James Beilby articulates a robust defense of postmortem opportunity. The book begins by introducing the "problem of the unevangelized". This problem normally focuses on standard examples of the unevangelized: (1) those geographically or...
moreJames Beilby articulates a robust defense of postmortem opportunity. The book begins by introducing the "problem of the unevangelized". This problem normally focuses on standard examples of the unevangelized: (1) those geographically or temporally isolated from hearing the gospel; (2) those who die in infancy; and (3) those with cognitive disabilities inhibiting one's comprehension of the gospel (pp. 3-10). Beilby also introduces examples of the "pseudoevangelized". These include: (4) those who hear "bastardized" version of the gospel being presented as inseparable from additional beliefs that are morally repugnant, such as the "gospel" of 18 th century slave traders; (5) those who experience abuse and trauma to the extent that, despite hearing the gospel, they are incapable of genuinely grasping it's message; and (6) those who hear to the gospel and progress toward responding in faith, but who's trajectory is interrupted by sudden death (pp. 10-4). These additional cases are important for the rest of Beilby's analysis, as he judges competing solutions to the problem of the unevangelized on their ability to accommodate 1-6. After surveying various solutions to the problem that have are available to Christians, Beilby launches into defending his preferred solution, postmortem opportunity. Beilby defines his position as follows: "those who die without receiving a genuine opportunity to hear and respond to the gospel will receive a Postmortem Opportunity to do so" (p. 50). It is important to recognize the Beilby does not claim everyone receives a postmortem opportunity. Postmortem opportunity is not a "second chance" (p. 152). Those who received a premortem opportunity to respond to the gospel and reject it will not be offered a postmortem opportunity. Beilby also makes no claim as to whether all, some, or none of the who receive a postmortem opportunity will respond positively. Moreover, unlike the hypothetical universalists account (p.55), Beilby affirms that, following God's final judgement, no more salvific opportunities will be available. Those who receive a postmortem opportunity will have a genuine chance to respond to the gospel, and those who reject will receive not receive another. Chapters 3-7 survey the theological, biblical, and historical arguments for and against postmortem opportunity. Beilby's theological argument assumes "an explicitly Arminian soteriology" (p. 75). This includes commitments to a synergistic understanding of God's grace and human cooperation, a libertarian account of human freedom, and a distinction between unconditional corporate election and conditional individual election (pp. 75-8). With these assumptions in place, Beilby's argument can be summarized in this way: God desires that all people be saved; being saved requires an opportunity to respond to the gospel; some people do not receive a premortem opportunity to respond to the gospel; therefore, God will provide a postmortem opportunity for those people to respond to the gospel (pp. 78-9). In chapter 4, Beilby addresses biblical objections to postmortem opportunity. The primary objection is that straightforward readings passages like Heb. 9:27, Luke 16:19-31, 2 Cor. 6:2 imply one's salvific status is fixed at death. Beilby aims to demonstrate that the passages do not rule out the possibility of postmortem opportunity, and that use of these passages to argue against postmortem opportunity often amounts improper exegesis and strawman fallacies (pp. 108-21). Beilby goes on in chapter 5 to examine what he considers "indirect support" from several passages that, while not providing explicit support for his view, render it more plausible.