to be necessary and sufficient conditions for being a living
system. Metabolic exchange, a real- (absolute) life criterion, is something that
livings systems must perform.
If these examples are representative of a general acceptance and use of life-
living equivalence on the part of biologists and philosophers, then a problem
arises in the context of understanding the biotic status of dormant spores.16 For
anyone who assumes life-living equivalence takes metabolic exchange as
necessary for being living system is committed to an incoherent view if there
are metabolically inert examples of life.17 Dormant spores, as we have already
seen, are one such example that most biologists acknowledge as such. Let us
now turn to look at Physarum spores in particular, focusing on what makes
spores metabolically inert and why one might plausibly consider them to be an
example of life. Although Physarum spores differ in some respects from those
of bacteria, something that I will soon clarify in more detail, there are shared
physiological changes that underly spore dormancy across taxa. It is the
15
Interestingly, later in an article entitled On Defining Life, Varela (1994) presents a similar
definition for (minimal) living systems. Given his earlier work (1973) with Maturana, his use
of life-living equivalence comes as a surprise to me.
16
Let it be stressed that the use of life-living equivalence is by no means limited to the context of
metabolic definitions (or theories) of life. Its prevalence extends to all aspects of biological
theorising that looks to expound upon life and biotic processes (e.g., theories and definitions of
life based upon reproduction, thermodynamics, etc.). The argument that I present here is merely
one manner to motivate renouncing life-living equivalence. A more general motivation, as I hope
to show, comes from the potential usefulness and conceptual clarity of the biotic taxonomy that
I develop in Section 3.3.
17
This is not meant to suggest that any of those authors who are committed to metabolic definitions
expounded upon above do or do not acknowledge that there are metabolically inert systems that
are examples of life. I am merely stating that if any of them do acknowledge that there are
metabolically inert systems that are examples of life, then given their use of life-living equiva-
lence their position is incoherent.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 31
I believe one implicit reason why many biologists acknowledge dormant spores
to be forms of life – a reason made explicit here by Gánti – has to do with the
idea that they retain a capacity to engage in metabolic exchange. Let me take
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
32 Philosophy of Biology
a moment to unpack this idea and put some ‘biological meat’ on what might
seem at first to be an abstract concept.
Were most organisms to undergo desiccation, they would die in the process;
their cellular structure would be destroyed beyond repair due to protein denatur-
ation (i.e., altering the shape or conformity of the proteins and hence preventing
them from playing a role in the various metabolic and regulatory functions that
they typically underwrite). This is not the case, however, with spores. In fact,
desiccation allows spores to remain viable despite the cessation of metabolism
that desiccation brings about, a process generally referred to as ‘anhydrobiosis’.18
During anhydrobiosis in eukaryotic spores, it is thought that most cellular water is
replaced by a sugar (‘trehalose’) that protects the structure of proteins and
membranes from the destructive effects of water loss (Clegg, 2001; Rikkinen
et al., 2019).19
In an anhydrobiotic state, if all goes well, a spore retains its capacity to
engage in metabolic exchange despite being metabolically inert. If something
goes awry and the spore loses this capacity, it dies and hence fails to be an
example of life any longer. I think this is an important point. If we don’t
recognise a spore as alive, then we can’t make sense of the significance of its
structure being destroyed. We wouldn’t be able to see this as ‘death’, but just an
ordinary physical degradation.
Suppose a desiccated spore encounters environmental water (or a moist
surface) again, and the preserved intercellular structure and membrane are put
to work once more so that metabolic exchange resumes. When this happens,
a spore’s capacity to engage in metabolic exchange is utilised. To be sure, even
when not utilising its capacity to metabolise, a spore retains that capacity (much
in the same way that your capacity to breathe does not somehow vanish when
you begin to breathe again after having held your breath for some seconds).
Retaining the capacity (unutilised or utilised) to engage in metabolic exchange
qualifies spores as examples of life and the mechanism underwriting anhydro-
biosis describes how a dormant spore retains its capacity to metabolise despite
its being unutilised. The continued functioning of metabolic pathways, on the
other hand, is how a non-dormant spore retains its capacity for metabolising; the
capacity is retained by utilising that very capacity. Non-dead dogs, bees,
18
Although the term ‘anhydrobiosis’ was not coined until 1959 by Keilin, that an organism’s
metabolism could come to a reversible halt was discovered around 300 years earlier by Antony
van Leeuwenhoek whilst doing experiments with desiccated ‘animacules’ (rotifers) that he
obtained from his gutter. Other anhydrobiotic organisms include tardigrades, brine shrimp,
some nematodes, resurrection plants, and some bacteria.
19
The idea that water is replaced by trehalose during anhydrobiosis is known as the ‘water
replacement hypothesis’ and was proposed by James Clegg (1986).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 33
20
Any of these organisms when dead, rather than representing an example of life, represent an
example of a biomarker – a sign of life that once existed.
21
See Segev et al. (2012) for evidence that entry into dormancy lasts several days for bacteria
B. subtilis. This spore development period in B. subtilis would be analogous to what I have
labelled period (1) in the development of Physarum spores.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
34 Philosophy of Biology
assuming life-living equivalence, holds onto the idea that metabolic exchange is
necessary for being a living system and yet acknowledges that biologists regard
spores as an example of life. The way of resolving this tension that I will now
pursue involves jettisoning life-living equivalence and developing a taxonomy
around a distinction proposed by Lane (2016).
Lane, referring to dormant spores, distinguishes between life and living and, as
such, does not assume what I have been calling life-living equivalence. He does,
however, as I read him, suggest that being alive is necessary and sufficient for life,
what might be called ‘life-alive equivalence’. Importantly, he suggests that
retaining a potential to revive – to go back to living – is necessary for being
alive. In order to make sense of this condition, we must first have an idea of what
living is since being alive is characterised relative to living. In elucidating what he
takes to be the difference between life (being alive) and living, Lane writes:
Life is about structure (dictated in part by genes and evolution) but living –
growing and proliferating – is as much about the environment, how structure
and environment interrelate. (2016: 55)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 35
in metabolic exchange is both retained and utilised. To see this, consider that
a dormant spore is alive because its structure has been preserved in an anhy-
drobiotic state, allowing it to retain its capacity to engage in metabolism; yet
a dormant spore fails to be a living entity since that capacity is not being utilised.
On the other hand, a germinating spore – one that has encountered favourable
environmental conditions – is both alive and living. It utilises its capacity to
engage in metabolic exchange, and also retains that capacity in virtue of its
structure. This is also true of the pre-dormant spore. Lane’s distinction between
being alive and living thus lends support to the idea articulated above that
dormant spores are acknowledged to be life because they retain the capacity
to engage in metabolic exchange. Lane fleshes this idea out with the notion of
preserved structure.
Assuming that this analysis is correct, living can be viewed as something that is
additional to being alive – it requires more than just having the right structure. To
understand how living builds upon being alive and yet both categories remain
distinct, consider the fact that being a member of the species P. polycephalum is
distinct from being a member of the genus Physarum (see Table 1). That this is the
case is compatible with the fact that being a P. polycephalum is a specific way of
being a Physarum. This kind of relation is often described by philosophers in
terms of being a ‘specification relation’, ‘where the more specific property can be
understood as a conjunction of the less specific property and some independent
property or properties’ (Wilson, 2023: 1). Living may be viewed as a species of
the genus being alive in the same way that P. polycephalum is a species of the
genus Physarum. This has the result that any entity that is living is also alive
(having the right structure and having the right interrelation with the environment
so as to utilise that structure), although there may be entities that are alive which
simultaneously fail to be living (only possessing the right structure). It is in this
way that living builds upon being alive – it is a way of being alive.
Lane, in the passage above, also describes living in terms of ‘growing and
proliferating’. Whether he sees growing and proliferation (i.e., reproduction) as
contingent features or necessary features of living is not clear. I would like to
argue that although vegetative growth and repair – protein synthesis – is part and
parcel of utilised metabolism (anabolism) and hence living, there is a reason to
view proliferation as a contingent feature of living systems. For example,
a metabolising and hence living Physarum spore is not a reproducing entity but
a reproductive cell that develops under suitable conditions into a reproducing
entity. In this sense, a non-dormant spore is similar to a metabolising sperm cell or
egg cell, none of which proliferate. Although non-dormant spores cannot repro-
duce, protein synthesis occurs until a spore enters dormancy (Sauer et al., 1969)
and again during germination. One general take home from this example is that
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
36 Philosophy of Biology
being a living system and being a proliferating system can come apart, although in
many cases they do not.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 37
as a result of injury. Since the biological processes that give rise to the separ-
ation of the categories structura vivens, living, and dead are not discrete, these
categories are themselves rendered fuzzy – exemplifying the kind of fuzzy
boundaries that are typical in the biological world.
The focus of this section thus far has largely been two of the three biotic states
which I have argued apply to Physarum spores (structura vivens and living).
A third biotic state, dead, which I have given less attention is, however, no less
important. When we think of death, we tend to intuitively think of irreversibly
passing from a state of living to one devoid of life altogether. This is an
oversimplification of a complex picture that is largely due to the fact that our
intuitions are based upon what we know best – human life – and this is not
representative of all life.
Different ways of influencing environmental selection effects that have evolved
over time, and resulted in stage-specific phenotypes within a life cycle, have also
opened up different ways that life can cease to be. Currently, it is thought that in the
acellular slime moulds (myxomycetes), the ameboflagellate stage was ancestral to
the plasmodial life cycle stage (Collins, 1979). Alone this would suggest not only
that sexual reproduction is an evolved trait in the acellular slime moulds but,
crucially, that sclerotisation and sporulation (see Section 2) evolved from a life
cycle that consisted exclusively of asexually reproducing ameboflagellates. Let this
sink in for a minute. The ability to decouple being alive from living evolved at least
two separate times in the acellular slime moulds (myxomycetes) with the evolution
of the sclerotia and the reproductive spore (and possibly a third with the microcyst).
The evolution of these different life cycle stages resulted in not only new ways to
meet selection pressures head-on but also new ways to die.
For Physarum, death can occur from not only from a state of living but also
from a state being alive. When a Physarum dies from a state of living, it dies
from a state of either being an ameboflagellate, a plasmodium, a reviving
sclerotium, a young fruiting body, an immature spore, or a germinating spore.
When a Physarum dies from a state of structura vivens, it dies whilst either
being a sclerotium, a microcyst, or a dormant spore. Let us now take a moment
to consider how a spore might die.
Given that being alive is about preserving structure (Lane, 2016), one way for
a spore to die is for it to somehow lose its life-bearing structure and, as a result,
irreversibly lose its capacity to engage in metabolic exchange. This degradation
may occur across a wide range of rates. At one extreme, a spore can suffer
significant structural damage instantaneously to such a degree that the capacity
to metabolise is altogether thwarted; at the other extreme it may suffer structural
deterioration over time such that the capacity to metabolise becomes increas-
ingly limited and is slowly lost. Both are changes to the structural integrity of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
38 Philosophy of Biology
the spore. The most vivid examples of the former extreme of structural damage
are a spore’s being destroyed by being crushed or digested. The latter extreme of
structural deterioration is spore ageing, something that is measured by the
reduced rate of germination (Smith and Robinson, 1975; Segev et al.,
2012).22 Either significant structural damage or structural deterioration over
time and their accompanying DNA damage and/or protein modification may
render a spore dead. This covers all three possible categories of the DSVL
taxonomy that biotic status of Physarum spores may fall into.
The DSVL taxonomy may be distinguished from the taxonomy elucidated by
Clegg (2001) and Wharton (2003), both of whom contend that biological organ-
isation may be classified in terms of three different biotic states: alive, dead, and
cryptobiotic. As I understand their taxonomy, ‘alive’ refers to being metabolically
active, whilst ‘cryptobiotic’ refers the state of metabolic standstill occurring in
response to various physical stresses, including desiccation (anhydrobiosis),
freezing (cryptobiosis), and osmotic stress (osmobiosis) (Keilin, 1959).
However, by conceptualising the difference between being structura vivens and
living in terms of retaining a capacity to metabolise and utilising that retained
capacity, the DSVL taxonomy offers the advantage over Clegg and Wharton’s
taxonomy of being able to capture the specification relation between being alive
and living. As conceptualised by Clegg and Wharton, the notion of ‘alive’
(metabolically active) cannot coherently be a specific way of being cryptobiotic
(metabolically inactive). This is undesirable because when answering a question
like ‘what makes a dormant spore a form a life?’ (or equally ‘what makes
a dormant spore alive?’) one of the things that biologists presumably would
like to do is identify the shared feature(s) of dormant and non-dormant spores.
The DSVL taxonomy, in capturing the specification relation between alive and
living captures at least one such feature: dormant and non-dormant spores both
retain the capacity to engage in metabolic exchange via their preserved structure.
Entering into an anhydrobiotic state is how spore structure is preserved and how
ametabolic dormant spores remain alive like non-dormant spores.
22
Instantaneous damage suffered by a spore may also not be severe enough for it to result in
immediate death; rather, such damage may only be fatal after an organism begins to utilise its
capacity to metabolise again. A telling case of this type is provided by Wharton (2003), who
describes Hinton’s (1960) observation of an anhydrobiotic larva of the midge P. vanderplanki.
The larva, after suffering damage during its dormancy, revived only to die as a result of that
damage.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 39
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
40 Philosophy of Biology
compare the biotic status of the stages making up the life cycle of the bacterium
Bacillus subtilis with those of Physarum. Upon identifying the stages in which
B. subtilis is structura vivens (i.e., dormant), the question of how B. subtilis
spores preserve their structure and whether those structure preserving mechan-
isms are similar to those underwriting spores, sclerotia, and/or microcysts in
Physarum can be posed (assuming that the mechanisms underwriting structural
preservation in the latter three stages differ to some degree). Examples of how
the DSVL taxonomy applies to spores across taxa, to each of the organisational
forms making up Physarum’s complex life cycle, and to organisational forms of
Bacillus is provided in Figure 4(a–d).
It should be clear that while the conceptual distinctions of the DSVL tax-
onomy are conducive towards thinking about the biotic status of spores, the uses
of the taxonomy are by no means limited to thinking about spores. It can be
applied to any organism but will provide the most insightful perspective on
those organisms which have evolved a capacity to decouple being alive from
Figure 4 (a–d)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 41
living. For example, tardigrades do not form dormant spores; however, they can
enter into various reversable dormant states and remain alive by balling up and
forming a resistant ‘tun’ during unfavourable conditions (Møbjerg and Cardoso
Neves, 2021) (Figure 4d). Although water replacement with trehalose may be
a common feature between dormant spores and dormant anhydrobiotic tuns
(Wharton, 2003), deploying the DSVL taxonomy prompts us to ask whether the
transition back to the state of living for both desiccated spores (i.e., spore
germination) and desiccated tuns (i.e., tun reviving) are similar processes.
This highlights that there are at least two explananda (phenomena to be
explained) when it comes to the developmental transitions that take place across
the domain of life: how some living entity transitions to being structura vivens
and how that entity goes back to living again.
23
This assumes that the samples found were not contaminated.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
42 Philosophy of Biology
A dormant spore’s potential to metabolise changes over time and as such, spore
ageing can be viewed as a decreasing capacity to metabolise. Spore death, on the
other hand, is the complete loss of the capacity to metabolise. ‘Senescence’, ageing
that is experienced exclusively by living entities, is characterised as the time-related
loss of cellular growth, repair, and reproductive functions (Gilbert, 2000). Casting
this loss of cellular function as a decreasing capacity to engage in metabolic
exchange on the part of a living system, when living is conceptualised as a way
of being alive, investigating spore ageing (and eventual spore death) may be
a valuable proxy method for gaining insights into senescence. Setting aside the
fact that different organisms have different senescence mechanisms (Bodnar,
2014), the question arises as to whether senescence may be underwritten by
some of the same irreversible structural changes as spore ageing. For example, is
cellular senescence accompanied by the same or similar kinds of protein structure
modifying degradation that accompanies modification of protein structure in ageing
spores? Another question is whether the same kinds of environmental factors that
affect the progression of spore ageing might also affect the progression of senes-
cence. In terms of practical implications, the possibility of using spore ageing in
Physarum (or other spore bearing organisms) as an easy-to-study model system/
phenomenon to investigate fundamental aspects of senescence in other taxa may
very well be where the rubber meets the biological road. The DSVL taxonomy
furnishes the conceptual distinctions to investigate this possibility.
Having made a case for how one particular stage of Physarum’s complex life
cycles (the spore) can be used as a starting point for thinking about the biotic
status of spores more generally, let us now turn to another stage, the plasmo-
dium, and a challenge that its fascinating behaviour poses for the notion of
biological individuality.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 43
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
44 Philosophy of Biology
counting the things that feature into the explanations of phenomena of interest.
Addressing the question of whether the two plasmodial cells in the described
combined experimental scenario jointly constitute a biological individual is
grounded in myxomycete biology and may indeed be of value to this subdisci-
pline (or microbiology more generally). This value may lie in arriving at a more
precise understanding of the kinds of behaviour that a single Physarum plasmo-
dium is capable of in controlled laboratory settings. Admittedly, it is not telling
of what a plasmodium does in its natural habitat. Another value may lie in
something as fundamental as understanding when plasmodial fragmentation
sometimes counts as reproduction and when it does not. Lastly, since the
question is based upon an assumption about what would be likely to occur if
two experiments were combined, it may prompt those interested biologists to
investigate fragmentation and fusion patterns in the lab. This is a case in which
the posing of a question about biological individuality may itself have some
potential value to biology regardless of how it is answered.
In what follows, two different concepts of biological individual will be
brought to bear on the question of whether the two plasmodial cell fragments
in the described scenario jointly constitute a biological individual with the hope
of gleaning some insight into plasmodial individuality. The respective concepts
are those associated with what has been called Darwinian individuals and
metabolic individuals (Godfrey-Smith, 2013a).24 I will argue that the plasmo-
dial dyad fails to qualify as a single Darwinian individual. On the other hand,
taking fragmentation and fusion patterns into account may indeed warrant
viewing the dyad as having some degree of metabolic individuality. This,
however, requires expanding the ‘orthodox’ view of metabolic individuality
in a way that does justice to the remarkable morphological and behavioural
plasticity exhibited by a plasmodium.
This section will be organised as follows: firstly, I will describe the details of
both Darwinian individuality and metabolic individuality. Using these notions
of individuality, I will then evaluate the plasmodial dyad arriving at negative
conclusion regarding its status as a Darwinian individuality. I shall then evaluate
the dyad in terms of metabolic individuality, taking into account the larger
behavioural context of fragmentation and fusion or non-fusion. After introdu-
cing a simple diagrammatic schema of plasmodial fragmentation-fusion and
fragmentation-non-fusion patterns, I will argue that the possibility of the first of
24
To be sure, Godfrey-Smith (2013a, 2013b) formulates an account of ‘organisms’ that is based
upon the process of metabolism. To avoid any unnecessary confusion that might arise in adopting
his specific use of the term, given how widely a more general notion of organism is used in this
Element, in what follows I will continue to use ‘metabolic individuals’ to refer to Godfrey-
Smith’s ‘organisms’.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 45
25
There have been numerous ways that the notion of biological individuality has been developed
by both biologists and philosophers. For many such examples, see both (Clark, 2010) and
(Lidgard and Nyhart, 2017).
26
For a different analysis biological individuality that considers Physarum’s ability to fuse after
being split into different smaller individuals, see (Smith-Ferguson and Beekman, 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
46 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 47
across all three features suggests the presence of a mere group. Darwinian
individuals can fall anywhere in between these high or marginal scores. Let
me briefly unpack each of these features in turn.
Germline refers to the presence of a division of reproductive labour amongst
the different entities in a collective. Germ cells in mammals, for example, are the
only cells from which the same kind of organism can be reproductively derived.
Mammalian somatic cells, on the other hand, can reproductively give rise to only
differentiated cells like themselves and not an entire organism. A colony of honey
bees also has a certain degree of reproductive specialisation, their different castes
functioning analogously to germ and soma cells in mammals in important ways.
Reproduction of the colony is limited to queens and male drones, whereas female
workers are functionally sterile. A division of reproductive labour is a mechanism
that ensures that selection occurs at the level of the collective individual (e.g., the
individual human or honeybee colony) as opposed to independent selection
occurring also at the level of its nested parts (e.g., somatic cells or the individual
honeybee); it de-Darwinises lower-level units (Godfrey-Smith, 2009).
Godfrey-Smith characterises a reproductive bottleneck as a narrowing that
marks the start of a new generation in a life cycle, something that often takes
the form of a single cell. Bottlenecks serve as a mechanism to introduce variation
into the next generation given that small genetic changes in a single cell can result
in significant downstream effects over the course of development. Like germ-
lines, bottlenecks are a matter of degree. Lastly, integration refers to a more
general kind of division of labour that is characteristically exhibited to greater or
lesser degrees by collective reproducers. It is a division of labour other than that of
a reproductive division of labour. For instance, integration may take the form of
‘the mutual dependence of parts, and the maintenance of a boundary between
a collective and what is outside it’ (Godfrey-Smith, 2013a: 21). Interestingly,
Godfrey-Smith (2013a) sees behaviour-coordinating chemical communication
and waggle dances that occur between honeybees as counting towards the colony
having some degree of integration, suggesting that spatial contiguity is only one
manner of being integrated (also see Herron, 2017).
Germlines, bottlenecks, and integration are features of one kind of Darwinian
individual – a collective reproducer. Both simple and scaffolded reproducers
represent other kinds of Darwinian individuals that, like collective reproducers,
speak of degrees of Darwinian individuality.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
48 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 49
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
50 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 51
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
52 Philosophy of Biology
Darwinian individuals. The two plasmodial cells score null for germ line; there is
no division of reproductive labour that the two spatially separate cells exhibit;
each cell is able to reproduce and do so independently of the other. The dyad has
a similar score for both reproductive bottleneck (a narrowing that marks the
beginning of a new generation) and integration (i.e., spatial boundedness).31
These scores across all three features suggest that the dyad is not itself
a collective lineage-forming system. In other words, the dyad is a mere group
and not the kind of thing that reproduces as a unit and/or takes part in the process
of evolution by natural selection. Does the plasmodial dyad stand a better chance
of exhibiting some degree of metabolic individuality?
This question boils down to one of whether or not the two plasmodial cells
engage in some degree of metabolic cooperation. At first blush, it seems that
neither member of the plasmodial dyad reciprocally interacts with the other,
metabolically integrating in the service of the dyad’s continued existence. One
might expect this to be the case since the two plasmodia making up the dyad,
unlike, say, symbiotic associations or different honeybee castes, are homoge-
neous members that share the same features (i.e., clones). Accordingly, it might
be thought that neither plasmodial fragment cell can provide the other with
something that it cannot already provide itself and thus interaction between
homogeneous parts does not lend itself to a cooperative metabolic division of
labour (cf. Godfrey-Smith, 2013a). This, however, I would like to argue is too
fast. In the next section, I will show that limiting the evaluation to the features of
the dyad in isolation from what occurs prior (fragmentation) and subsequent to it
(fusion or non-fusion) obscures the big picture – a picture which is necessary for
recognising potential instances of at least one unusual form of metabolic indi-
viduality. Seeing the big picture means recognising patterns of plasmodial behav-
iour as they occur over time, taking more generally what has become known as
a processual view of biological individuality (see Meincke and Dupré, 2020).
31
The dyad is not a bottleneck since it is a doubling in cell number relative to the fragmenting
plasmodium.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 53
fully separate cells at t3 that continue to consume the two food sources independ-
ently. After the food has been consumed, the t3 cells fuse at t4 (see Figure 6).
The second pattern, FN, is identical to FF except that the two plasmodia, after
consuming the separate food sources at t3, do not fuse at t4 but continue to live as
independent cells (see Figure 7). One result of what I am calling non-fusion is
that the two cells become resource competitors. This can even potentially lead
to one of the two cells consuming the other (see Clark and Haskins, 2012).
I will now show how evaluating the metabolic individuality of plasmodial dyad
in the larger contexts of FF and FN reveals an interesting possibility that is
consistent with viewing the dyad at t3 as a spatially non-contiguous metabolic
individual. Let’s put some flesh on the bones of this way of looking at FF and FN.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
54 Philosophy of Biology
behaviour that occurs in response to separate food sources. What kinds of conditions
would affect whether fragmentation occurs after the cell reaches the two food
sources? One condition, but not the only one I suspect, has to do with the distance
between the food sources relative to the size of the plasmodial cell. If the distance
separating the food sources is significantly shorter than the size of the cell, then the
cell could cover both sources without needing to extend itself in any manner. On
the other hand, if the distance between the food sources is significantly greater
than the overall size of the cell, then to cover and consume both sources simultan-
eously, the cell must plastically modify its shape to reach both sources. It is only in
this latter ‘stretched out’ case that fragmentation would seem to benefit the cell in
exploiting both resources. In other words, ‘network shape is the solution to the
organism’s survival problems’ (Nakagaki et al., 2004: 2305).
If the cell at t1 can reach both food sources by altering its morphology and
connecting the two sources, what is the benefit of fragmenting? One possible
answer, and not the only one, is that the shuttling of protoplasm between the
spatially distributed regions of the plasmodial cell when it has covered both
food sources is metabolically expensive and may slow down the process of
consuming each of the sources of food (cf. Nakagaki et al., 2004); that is, in
certain foraging landscapes two smaller cells may be more efficient at consum-
ing each food source simultaneously than a larger stretched-out cell is.
Therefore, if fragmentation offers a benefit that is contingent upon both the
size of the cell and the length of the distance between the food sources, then
fragmentation in response to food may be viewed as a behavioural strategy for
efficient food consumption.
Fragmentation in plasmodia, when extending across two distant food
sources, is driven by changes in internal protoplasmic shuttling (Section 2)
that reallocate cytoplasm, nutrients, and other cellular components towards
separate growth regions (Nakagaki et al., 2001). With reduced protoplasmic
flow between the two regions that are in contact with the food, the vein-like
tubule that connects them decays, resulting in the fragmenting of the cell. Does
this mean that fragmentation is something that happens to the cell, rather than
something that the cell actively does? There is a compelling reason to think that
fragmentation is, in fact, under the cell’s behavioural control. Protoplasmic
shutting is how a plasmodium normally locomotes, in addition to how it forages
and explores its environment. It is an underlying behavioural mechanism. As
such, the fact that changes in protoplasmic shuttling underwrite fragmentation
fails to be a reason to view fragmenting as something other than controlled
behaviour – any more than it is a reason to deny that locomotion, foraging, or
exploring are controlled behaviours. Fragmenting in this case is something that
a plasmodial cell does and not something that merely happens to it.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 55
Thus far, the description of the behavioural pattern, from t1 to t3, is common
to both FF and FN. The difference between the two patterns is paramount to
evaluating plasmodial metabolic individuality. In the case of FF, the two cells of
the dyad fuse at t4. This is something that would be expected to occur given that
the cells originated from the same larger cell (i.e., they are genetic clones) and
that no mutations accumulated in the short period of time since fragmentation,
rendering them too genetically different to fuse (cf. Clark and Haskins, 2012).
What is relevant here is that fusion can occur at t4 because the cells of the dyad
are clones (closely genetically related if not identical). When the two cells fuse,
something interesting happens. The cell boundary separating the two adjacent
cells begins to degrade and the protoplasm shuttling tubules from each cell
begins to connect with the other cell’s tubules. As this occurs, the ‘fruit’ of each
cell’s metabolic labour is reciprocally shared as protoplasm flows through the
connecting tubules. During the final step of complete fusion, the two cells can
no longer be distinguished from the larger plasmodial cell that they become; the
cells lose their metabolic (and Darwinian) individuality for that of the larger
plasmodial cell they become at t4.
Recall that metabolic individuals persist over time despite turnover of mater-
ials and, more generally, change. Varying degrees of metabolic integration of
interacting parts (i.e., cooperation) is the functional ‘glue’ of the persisting
individual. The plasmodial cell at t1 and at t2, respectively, have high degrees of
metabolic cooperation amongst their intracellular parts. Similarly, the fused
plasmodial cell at t4 is also a highly metabolically integrated unit. It is not
immediately obvious, on the other hand, how each cell of the dyad at t3 may
metabolically cooperate with the other given the fact that each cell’s metabolic
machinery is highly autonomous. On closer inspection and when placed in the
context of FF, however, there is a precursory process which enables subsequent
metabolic integration and is mediated by the shared environmental substrate
that the two cells occupy. Although this precursory process is not itself direct
metabolic integration (it does not affect either cells’ metabolic activity), it
counts as a form of indirect metabolic integration when placed in the context
of FF. How might this be the case?
Plasmodia exude various biochemicals such as calcium into the substrate
upon which they locomote and rest (Vogel et al., 2015; Briard et al., 2020). In
a lab setting, this substrate is typically ‘agar’ (i.e., a non-living gelatinous
substance that is derived from seaweed) that covers the bottom of a Petri dish.
It has been shown that biochemicals that diffuse into a substrate can be used as
cues by those plasmodia which detect them to guide their navigational behav-
iour. More precisely, if the plasmodium which leaves the biochemical cue is
stressed (e.g., starved), then the cue will elicit an aversion response on the part
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
56 Philosophy of Biology
of the plasmodium that detects it. On the other hand, if the plasmodium that
exudes the biochemical is well-nourished, then the cue acts as an attractant.
Being an attractant means that a plasmodium that detects it will be likely
to approach the source of the diffusing biochemical gradient (Vogel et al.,
2015; Briard et al., 2020). Sometimes this source will be the plasmodium that
left the cue.
With this in mind, and returning to FF, if each separate plasmodial cell that
consumes the spatially separate food sources exudes a cue that acts as an
attractant (or a repellent) for the other, relaying the condition of the plasmodium
that left the cue, then it seems that in addition to genetic similarity, the
physiological condition of the two plasmodia can affect whether or not they
fuse. Given the use of environment-mediated chemical cues that lead to
fusion of the two cells in FF, I would like to suggest that there is a sense in
which the two separate cells have a degree of indirect metabolic integration.32
Importantly, such indirect integration occurs only when both plasmodial cells
leave and use cues that are attractive and, as a result, pave the way for subse-
quent fusion to occur.33 In this sense, calcium may play a similar role in
indirectly integrating spatially separate plasmodia as autoinducers produced
by V. fischeri during quorum-sensing play in indirectly integrating bacteria and
bobtail squid prior to bioluminescence of the squid–Vibrio individual.
Putting all of the pieces together: the occurrence of fragmentation followed
by fusion, FF, I would like to argue, licenses viewing fusion as the reforming of
the plasmodial cell that fragmented. The plasmodial dyad, if this is correct,
despite being homogeneous parts, represent a spatial division of metabolic
labour on the part of the fragmenting plasmodium. When the plasmodium at
t2 fragments, it persists as a higher-level metabolic individual comprised of the
two cells (lower-level metabolic individuals), metabolically benefiting as a unit
from the behaviour of each of its non-contiguous parts only after fusion. There
is a degree of indirect metabolic integration between the two separate plasmo-
dial cells at t3. However, and in contrast to the orthodox view of metabolic
individuality, what matters most in the case of FF is that the fruit of each cell’s
metabolic labour is shared during subsequent fusion. If this is correct, then FF
represents an interesting case in which an initially high degree of direct meta-
bolic integration of the plasmodial cell at t1 and t2 is temporarily interrupted at
t3 and then subsequently re-established at t4. This temporary interruption also
means a substantial temporary decrease in the degree of metabolic independ-
ence (and hence metabolic individuality) of the persisting higher-level dyadic
32
See Seeley (1989) on honeybee colony integration via cues and shared environment.
33
It follows that such indirect metabolic integration would not occur if the two cells were separated
by a large distance or if they were unable to detect and respond to each other’s cues.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 57
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
58 Philosophy of Biology
more generally). Although the evaluation that I have proposed may be less
intuitive than the alternative, this by itself is no reason to prefer the latter.34
One might still object that, regardless of differences in intuitions, this evalu-
ation unnecessarily multiplies metabolic individuals in a way that the simpler
alternative does not, thus dulling Occam’s razor. The proposed evaluation posits
three coexisting metabolic individuals after fragmentation (the two separate
cells of the dyad and the joint individual that they constitute), whereas the
alternative posits only two (each cell of the dyad). Although simplicity is
generally viewed as a value in scientific explanation and evaluation, it does
not necessarily mean that simpler evaluations (or explanations) are always
preferable. In the context of biological individuality, the notion of simplicity
must be approached with caution. Take for example the symbiotic association
between the bobtail squid and V. fischeri: if one considers this – as many
philosophers of biology do – a transient metabolic individual, one implicitly
acknowledges a nested individual, the existence of which is above and beyond
that of the squid and its numerous bacterial symbionts. All such analyses of
symbiotic associations, however, are rendered dead in the water if simpler
evaluations are viewed as inherently superior. Moreover, the very question of
whether a symbiotic association is a metabolic individual (or a Darwinian
individual) turns out to be ill-posed under the assumption the simpler evalu-
ations trump all others. Given that we continue to pose interesting questions
about metabolic individuality regarding systems like symbiotic associations –
questions that play a role in legitimate scientific theorising – I do not see why the
plausibility of the proposed evaluation should be dismissed because it is less
simple than the alternative.35
34
Perhaps the idea that a metabolic individual is spatially non-contiguous is one source of
discomfort with the proposed solution. It should be remembered, however, that this idea is not
by any means a unique feature of the particular solution that I have argued for; it is generally
acknowledged that metabolic individuals can be spatially non-contiguous. Ant colonies are one
such example that will be explored in Section 5.
35
Many thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to discuss this alternative way of
evaluating FF.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 59
integration of its constituent parts. What is not taken into account, however, is
whether the constituent parts have a shared beginning and whether or not it is
typical for those parts to have a shared end. More precisely, the evaluation of
metabolic individuality that is typical of the orthodox view does not take into
account whether the entities being evaluated are the products of fragmentation
and whether those entities are likely to fuse together subsequent to exercising
their independent metabolic machinery.
Perhaps one reason for this is that the problem cases for metabolic individuality
(or more generally for physiological individuality) that philosophers and biolo-
gists have tended to focus on evaluating have often taken the form of symbiotic
associations of various calibres. Symbionts, being heterospecific, are not them-
selves the products of fragmentation events of a monospecific organism. Another
reason may be as simple as rarity of occurrence. Although asexual reproduction
via fragmentation is common in a number of taxa ranging from some plants,
animals, and fungi, what is much less common is the combination of organism-
initiated fragmentation and subsequent fusion of those fragments.36 In the case
of FN, absence of fusion suggests that FN events end up being an instance of
asexual reproduction. When the combination of fragmenting and subsequent
fusion occurs, fragmentation may be seen as a form of plastic, metabolism-
driven behaviour. Physarum plasmodia (and myxomycetes more generally)
may be unique in exhibiting both fragmentation and fusion. Assuming that the
FF pattern would occur given that fragmentation and fusion occur separately, the
orthodox notion of metabolic individual may be stretched to its limit in this
particular case.
36
Sponges can fuse sometimes when conditions are suitable after fragmentation due to damage.
However, since it is damage that causes fragmentation rather than something that the sponge
itself does in response to separate food sources, such a pattern differs significantly from FF.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
60 Philosophy of Biology
It is only after the two cells have fused – if they do – that we can look back at
their behaviour as representing a division of metabolic labour that the higher-
level individual comprised of the two cells benefits from as a unit. Thus,
whether or not the dyad is a metabolic individual is contingent upon what
would occur after fragmentation. I would like to suggest that when adjudicating
the metabolic individuality of the dyad at t3 without knowing what happens
next, the best we can settle for is a counterfactual analysis. This may take
something like the following form:
37
In what follows, I will assume the following working definition of cognition: ‘Cognition
comprises the sensory and other information-processing mechanisms an organism has for
becoming familiar with, valuing, and interacting productively with features of its environment
[exploring, exploiting, evading] in order to meet existential needs, the most basic of which are
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 61
survival/persistence, growth/ thriving, and reproduction’ (Lyon et al., 2021: 4). Awareness, on
this characterisation, is not a requirement of cognition.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
62 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 63
reach the food source would be significantly longer in the coated condition
compared to the blank condition. This is because the slime-treated agar would
obscure the plasmodium’s own extracellular slime tracks. Remarkably, Reid
et al. discovered that the average time that a plasmodium spent migrating across
areas of agar it had previously explored was nearly ten times longer in the
coated condition than in the blank condition. According to Reid et al., these
findings ‘offer a unique demonstration of a spatial memory system in a non-
neuronal organism, supporting the theory that an externalised spatial memory
may be the functional precursor to the internal memory of higher organisms’
(2012: 1). Is extracellular slime really memory, and if so, is it the kind of
memory that is significant to the study of cognition?
Here is one working definition of biological memory offered by biologists
Frantisek Baluška and Michael Levin:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
64 Philosophy of Biology
39
Whereas extracellular slime is considered to be a medium for information storage, the causal
interaction between a plasmodium and extracellular slime has been argued to represent a form of
recall or what has been called ‘memory making’ (Sims and Kiverstein, 2022).
40
For my purposes in this section, the notion of metabolic individuality that I shall use will be
indifferent to what was called the ‘orthodox’ view and the expanded view that was argued in
Section 4 is required to make sense of fragmentation and fusion patterns.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 65
Metabolic individuals can be, but needn’t be reproducers (i.e., Darwinian individ-
uals), thus allowing for some heterospecific symbiotic associations that do not
reproduce as a unit to nonetheless qualify as delineable units of function. Relatedly,
metabolic individuals can be nested; a highly metabolically integrated individual
can be made up of other metabolic individuals; however, those at lower organisa-
tional level(s) give up some of their metabolic independence (i.e., autonomy) for
the continued functioning of the individual at the higher level. Taking all of these
core features into account, how might the notion of metabolic individuality hint at
where cognitive explanations of memory might get the most purchase? If metabolic
individuals are first and foremost persisters (Godfrey-Smith, 2013a), and such self-
maintenance is the fundamental background against which all cognitive capacities
might be thought to arise (Lyon et al., 2021; Sims, 2023), then it would seem that
the kind of memory (learning and decision making for that matter) that warrants
possible cognitive explanation qua cognitive process is that which arises at the level
of a metabolic individual (cf. Keijzer, 2021).
This suggestion requires some refining however: although this rules out
entities that are clearly not metabolic individuals such as genes, viruses, and
genetic regulatory networks, because metabolic individuality is a matter of
degree, an immediate challenge to this approach is that it requires drawing
a non-arbitrary line between how much metabolic individuality is required to
warrant memory being subject to cognitive explanation and how much is too
little. Whilst I am sceptical that such a non-arbitrary line can be drawn, there is
another way to decide upon the matter. It involves considering levels of
biological organisation and their relative degrees of metabolic individuality.
Even if some entity qualifies as a marginal metabolic individual, the fact that it
is part of a larger system which has an even higher degree of metabolic
individuality would suggest that the behaviour of the organisational level with
the highest degree of relative metabolic individuality would be subject to
explanation in terms of cognitive memory. To be clear, being subject to cogni-
tive explanation means that the observed memory can be tested or investigated
using criteria from specific theories of cognition (e.g., criteria for spatial
memory, procedural memory, etc.). Satisfying those criteria, however, is an
additional step, and one that can fail. On the other hand, if an entity fails to be
a metabolic individual or fails to score as having the highest degree of relative
metabolic individuality, investigating its observed memory using cognitive
theories would constitute a category error.
Next, we will consider what this suggests about where the use of cognitive
explanation of memory is warranted across different levels of biological organ-
isation, beginning with bodily cells then and working up to groups of metabolic
individuals. Two questions will be addressed at each level: (1) how is memory
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
66 Philosophy of Biology
exhibited and (2) does the entity/entities occupying that specific level qualify as
a metabolic individual?
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 67
cannot be considered bona fide metabolic individuals. This suggests that their
cellular memory is not subject to cognitive explanation.
This conclusion is consistent with acknowledging that cellular memory can
be fruitfully modelled ‘as if’ it was a cognitive process (cf. Pezzulo and Levin,
2016). However, due to the evolutionary path that somatic cells have followed,
favouring the suppression of their metabolic independence in favour of the
autonomy of the larger metabolic entity they constitute (such as the organism),
treating them as cognitive agents, if I am correct, bottoms out as a useful fiction
(e.g., helping to identify and highlight similar underlying mechanisms in use).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
68 Philosophy of Biology
up the immune system is dependent upon their being functionally integrated within
an organism; the immune cells with high pathogen affinity that are maintained in
the immune memory repertoire, for example, require energy and nutrients to
function, which are supplied by various non-immune system cells and tissues.
Relative to the organism that harbours immune cells, the continued functioning of
their metabolic machinery is tied up with the encompassing organismal system
within which the immune system has evolved to function as a part of. Therefore,
like the cellular memory of somatic cells within a multicellular organism,
immunological memory of the immune system, I would like to argue is not subject
to cognitive explanation for the same reason.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 69
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
70 Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Slime Mould and Philosophy 71
41
More precisely, habituation occurs when there is a decrease in response to a specific cue to
repeated encounters with that stimulus.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
72 Philosophy of Biology
visual cues in the environment (Aron et al., 1993). Such learning may contribute
to colony-level memory that can remain stable for many years, ‘outliving’ the
individual ants that contributed to the formation and stabilisation of the colony
memory (see Rosengren and Fortelius, 1987).
6 Conclusion
Philosophy of biology brims with a panoply of interesting and difficult puzzles,
challenging much of our quotidian understanding of the biological world. This
Element has served as a starting point and a full-bodied exercise in illustrating
how attention to the outlier model organism – the acellular slime mould,
P. polycephalum – can go a long way in terms of bringing some of those puzzles
to the fore; a long way in providing concrete cases with which to consider just
how wondrous and wondrously unintuitive the biological world can be. Given
that biological theory is not an island that is somehow isolated from our pre-
theoretical assumptions, the work that Physarum can do does not stop at
challenging folk biological assumptions. This Element represents a mere
scratching of the perennial surface when it comes to how Physarum can
contribute to the philosophy of biology. If it has piqued the interest of the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
Memory that Cases of trial-and -error learning, habituation and Associative conditioning at levels below the metabolic individual
results from conditioning at the level of the organism (e.g., conditioning in gene regulatory networks (Biswas et al., 2021))
learning (e.g., habituation in P. polycephalum (Vogel and Dussutour, 2016); Conditioning at levels below the highest scoring metabolic individual
habituation in Stentor coeruleus (Rajan et al., 2023); trial-and-error (e.g., associative learning in purkinje cells (Jirenhed et al., 2017))
learning in Stentor roeseli (Jennings, 1902; Dexter et al., 2019); Immunological memory (e.g., primed antibody response to pathogens at
conditioning in Paramecium aurelia (Gelber, 1962; Armus et al., level of immune system (Cohen, 1992))
2006); conditioning in Amoeba proteus (de la Fuente et al., 2019); Some cases of learning at the level of the colony or ‘superorganism’
conditioning in Caenorhabditis elegans (Morrison et al.,1999); and (?)
conditioning in dogs (Pavlov, [1897] 1902))
Some cases of learning at the level of the colony or ‘superorganism’
(e.g., learned task reallocation in response to perturbation
(Gordon et al., 1989))
Memory that does Transferred memory that results in matching behavioural profile in Epigenetically stabilised somatic cell differentiation and development
not result from transferee to that of the trained individual that learned (e.g., epigenetic regulation in pluripotent stem cells (Watanabe et al.,
learning (e.g., Physarum fusion habituation transfer (Vogel and Dussutour, 2013))
2016); sensitisation transfer in Aplysia (Bédécarrats et al., 2018)) Transgenerational cellular memory (e.g., proliferation and maintenance of
Production and use of environmentally mediated cues and signals for heterogeneity in bacterial cell characteristics over multiple generations
spatial navigation (e.g., Physarum’s production and use of due to epigenetically inherited marks (Vashistha et al., 2021))
extracellular slime to navigate complex environments
(Reid et al., 2012, 2013))
74 Philosophy of Biology
philosopher to look further into the fascinating life cycle and behaviour of slime
mould, if it has inspired the biologist to consider the deep philosophical
challenges made salient by Physarum, or if it has provided some common
ground for future research that both the philosopher and the biologist can
tread upon in tandem, then ‘Slime Mould and Philosophy’ has done its job.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
References
Aaby, Bendik Hellem, and Grant Ramsey. 2019. ‘Three Kinds of Niche
Construction’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 73 (2):
351–72.
Armus, Harvard L., Amber R. Montgomery, and Rebecca L. Gurney. 2006.
‘Discrimination Learning and Extinction in Paramecia (P. Caudatum)’.
Psychological Reports 98 (3): 705–11.
Aron, Serge, R. Beckers, Jean-Louis Deneubourg, and Jacques Pasteels. 1993.
‘Memory and Chemical Communication in the Orientation of Two Mass-
Recruiting Ant Species’. Insectes Sociaux 40 (4): 369–80.
Bédécarrats, Alexis, Shanping Chen, Kaycey Pearce, Diancai Cai, and David
L. Glanzman. 2018. ‘RNA from Trained Aplysia Can Induce an Epigenetic
Engram for Long-Term Sensitization in Untrained Aplysia’. Eneuro 5 (3):
ENEURO.0038–18.2018: 1–11.
Baedke, Jan, Alejandro Fábregas-Tejeda, and Guido I. Prieto. 2021. ‘Unknotting
Reciprocal Causation between Organism and Environment’. Biology and
Philosophy 36: 48.
Bailey, Juliet. 1997. ‘Building a Plasmodium: Development in the Acellular
Slime Mould Physarum Polycephalum’. BioEssays 19 (11): 985–92.
Baluška, František, and Michael Levin. 2016. ‘On Having No Head: Cognition
throughout Biological Systems’. Frontiers in Psychology 7 (June): 902.
Bateson, Patrick, and Peter Gluckman. 2011. Plasticity, Robustness, Development
and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Biswas, Surama, Santosh Manicka, Erik Hoel, and Michael Levin. 2021. ‘Gene
Regulatory Networks Exhibit Several Kinds of Memory: Quantification of
Memory in Biological and Random Transcriptional Networks’. IScience
(February): 102131.
Bitbol, Michel, and Pier Luigi Luisi. 2004. ‘Autopoiesis with or without
Cognition: Defining Life at Its Edge’. Journal of the Royal Society Interface
1 (1): 99–107.
Blackwell, Meredith. 1984. ‘Myxomycetes and Their Arthropod Associates’. In
Fungus–Insect Relationships: Perspectives in Ecology and Evolution, (Eds.)
Quentin D. Wheeler and Meredith Blackwell. pp. 67–90. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Bock, Walter J. 1980. ‘The Definition and Recognition of Biological Adaptation’.
Integrative and Comparative Biology 20 (1): 217–27.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
76 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
References 77
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
78 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
References 79
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
80 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
References 81
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
82 References
Rajan, Deepa, Peter Chudinov, and Wallace Marshall. 2023. ‘Studying Habituation
in Stentor Coeruleus’. JoVE (Journal of Visualized Experiments), 191 (January):
e64692. https://doi.org/10.3791/64692.
Reid, Chris R. 2023. ‘Thoughts from the Forest Floor: A Review of Cognition in
the Slime Mould Physarum Polycephalum’. Animal Cognition 26: 1783–97.
Reid, Chris R., Tanya Latty, Audrey Dussutour, and Madeleine Beekman. 2012.
‘Slime Mold Uses an Externalized Spatial ‘Memory’ to Navigate in Complex
Environments’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the
United States of America 109 (43):17490–94.
Reid, Chris R., Madeleine Beekman, Tanya Latty, and Audrey Dussutour. 2013.
‘Amoeboid Organism Uses Extracellular Secretions to Make Smart Foraging
Decisions’. Behavioral Ecology 24 (4): 812–18.
Rikkinen, Jouko, David A. Grimaldi, and Alexander R. Schmidt. 2019.
‘Morphological Stasis in the First Myxomycete from the Mesozoic, and the
Likely Role of Cryptobiosis’. Scientific Reports 9 (1): 1–8.
Rosengren, Rainer, and Wilhelm Fortelius. 1987. ‘Trail Communication and
Directional Recruitment to Food in Red Wood Ants (Formica)’. Annales
Zoologici Fennici 24 (2): 137–46.
Sagan, Lynn. 1967. ‘On the Origin of Mitosing Cells’. Journal of Theoretical
Biology 14 (3): 225–IN6.
Sagan, Carl. 2010. ‘Definitions of life’. In The Nature of Life: Classical and
Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science, M. Bedau &
C. Cleland (Authors), pp. 303–306. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Saigusa, Tetsu, Atsushi Tero, Toshiyuki Nakagaki, and Yoshiki Kuramoto.
2008. ‘Amoebae Anticipate Periodic Events’. Physical Review Letters 100
(1): 1–5.
Sauer, Herbert W., Kenneth L. Babcock, and Harold P. Rusch. 1969.
‘Sporulation in Physarum Polycephalum: A Model System for Studies on
Differentiation’. Experimental Cell Research 57 (2): 319–27.
Schrödinger, Edward. 1944. What Is Life? Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Scott-Phillips, Thomas C., Kevin N. Laland, David M. Shuker, Thomas
E. Dickins, and Stuart A. West. 2014. ‘The Niche Construction Perspective:
A Critical Appraisal’. Evolution 68 (5): 1231–43.
Seeley, Thomas D. 1989. ‘The Honey Bee Colony as a Superorganism’.
American Scientist 77 (6): 546–53.
Segev, Einat, Yoav Smith, and Sigal Ben-Yehuda. 2012. ‘RNA Dynamics in
Aging Bacterial Spores’. Cell 148 (1–2): 139–49.
Shatilovich, Anastasia, Vamshidhar R. Gade, Martin Pippel, et al. 2023.
‘A Novel Nematode Species from the Siberian Permafrost Shares Adaptive
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
References 83
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
84 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank the following people for the many discussions that shaped this
Element and for providing comments on either all or parts of the manuscript: Jan
Baedke, Nick Brancazio, David Colaço, Si Qiao Ding, John Dupré, Audrey
Dussutour, Carrie Figdor, Debora Gordon, Jeremy Gunawardena, Eva Jablonka,
Fred Keijzer, Michael Levin, Pamela Lyon, Kevin Mitchell, Kathryn Nave, Emma
Otterski, Guido I. Prieto, Sofiia Rappe, Chris Reid, Tobias Schlict, Caroline
Stankozi, Tobias Starzak, Stephen Stevenson, and Alejandro Fárbregas Tejeda.
A very special thanks to two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments
and to Grant Ramsey and Michael Ruse for their support and encouragement to
write this Element. Lastly, I am grateful to Benjamin Little for his unwavering love
and being a constant source of inspiration. This research was made possible through
generous support from the VolkswagenStiftung.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Philosophy of Biology
Grant Ramsey
KU Leuven
Grant Ramsey is a BOFZAP research professor at the Institute of Philosophy,
KU Leuven, Belgium. His work centers on philosophical problems at the foundation of
evolutionary biology. He has been awarded the Popper Prize twice for his work in this area.
He also publishes in the philosophy of animal behavior, human nature and the moral
emotions. He runs the Ramsey Lab (theramseylab.org), a highly collaborative research
group focused on issues in the philosophy of the life sciences.
Michael Ruse
Florida State University
Michael Ruse is the Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy and the Director
of the Program in the History and Philosophy of Science at Florida State University. He is
Professor Emeritus at the University of Guelph, in Ontario, Canada. He is a former
Guggenheim fellow and Gifford lecturer. He is the author or editor of over sixty books,
most recently Darwinism as Religion: What Literature Tells Us about Evolution; On Purpose;
The Problem of War: Darwinism, Christianity, and their Battle to Understand Human
Conflict; and A Meaning to Life.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648
Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.203.236.202, on 13 Dec 2024 at 09:20:56, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009488648