Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
10 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
William of Ockham's concept of mental language, explored alongside perspectives from Wittgenstein and Fodor, asserts that mental language is a legitimate form of language characterized by its own syntax and semantics. Ockham's analysis suggests that mental concepts represent meaning independently of spoken or written languages, which rely on social conventions for signification. This paper examines the distinctions between these forms of language, ultimately defending the claim that mental language possesses qualities of formal languages despite critiques regarding its private nature.
Analytica - Revista de Filosofia
Uma das principais teses de meu livro Le discours intérieur. De Platon à Guillaume d'Ockham era a de que, estritamente falando, a ideia de linguagem mental tinha origem com Guilherme de Ockham, entre o fim da segunda e o início da terceira década do século XIV. Em um artigo recente, no entanto, Peter King defende que "Abelardo foi o autor da primeira teoria plenamente desenvolvida da linguagem mental na Idade Media". Neste artigo gostaria de responder à afirmação de King, e de indicar as diferenças extremamente significantes que há entre as posições de Abelardo e de Ockham sobre a linguagem mental. One of the main tenets of my book Le discours intérieur. De Platon à Guillaume d'Ockham was that strictly speaking, the idea of mental language originated with William of Ockham in the late 1310s and early 1320s. In a recent paper, however, Peter King claims that "Abelard was the author of the first full-fledged theory of mental language in the Middle Ages". In...
Logos & Episteme, 2018
praises Panaccio's 1999 monograph as "more actual than ever" and with a superb translation provides a proof of concept: "Mental Language" translates the original title ("Discours Intérieur") and expresses the same concept. In one sense, the work is actual because The Language of Thought (1975) by the late Jerry A. Fodor, whom Panaccio refers to by name over thirty times, was reformulated by Fodor into LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited (2008). Fodor's thesis is ahistorical, but Panaccio wants to show "striking" historical resemblances (2). In another sense, the translation is actual because "quite a lot of research" has been done in the history of the idea of a mental language since Panaccio's original work (229). The book's ten chapters are divided into three parts: "The Sources" (chs. 1-4), "Thirteenth-Century Controversies" (chs. 5-8), and "The Via Moderna" (chs. 9-10).
2021
This is a screen-friendly version of the document. For the print version, please visit https://orbilu.uni.lu/handle/10993/47684 Comments are very welcome! This dissertation is concerned with the relation between mind and language. Parts I and II of the document deal with the impact of language on thought, while the concluding Part III investigates into the scope of language and thought respectively. In Part I it is shown that thought is not independent of language. This is done by applying an analogue of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Private Language Argument to the domain of reasoning, i.e., an important subset of our conscious cognitive processes. The resulting Private Reasoning Argument leads to the conclusion that reasoning is not available for a creature which does not master a public language. Part II is concerned with linguistic relativity and argues that a prevalent motivation for holding linguistic relativity theories is built on mistaken assumptions about the inseparability of language and culture. This wrongheaded picture is criticized by discussing two constructed languages, namely Klingon and Esperanto. Part III is guided by analysis and discussion of John Searle’s Principle of Expressibility, according to which whatever can be thought can also be said. Probing this principle and potential problem cases will lead to the conclusion that, indeed, nothing we can think is in principle ineffable.
Filosofia Unisinos – Unisinos Journal of Philosophy, 2021
I will defend the claim that we need to differentiate between thinking and reasoning in order to make progress in understanding the intricate relation between language and mind. The distinction between thinking and reasoning will allow us to apply a structural equivalent of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Private Language Argument to the domain of mind and language. This argumentative strategy enables us to show that and how a certain subcategory of cognitive processes, namely reasoning, is constitutively dependent on language. The final outcome and claim of this paper can be summarized as follows: We can think without language, but we cannot reason without language. While this still leaves several questions about the relation between mind and language unanswered, I hold that the insights defended in this paper provide the basis and proper framework for further investigation about the relationship between language and the mind. Keywords: Private language argument, Wittgenstein, thought/mind and language, reasoning, linguistic relativity, non-linguistic cognition.
ENGLISH LINGUISTICS, 1992
Reviewed by ISAO HiGASHIMORI, Kyoto Women's University* ' language of thought' (Fodor (1983)). A mental representation can be used 6 Smith (1990) interestingly analyses certain 'present tense' uses as interpretive. 7 Fodor's claim of a 'language of thought' is still criticized by some papers such as Churchland and Churchiand (1990). 8 Jackendoff (1990: 39-40) strongly attacks Fodorean noncompositional lexical concepts. 9 Sperber and Wilson (1986: Ch. 2) claim that all the deductive rules used in information processing are elimination rules, but Gazdar and Good (1982) have argued that this claim is too restrictive. (Sperber and Wilson (1986: Ch. 2) provide arguments against Gazdar and Good.
Topoi, 1997
In this paper, Ockham's theory of an ideal language of thought is used to illuminate problems of interpretation of his theory of truth. The twentieth century idea of logical form is used for finding out what kinds of atomic sentences there are in Ockham's mental language. It turns out that not only the theory of modes of supposition, but also the theory of supposition in general is insufficient as a full theory of truth. Rather, the theory of supposition is a theory of reference, which can help in the determination of truth values within the scope of simple predications. Outside this area, there are interesting types of sentences, whose truth does not depend on whether the terms supposit for the same things or not for the same things.
Philosophical Papers: Journal of the Department of Philosophy, University of North Bengal, 2007
Cahiers de l'ACEDLE, 2024
India Review, 2018
Bollettino dei Musei Comunali di Roma, 2023
The Open Public Health Journal
Revista de Geociências do Nordeste, 2021
Autoctonía. Revista de Ciencias Sociales e Historia, 2025
Physical Review Letters, 1997
Livro de Resumos da VII Simpósio de Estrutura Eletrônica e Dinâmica Molecular, 2018
Bulletin of the Chemical Society of Japan, 1985
Healthcare Quarterly, 2006
Journal of Fungi, 2022