Care Ethics - Maureen Sander-Staudt
Care Ethics - Maureen Sander-Staudt
Care Ethics - Maureen Sander-Staudt
The moral theory known as “ the ethics of care” implies that there is moral significance in the funda‐
mental elements of relationships and dependencies in human life. Normatively, care ethics seeks to
maintain relationships by contextualizing and promoting the well-being of care-givers and care-
receivers in a network of social relations. Most often defined as a practice or virtue rather than a the‐
ory as such, “care” involves maintaining the world of, and meeting the needs of, ourself and others. It
builds on the motivation to care for those who are dependent and vulnerable, and it is inspired by both
memories of being cared for and the idealizations of self. Following in the sentimentalist tradition of
moral theory, care ethics affirms the importance of caring motivation, emotion and the body in moral
deliberation, as well as reasoning from particulars. One of the original works of care ethics was Milton
Mayeroff’s short book, On Caring, but the emergence of care ethics as a distinct moral theory is most
often attributed to the works of psychologist Carol Gilligan and philosopher Nel Noddings in the
mid-1980s. Both charged traditional moral approaches with male bias, and asserted the “voice of care”
as a legitimate alternative to the “justice perspective” of liberal human rights theory. Annette Baier,
Virginia Held, Eva Feder Kittay, Sara Ruddick, and Joan Tronto are some of the most influential
among many subsequent contributors to care ethics.
Table of Contents
1. History and Major Authors
a. Carol Gilligan
b. Nel Noddings
c. Other Influential authors
i. Annette Baier
ii. Virginia Held
iii. Eva Feder Kittay
iv. Sara Ruddick
v. Joan Tronto
2. Definitions of Care
3. Criticisms
a. Care Ethics as a Slave Morality
b. Care Ethics as Empirically Flawed
c. Care Ethics as Theoretically Indistinct
d. Care Ethics as Parochial
e. Care Ethics as Essentialist
f. Care Ethics as Ambiguous
4. Feminine and Feminist Ethics
5. Relation to Other Theories
6. Maternalism
7. International Relations
8. Political Theory
9. Caring for Animals
10. Applied Care Ethics
11. Care Movements
12. References and Further Reading
a. Carol Gilligan
While early strains of care ethics can be detected in the writings of feminist philosophers such as Mary
Wollstonecraft, Catherine and Harriet Beecher, and Charlotte Perkins, it was first most explicitly artic‐
ulated by Carol Gilligan and Nel Noddings in the early 1980s. While a graduate student at Harvard,
Gilligan wrote her dissertation outlining a different path of moral development than the one described
by Lawrence Kohlberg, her mentor. Kohlberg had posited that moral development progressively
moves toward more universalized and principled thinking and had also found that girls, when later in‐
cluded in his studies, scored significantly lower than boys. Gilligan faulted Kohlberg’s model of moral
development for being gender biased, and reported hearing a “different voice” than the voice of justice
presumed in Kohlberg’s model. She found that both men and women articulated the voice of care at
different times, but noted that the voice of care, without women, would nearly fall out of their studies.
Refuting the charge that the moral reasoning of girls and women is immature because of its preoccu‐
pation with immediate relations, Gilligan asserted that the “care perspective” was an alternative, but
equally legitimate form of moral reasoning obscured by masculine liberal justice traditions focused on
autonomy and independence. She characterized this difference as one of theme, however, rather than
of gender.
Gilligan articulated these thematic perspectives through the moral reasoning of “Jake” and “Amy”,
two children in Kohlberg’s studies responding to the “Heinz dilemma”. In this dilemma, the children
are asked whether a man, “Heinz”, should have stolen an overpriced drug to save the life of his ill
wife. Jake sees the Heinz dilemma as a math problem with people wherein the right to life trumps the
right to property, such that all people would reasonably judge that Heinz ought to steal the drug. Amy,
on the other hand, disagrees that Heinz should steal the drug, lest he should go to prison and leave his
wife in another predicament. She sees the dilemma as a narrative of relations over time, involving
fractured relationships that must be mended through communication. Understanding the world as pop‐
ulated with networks of relationships rather than people standing alone, Amy is confident that the
druggist would be willing to work with Heinz once the situation was explained. Gilligan posited that
men and women often speak different languages that they think are the same, and she sought to correct
the tendency to take the male perspective as the prototype for humanity in moral reasoning.
Later, Gilligan vigorously resisted readings of her work that posit care ethics as relating to gender
more than theme, and even established the harmony of care and justice ethics (1986), but she never
fully abandoned her thesis of an association between women and relational ethics. She further devel‐
oped the idea of two distinct moral “voices”, and their relationship to gender in Mapping the Moral
Domain: A Contribution of Women’s Thinking to Psychological Theory and Education (Gilligan,
Ward, and Taylor, 1988), a collection of essays that traced the predominance of the “justice perspec‐
tive” within the fields of psychology and education, and the implications of the excluded “care per‐
spective”. In Making Connections: The Relational Worlds of Adolescent Girls at Emma Willard
School, Gilligan and her co-editors argued that the time between the ages of eleven and sixteen is cru‐
cial to girls’ formation of identity, being the time when girls learn to silence their inner moral intu‐
itions in favor of more rule bound interpretations of moral reasoning (Gilligan, Lyons, and Hamner,
1990, 3). Gilligan found that in adulthood women are encouraged to resolve the crises of adolescence
by excluding themselves or others, that is, by being good/responsive, or by being selfish/independent.
As a result, women’s adolescent voices of resistance become silent, and they experience a dislocation
of self, mind, and body, which may be reflected in eating disorders, low leadership aspiration, and
self-effacing sexual choices. Gilligan also expanded her ideas in a number of articles and reports
(Gilligan, 1979; 1980; 1982; 1987).
b. Nel Noddings
In 1984 Noddings published Caring, in which she developed the idea of care as a feminine ethic, and
applied it to the practice of moral education. Starting from the presumption that women “enter the
practical domain of moral action…through a different door”, she ascribed to feminine ethics a prefer‐
ence for face-to face moral deliberation that occurs in real time, and appreciation of the uniqueness of
each caring relationship. Drawing conceptually from a maternal perspective, Noddings understood
caring relationships to be basic to human existence and consciousness. She identified two parties in a
caring relationship—“one-caring” and the “cared-for”—and affirmed that both parties have some form
of obligation to care reciprocally and meet the other morally, although not in the same manner. She
characterized caring as an act of “engrossment” whereby the one-caring receives the cared-for on their
own terms, resisting projection of the self onto the cared-for, and displacing selfish motives in order to
act on the behalf of the cared-for. Noddings located the origin of ethical action in two motives, the hu‐
man affective response that is a natural caring sentiment, and the memory of being cared-for that gives
rise to an ideal self. Noddings rejected universal principles for prescribed action and judgment, argu‐
ing that care must always be contextually applied.
Noddings identified two stages of caring, “caring-for” and “caring-about”. The former stage refers to
actual hands-on application of caring services, and the latter to a state of being whereby one nurtures
caring ideas or intentions. She further argued that the scope of caring obligation is limited. This scope
of caring is strongest towards others who are capable of reciprocal relationship. The caring obligation
is conceived of as moving outward in concentric circles so enlarged care is increasingly characterized
by a diminished ability for particularity and contextual judgment, which prompted Noddings to specu‐
late that it is impossible to care-for everyone. She maintained that while the one-caring has an obliga‐
tion to care-for proximate humans and animals to the extent that they are needy and able to respond to
offerings of care, there is a lesser obligation to care for distant others if there is no hope that care will
be completed. These claims proved to be highly controversial, and Noddings later revised them some‐
what. In her more recent book Starting From Home, Noddings endorsed a stronger obligation to care
about distant humans, and affirms caring-about as an important motivational stage for inspiring local
and global justice, but continued to hold that it is impossible to care-for all, especially distant others.
(See 3a.iv below)
i. Annette Baier
Annette Baier observes certain affinities between care ethics and the moral theory of David Hume,
whom she dubs the “women’s moral theorist.” Baier suggests both deny that morality consists in obe‐
dience to a universal law, emphasizing rather the importance of cultivating virtuous sentimental char‐
acter traits, including gentleness, agreeability, compassion, sympathy, and good temperedness (1987,
42). Baier specially underscores trust, a basic relation between particular persons, as the fundamental
concept of morality, and notes its obfuscation within theories premised on abstract and autonomous
agents. She recommends carving out room for the development of moral emotions and harmonizing
the ideals of care and justice.
v. Joan Tronto
Joan Tronto is most known for exploring the intersections of care ethics, feminist theory, and political
science. She sanctions a feminist care ethic designed to thwart the accretion of power to the existing
powerful, and to increase value for activities that legitimize shared power. She identifies moral bound‐
aries that have served to privatize the implications of care ethics, and highlights the political dynamics
of care relations which describe, for example, the tendency of women and other minorities to perform
care work in ways that benefit the social elite. She expands the phases of care to include “caring
about”, “taking care of” (assuming responsibility for care), “care-giving” (the direct meeting of need),
and “care-receiving”. She coins the phrase “privileged irresponsibility” to describe the phenomenon
that allows the most advantaged in society to purchase caring services, delegate the work of care-
giving, and avoid responsibility for the adequacy of hands-on care. (See Sections 2 and 8 below).
2. Definitions of Care
Because it depends upon contextual considerations, care is notoriously difficult to define. As Ruddick
points out, at least three distinct but overlapping meanings of care have emerged in recent decades—
an ethic defined in opposition to justice, a kind of labor, and a particular relationship (1998, 4).
However, in care ethical literature, ‘care’ is most often defined as a practice, value, disposition, or
virtue, and is frequently portrayed as an overlapping set of concepts. For example, Held notes that care
is a form of labor, but also an ideal that guides normative judgment and action, and she characterizes
care as “clusters” of practices and values (2006, 36, 40). One of the most popular definitions of care,
offered by Tronto and Bernice Fischer, construes care as “a species of activity that includes everything
we do to maintain, contain, and repair our ‘world’ so that we can live in it as well as possible. That
world includes our bodies, ourselves, and our environment”. This definition posits care fundamentally
as a practice, but Tronto further identifies four sub-elements of care that can be understood simultane‐
ously as stages, virtuous dispositions, or goals. These sub-elements are: (1) attentiveness, a proclivity
to become aware of need; (2) responsibility, a willingness to respond and take care of need; (3) com‐
petence, the skill of providing good and successful care; and (4) responsiveness, consideration of the
position of others as they see it and recognition of the potential for abuse in care (1994, 126-136).
Tronto’s definition is praised for how it admits to cultural variation and extends care beyond family
and domestic spheres, but it is also criticized for being overly broad, counting nearly every human ac‐
tivity as care.
Other definitions of care provide more precise delineations. Diemut Bubeck narrows the definitional
scope of care by emphasizing personal interaction and dependency. She describes care as an emotional
state, activity, or both, that is functional, and specifically involves “the meeting of needs of one person
by another where face-to-face interaction between care and cared for is a crucial element of overall ac‐
tivity, and where the need is of such a nature that it cannot possibly be met by the person in need her‐
self” (129). Bubeck thus distinguishes care from “service”, by stipulating that “care” involves meeting
the needs for others who cannot meet their needs themselves, whereas “service” involves meeting the
needs of individuals who are capable of self-care. She also holds that one cannot care for oneself, and
that care does not require any emotional attachment. While some care ethicists accept that care need
not always have an emotional component, Bubeck’s definitional exclusion of self-care is rejected by
other care ethicists who stress additional aspects of care.
For example, both Maurice Hamington and Daniel Engster make room for self-care in their definitions
of care, but focus more precisely on special bodily features and end goals of care (Hamington, 2004;
Engster, 2007). Hamington focuses on embodiment, stating that: “care denotes an approach to per‐
sonal and social morality that shifts ethical considerations to context, relationships, and affective
knowledge in a manner that can only be fully understood if care’s embodied dimension is recognized.
Care is committed to flourishing and growth of individuals, yet acknowledges our interconnectedness
and interdependence” (2004, 3). Engster develops a “basic needs” approach to care, defining care as a
practice that includes “everything we do to help individuals to meet their vital biological needs, de‐
velop or maintain their basic capabilities, and avoid or alleviate unnecessary or unwanted pain and
suffering, so that they can survive, develop, and function in society” (2007, 28). Although care is often
unpaid, interpersonal, and emotional work, Engster’s definition does not exclude paid work or self-
care, nor require the presence of affection or other emotion (32). Although these definitions emphasize
care as a practice, not all moral theorists maintain this view of.
Alternatively, care is understood as a virtue or motive. James Rachels, Raja Halwani, and Margaret
McLaren have argued for categorizing care ethics as a species of virtue ethics, with care as a central
virtue (Rachels, 1999; McLaren, 2001; Halwani, 2003). The idea that that care is best understood as
virtuous motives or communicative skills is endorsed by Michael Slote who equates care with a kind
of motivational attitude of empathy, and by Selma Sevenhuijsen, who defines care as “styles of situ‐
ated moral reasoning” that involves listening and responding to others on their own terms.” (Slote,
2007; Sevenhuijsen, 1998, 85).
Some ethicists prefer to understand care as a practice more fundamental than a virtue or motive be‐
cause doing so resists the tendency to romanticize care as a sentiment or dispositional trait, and reveals
the breadth of caring activities as globally intertwined with virtually all aspects of life. As feminist
ethicists, Kittay and Held like to understand care as a practice and value rather than as a virtue because
it risks “losing site of it as work” (Held, 2006, 35). Held refutes that care is best understood as a dispo‐
sition such as compassion or benevolence, but defines “care” as “more a characterization of a social
relation than the description of an individual disposition.”
Overall, care continues to be an essentially contested concept, containing ambiguities that Peta
Bowden, finds advantageous, revealing “the complexity and diversity of the ethical possibilities of
care”(1997, 183).
3. Criticisms
A number of criticisms have been launched against care ethics, including that it is: a) a slave morality;
b) empirically flawed; c) theoretically indistinct; d) parochial, e) essentialist, and f) ambiguous.
But once it is acknowledged that women are diverse, and that some men exhibit equally strong tenden‐
cies to care, it is not readily apparent that care ethics is solely or uniquely feminine. Many women, in
actuality and in myth, in both contemporary and past times, do not exhibit care. Other factors of social
identity, such as ethnicity and class, have also been found to correlate with care thinking. Nonetheless,
care has pervasively been assumed to be a symbolically feminine trait and perspective, and many
women resonate with a care perspective. What differentiates feminine and feminist care ethics turns
on the extent to which there is critical inquiry into the empirical and symbolic association between
women and care, and concern for the power-related implications of this association. Alison Jaggar
characterizes a feminist ethic as one which exposes masculine and other biases in moral theory, under‐
stands individual actions in the context of social practices, illuminates differences between women,
provides guidance for private, public, and international issues, and treats the experiences of women re‐
spectfully, but not uncritically (Jaggar, 1991).
While most theorists agree that it is mistaken to view care ethics as a “woman’s morality”, the best
way to understand its relation to sex and gender is disputed. Slote develops a strictly gender neutral
theory of care on the grounds that care ethics can be traced to the work of male as well as female
philosophers. Engster endorses a “minimally feminist theory of care” that is largely gender neutral be‐
cause he defines care as meeting needs that are more generally human. Although he acknowledges that
women are disadvantaged in current caring distributions and are often socialized to value self-effacing
care, his theory is feminist only in seeking to assure that the basic needs of women and girls are met
and their capabilities developed.
In contrast, Held, Kittay, and Tronto draft more robust overlaps between care and feminist theory, re‐
taining yet challenging the gender-laden associations of care with language like “mothering persons”
or “dependency workers”. While cautious of the associations between care and femininity, they find it
useful to tap the resources of the lived and embodied experiences of women, a common one which is
the capacity to birth children. They tend to define care as a practice partially in order to stay mindful
of the ongoing empirical (if misguided) associations between care and women, that must inform
utopian visions of care as a gender-neutral activity and virtue. Complicating things further, individuals
who are sexed as women may nonetheless gain social privilege when they exhibit certain perceived
traits of the male gender, such as being unencumbered and competitive, suggesting that it is potentially
as important to revalue feminine traits and activities, as it is to stress the gender-neutral potential of
care ethics.
As it currently stands, care ethicists agree that women are positioned differently than men in relation
to caring practices, but there is no clear consensus about the best way to theorize sex and gender in
care ethics.
Some theorists move to integrate care and virtue ethics for strategic reasons. Slote seeks to form an al‐
liance against traditional “masculine” moral theories like Kantianism, utilitarianism, and social con‐
tract theory (Slote, 1998). He argues that, in so doing, care ethics receives a way of treating our obli‐
gations to people we don’t know, without having to supplement it with more problematic theories of
justice. McLaren posits that virtue theory provides a normative framework which care ethics lacks
(McLaren, 2001). The perceived flaw in care ethics for both authors is a neglect of justice standards in
how care is distributed and practiced, and a relegation of care to the private realm, which exacerbates
the isolation and individualization of the burdens of care already prevalent in liberal societies.
McLaren contends that virtue theory provides care ethics both with a standard of appropriateness and
a normative framework: “The standard of appropriateness is the mean—a virtue is always the mean
between two extremes…The normative framework stems from the definition of virtue as that which
promotes human flourishing” (2001, 105). Feminist critics, however, resist this assimilation on the
grounds that it may dilute the unique focus of care ethics (Held, 2006; Sander-Staudt, 2006). They are
optimistic that feminist versions of care ethics can address the above concerns of justice, and doubt
that virtue ethics provides the best normative framework.
Similar debates surround the comparison between care ethics and Confucianism. Philosophers note a
number of similarities between care ethics and Confucian ethics, not least that both theories are often
characterized as virtue ethics (Li, 1994, 2000; Lai Tao, 2000). Additional similarities are that both the‐
ories emphasize relationship as fundamental to being, eschew general principles, highlight the parent-
child relation as paramount, view moral responses as properly graduated, and identify emotions such
as empathy, compassion, and sensitivity as prerequisites for moral response. The most common com‐
parison is between the concepts of care and the Confucian concept of jen/ren. Ren is often translated
as love of humanity, or enlargement. Several authors argue that there is enough overlap between the
concepts of care and ren to judge that care ethics and Confucian ethics are remarkably similar and
compatible systems of thought (Li, 1994; Rosemont, 1997).
However, some philosophers object that it is better to view care ethics as distinct from Confucian
ethics, because of their potentially incompatible aspects. Feminist care ethicists charge that a feminist
care ethic is not compatible with the way Confucianism subordinates women. Ranjoo Seodu Herr lo‐
cates the incompatibility as between the Confucian significance of li, or formal standards of ritual, and
a feminist care ethics’ resistance to subjugation (2003). For similar reasons, Lijun Yuan doubts that
Confucian ethics can ever be acceptable to contemporary feminists, despite its similarity to care ethics.
Daniel Star categorizes Confucian ethics as a virtue ethic, and distinguishes virtue ethics and care
ethics as involving different biases in moral perception (2002). According to Star, care ethics differs
from Confucian ethics in not needing to be bound with any particular tradition, in downgrading the
importance of principles (versus merely noting that principles may be revised or suspended), and in re‐
jecting hierarchical, role-based categories of relationship in favor of contextual and particular re‐
sponses.
There are also refutations of the belief that care ethics is conceptually incompatible with the justice
perspectives of Kantian deontology and liberal human rights theory. Care ethicists dispute the infer‐
ence that because care and justice have evolved as distinct practices and ideals, that they are incompat‐
ible. Some deny that Kantianism is as staunchly principled and rationalistic as often portrayed, and af‐
firm that care ethics is compatible with Kantian deontology because it relies upon a universal injunc‐
tion to care, and requires a principle of caring obligation. An adaptation of the Kantian categorical im‐
perative can be used to ground the obligation to care in the universal necessity of care, and the incon‐
sistency of willing a world without intent to care. Other theorists compare the compatibility between
care ethics and concepts of central importance to a Kantian liberal tradition. Thus, Grace Clement ar‐
gues that an ideal of individual autonomy is required by normative ideals of care, in the sense that
care-givers ideally consent to and retain some degree of autonomy in caring relations, and also ideally
foster the autonomy of care-receivers (Clement, 1996). Mona Harrington explores the significance of
the liberal ideal of equality to care ethics by tracing how women’s inequality is linked to the low social
valuing and provision of care work (Harrington, 2000). Other ways that Kantianism is thought to ben‐
efit care ethics is by serving as a supplementary check to caring practice, (denouncing caring relations
that use others as mere means), and by providing a rhetorical vehicle for establishing care as a right.
6. Maternalism
As a theory rooted in practices of care, care ethics emerged in large part from analyses of the reason‐
ing and activities associated with mothering. Although some critics caution against the tendency to
construe all care relations in terms of a mother-child dyad, Ruddick and Held use a maternal perspec‐
tive to expand care ethics as a moral and political theory. In particular, Ruddick argues that “maternal
practice” yields specific kinds of thinking and supports a principled resistance to violence. Ruddick
notes that while some mothers support violence and war, they should not because of how it threatens
the goals and substance of care. Defining a mother as “a person who takes responsibility for children’s
lives and for whom providing child care is a significant part of his or her working life”, Ruddick stipu‐
lates that both men and women can be mothers (40). She identifies the following metaphysical atti‐
tudes, cognitive capacities, and virtues associated with mothering: preservative love (work of protec‐
tion with cheerfulness and humility), fostering growth (sponsoring or nurturing a child’s unfolding),
and training for social acceptability (a process of socialization that requires conscience and a struggle
for authenticity). Because children are subject to, but defy social expectations, the powers of mothers
are limited by the “gaze of the others”. Loving attention helps mothers to perceive their children and
themselves honestly so as to foster growth without retreating to fantasy or incurring loss of the self.
Expanding on the significance of the bodily experience of pregnancy and birth, Ruddick reasons that
mothers should oppose a sharp division between masculinity and femininity as untrue to children’s
sexual identities. In so doing, mothers should challenge the rigid division of male and female aspects
characteristic of military ideology because it threatens the hope and promise of birth. Ruddick creates
a feminist account of maternal care ethics that is rooted in the vulnerability, promise, and power of hu‐
man bodies, and that by resisting cheery denial, can transform the symbols of motherhood into politi‐
cal speech.
But however useful the paradigm for mothering has been to care ethics, many find it to be a limited
and problematic framework. Some critics reject Ruddick’s suggestion that mothering is logically
peaceful, noting that mothering may demand violent protectiveness and fierce response. Although
Ruddick acknowledges that many mothers support military endeavors and undermine peace move‐
ments, some critics are unconvinced that warfare is always illogical and universally contrary to mater‐
nal practice. Despite Ruddick’s recognition of violence in mothering, others object that a motherhood
paradigm offers a too narrowly dyadic and romantic paradigm, and that this approach mistakenly im‐
plies that characteristics of a mother-child relationship are universal worldly qualities of relationship.
For these reasons, some care ethicists, even when in agreement over the significance of the mother-
child relationship, have sought to expand the scope of care ethics by exploring other paradigms of care
work, such as friendship and citizenship.
7. International Relations
Care ethics was initially viewed as having little to say about international relations. With an emphasis
on known persons and particular selves, care ethics did not seem to be a moral theory suited to guide
relations with distant or hostile others. Fiona Robinson challenges this idea, however, by developing a
critical ethics of care that attends to the relations of dependency and vulnerability that exist on a global
scale (Robinson, 1999). Robinson’s analysis expands the sentiment of care to address the inequalities
within current international relations by promoting a care ethic that is responsive and attentive to the
difference of others, without presuming universal homogeneity. She argues that universal principles of
right and wrong typically fail to generate moral responses that alleviate the suffering of real people.
But she is optimistic that a feminist phenomenological version of care ethics can do so by exploring
the actual nature, conditions, and possibilities of global relations. She finds that the preoccupation
with the nation state in cosmopolitanism and communitarianism, and the enforced global primacy of
liberal values such as autonomy, independence, self-determination, and others, has led to a ‘culture of
neglect’. This culture is girded by a systemic devaluing of interdependence, relatedness, and positive
interaction with distant others. A critical ethic of care understands the global order not as emerging
from a unified or homogeneous humanity, but from structures that exploit differences to exclude,
marginalize and dominate. While Robinson doubts the possibility of “a more caring world” where
poverty and suffering are entirely eliminated, she finds that a critical care ethic may offer an alterna‐
tive mode of response that can motivate global care.
Likewise, Held is hopeful that care ethics can be used to transform international relations between
states, by noticing cultural constructs of masculinity in state behaviors, and by calling for cooperative
values to replace hierarchy and domination based on gender, class, race and ethnicity (Held, 2006).
Care ethicists continue to explore how care ethics can be applied to international relations in the con‐
text of the global need for care and in the international supply and demand for care that is served by
migrant populations of women.
8. Political Theory
As a political theory, care ethics examines questions of social justice, including the distribution of so‐
cial benefits and burdens, legislation, governance, and claims of entitlement. One of the earliest explo‐
rations of the implications of care ethics for feminist political theory was in Seyla Behabib’s article
“The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan Controversy and Feminist Theory”
(Benhabib, 1986). Here, Benhabib traces a basic dichotomy in political and moral theory drawn be‐
tween the public and private realms. Whereas the former is thought to be the realm of justice, the so‐
cial and historical, and generalized others, the latter is thought to be the realm of the good life, the nat‐
ural and atemporal, and concrete others. The former is captured by the favored metaphor of social con‐
tract theory and the “state of nature”, wherein men roam as adults, alone, independent, and free from
the ties of birth by women. Benhabib traces this metaphor, internalized by the male ego, within the po‐
litical philosophies of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and John Rawls, and the moral theories of
Immanuel Kant and Lawrence Kohlberg. She argues that under this conception, human interdepen‐
dency, difference, and questions about private life become irrelevant to politics.
The earliest substantial account of care as a political philosophy is offered by Tronto, who identifies
the traditional boundary between ethics and politics as one of three boundaries which serves to stymie
the political efficacy of a woman’s care ethic, (the other two being the boundary between the particular
and abstract/impersonal moral observer, and the boundary between public and private life) (Tronto,
1993). Together, these boundaries obscure how care as a political concept illuminates the interdepen‐
dency of human beings, and how care could stimulate democratic and pluralistic politics in the United
States by extending a platform to the politically disenfranchised. Following Tronto, a number of femi‐
nist care ethicists explore the implications of care ethics for a variety of political concepts, including
Bubeck who adapts Marxist arguments to establish the social necessity and current exploitation of the
work of care; Sevenhuijsen who reformulates citizenship to be more inclusive of caring need and care
work; and Kittay who develops a dependency based concept of equality (Bubeck, 1995; Sevenhuijsen,
1998; Kittay, 1999). Other authors examine the relevance of care ethics to the political issues of wel‐
fare policy, restorative justice, political agency, and global business.
The most comprehensive articulation of care ethics as a political theory is given by Engster, who de‐
fends a need based account of moral obligation (Engster, 2007). Engster’s “minimal capability theory”
is formed around two major premises—that all human beings are dependent upon others to develop
their basic capabilities, and that in receiving care, individuals tacitly and logically become obliged to
care for others. Engster understands care as a set of practices normatively informed by three virtues:
attention, responsiveness, and respect. Defining care as everything we do to satisfy vital biological
needs, develop and sustain basic capabilities, and avoid unnecessary suffering, Engster applies these
goals to domestic politics, economic justice, international relations, and culture. Engster holds govern‐
ments and businesses responsible for offering economic provisions in times of sickness, disability,
frail old age, bad luck, and reversal of fortune, for providing protection, health care, and clean envi‐
ronments, and for upholding the basic rights of individuals. He calls for businesses to balance caring
and commodity production by making work and care more compatible, although he surmises that the
goals of care need not fully subordinate economic ends such as profitability.
According to Engster, care as a political theory has universal application because conditions of depen‐
dency are ubiquitous, but care need not be practiced by all groups in the same way, and has no neces‐
sary affinities with any particular political system, including Marxism and liberalism. Governments
ought to primarily care for their own populations, but should also help the citizens of other nations liv‐
ing under abusive or neglectful regimes, within reasonable limits. International humanitarian interven‐
tions are more obligatory than military given the risk of physical harm, and the virtues of care can help
the international community avoid dangers associated with humanitarian assistance. With specific ref‐
erence to cultural practices in the U.S., Engster recommends a number of policy changes to education,
employment, and the media.
The application of care ethics to the moral status of animals has been most thoroughly explored by
Carol Adams and Josephine Donovan (Adams and Donovan 1996; 2007). Expanding on Adams’ orig‐
inal analysis of the sexual politics of meat (Adams, 1990), they maintain that a feminist care tradition
offers a superior foundation for animal ethics. They specifically question whether rights theory is an
adequate framework for an animal defense ethic because of its rationalist roots and individualist ontol‐
ogy, its tendency to extend rights to animals based on human traits, its devaluing of emotion and the
body, and its preference for abstract, formal, and quantifiable rules. Alternatively, they argue that a
feminist care ethic is a preferable foundation for grounding moral obligations to animals because its
relational ontology acknowledges love and empathy as major bases for human-animal connections,
and its contextual flexibility allows for a more nuanced consideration of animals across a continuum
of difference.
Engster similarly argues that the human obligation to care for non-human animals is limited by the de‐
gree to which non-human animals are dependent upon humans (Engster, 2006). Because an obligation
to care is rooted in dependency, humans do not have moral obligations to care for animals that are not
dependent upon humans. However, an obligation to care for animals is established when humans make
them dependent by providing food or shelter. Engster surmises that neither veganism nor vegetarian‐
ism are required providing that animals live happy, mature lives, and are humanely slaughtered, but
also acknowledges that the vast majority of animals live under atrocious conditions that care ethics re‐
nounces.
Empirical studies suggest interesting differences between the way that men and women think about
the moral status of animals, most notably, that women are more strongly opposed to animal research
and meat eating, and report being more willing to sacrifice for these causes, than men (Eldridge and
Gluck, 1996). While feminist care ethicists are careful not to take such empirical correlations as an au‐
tomatic endorsement of these views, eco-feminists like Marti Kheel explicate the connection between
feminism, animal advocacy, environmental ethics, and holistic health movements (Kheel, 2008).
Developing a more stringent obligation to care for animals, Kheel posits the uniqueness of all animals,
and broadens the scope of the moral obligation of care to include all individual beings as well as larger
collectives, noting that the majority of philosophies addressing animal welfare adopt masculine ap‐
proaches founded on abstract rules, rational principles, and generalized perspectives.
Author Information
Maureen Sander-Staudt
Email: Maureen.Sander-Staudt@asu.edu
Arizona State University
U. S. A.