Theory Beyond the Codes: tbc048
Date Published: 2/5/2013
www.ctheory.net/articles.aspx?id=717
Arthur and Marilouise Kroker, Editors
THEORY BEYOND THE CODES
Automated Labor: The 'New Aesthetic' and Immaterial
Physicality
Michael Betancourt
In 'The Fragment on Machines' Karl Marx laid out a series of logical propositions about
machine-enabled labor that appears to suggest the elimination of the living labor (human
agency) required by these machines; however, this interpretation is obviously incorrect when the
assumptions and context that produced his theorization are taken into consideration. Automated
labor is a fundamental shift in the nature of value production, one that is potentially destabilizing
to the entire capitalist productive system, revealing the inherent incompatibility between digital
capitalism and social reproduction, not simply a matter of economic or class structure, but of
machinic relations orchestrated by the different degrees of human agency required -- greater
and lesser control produced, maintained and reified by how digital capitalism and the ideology of
the digital reinforce each other through technology.
I
James Bridle's 'new aesthetic,' presented as an online research project in 2011 and 2012,[1]
suggests a physicalization of what was/is more commonly purely digital -- a realization of
immateriality as physicality. It traces similar aesthetic developments as earlier exhibitions such
as Post-Digital Painting did in 2002.[2] His 'new aesthetic' collects examples where automated
production becomes a tangible dimension of human society, ranging from the autonomous
action of Google Street View's face-blurring algorithm to the translation of bitmaps into
decorative textile patterns. The particular sense this collection documents is a concerted effort
at realizing and acknowledging the digital nature not only of the immaterial 'space' produced by
computers and algorithmic systems (the results of digital automation), but the transfer of these
autonomously produced artifacts into the physical realm. The automated machine labor
revealed by this project is a symptom of the emergent autonomous production it documents,
revealing the paradox of automation, labor, and value production: the cultural, historical, and
aesthetic ruptures between automation and the (traditional) conceptual mappings of human
society.
Within Bridle's archive there are several overlapping categories of material: (1) autonomously
generated images that contain markers of the digital such as glitches of various types (encoding
errors, algorithmic misidentifications of faces, pixilation / scan lines / digital noise, etc.); (2)
physical constructions employing signifiers of digital forms (blocky pixel-imitating construction,
scanlines, etc.); (3) translations of digital forms into a visual style (QR codes, low resolution
bitmaps, etc.); (4) dynamic, interactive data visualizations (art installations such as Pixels Per
Person by Carina Ow that visualizes Wi-Fi usage, biometric scanners, and augmented reality -the Google Glass project is another prime example). These groupings are neither exhaustive
nor mutually exclusive. While there are points of contact and degrees of overlap between them,
they articulate general tendencies in the formal appearance of digital technology, and document
an apparent paradox: immaterial physicality.
Bridle's 'new aesthetic' also contains examples of camouflage used to 'hide' from digital military
systems. These images demonstrate a reorientation of physical structures towards their
engagement with digital technology, specifically designed to resemble the artifacts and forms of
digital imaging. Unlike earlier approaches that addressed specifically human recognition and
capabilities, contemporary camouflage mimics the pixilation of digital imagery -- it is addressing
not human sight, but the automated recognition systems of machines and the digital cameras
that accompany them. This shift from a primary concern with human recognition to the
disruption of machine vision is a transformation of degree and locus of address, mirroring the
shifts posed by the 'new aesthetic' generally.
The importance of primitive accumulation to capitalist expansion -- the annexing of domains
without required payments commonly given to labor -- assumes a consumptive dimension in the
latter half of the twentieth century as the technologies employed in war become increasingly
expensive and (self)destructive; thus, war as a productive stimulus for capitalist expansion both
through productive demand and through primitive accumulation (which the Iraq War under
President Bush so clearly demonstrated).[3]
All these works appear to render the aura of information tangible, physically present, but at the
same time withdraw from immediate engagement: the 'new aesthetic' offers itself as proof the
digital aspiration to the state of information is immanent -- the translation of information to pure
instrumentality -- emanating directly from how the digital reifies the capitalist ideology of
accumulation in autonomous production. The technical aspects of digital technology become
style -- thus new aesthetic -- a transfer instantiating the immaterial in a physical form, a
"print-out" whose tangibility then becomes the operative dimension in asserting the presence of
an immaterial, digital 'information space.' This physicality proffers the realization of information
as instrumentality. Objects collected by Bridle reflect digitally-derived features displaying the
existing capacities (both current and historical) of digital technology: the illusion they produce is
one where what was immaterial, penumbral, crystalizes from the air into solid, tangible form:
reification becomes realization -- immaterial physicality.
II
Capitalism is the transformation of labor into a commodity; the worker's externalization of their
productive capacity as a thing to be exchanged. The historical machine is the crystallization of
this externalized labor-commodity as a physical productive force, itself valuable, but at the same
time dependent upon the very human labor it encapsulates. The categorical divisions Marx
proposed -- material of labor: those physical commodities transformed by the labor process,
including but not limited to raw material; means of labor: the tools, machinery, and buildings
utilized by labor; and finally what he terms living labor: the workers who run the machines and
enable the production to proceed -- reveal how the automated system can be recognized as the
logical extension of the means of labor, an ultimate rendering of human living labor unnecessary
to the completion of production.
This trajectory is inherent in the machine itself as an apparatus magnifying and supplanting
human action. The evolution of the technical requirements to print a single sheet on a printing
press is an example of this process: the earliest European printing press with moveable type
built by Johannes Guttenberg around 1439 required human labor to set the type, wipe ink on the
plates, situate the paper, and remove each sheet; a modern computer printer does all these
actions autonomously, faster, and with much greater precision -- in the process transforming the
earlier printing press into a machine that only requires limited human involvement in its actual
functioning (a human needs to load its paper reservoir). All the productive functions that
required several people and both extended time and labor in 1439 are now entirely
autonomous.
However, when Marx wrote 'The Fragment on Machines,' the role of human agency in industrial
production was not in doubt; his series of propositions concerned the relationships between
capital, fixed capital (the investments made in machinery and buildings to house them) and
labor (necessary to operate the machines). The trajectory of mechanization had not passed
beyond being an enhancement to human productive capacity: first the development of hand
tools, which enabled an absolute distinction between labor requiring manual capacities and that
requiring intellectual labor, visible in the distinction between the stylus used in cuneiform writing
and the plow used in cultivating crops. The emergence of mechanical and machine tools prior to
and including the industrial revolution all serve to magnify human action and improve productive
capabilities, but remain limited by the abilities of the machine operators. Production in the
nineteenth century, even when employing mechanization, remained dependent on the agency of
human labor to both keep the machines running and to guide their use in facture itself -- for
these machines, however much they streamlined the manufacturing process, human labor was
essential. This assumption that machines require human participation for their productive action,
still true with physical manufacturing, is entirely false within the realm of immaterial production.
Marx's minimal discussion of the role of machines in production makes the observation that
mechanization (and automation) requires labor for its action:
Transposition of powers of labor into powers of capital both in fixed and in circulating
capital. -- To what extent fixed capital (machine) creates value. -- Lauderdale.
Machine presupposes a mass of workers. [...] As such a means of production, its
use value can be that it is merely the technological condition for the occurrence of
the process (the site where the production process proceeds), as with buildings etc.,
or that it is a direct condition of the action of the means of production proper, like all
matières instrumentales. Both are in turn only the material presuppositions for the
production process generally, or for the employment and maintenance of the means
of labor.[4]
The role of industrial machinery within this theoretical framework is marginal because the
transformation of labor into commodity retains an implicit understanding that production requires
human action, a "mass of workers," and even the term 'manufacture' literally references this
hand-work aspect of production. Thus machinery appears as an addendum to the costs of
production as an expense -- the purchase of "tools" employed in manufacturing -- but is not a
substitute for labor, nor its replacement. Within this construction, the machine functions as a
crystallization of capital expenditure in a form that is simultaneously a commodity -- the
machinery -- and a generator of value as it is put in motion by human labor, itself alienated by
the protocols of mechanization:
As long as the means of labor remains a means of labor in the proper sense of the
term, such as it is directly, historically, adopted by capital and included in its
realization process, it undergoes a merely formal modification, by appearing now as
a means of labor not only in regard to its material side, but also at the same time as
a particular mode of the presence of capital, determined by its total process -- as
fixed capital. But, once adopted into the production process of capital, the means of
labor passes through different metamorphoses, whose culmination is the machine,
or rather, an automatic system of machinery (system of machinery: the automatic
one is merely its most complete, most adequate form, and alone transforms
machinery into a system), set in motion by an automaton, a moving power that
moves itself; this automaton consisting of numerous mechanical and intellectual
organs, so that the workers themselves are cast merely as its conscious linkages.[5]
While Marx's description seems to invoke a contemporary, cybernetic understanding where
human labor merges with mechanical procedures, this "automation" is not the automation of the
digital system. While the agency of these human workers is severely constrained by machine
technology, it is human labor's conscious action (what he calls "intellectual organs") that enables
production. Labor was the fundamental 'component' of these technological innovations that
gave rise to industrial production. It took an alienated form because of the demands production
placed on labor as an intelligent, highly complex "cog" within an otherwise regimented activity -Marx's "intellectual organs" (agency) -- the allowed actions within themechanized factory are
limited to and contained by the requirements of the device.
The assumption that machines require human agency only emerges as the complexity of those
machines reaches a transition point, and parts of their operation requiring human action (but not
agency) are replaced by automatic functions. This necessary labor, in which the machine's role
is to magnify and aid human production was a factual part of the available machinery during the
nineteenth century when Marx was alive; the emergence of the factory robot and computerdriven autonomous production line was more than a century away. Factories were adopting the
'labor-saving' efficiency of mechanizing repetitive processes -- those procedures that do not
require intelligent guidance (agency), and are instead functions of fragmented and
compartmentalized procedures such as those performed by a clockwork mechanism, much like
the Rathaus-Glockenspiel clock in Munich, where the device follows an elaborate series of
automated actions through careful gearing and organization of the mechanism itself. Human
agency remains an essential, guiding part of the machine, but at the same time, there is an
absolute distinction between the mechanical and the human, a division mandated by the nature
of the technical apparatus itself, even and especially when the orchestration of these devices is
designed to create the appearance of self-awareness. It is these increasingly complex machines
of the industrial revolution powered by steam or electricity that perform calculations and other
precise, highly specialized kinds of intellectual activity that place the role of human agency in
doubt.
The nature of mechanized production in the nineteenth century is fundamentally different than
autonomous, immaterial production: digital systems have enabled machines where human labor
has been minimized or entirely eliminated, and production proceeds without human control,
guidance, or interaction; High Frequency Trading (HFT) is a typical example of this automation
of the decision process through algorithmic rules. The shifts apparent in the printing press are
common features of how automated production replaces necessarily dehumanized labor.
Autonomous production that began as a 'labor-saving' procedure now saves all human labor
in/as the productive machine: it is this specific dimension of automated (immaterial) labor using
digital technology that reflects an ideology of production-without-consumption.
Digitally-enabled automation makes the human labor previously rendered subservient within the
productive system itself uncertain, posing a fundamental challenge to capitalism as historically
defined through the transformation of human labor into a commodity -- the use of human
intelligence, skill, and labor time as a specific form of productive value. The potential for full
automation emerges with the development of digital automation, one where human labor -human agency -- becomes a wasted value, and which the 'new aesthetic' documents.
III
The industrial revolution's innate challenges to traditional social structures apparent in the
de-skilling of those trades replaced by industrial production resulted in the emergence of design
reform movements throughout industrial Europe at the end of the nineteenth century under the
influence of John Ruskin via William Morris (Arts and Crafts in the UK, Art Nouveau in France
and Belgium, and both the Secession and Jugendstyl movements in Germany and Austria).
These movements created classic examples of ressentiment -- an anti-industrial aesthetic of
hand-working.[6] 'The Fragment on Machines' was written in the same period and addressed
these same issues of industrial production as Ruskin, however Marx's analysis emerged from
economics rather than considering industrialization as an aesthetic problem.
In contrast to mechanized production's impact on the skilled trades, automation initially
impacted intellectual (immaterial) labor rather than physical (manual) labor -- from the
Antikythera Mechanism produced around 100 BCE, to the Prague Orloj clock from 1410, to the
Rathaus-Glockenspiel in 1907 -- automation and automated systems have principally been
concerned not with manual production, but with the elimination of intelligent labor. This
separation of the intellectual potential of labor from its actions quickly became apparent during
the nineteenth century in the regimentation of intelligent tasks limited by machinery. But while
the role of human agency is reduced by early calculating machines, they remained within the
realm of labor-saving devices, replicating complex computations with only limited use value, and
whose production required specialized intellectual labor: these are devices outside the realm of
material production. Yet, following the same set of concerns with mechanical production as
Ruskin, Marx is not addressing these devices.
The 'new aesthetic' emerges as the antipode of the Ruskin/Morris hand-worked aesthetic, as a
parallel to the early twentieth century's "machine style": the Modernist, Art Deco style where
human handiwork was systematically elided in favor of the glittering chrome and smooth
surfaces now synonymous with industrial production on a mass scale. However, these
Modernist designs remained unquestionably a product of human action -- both intellectual and
physical; it is the role of human agency that comes into question with the 'new aesthetic': the
necessity not only for human labor in the production of the work, but the requirement of human
agency (following the aura of the digital) as a productive and organizational principle. The
immaterial physicality of the 'new aesthetic' presents a convergence of these machinic, semiotic,
and biologic productions, revealing a fundamental contradiction posed by human agency in
relation to autonomous production.
Autonomy from human production and the elision of human agency emerges as the
intermediary between designer-engineer and final result becomes simply the action of the tool
which exactly executes the planned work. The various artifacts brought together as the 'new
aesthetic' are united by their orientation not towards human observation or functional utility, but
rather by their invocation of productive values without human action -- the aura of the digital's
separation of product from all that is required to produce it: labor, capital, resources. This
transition point marks a shift from the fragmentation of the assembly-line where tasks are
organized around the repetitive action of masses of human labor (itself an organization that
implies semiotic disassembly and standardization) to an automated fabrication where the design
is generated on digital machines and then implemented by other digital machines without
human labor in the facture process; the necessity of human-as-designer thus comes into
question as it is the only aspect of non-machine agency remaining, an element whose necessity
is challenged by evolutionary algorithms and automated design.
What the 'new aesthetic' documents is the shift from earlier considerations of machine labor as
an amplifier and extension of human action -- as an augmentation of human labor -- to its
replacement by models where the machine does not augment but supplant, in the process
apparently removing the human intermediary that is the labor that historically lies between the
work of human designer-engineers and fabrication following their plans. The 'new aesthetic'
figures in this cycle as a symptom of a reorientation already underway, rather than its outcome,
as human agency becomes insignificant to these modes of production, and automation usurps
its position (agency) in the system as a whole.
The shift from immaterial values generated by automation (semiosis) to material values
generated by automation (facture) signals a fundamental shift in the nature of capitalist
production, one where human labor is of lesser significance to that of automation. It is through
this convergence that problems posed by autonomous production are elided following the aura
of the digital's stripping of physical considerations and limitations from consciousness: the
emergence of production without human labor, of commodity and exchange values (both
physical and immaterial) generated without the action of human agency. The fundamental
condition of Marx's capitalism (labor-as-commodity) returns to a central position through the
transformation of labor to automation and the inherent commodity nature of machines: the
definitional condition of capitalism becomes the literal condition of production under automation.
In the autofactory, there is no role for humans; unlike human labor which is entangled with the
minimum dimensions of society (Agamben's "bare life"), the autonomous machine is pure
commodity, non-life. Large bodies of the "human resource" fall idle as their manual functions in
production are now automated, their own commoditization of their human labor becomes
superfluous to the productive capitalism of automation -- this is the ideology of automation that
follows one fundamental law:
Anything that can be automated, will be.
The autonomous labor performed by machines -- whether through automated processes
algorithmically driven (as with High Frequency Trading software), through generative systems,
or physically in the robot assembly line -- is a crystallization of labor-as-commodity without
requiring living labor's social reproduction costs: automation does not require a wage, does not
impose social demands on its owners, and when it is expended, it can be discarded to be
replaced by newer technology.
IV
The paradox of automated labor and capitalism arises directly from the limiting role that scarcity
of capital poses to this productive system: the automated production of values can only continue
if it is possible to exchange those values for other values. The aura of the digital, when
instantiated through automated production necessary creates a paradox where instead of an
exponential escalation in value production, it generates surplus values for which there is
exponentially decreasing opportunity for exchange: the immaterial physicality that automation
brings into existence (and which is documented by the 'new aesthetic') is one where the
elimination of human labor also serves to undermine the concept of 'exchange value' itself, as
Marx noted:
Exchange-value appears first of all as the quantitative relation, the proportion, in
which use-values of one kind exchange for use-values of another kind. This relation
changes constantly with time and place. Hence exchange-value appears to be
something accidental and purely relative, and consequently an intrinsic value, i.e., an
exchange-value that is inseparably connected with the commodity, inherent in it,
seems a contradiction in terms.[7]
The paradox appears precisely because exchange value emerges from the relationship
between one commodity and another -- from the exchange of a commodity for the acquisition of
another; in capitalism this exchange devolves fundamentally to transfers of labor between
different social strata where higher level values derive from the action of labor at lower levels in
that same society. Thus the elimination of the lowest levels of human labor from the production
process destabilizes the upper levels in a cascading fashion. This proposition is not an "end of
capitalism" fantasy where automation ends the scarcity of both capital and physical limitations,
but a structural contradiction in the nature of value itself when decoupled from human labor. By
replacing the lowest levels of human labor with automation, greater efficiencies in production
emerge, but at the same time that human labor is displaced; some of it occupies (is absorbed by
its society into) higher-skilled (greater degree of intelligent agency) positions supported by those
automated procedures; however, as that higher-skilled labor is also automated, the ability of
society to absorb this displaced labor necessarily creates a new problematic not specifically
recognizable as the issue of class struggle described by Marx -- a shift from conflict between
those who labor and those who do not, to conflict between those controlling the production of
exchange values and those excluded from exchange entirely: the human labor whose laboras-commodity not longer possesses any utility, hence is not an exchange value.
The disappearance of the historical Luddites from contemporary digital production reflects the
aura of the digital encroaching and conditioning consciousness. The view that machines,
including computers, are not a challenge to human labor has become an axiomatic belief about
machinery (The Luddite Fallacy). Instead, it is the cybernetic understanding implicit in
misreading the 'Fragment on Machines' -- a worry that machines will colonize the living, human
body -- that had a currency at the end of the twentieth century, both in popular entertainment
(the "Borg" of Star Trek) and in the Critical Art Ensemble's comments from Electronic Civil
Disobedience published in 1996:
Although technological development causes many people fear and anxiety, fewer
and fewer believe that technology will replace them. In fact, the fear is really quite
the opposite. As technology attaches itself to the body, the relationship between the
body and technology becomes increasingly symbiotic.[8]
In the general failure to acknowledge the potential of digital computers to automate cognitive
tasks, (a fact evident from the earliest surviving calculation device, the Antikythera Mechanism
to the most contemporary digital computer: any intellectual activity that can be reduced to
particular rules can be rendered autonomous) -- the threat posed by automation to human
exceptionalism is sublimated as fears about digital technology colonizing the organic, human
realm: the idea that humanity must merge with computers to enable them to begin thinking. If
computers do not need to merge with humanity in such a fashion, then humanity is not
exceptional -- opening the possibility for (at least some portions of) human intellectual labor
being rendered obsolete, as HFT does with the decision making process for stock and
commodity trades in the financial markets.
A herald of the ideology of automation's expanding force is apparent in the intersection of
automated immaterial labor with the formerly intellectual labor of human agents, and is a literal
realization of the bifurcation between design and facture, one where the devaluation of human
labor reaches its apogee: rendered obsolete by the machine, there is no longer any need for
human agency once the autonomous factory has been built except to switch it on. This situation
is the implicit horror/terror common to computer technology (and its earlier realization as the
golem or homunculus) as an actor in society. The ideology of automation reveals its close
relationship to the earlier ideology of the self-made man whose success is not a product of
family, investment, or privileged position in society -- shorn of the requirement for a network of
human actors working in concert to produce wealth (material or immaterial), the automated
system enables an ideology where the productive human population appears obsolete,
parasitic, on the "designers" whose plans they formerly executed -- this is the ideology of
automation embraced by the middle classes.
Ironically by working to create computer systems that emulate or replace both human labor and
human agency, the United States' middle class belief in the self-made man, in "autonomous
achievement," becomes the reality of "automated achievement" for the upper classes, leaving
the remainder of society to 'work' as consumers/debt generators, automation effectively
eliminating them from the production process. HFT is one sign of this ideology of automation
coming into action -- a procedure that removes human agency from its historical role in
immaterial production: the response time of the computer system is such that only machines
can compete in a market where price fluctuations determined in microseconds make the
difference between profit and loss. It is reified in the digital, reflecting a denial of the physical
realm and the necessary role of human agency in creating and sustaining the social structures
which enable the ideology of automation's fantasy of "freedom" from social (re)production and
the constraints required by human society. This complex of relationships reflects the underlying
bias of digital capitalism against the social.
Notes
----------------
[1] "New Aesthetic" was the title of the blog James Bridle used to collect his materials:
new-aesthetic.tumblr.com; he started posting on May 6, 2011 and noted on May 12, 2012 that
"The New Aesthetic tumblr is now closed."; he resumed posting new materials on August 20,
2012.
[2] Joe Houston. Post-Digital Painting (Bloomfield Hills: Cranbrook, 2002).
[3] James A. Baker, III and Lee H. Hamilton, chairs. The Iraq Study Group Report (New York:
Vintage, 2006).
[4] Karl Marx. The Grundrisse (The Fragment on Machines) (London: Penguin Classics Reprint
edition: 1993) 690-691.
[5] Ibid, 692.
[6] Nickolaus Pevsner. Pioneers of Modern Design: From William Morris to Walter Gropius
(Bath: Palazzo Editions, 2011).
[7] Karl Marx. Capital: Volume 1 (London: Penguin Classics Reprint edition: 1990) 126.
[8] Critical Art Ensemble. Electronic Civil Disobedience and Other Unpopular Ideas (Brooklyn:
Autonomedia, 1996) 59; essay was originally published in 1995.
---------------Michael Betancourt is an artist, art historian, critical theorist, and curator. His writing is
concerned with the convergence of digital technology and capitalist ideology. His essays have
been translated into Chinese, French, Greek, Italian, Persian, Portuguese, and Spanish;
journals such as Leonardo, Semiotica and CTheory have published his essays. He is currently a
Professor of Motion Media Design at the Savannah College of Art and Design where he teaches
critical theory and the history of visual music, motion graphics and video art.
© CTheory. All Rights Reserved