Title: Recursive Ontology: a Systemic Theory of Reality
Author: Valerio Velardo
Affiliation: University of Huddersfield
Address for correspondence: Queensgate, Huddersfield, HD1 3DH;
valerio.velardo@hud.ac.uk
1
Recursive Ontology: a Systemic Theory of Reality
Abstract
The article introduces recursive ontology, a general ontology which aims
to describe how being is organized and what are the processes that drive
it. In order to answer those questions, I use a multidisciplinary approach
that combines the theory of levels, philosophy and systems theory. The
main claim of recursive ontology is that being is the product of a single
recursive process of generation that builds up all of reality in a
hierarchical fashion from fundamental physical particles to human
societies. To support this assumption, I provide the general laws and the
basic principles of recursive ontology as well as a semi-formalised model
of the theory based on a recursive generative grammar. Recursive
ontology not only actively promotes a multidisciplinary investigation of
reality, but also can be used as a general framework to develop future
domain-specific theories.
Keywords
complex systems, general ontology, generative grammars, recursion,
theory of levels.
2
1
Introduction
Human beings have always asked: how is the universe organized? Is it
possible to find some fundamentals that account for reality? What is
reality? Some answers to these questions come both from science and
philosophy. There are some relevant differences between the approaches
adopted by these two disciplines. While science is focused on empirical
evidence and observation, philosophy is usually more speculative and
based upon argument and reasoning from principles. In this paper, I adopt
a mixed approach. I rely on philosophy to speculate about the nature of
the universe, and at the same time, I rely on science to guide my
philosophical speculations based on empirical evidences.
Among the many branches of philosophy, general ontology is the
discipline that deals with being and in turn with fundamental
philosophical questions. This discipline should discover the categories of
the world and the rules that govern them (Grossmann 1983). Many
definitions of being have been proposed over time. For the purpose of this
article, I consider being from three complementary perspectives:
structure, process and organization as defined by the physicist Fritjof
Capra (1996). Structure is the physical instantiation of an abstract pattern
of organization, and is subject to dynamic processes of transformation. In
other words, structure accounts for the physical aspect of a construct,
organization for the abstract properties and process for the forces which
transform both structure and organization. Starting from this point, I
define being as the superset containing all physical, biological,
psychological and socio-cultural structures, patterns of organization and
3
processes already manifested or yet to manifest. This definition is similar
to the concept of universe from a systemic point of view, and is
interchangeable with the notion of reality. The systemic approach
considers the universe as a system with a structure, organization and a
process, which comprehends every component as a subsystem.
The following are the research questions that drive this article:
Are the different domains of reality related to one another? If so,
how are they related?
How is being organized?
What are the ontological categories of being?
What are the driving processes of being?
What are the fundamentals of being?
To answer those questions I propose a recursive ontology (RO), a general
ontology which provides a semi-formal description of reality. RO
suggests a list of ontological categories, general laws and basic principles
that account for the behaviour of being. Furthermore, RO proposes a
hierarchical structure of reality, based on a recursive process of
aggregation between the elements of being. The theory can be regarded as
a general framework of reality, that can be adopted as a basis to develop
domain-specific theories.
Previous research has attempted to define a general ontology based on
hierarchical levels. Hartmann proposed a theory of integrative levels,
suggesting that reality can be divided into four strata (Hartmann 2012).
4
Feibleman developed some general rules that could explain the behaviour
of levels (Feibleman 1954). Pattee proposed a more detailed theoretical
framework of reality, which combined the classical theory of levels with
systems theory (Pattee 1973). Poli refined these theories and developed a
powerful ontology that divides reality into three multi-layered strata (Poli
1998, 2001). Finally, Brown proposed a sophisticated mathematical
model of the theory of levels intended for emergent biosystems (Brown et
al. 2007).
However, all these studies show some limitations. The majority lack a
mathematical formalization, which would clarify and empower the
theoretical frameworks. Additionally, some of them (Poli 2001; Hartmann
2012) divide reality into distinct parallel strata (e.g., physical,
psychological, social), rather than providing a single unified structure of
being. Finally, even though this research acknowledges the hierarchical
structure of reality, none of them proposes a specific process of
generation, which could explain the organization of being. Indeed, those
studies are descriptive rather than explanatory. On the other hand, RO not
only suggests a unified structure of being, but also a single recursive
process of generation that explains the organizational patterns of reality.
This article has three main aims. First, it introduces the fundamentals of
RO. Second, it demonstrates that reality can be regarded as a hierarchical
structure engendered by a recursive process of generation. Finally, it
provides a semi-formalised recursive grammar, which is capable of
producing being as the result of a continuous generative process.
5
To investigate these topics, I adopt a multidisciplinary approach which
combines philosophy, complexity and systems theories as well as
complex networks and linguistics. Indeed, given the extraordinary
complexity of the issue, I think that only a multidisciplinary approach can
provide useful results. Also, I use a theoretical approach which focuses on
abstract concepts rather than on empirical case studies, in order to present
a general overview of RO. Furthermore, I claim that it is possible to
analyse the structure of being by using some constructs specifically
developed for natural language, since language and being, as we will see,
are inherently isomorphic.
The remainder of this article is organized in three parts. First, it provides a
review of the literature which explores the concept of recursion (2.1) and
introduces the theory of levels (2.2). Next, the paper introduces RO
presenting the general laws (3.1), a semi-formalised model (3.2) and the
basic principles of the theory (3.3). Finally, a discussion summarizes the
principal findings (4.1), clarifies the implications of the theory (4.2) and
highlights both the limitations of RO and future necessary research (4.3).
2
Background
This section introduces the fundamental theoretical constructs necessary
to understand RO. Initially, it provides a definition of recursion and
introduces some relevant applications of recursive processes in nature,
language and cognition (2.1). Then, it outlines the main features of the
theory of levels (2.2).
6
2.1
Defining recursion
Recursion is a universal process that appears within all the domains of
reality such as the physical, the biological and the cultural. Even though
the recursive process is inherently simple, it is stunningly elusive and
difficult to grasp (Koshcmann 2010). Moreover, there is no unique
definition of recursion. Sometimes, different definitions even oppose one
another. Recursion can be understood either as a process or as a structure
(Corballis 2011). It is possible to have a recursive process that does not
necessary entail a recursive structure, as well as a recursive structure that
is not necessary entailed by a recursive process (Martins and Fitch 2014).
The term recursion usually indicates the process of embedding some
constructs within other constructs of the same kind (Pinker and
Jackendoff 2005). This definition focuses only on the structural aspect of
recursion. A more useful definition for the present research considers
recursion as the set of rules that can apply to their output infinite times
(Everett 2009). This definition focuses on process rather than on
structure, considering recursion as a steady process that applies either to
systems or functions. From a computational point of view, it is possible to
define recursion as a procedure that calls itself, or that calls an equivalent
kind of procedure (Corballis 2007).
Recursion is a blurred concept that can be confused with other similar
processes, such as iteration or hierarchical embedding (Martins and Fitch
2014). Iteration is the process of repeating a process a certain number of
7
times (Fitch 2010). Iteration neither necessarily involves a hierarchical
structure nor entails a structure based on self-similarity. On the other
hand, hierarchical structures always involve the embedding of elements
within other elements (Martins and Fitch 2014). Hierarchical structures
are not necessarily recursive structures. However, the opposite is true. In
particular, the ability to generate higher hierarchical levels beyond the one
which is already given is a relevant feature of recursion (Martins and
Fitch 2014).
One important class of recursive structures is fractals (Mandelbrot 1983).
These are structures that have the property of self-similarity. Fractals
exhibit the same pattern when observed at different levels of resolution
(Figure 1). Although fractals appear as highly complex hierarchical
structures, they can be generated by a small set of rules. This property is
another relevant aspect of recursion.
Figure 1 - Examples of fractal structures exhibiting self-similarity.
Recursion not only occurs at the physical and biological levels, but also
within the psychological and socio-cultural domains. Indeed, the only
feature that distinguishes human language from the languages of other
8
animals such as birds and dolphins appears to be recursion (Hauser et al.
2002). Humans can generate recursive sentences that embed other
sentences. This feature exponentially amplifies the power of human
language. The recursive process not only happens at the syntactical level
of the language, but also involves the conceptual levels of semantics and
pragmatics (Evans and Levinson 2009). It has even been proposed that
recursion is what distinguishes us as humans (Corballis 2011). In
particular, the capacity of embedding thoughts within other thoughts is
the key feature that could explain the astonishing capacities of the human
mind and human creativity (Hofstadter 1980).
2.2
Theories of levels
Many theoretical frameworks that describe reality from an ontological
point of view fall under the umbrella of the theory of levels, although they
usually have different names. Some examples are the hierarchy theory
(Pattee 1973; Allen and Starr 1982; Simon 1991), the theory of
integrative levels (Novikoff 1945; Feibleman 1954; Hartmann 2012),
transdisciplinarity (Nicolescu 2002) and the theory of levels of reality
(Poli 1998). All these theories describe reality in terms of hierarchical
organization. In particular, they all assume that reality can be regarded as
a hierarchical structure, divided into different levels. These theories claim
that the universe can be analysed at different levels of resolution along a
scale based on complexity. At the base of the scale there are atomic and
molecular physical structures, whereas at the top there are complex social
systems. Every level considers a particular discrete portion of this
9
hierarchical scale. Moreover, a specific level of reality is implied by the
interactions between components of the lower levels, and in turn
contributes to the formation of the higher levels (Feibleman 1954).
Although the concept of level is quite intuitive, its definition usually
changes depending on the researcher. However, all definitions consider
some
relevant
issues,
such
as
coordination
between
levels,
dependency/autonomy among levels and categorical closure of levels
(Poli 2001). Levels can be regarded as collections of units that interact
with one another, creating a coherent unitary structure at a particular point
within the hierarchical scale of reality (Pattee 1973). This definition
stresses the concept of dependency among levels, even though it does not
specify the nature of the units. Combining the ideas of the theories of
levels and systems, units that make up levels can be considered as
systems (Nicolescu 2002). Recursive ontology borrows this idea and
develops its implications.
Another relevant distinction between theories of levels is the fact that they
either consider levels as discrete or as continuous constructs. However, a
majority of researchers support the idea of discrete levels (Hartman 1952;
Pattee 1973; Poli 2009). This theoretical perspective is backed up by the
intuitive notion of the discrete unfolding of the structure of nature, where
different constructs – such as atoms, animals and human social systems –
show clear quantifiable differences. It is worth noting that, even if most of
the literature focuses on discrete levels, these can also be considered as
analogue constructs (Nicolescu 2002). This implies an infinite number of
hierarchical levels with slightly different amounts of complexity.
10
Regarding the type of levels, some theories suggest that all levels are of
the same type (Nicolescu 2002), while others claim that there are different
types of levels (Poli 2001; Hartmann 2012). This difference is crucial.
The former typology of theories considers reality as a single structure,
where all levels from the physical to the socio-cultural are considered
qualitatively identical. On the other hand, the latter typology divides
reality into more than one type of stratum. For example, Hartman divides
reality into four different strata (i.e., inorganic, organic, emotional,
cultural), which are considered qualitatively different (Hartman 1942).
The different strata can interact with each other and concur to compose all
of reality, even though they are intrinsically diverse (Minati et al. 2006).
A large number of rules governing the behaviour of levels has been
proposed (Feibleman 1954; Austin 1969). However, just a few of them
have been recognized as valid by the majority of the scientific
community. One rule generally acknowledged by all researchers is the
law of emergence. The law of emergence states that the properties of the
higher hierarchical levels emerge as the result of the interaction between
the components of the lower levels (Korn 2007). This concept, based on
the principle of self-organization of complex systems (Nicolis and
Prigogine 1977), is of primary importance for the development of RO.
3
Fundamentals of recursive ontology
This section is the main contribution of the article, since it introduces the
basic concepts of recursive ontology. Initially, it provides some general
11
laws that applies to the entire domain of being (3.1). Then, it proposes a
semi-formalised model of RO, delving into some details of the theory
(3.2). Finally, it introduces the basic principles of being (3.3).
3.1
General laws
This section introduces the most relevant laws associated with being.
These laws are intended as general rules that apply to every construct of
being, and to being as a whole. General laws of RO affect all of the levels
of being, and therefore span several disciplines such as physics, biology
and sociology. For this reason, they can be regarded as meta-laws which
transcend the specific domain of study. Even though general laws work
on a very abstract level, they are susceptible to empirical enquiry. General
laws cannot be verified, but can be falsified by finding valid domainspecific counterexamples.
The law of building blocks explains what are the elements that compose
reality (3.1.1). The law of recursive organization describes how those
elements are connected together, in order to form being (3.1.2). The law
of emergence clarifies how the properties of reality can emerge in a nonpredetermined fashion by interaction between elements of reality (3.1.3).
The law of isomorphism between levels analyses being from an
operational point of view (3.1.4).
3.1.1 Law of building blocks
12
The building blocks of being are systems with different degrees of
complexity.
This law describes the atomic components of being and claims that being
is made up of systems. A system is a set of interacting or interdependent
components forming an integrated whole (Backlund 2000). Every system
is characterized by inputs and outputs, which allow it to establish a
relationship with its environment, and to evolve according to new
information acquired.
Systems are content-independent. Indeed, they transcend their particular
domains. Systems are based on the relationships between different
components that exchange information, rather than on the content of the
information itself. A process can be described from a systemic point of
view, even if the specific content of the process is unknown. As a
consequence, systems can be used as high-level representations of
specific processes.
One evident implication of the law of building blocks, is that systems
transcend a particular domain and embrace the whole of reality
(Bertalanffy 1968). For instance, it is possible to describe a molecule, a
cell, a rock or even a society as a system. Generalizing, every item that
contributes to build up being – such as the aforementioned molecules,
rocks and cells – can each be described as a system. Therefore, all items
that make up reality are qualitatively equal, in the sense that they can all
be regarded as systems, which exchange information with their
environment. Being as a whole can be regarded as a system containing
13
systems, which exchange information with one another and which evolve
over time.
Of course, different systems in different domains manifest different
degrees of complexity. For example, a cell is more complex than a rock, a
human is more complex than a cell, and an entire society is a system far
more complex than a single human being. Complexity arises when
moving from the physical domain towards the biological and the cultural
levels (Feibleman 1954).
However, I still have precisely to define the concept of complexity. There
are many, sometimes opposing, definitions of complexity which come
from different disciplines such as information theory, computer science
and mathematics. RO adopts the definition of complexity proposed by the
theory of complex adaptive systems, which measures the complexity of a
system based on the following attributes:
number of components
non-linear relationships between components
capacity to memorize information
presence of feedback loops
non-linear relations between the system and its environment
sensitivity to initial condition (i.e., the butterfly effect)
capacity to adapt to the environment
capacity to influence the environment
14
3.1.2 Law of recursive organization
Systems connect with other systems at the same hierarchical level
of being, and build up more complex systems at higher
hierarchical levels in a recursive fashion.
This law answers the question of how being is organized. Although I have
hypothesized that systems are the building blocks of being, we now need
to uncover the process that allows being to be formed. This process is
recursive and is based on connections between systems at the same level.
Being is an extremely complex system itself. By definition, it is the most
complex system of all, since it embraces reality as a whole. Being is
organized into hierarchical levels that manifest different degrees of
complexity. Every level is made up of systems that have approximately
the same amount of complexity. These systems are connected together in
very complex networks.
Starting from the lowest level, it is possible to describe the formation of
being by following an apparently simple recursive process. Systems
which have the least amount of complexity belong to the lowest level.
These connect together and tend to form a new super-system at the next
higher level. The new super-system is more complex than its components
and of course cannot be reduced to its sub-systems (Prigogine and
Stengers 1984). Indeed, the establishment of new connections between
the components of the super-system, which are the systems of the lowest
level, adds extra complexity. Recursively, more super-systems tend to
connect with each other in order to form a super-super-system (Figure 2).
15
The process keeps going until it reaches the maximum level of
complexity, which corresponds to being itself.
Figure 2 - Systems connect with each other recursively in order to generate higher level
systems.
Generalizing, this recursive process unfolds at every hierarchical level of
being both on a horizontal and vertical basis. To explain, one might use
the example of atoms and molecules. Molecules, which populate the
molecular level of being, emerge as the associations between many
atoms, which make up the atomic level. Atoms are spread throughout a
horizontal plane, which represents the atomic level of being. A subset of
these atoms connect with each other in order to create a single molecule,
but at the same time, many other subsets of atoms in other portions of the
plane make up other molecules. This process unfolds horizontally
throughout the atomic level and recursively organizes many supersystems (i.e., molecules), which belong to the higher molecular level,
represented by a horizontal plane positioned above the atomic level. This
16
phenomenon is a many-many-many creation process. That is, it involves
many sets of many systems at a specific horizontal level, which are
projected vertically at the next hierarchical level of being to create many
super-systems. As a consequence, it is possible to claim that the total
number of super-systems which populate a higher hierarchical level of
being is less than the total number of components at the lower level. This
generative process is more than simple hierarchical embedding as
proposed by previous research (Pattee 1973; Salthe 1985; Ahl and Allen
1996). Rather, it can be regarded as a recursive process, since it involves
the embedding of constructs within other construct of the same type.
Specifically, the process involves the embedding of systems within other
systems, thanks to a generative process that continuously feeds the output
of its previous iterations (i.e., systems) into new instances of the same
generative mechanism.
This recursive process partially opposes the claims of some theories of
integrative levels (e.g., Poli 2001; Hartmann 2012), which divide being
into qualitatively different levels of reality, such as the material, mental
and social strata. These levels may sometimes overlap each other, but are
generally separated. On the other hand, RO claims that reality is a unitary
process that unfolds along a single scale from the lower towards the
higher levels. As a consequence, the different strata described by the
theories of levels proposed by Hartmann and Poli belong in RO to the
same recursive process and are manifestation of being at different vertical
levels. In particular, the physical level lies at the bottom of the scale.
Next, come the biological level, the psychological level and so on. For
17
RO, all these levels are not qualitatively different, just quantitatively
different. Specifically, the difference is based on the degree of complexity
of the systems which constitute the levels.
At the end of this section, a couple of questions still remain unanswered:
why is recursion the process followed by being to build up reality? Is it
possible to justify this process? Indeed, there might be several other
processes to build up being. For instance, new systems might be the result
of transformations of other existing systems, or it is possible to postulate
that radically different systems such as physical and biological systems
might be regarded as qualitatively diverse systems (Poli 2001; Hartmann
2012). However, all these strategies are far more expensive than recursion
in terms of resources used to shape reality. Indeed, the epistemological
justification of the law of recursive organization lies in the principle of
economy of resources, which will be thoroughly discussed later in the
article (3.3.1). This principle claims that systems at every level of being
employ the least amount of resources possible. In that regard, recursion is
the most resource-efficient process to form being, since it guarantees that
brand new systems are born from the simple association of already
existing lower level systems.
3.1.3 Law of emergence
The properties of being emerge moving from the lower towards
the higher hierarchical levels.
18
The law of emergence accounts for the properties of being. It is possible
to define a property as a behaviour of a system both expected or
unexpected. An expected behaviour is one we can predict based on the
knowledge we already have of the structure, organization and processes
of the system. On the contrary, an unexpected behaviour is one we cannot
predict based on the information we have.
The law of emergence states that the properties of being emerge while we
are moving towards the higher levels. However, a precise definition of the
term is needed, in order to avoid ambiguity. ‘Emerge’ in this context
means that a property unexpectedly arises from the interactions of the
systems at a certain level. In other words, most of the properties of being
are not determined a priori. The emergence of properties is the result of
the extra complexity added by the non-linear relationships established by
systems at specific hierarchical levels. As a consequence, the supersystem at the higher level manifests some unexpected properties that are
not predictable from its components.
For example, this is the case with the properties of consciousness, mind or
society. All of these can be regarded as emergent properties of being that
derive from the interactions of the components at lower levels. Mind can
be described as an emergent property resulting either from the complex
relationships between neurons (Minsky 1988) or from the non-linear
relationships between functional modules (Fodor 1983). Society is an
emergent property that arises from the interaction of single psychological
systems (i.e., individuals) connected together (Luhmann 1995).
19
Properties are the result of the complex structure of reality. These are a
by-product of the recursive process of organization of systems. Properties
are strictly related to the concept of complexity. The more complex the
level of being considered, the more unexpected the properties that might
emerge from the interactions of its components. Hence, a low level of
complexity allows fewer unexpected properties to emerge.
Emergence, complexity and chaos are all tied together. Complex systems
are systems which evolve on the edge of chaos, and therefore can be
called quasi-chaotic systems. There is a strong relationship between
quasi-chaotic systems and emergence, since emergent properties are a
peculiar aspect of complex systems. Being is characterised by emergent
properties, therefore it can be regarded as a hyper-complex system that
evolves on the edge of chaos. It neither follows a completely chaotic
dynamic, nor does it follow a completely deterministic path. Rather, being
is a quasi-chaotic system characterized by the emergence of its properties
based on the interactions between its components. The process of
emergence of properties entails an inner creativity of being as a whole,
which continuously renews its structures, patterns of organization and
processes. Indeed, reality can evolve and manifest unexpected forms of
organization
and
behaviours
that
otherwise,
imagining
a
deterministic/linear being, would be impossible.
3.1.4 Law of isomorphism between levels
20
All hierarchical levels of being can be described by the same
qualitative/quantitative models.
This law analyses being from an operational point of view. Specifically, it
indirectly states that all the hierarchical levels of being operate in a
similar manner. This is not an unexpected assumption, since we are using
systems to describe reality. Indeed, systems are
content-
independent constructs, which can be used to describe numerous abstract
processes, even if they are characterized by different contents .
The levels referred to in the law of isomorphism between levels are the
different vertical levels that build up being in a hierarchical fashion.
Levels show various differences between each other. Levels are
characterized by varying degrees of complexity; they are constituted by
different kinds of systems; and they are different in the domains they
span, since they represent diverse portions of reality. Some levels belong
to the physical domain, others to the biological, psychological, or social
domains.
However, all levels share a fundamental common feature. They are all
based on the same recursive process of connection of systems. Therefore,
it is possible to use the same model to describe all the different levels.
This is the core idea of systems theory (Bertalanffy 1968). Indeed, the
systemic approach can be regarded as a meta-description of reality based
on the interactions between the components of a general system.
Recursive ontology appears as a meta-theory of reality, which provides a
general framework for being. The framework is modular and can be filled
21
by many domain-specific theories that describe and analyse specific
portions of reality. Therefore, RO traces a general path that can be
progressively explored in more detail by domain-specific systemic
theories.
Thus, the main idea behind RO is that reality can be regarded as a
manifestation of a single recursive process, that gradually builds being in
its entirety, moving from one level of complexity to another. This process
is what unifies the different domains of reality such as the physical, the
biological, the cultural and the social.
3.2
A semi-formalised model of recursive ontology
This section introduces a first attempt at formalising the ideas and general
laws of RO. Initially, I define a recursive grammar that can thoroughly
represent the core concepts of RO (3.2.1). Then, I describe in more detail
how the systems that make up being are organized in networks, and how
they exchange information (3.2.2). Additionally, I present an ontological
journey from the bottom levels towards the top levels of being, in order to
describe the main ontological categories within the framework of RO
(3.2.3). Finally, I point out the difference between domain-specific and
domain-general laws (3.2.4).
3.2.1 Defining a recursive grammar
There are some striking similarities between language and being. They
both are extremely complex systems which can be described in terms of
22
structure, organization and process. Particularly, they both show a syntax
and a semantics. The syntax of being tells us how to generate more
complex systems starting from less complex systems. Indeed, the syntax
associated with being is a simple process that can produce all of reality.
On the other hand, the semantics of being informs us about the specific
contents and processes of the systems analysed. Therefore, syntax is
concerned with how reality unfolds, whether semantics considers what
reality consists of.
This isomorphism between being and language can be extended even
more. It is possible to trace a semi-formal representation of being based
on a generative grammar (Chomsky 1956). This generative grammar of
being, can generate all of reality, based on a recursive process. However,
in order to recognize the validity of this grammar, it is necessary to find a
valid mapping between the strings generated by the grammar and the real
constructs of being. In this sense, the strings produced by the grammar are
a model of being.
The grammar of being
is a quadruple
.
is a finite set of non-terminal symbols. These symbols represent
compound constructs that can be substituted by other symbols.
They are mapped onto higher level systems of being, which are
made of subsystems.
corresponds to the set of all systems which
make up being. Particularly, we have that
is a set of sets
, where the subscript
indicates the hierarchical level of the systems, and the superscript
23
indicates different instances of systems which are at the same
hierarchical level of being, since they have a similar degree of
complexity. For example, even though oxygen and hydrogen are
two different physical constructs, they can be regarded as two
instances of the same atomic level. It is interesting to notice that
the number of instances of systems at different levels is usually
diverse. Moreover, the highest hierarchical level
possible system
has just one
, that corresponds to being considered as a
whole.
is a finite set of terminal symbols. These symbols are the
elementary constructs of a language. They are mapped onto the
lowest level systems of being (i.e., the fundamental particles).
Particularly, we have
, where the subscript
indicates the lowest level system of the hierarchy, and the
superscript indicates different instances of systems at the same
lowest level.
is the set of production rules necessary to build the sentences of
the language. These rules are mapped onto the rules of
organization of being.
is always in the following form:
where * is the Kleene Star operator and
the set union operator.
The production rule states that the head should always have one
non-terminal symbol, whereas the body can have one or more
terminal and/or non-terminal symbols.
24
is the start symbol that belongs to the set
.
the first level systems of being. Formally, we have
is mapped onto
.
Considering the elements of the grammar presented above, it is possible
to formalise the recursive hierarchical organization of being through some
simple production rules. To represent these rules, I use the Augmented
Backus-Naur Form, which is a meta-language that allows an intuitive
representation of formal systems. It is possible to devise a simpler form of
the production rules by removing the different instances of possible
systems at the same level (i.e., removing the superscripts):
These production rules build all of being recursively and appear as a
formalization of the law of recursive organization. The higher level
systems are the product of the connections of at least two lower level
systems. In this manner, it is possible to produce all the complexity of
being by connecting together systems and recursively repeating the
process on many levels.
Of course, the actual production rules of being are far more complex than
these, if one considers different types of systems at the same hierarchical
level. Nevertheless, the basic process of production is uniform, and
25
therefore the production rules provided here are still valid. The only
substantive difference is the larger number of systems that can be
generated at a particular level by the generalized grammar. This process is
similar to the horizontal exploration of a single level, that reveals many
different systems which share more or less the same degree of
complexity. However, the formalization of this generalized process will
not be provided here.
The different sentences generated by the recursive grammar can be
represented as a tree. Indeed, this is another strategy to visualize being.
Every node of the tree corresponds to a specific sentence generated, and
every connection describes the relationships between two nodes. This
representation ignores the horizontal connections between nodes at the
same level of the tree, since it considers only the vertical parent-child
relationships. Even though this visual representation is incomplete, it is
quite informative about the structural hierarchies of being.
Time plays a central role in the generation of being, since the building up
of sentences happens in time. Given the finite amount of constituents in
the universe, an issue might arise if the process of generation was the only
one to take place. In this case, the number of higher level systems would
constantly increase. As time passes by, the generation of higher level
systems would increase exponentially, and in the end only systems with
maximum complexity which inhabit the top level of being would be
present. Obviously, this is not what happens in the real world where it is
possible to find instances of systems at every level of being. Furthermore,
the generative process does not guarantee the recombination of systems
26
which played the role of constituents for higher level systems. For this to
happen, it is necessary to introduce a process of breaking up of sentences,
which converts high-level systems into its components. To clarify the
breaking up process, it is possible to think of molecules that split into
their atomic components, or to the process of body decomposition which
breaks down organic substances into simpler form of matter. The
generative process and the breaking up process happen in time in a
balanced fashion, and work together so that new systems are born at any
time while others are decomposed into their components. This cyclic
process of generation and destruction is necessary to model being. First, it
allows being to continuously renovate its content by relying always on the
same raw materials. Secondly, it avoids the analyticity of the generation
of sentences, which would lead to an exponential growth of systems
inhabiting the higher levels of being.
3.2.2 Systems, networks and exchange of information
Even though the recursive grammar explains how the different levels of
being are formed from an abstract point of view, it remains unclear how
the different systems physically interact with each other. Every system is
an input/output processor that can be connected to other systems. Many
systems at the same level can connect with each other. The result is a nonlinear complex network, where the nodes correspond to the systems and
the links represent the connections between systems. Systems exchange
information with one another and coevolve. RO adopts the concept of
27
information as defined by thermodynamics: information is every kind of
event that can affect the state of a system.
If we consider an entire network as a system itself, we can shift our point
of view to a higher level. This new higher-level system, which is in turn a
network, can interact with other networks, in order to generate a supersystem, which results in a network of networks. This process iterates until
it reaches the top level, which corresponds to being considered as a
whole.
These networks are extremely complex systems that follow a quasichaotic dynamic. Their behaviour is unpredictable. However, complexity
does not depend on the specific content of the network; rather, it depends
on the overall non-linear structure as well as on the local connections.
This principle directly derives from systems theory and applies to being
as a whole. Structure and organization are the most important features of
reality, since they determine both the nature and the behaviour of being.
The exchange of information between systems allows being to evolve
from one state to another. Exchange of information directly affects
systems at every level. First, the exchange of information facilitates
change of the internal states of the systems. Secondly, it helps systems to
break old connections and to form new ones. These processes reverberate
within the entire recursive structure of being. The final result is the
emergence of unpredictable behaviours, constructs and properties, which
are a simple by-product of the exchange of information.
28
3.2.3 Levels, ontological categories and domains
Reality is organized in a complex hierarchical structure. Being can be
easily visualized in a network of networks arranged in a vertical fashion.
Complexity always increases moving from the lower towards the higher
levels. Although the concept of level is quite intuitive, we need formally
to define it in order to avoid ambiguity. I define a specific level of being
as the set of all the systems that manifest a similar degree of complexity
and similar emergent properties. The levels correspond to iso-complex
surfaces of being. In other words, if we could plot all systems of being in
a graph in which the vertical axis represents complexity, a level would be
represented by a horizontal slice of the graph, where all systems with the
same level of complexity lie. Of course, different systems characterised
by different structures serving different functions can be iso-complex,
since complexity is totally content-independent. The levels are discrete,
since the passage from one level to the next higher or lower level involves
a discrete change in the degree of complexity, as well as a manifestation
of some emergent properties. Higher hierarchical levels inherit the
properties of lower levels.
It is possible to explore being following a vertical and a horizontal path.
The former analyses being from the lower levels straight to the upper
levels considering every level at each step. On the contrary, the horizontal
approach explores a single level and reveals all those systems at a specific
level with a certain amount of complexity. The vertical approach is a
synthetic exploration, while the horizontal approach is an analytic
exploration.
29
Being is vertically divided into macro-categories which I term ontological
categories. The definition of ontological categories that I use here is
different from the traditional philosophical definitions. For RO,
ontological categories are groups of contiguous levels which present an
overall similar set of structures, patterns of organization and processes.
Ontological categories span many levels of being, since they are
extremely complex elements of reality. Different ontological categories
manifest radical different emergent properties.
Indeed, the passage from one ontological category to another is a discrete
quantum leap that involves an overall reorganization of the systems which
inhabit the new category. This passage is a discontinuity of reality, made
possible by new emergent properties that completely revolutionize the
behaviour of being. Although all levels within an ontological category
have different degrees of complexity, they show similar structures,
behaviours and properties overall. In other words, the differences between
levels within the same ontological category are far smaller than the
differences between levels of different categories. Even though there are
significant differences between different ontological categories, the
overall recursive structure and the properties entailed by the general laws
are still the same for every category. This guarantees the self-similarity of
being at every level.
The ontological categories considered by RO are the physical, the
biological, the psychological and the socio-cultural (Figure.3). The
physical category embraces all physical systems. This ontological
category is structured in hierarchical levels that show different amounts of
30
complexity. Starting from scratch, elementary particles build up protons,
electrons and neutrons. These new particles connected together generate
atoms, which in turn create molecules. This process keeps going until it
reaches a threshold which allows chemistry to turn into biology. Indeed,
the physical category acts as the basis for the biological category.
The biological category arises when biological replicators emerge.
Replicators are anything in the universe of which copies are made
(Dawkins 1999). DNA is the main replicator within the biological
category. Replicators allow the evolutionary process to unfold because
they mutate over time and are selected depending on their fitness. The
biological category considers hierarchical constructs such as cells, organ
and animals.
The psychological category arises when mind emerges. Mind is an
emergent property that arises by the non-linear local interactions of a
large number of neurons (Minsky 1988). The psychological level
considers constructs such as perception, memory, and different functional
modules of mind (Fodor 1983) that allow an individual to interact with its
environment.
The socio-cultural category arises when cultural replicators emerge.
These are called memes (Dawkins 2006) and are pattern of information
that can spread within a society. Memes are also characterised by an
evolutionary process. The socio-cultural domain considers constructs
such as society and philosophy. It is worth remembering that the four
ontological categories altogether represent the entirety of being.
31
Summarizing, the ontological categories are vertically distributed along a
complexity scale (Fig.3). Threshold properties allow being to pass from
one category to another. In particular, the passage from the physical
category to the biological category is made possible by the emergence of
biological replicators. The passage from the biological category to the
psychological is possible thanks to the emergence of mind. Finally, the
last threshold, that allows the passage from the psychological to the sociocultural category, is the emergence of cultural replicators.
Figure 3 – The four ontological categories that make up being, and the threshold
properties which divide them
(i.e., replicators, mind, memes).
Another useful concept of RO is the idea of domain. Domains are sets of
functionally coherent systems that can transcend the boundaries of
ontological categories. They are portions of being extended in both the
vertical and horizontal directions. Domains can embrace many levels and
32
even more than one ontological category. An example of a domain is
music. Music is a coherent functional model of reality that embraces all
four ontological levels: the physical, the biological, the psychological and
the socio-cultural. Music is made possible thanks to physical pressure
waves, is encoded in our brains at the neuronal level, is processed by
some functional modules of mind, and happens to be a socio-cultural
construct.
In conclusion, being is organized into levels, ontological categories and
domains (Table 1). In theory, each of these constructs contains the entire
structure of being. This is possible thanks to the self-similarity of being.
Indeed, reality shows a fractal structure entailed by the recursive process
of formation. As a consequence, every component is structurally similar
to the whole.
33
Constructs of being
Definition
Examples
Level
Set of all the systems which
molecules, animals,
have a similar degree of
ecosystems.
complexity and similar
emergent properties.
Ontological category
Group of contiguous levels
physical, biological,
which have similar structures,
psychological, socio-
patterns of organization and
cultural
processes.
Domain
Set of functionally coherent
music, language
systems that can transcend the
boundaries of ontological
categories.
Table 1 – Definitions and examples of the main constructs of being.
3.2.4 Domain-specific and domain-general laws
Being is characterized by two kinds of laws: domain-general and domainspecific laws. The former typology of laws transcends the specific domain
of interest and applies to reality as a whole. On the contrary, the second
typology of laws only applies to specific domains.
The domain-general laws correspond to the four general rules previously
stated (3.1). These laws are extremely important, since they guarantee
both the recursive structure and the behaviour of being. Indeed, by acting
on a global scale, domain-general laws allow a complete isomorphism
between different domains. Moreover, domain-general laws are the
34
operational manifestation of the recursive structure of being, and apply at
each vertical level of reality. The structure as well as the pattern of
organization of being is inherently shaped by these laws. Domain-general
laws guarantee the fractal structure of being as well. Every level is at the
same time a parent of some lower level and a child of some higher level,
and expresses the same inner structure at different levels of resolution.
Domain-specific laws only apply on a local basis and cannot be
generalized. These laws focus on small regions of being and trace the
particular behaviours of one specific domain. Indeed, every domain is
characterized by domain-specific laws that are exclusive to that domain
and contribute to the uniqueness of the domain itself. Domain-specific
laws are qualitatively different from domain-general laws. The difference
lies in the diverse scope of the two kinds of law. However, sometimes
domain-specific laws apply to more than a single domain. Thus, the
distinction between the two typologies becomes blurred. Rather, it
appears that laws can have greater or lesser specificity depending on the
number of domains to which they apply. Domain-specific and domaingeneral laws can be regarded as two extremes of a continuous scale that
measures the number of domains spanned by a single law. Therefore,
laws are distributed on that scale depending on the number of domains
they govern.
Both domain-general and domain-specific laws contribute to shape
reality. However, their roles are quite different. Domain-general laws
guarantee an overall symmetry of being, and a consistent structure of
reality. On the other hand, domain-specific laws tend to amplify the
35
differences between different domains of being. The two processes
oppose each other. A metaphor taken from physics clarifies the
differences. Domain-general laws involve a centripetal process, which
tends to flatten the differences between the domains of reality. Domainspecific laws involve a centrifugal process, which sharpens the
differences between domains. However, only a perfect equilibrium
between the two opposing processes guarantees both the overall fractal
similarity of reality and the specific diversity between domains.
3.3
Principles of recursive ontology
This section introduces some basic principles of RO that can be inferred
by direct observation of being. Of course, it is not possible entirely to
demonstrate these principles, nor it is possible entirely to reject them.
However, they can be treated as a plausible set of features that explain
some of the constructs involved in being such as structure, organization
and semantics.
It is worth remembering that there is a significant difference between
principles and laws. Principles are generalizations which arise from
induction. Laws are derived using principles and appear in the form of
statements about being. Thus, principle are first sources of knowledge
from which it is possible to derive other operational statements (i.e.,
laws).
The section introduces three fundamental principles of being. The
principle of economy of resources describes the relationships between
36
systems of being and the resources allocated (3.3.1). The principle of
digital infinity delves into the formation process of systems (3.3.1).
Finally, the principle of compositionality analyses the semantic of
systems in relation to their components.
There is an evident isomorphism between RO and the domain of
language, as stated above (3.2.1). Two of these principles (i.e., digital
infinity and compositionality) are directly inspired by linguistics
(Chomsky 1991). This analogy is possible thanks to the law of
isomorphism between levels.
3.3.1 Principle of economy of resources
Systems at every level of being tend to use the least amount of
resources possible.
This is a principle that reverberates at every level of being. The principle
is highly represented in all the physical, biological, psychological and
socio-cultural ontological categories. The principle of economy of
resources is well known in physics. Physical systems always tend to reach
states of minimum energy (i.e., equilibrium). Every physical system uses
the least amount of information possible. The principle is also true within
the biological category. Evolution usually rewards the individuals that are
most energy efficient, because they need a smaller quantity of food in
order to survive. The same is true at the genetic level as well. The entire
genetic code is based on just four bases: adenine, cytosine, guanine and
thymine. Here, the application of the principle of economy of resources is
37
straightforward. Highly complex systems such as plants, animals and
humans are the result of the combinations of just four elements.
Language is another example of a domain that exploits the principle of
economy of resources. Even though human alphabets contain only a small
number of symbols, we, as humans, are able to express a potentially
infinite number of ideas and concepts. Likewise, society follows the
principle of economy of resources. Humans are organized in highly
efficient
clusters which guarantees the economy of resources.
Furthermore, the history of society presents a continuous improvement of
the way we use resources in order to optimize the results of our processes.
In this sense, it is possible to define being as a Humboldt system which
makes infinite use of finite means.
These are just a few examples of the ubiquitous principle of economy of
resources within different domains of reality. Even though I have isolated
the principle, it is still unclear why the entire spectrum of reality is
dominated by this process of optimization. One possible answer is that the
principle of economy of resources is the only process that allow the
formation of complex systems. Since all systems at every level are finite
constructs, they cannot process and/or store too much information,
otherwise they would just desegregate and/or never gain a high level of
complexity. As a consequence, it is possible that this principle provides
the only possible basis in order to guarantee the emergence of complex
systems. Of course, this is just a hypothesis that requires further research.
38
3.3.2 Principle of digital infinity
Irreducible atomic elements of being are combined to produce an
infinite range of systems at different levels.
This principle is an operational instantiation of the principle of economy
of resources. The principle claims that an infinite number of constructs
can be formed based on a set of finite (atomic) particles. This idea
guarantees a highly efficient generation of systems. The process is
directly related to the linguistic domain, since it supports the idea of a
generative grammar of being based on fundamental particles.
The atomic particles of being at the lowest level coincide with the
elementary particles of the physical ontological category. Therefore,
starting from these constructs it is possible to build up the whole of being.
The strategy to generate all of reality from the lowest level has been
already covered in this article (3.2.1), and corresponds to the recursive
grammar of the RO.
It is worth remembering that digital infinity is a phenomenon that happens
at every level of being. This implies that it is possible to define different
‘virtual’ atomic particles depending on the domain of interest. For
example, in music single tones can be regarded as the atomic particles
that, combined together, generate complete musical statements. The same
is true also for DNA. If the four genetic bases were regarded as
fundamental particles, it would be possible to apply generative rules,
which allow the production of the entire genome of a single individual.
39
Generalizing, it is possible to claim that every domain has its own
domain-specific atomic particles. Of course, these are not univocally
determined, since every specific level of the domain can be considered as
the basic level of generation. Therefore, the process directly transfers the
act of determining the atomic particles of a certain vertical construct to
the beholder. For example, if we analyse music at the socio-cultural level
it is possible to consider entire musical pieces, rather than single tones, as
fundamental particles. This subjective approach is obviously entailed by
the self-similarity of being. As a consequence, there are as many possible
definitions of elementary particles of a domain as there are levels of
analysis. However, this is not a problem at all, since it is an organic
element of being itself.
Likewise, it is not strange that the principle of digital infinity is derived
from the domain of language. In linguistics, this principle guarantees the
generation of infinite meanings from a finite set of symbols. The
similarity between being and language is straightforward, and yet again
can be implied by the part-whole self-similarity of being. Even though
language is a part of reality, its structure is isomorphic with the structure
of being as a whole. Hence, it is possible to extend the general principle
of digital infinity to the largest possible domain, being. Of course, this
principle is a domain-general feature of language that can be applied to
being, and differs from many other domain-specific rules of language,
which cannot be directly transferred to being as a whole.
3.3.3 Principle of compositionality
40
The properties of systems at higher levels depend directly on the
systems which constitute them.
This principle is based on the idea that compound structures rely on the
structure and properties of their components. The process is quite intuitive
and is true both for simple and complex systems. Higher level systems
cannot be reduced to the sum of their components. Nonetheless, their
properties are obviously dependent both on their components and on the
interactions established by their components.
The principle of compositionality is true at every level of being, and
guarantees that the complexity and the number of emerging properties of
a high-level system grows exponentially. High-level systems acquire such
a large amount of complexity that their behaviour is not predictable any
more, though it can yet be deterministic, since systems always follow
deterministic laws. Thus, there is a threshold based on the amount of
complexity that differentiates systems which show a linear behaviour
from systems which show a quasi-chaotic behaviour.
There are endless examples that support the validity of the principle of
compositionality within all domains of reality. All physical systems
depend on their components. For example, molecules derive their
properties from the atoms of which they are composed. Biological
systems depend on their components as well. For instance, the cell
directly relies on the interactions of its components such as the
membrane, organelles, proteins and nucleic acids. The same is true also
for humans considered as single systems. From a biological point of view,
every human is the product of the interactions between different
41
apparatuses such as the respiratory apparatus, the nervous system and the
circulatory system.
At the psychological level, the mind is an example of a complex system
which is based on its components. Indeed, the mind depends on the
activity of individual neurons and on their interconnections. Society is yet
another example, since it relies on individuals and on their exchanges of
information. At the cultural level, I propose the examples of music and
language. Music is an extremely intricate system, which is the result of
the interactions between its components. These components are musical
memes that interact with each other in order to create complete musical
statements (Jan 2007). Likewise, a sentence of natural language derives
its overall meaning from the words that contributes to build the sentence
up.
The principle of compositionality reinforces the overall idea of selfsimilarity of being based on the ubiquitous presence of isomorphism
between domains and levels. Indeed, all domains and levels exhibit the
feature of dependency on their components.
4
Discussion
This section provides an assessment of recursive ontology. First, it
outlines the principal findings that emerge from the RO (4.1). Secondly, it
analyses the possible implications and applications of the RO (4.2).
Finally, it discusses the theoretical/methodological limitations of the
article and traces avenue for future research (4.3).
42
4.1
Summary of findings
The article proposed a new logical framework to describe reality, by
providing a general ontology based on the concepts of recursion, complex
systems and levels of reality. Recursive ontology claims that the all of
reality can be regarded as the manifestation of a single process of
construction.
RO states that all of being is governed by four general laws that apply at
all levels of reality:
The law of building blocks claims that being is composed of
systems, characterized by different levels of complexity. This law
is derived from systems theory (Bertalanffy 1968), which analyses
the universe in terms of connected systems.
The law of recursive organization states that being is made up of
hierarchical levels, which consist of networks of systems
recursively connected at different levels. Although RO rejects the
idea of multiple parallel strata of reality, the law of recursive
organization is directly related to the theory of levels (Poli 2001;
Hartmann 2012).
The law of emergence guarantees that the properties of being
spontaneously arise while moving from the lower towards the
higher levels. This law is strictly related to chaos-theory and to the
inner nature of complex systems (Prigogine and Stengers 1984).
43
The law of isomorphism between levels states that a single
theoretical model can be used to describe different levels of
reality. This law derives from principles of systems theory.
This article has provided a semi-formalised recursive grammar inspired
by linguistics (Chomsky 2002). This grammar can be used in order
recursively to generate all of being. As a consequence, a direct parallelism
between being and language has been postulated.
I have suggested a new definition of levels, ontological categories and
domains, one that is completely different from traditional philosophical
definitions as well as from the definition provided by researchers of the
theory of levels. Indeed, a level is the set of all the systems that share a
similar amount of complexity and similar emergent properties. An
ontological category is a set of contiguous vertical levels which manifests
similar structures, patterns of organization and processes. There are four
ontological categories which, from the least to the most complex, are the
physical, the biological, the psychological and the socio-cultural. Some
threshold properties allow the passage from one ontological category to
another. Those properties are: biological replicators, mind and cultural
replicators. A domain is a coherent set of systems arranged together in
order to form a functional module of being. The systems encompassed by
a domain can span several levels and categories.
Additionally, I have defined domain-specific and domain-general laws.
The first typology applies locally to a single domain of reality, whereas
the second has a universal impact, since it affects all of being.
44
Finally, three basic principles have been identified. These three principles
are the foundations of RO and all laws can be derived from them:
The principle of economy of resources claims that systems at all
levels tend to use the least amount of resources possible.
The principle of digital infinity claims that an infinite number of
systems at every level of reality are generated by few irreducible
elementary particles. This principle is derived from linguistics
(Chomsky 1991).
The principle of compositionality states that the properties of
systems directly depend on their components. This principle is yet
again derived from linguistics and systems theory.
4.2
Implications and applications
RO has relevant implications and applications in many domains. RO
changes the view we have of reality: it promotes a trans-disciplinary study
of being and can be regarded as the basis for future domain-specific
theories.
RO radically changes the current view of reality as a heterogeneous group
of different constructs not related one another. Indeed, RO reduces all the
apparent differences between domains to a common general structure. RO
considers the various different levels, domains and ontological categories
as different manifestations of a single process of organization. Hence,
reality appears as a self-similar structure which manifests the same
structure at different levels of resolution.
45
RO actively encourages a trans-disciplinary exploration of reality. All the
different ontological categories of being – the physical, the biological, the
psychological and the socio-cultural – are regarded as different
manifestations of a single recursive process. This implies that the transdisciplinary approach is inherently embedded within RO.
RO can be used as a general framework to develop domain-specific
theories. Indeed, RO can act as a meta-theory that provides tools to
develop domain-specific theories which can describe society, mind,
language and music. RO provides general principles and domain-general
laws that can be considered as a foundation for studies of specific
domains. In practice, the principles and the laws of RO can help domainspecific theories to avoid a number of epistemological errors. First, by
considering the notions proposed by RO, a domain-specific theory would
be prevented from being too reductionist. Although reductionism has
worked for centuries in several fields, it is now time to use the systemic
approach to model reality, due to the complexity of most systems studied
nowadays. Second, a domain-specific theory which follows the notions of
RO would never be detached from other theories, therefore never losing
track of the bigger picture. Too often domain-specific theories are so
specific and so much focused on an extremely small set of phenomena to
result completely disconnected from other theories. On the other hand,
RO promotes integration between theories which describe systems which
are horizontally and vertically adjacent in the structure of being. The long
term objective of RO is to formalise a series of domain-specific theories
each of which covers a section of being and it is connected with all other
46
neighbour theories. A metaphor for this would be a puzzle in which each
piece covers a part of the hidden picture and it is connected with all other
adjacent pieces both vertically and horizontally. All these theories
although radically different in terms of low-level details, would all follow
the general principles and laws of RO.
4.3
Limitations and directions for future research
This article manifests both theoretical and methodological limitations.
First, it is difficult to prove the empirical validity of RO. Second, this
overview lacks specific case studies that could help to support the
hypothesis stated within the theoretical framework.
It is difficult to demonstrate the hypotheses stated by RO. The framework
is so broad that is almost unthinkable to devise some experiments that
could ultimately support the overall theory. However, it is possible to
address the complexity of being by dividing it into different domains.
Then, one can set up specific experiments that cover just a part of being.
Finally, one can analyse the results of the experiments within the different
domains and come up with a possible answer regarding the validity of
RO.
The present article lacks an extensive analysis of case studies that could
support RO. Indeed, the paper sporadically presented pragmatic
examples, which examined the possible implications of RO from an
empirical perspective. However, I preferred to propose the theory from a
47
more abstract point of view in order to provide an initial overview of the
framework.
Of course, future research is necessary. In this sense, I will improve and
formalise the core ideas of RO. Next, I will develop domain-specific
theories of music, mind and society based on RO.
References
Ahl V, Allen T F (1996) Hierarchy theory: a vision, vocabulary and
epistemology. Columbia University Press, New York
Allen T F, Starr T B (1982) Hierarchy: perspectives for ecological
complexity. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Austin D (1969) The theory of integrative levels reconsidered as the basis
of
a
general
classification. In:
Classification
Research
Group,
Classification and information control. Library Association London, pp
81-95
Backlund A (2000) The definition of system. Kybernetes 29(4): 444-451
Bertalanffy von L (1968)
General system theory: Foundations,
development, applications. Braziller, New York
Brown R, Glazebrook J F, Baianu I C(2007) A conceptual construction
of complexity levels theory in spacetime categorical ontology: non-
48
abelian algebraic topology, many-valued logics and dynamic systems.
Axiomathes 17(3-4): 409-493
Capra F (1996) The web of life: A new scientific understanding of living
systems. Random House LLC, New York
Chomsky
N
(1956)
Three
models
for
the
description
of
language. Information Theory, IRE Transactions on 2(3): 113-124
Chomsky N (2002) Syntactic structures. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin
Chomsky N (1991) Linguistics and cognitive science: problems and
mysteries. In: Kasher A (ed) The Chomskyan turn. Blackwell, Hoboken
Corballis M C (2007) Recursion, language, and starlings. Cognitive
Science 31(4): 697-704
Corballis M C (2011) The recursive mind: The origins of human
language, thought, and civilization. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Dawkins R (2006) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Dawkins R (1999) The extended phenotype: The long reach of the gene.
Oxford University Press, Oxford
49
Evans N, Stephen C L (2009) The myth of language universals: Language
diversity and its importance for cognitive science. Behavioral and brain
sciences 32(5): 429-448
Everett D L (2009) Pirahã culture and grammar: A response to some
criticisms. Language 85(2): 405-442
Feibleman J K (1954) Theory of integrative levels. British journal for the
philosophy of science 5(17): 59-6
Fitch W T (2010) Three meanings of ‘recursion’: key distinctions for
biolinguistics. In: Larson R K, Deprez V, Yamakido H (ed) The evolution
of human language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Fodor J A (1983) The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty
psychology. MIT press, Cambridge
Grossmann R (1983) The categorial structure of the world. Indiana
University Press, Bloomington
Hartmann N (2012) New ways of ontology. Transaction Publishers,
Piscataway
50
Hauser M D. Chomsky N , Fitch W T (2002) The faculty of language:
What is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?. Science 298(5598): 15691579
Hofstadter D R (1980) Goedel, Escher, Bach: an eternal golden braid.
Penguin, London
Jan S B (2007) The memetics of music: A neo-Darwinian view of musical
structure and culture. Ashgate Publishing, Farnham
Korn J (2007) Systems view, emergence and complexity. Kybernetes
36(5/6): 776-790
Koschmann T (2010) On the universality of recursion. Lingua 120(12):
2691-2694
Luhmann N (1995) Social systems. Stanford University Press, Redwood
Mandelbrot B B (1983) The fractal geometry of nature. Macmillan,
London.
Martins M J, Fitch W T (2014) Investigating recursion within a domaingeneral framework. In: Lowenthal F, Lefebvre L (ed) Language and
recursion. Springer, New York
51
Minati G, Pessa E, Abram M R (eds) (2006) Systemics of emergence:
research and development. Springer, New York
Minsky M (1988) Society of mind. Simon and Schuster, New York
Nicolescu B (2002) Manifesto of transdisciplinarity. Suny, Albany
Nicolis G, Prigogine I (1977) Self-organization in nonequilibrium
systems. Wiley, Hoboken
Novikoff A B (1945) The concept of integrative levels and
biology. Science 101(2618): 209-215
Pattee H H (eds) (1973) Hierarchy theory: the challenge of complex
systems. Braziller, New York
Pinker S, Jackendoff R (2005) The faculty of language: what's special
about it?. Cognition 95(2): 201-236
Poli R (1998) Levels. Axiomathes 9(1-2): 197-211
Poli R (2001) The basic problem of the theory of levels of
reality. Axiomathes 12(3): 261-283
Poli R (2009) Two theories of levels of reality. In dialogue with Barsab
Nicolescu. Transdisciplinarity in science and religion 6: 135-150
52
Progogine I, Stengers I (1984) Order out of chaos: Man’s new dialogue
with nature. Bantam books, New York
Salthe S N (1985) Evolving hierarchical systems: Their structure and
representation. Columbia University Press, New York
Shannon C E (1948) A mathematical theory of communication.” Bell
system technical journal 27: 379-423.
Simon H A (1991) The architecture of complexity. Springer, New York
53