Analyse & Kritik 30/2008 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 121–138
Piotr Machura
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
Abstract: The question I address in the paper is “What is the ideal of MacIntyre’s
moral philosophy? What is the telos of human nature?” Considering MacIntyre’s
critique of modern culture, politics and philosophy, anti-intellectualism emerges as the
main reason for his refutation of these values. So is it a reason for moral and political
distortion that leads to the interpassivity of the modern self. Taking into account
MacIntyre’s idea of characters I pinpoint the character of the philosopher as a moral
ideal of MacIntyre’s thought. For it is not only intellectual activity within any practice
that enables us to develop our distinctively human nature but also philosophy that is
the highest form of that kind of activity. From this point of view, it is crucial to grasp
philosophy as a required way of life and the craft that enables us to be moral and
political agents.
0. Introduction
The question I address in the present paper is “What is the ideal of MacIntyre’s
moral philosophy? What is the telos of human nature?” If MacIntyre’s critique
of modernity is something more than just a form of resentment, what should we
recognize as the core of the critique? And finally—can we find in MacIntyre’s
thought some kind of a basis for both political and personal solutions that would
overcome the poverty of the modern self? I shall argue that we should point to
intellectualism as a primary constituent of the basis.
My argument is threefold: I start with some general remarks about the idea
of moral ideals and personal examples and, simultaneously, with a presentation
of MacIntyre’s concept of character. Then using that concept I will pinpoint the
common basis of MacIntyre’s critique of modernity. And finally I will present
the idea of the moral example (the ideal) which emerges form MacIntyre’s conception.
1. Moral Ideals as Forms of Moral Consciousness
The fundamental query that I think needs to be raised is: “Why should we
reconsider moral ideals?” It seems, as Susan Wolf notes, that “a moral theory
that does not contain the seeds of an all-consuming ideal of moral sainthood thus
seems to place false and unnatural limits on our opportunity to do moral good
122
Piotr Machura
and our potential to deserve moral praise” (Wolf 1982, 433) and it does so, we
can add, to our descriptive and normative possibilities in ethics. An analysis of
human acting which confines its classification to the wrong/right distinction only
seems to be too narrow, not only because it passes over what is between these
two judgements but also because it does not take into account heroic actions.
As J. O. Urmson claims, there are, however, at least five reasons for which
what he calls “a moral code” should distinguish between basic norms and ‘higher
flights of morality’ (Urmson 1958, 211–214). First, taking into account the impoverishment of moral life in which neither saints nor heroes can show up, he
emphasizes those crucial matters “in which compliance with the demands of
morality by all is indispensable” (211). Second, due to this distinction, a difference between fundamental and supererogatory actions emerges to the extent
that it becomes possible to justly enforce the basic social norms. Third, as Urmson says: “a moral code, if it is to be a code, must be formulable, and if it is to
be a code to be observed it must be formulable in rules of manageable complexity” (212). Those rules should be easy to interpret for an ordinary person. We
can also add that it is one of the reasons for which the personal example is the
most common form of the presentation of ‘higher flights of morality’. Fourth,
this distinction should be introduced so that one will know which norms are
required to be obeyed and which norms are only expected to be obeyed. And
fifth, this distinction enables us to formulate an encouragement to perform the
best possible action which is not necessarily derived from the norms that restrict
us.
It is important to notice that Urmson searches for the meaning of the terms
“saint” and “hero” in some especially desirable forms of conduct. These forms,
however, cannot be considered in separation from a person’s character. For
the category of supererogatory actions does not describe any particular kind
of action, but only some isolated actions which transcend the norm. For that
reason this category of actions is usless for normative ethics.
If we want then to find any space for the ‘higher flights of morality’ in normative ethics, we should invoke to the idea of essential perfection. It is not an
objective of mine to analyse this conception in detail.1 It is crucial, however,
to notice, as Felix Adler did, that the idea of moral perfection, that is, of the
ideal, can appear in moral thinking in two fundamental ways. First, it takes the
form of “the idea of a non-existent thing, or state or being, or mode of conduct
regarded as worthy of being realised” (Adler 1910, 387). This is how we imagine
ideal happiness or ideal justice. Second, “we may think of ideal as an object in
which the desired perfection, whatever it be, is realized already” (Adler 1910,
387). In other words, we can analyse either the nature of some particular value
in its entirety or fulfilment of the moral code typical of a particular community
or normative conception, embodied in an all-consuming example. Jesus is an
example of this kind of ideal which represents the fulfilment of Christianity.
It is crucial, however, to add to this two further points. First, our mode of
enquiry must be able to take into account both basic norms which an ordinary
imperfect human can obey in everyday life and heroic deeds which characterize
1
See e.g. Aristotle’s definition of perfection in Metaphysics 6, 16.
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
123
Urmson’s (1958) ‘higher flights of morality’. Impossibility to distinguish between
these two levels of the ‘moral code’ must lead to an overbearing fanatic vision of
morality or to a significant decrease in moral demands. Without specifying the
uppermost limit to our requirements, we are not able to say what must be done.
Second, what follows from the above is that an idea of that kind must include
an anthropological conception of incomplete and imperfect human nature. It is
not just a coincidence that the idea of the moral ideals and examples in some
way goes back to ancient moral philosophy, especially to the Aristotelian moral
ideas.
MacIntyre’s Aristotelianism meets both these criteria. Not only does he
acknowledge the ‘fundamental contrast between man-as-he-happens-to-be and
man-as-he-could-be-if-he-realized-his-essential-nature’, but he also claims that,
in order to make a transition from the former to the letter, an individual needs
standards of excellence (and its examples) which should be provided by ethics.
It is crucial then to consider the idea of character as a interpretative key to both
MacIntyre’s critique of modernity and his own conception.
What is a character ? MacIntyre, while introducing this idea, refers to the
dramatic tradition which makes use of “a set of stock of characters immediately recognizable to the audience” and “to understand them is to be provided
with means of interpreting the behaviour of actors who play them” (MacIntyre
1984, 27). Characters are thus role-models of special significance for community
members, as they embody the moral code of particular community. Incidentally MacIntyre does not explain the method of character ’s selection. Is this
selection connected only with the tradition of a particular community, or—as
e.g. Max Scheler (who offers a totally different perspective than that of MacIntyre) claims—there are some fixed types of those models, defined by the set of
fundamental values shaped by the life of every human community (see Scheler
1987)?
Characters represents the morality of the community and they are, as MacIntyre puts it, “masks worn by moral philosophies” (MacIntyre 1984, 28). Social
significance of characters lays in their rechanneling moral views and actions of
community members. For characters are not only objects of regard for the community members, but also they furnish them “with a cultural and moral ideal”
(MacIntyre 1984, 29) defining simultaneously the content of the idea of morality
shared by a particular community. In this sense, characters provide community
members with an incentive to develop in a direction contingent on the moral
scheme accepted by the community. They do not embody the perfection but,
as MacIntyre claims, they embody the conflict as to the content of a particular
character, and so, that is to say, as to the content of the idea of perfected human
life.
How can an individual get in touch with a character ? In order to account for
this, MacIntyre’s conception of practice should be recalled. He defines practice
as
“any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative
activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are
124
Piotr Machura
realized in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form
of activity, with the result that human powers to achieve excellence,
and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended” (187).
Practice is then a form of craft (techne), an art, taken as a form of ars liberalis.
It comes into being not as a part of an individual-made sphere of co-operation
with others, but it is determined independently of that individual. It is a way of
establishing the relation between an individual’s particular personality and background and their social and cultural environment (Umwelt). The involvement
in practice is thus a moment of transcending the sphere of individuality and so
is it a moment of establishing the relation with the social setting (206–207).
It is important to take note of at least three features of the idea of practice
(craft). First, its aim is good which can be understood in at least three ways.
Second, it comprises standards of excellence. Third, the structure of action
within the practice is, in fact, a hermeneutical circle and, as such, it constitutes
a general model for all human intellectual activity.
Let me start from the very end. To enter into practice is to accept its historically determined norms and standards of excellence. But it does not mean that
we should reduce our activity to the automatic application of its rules (MacIntyre 1988, 31; see also MacIntyre 1999, 93). For the aim of learning practice is
not only to acquire some competence typical of this particular practice, but also
to become its independent creative participant. For that purpose an authority
inherent to this practice must not only show others how to become an apprentice
in this practice, but also how to reinterpret the goal of the practice itself. In
Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry MacIntyre says that to become an apprentice is to transform one’s personality (MacIntyre 1990, 60–61). To become
an apprentice is not only to act according to some external criteria independent
of us, but also to give up, at least to some extent, our personal autonomy and
allow ourselves to be in some part determined by the community and history of
the practice.
In this way the fundamental relationship between the authority and the apprentice shows up. The general function of the authority is to indicate and
legitimize norms and rules defining particular practice and to introduce an individual to that practice. On the other hand, the relationship with the authority
thus defined is also a moment of connecting practical thinking (associated with
particular craft) with the wider cultural context. For neither practice nor ethos
can exist alone, but they are defined (at least to some extent), and their status is determined, by the tradition of a particular community. It is for that
purpose that MacIntyre, while analysing the character, points out some moral
restrictions placed by the character on the personality of an individual who has
this particular social role (MacIntyre 1984, 27). There is no difference between
learning the technical part of practice and being introduced to its ethos which
is determined by the tradition of a community. It is thus the authority who
provides the grasp of the tradition and links isolated actions into a coherent
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
125
and intelligible whole by referring them to the wider context of the community.
What makes the character unique as a type of a moral authority is that it is a
social role representative of the whole cultural context. For, as MacIntyre says
in Three Rival Versions:
“By accepting authority [. . . ] one acquires a teacher who both introduces one to certain texts and educates one in becoming a sort of
person capable of reading those texts with understanding, texts in
which such a person discovers the story of him or herself, including
the story of how he or she was transformed into a reader of these
texts. This story of oneself is embedded in the story of the world, an
overall narrative within which all other narratives find their place.
That history is a movement towards the truth becoming manifest, a
movement towards intelligibility. But in the course of discovering the
intelligibility of the order of things, we also discover why at different
stages greater or lesser degrees of unintelligibility remain. And in
learning this we learn that authoritative testimony, to point us forward from where we are now, can never in our present bodily life be
dispensed with. So continuous authority receives its justification as
indispensable to continuing progress, the narrative of which we first
learned how to recount from that authority and the truth of which is
confirmed by our further progress, including that progress made by
means of dialectical enquiry.” (MacIntyre 1990, 92)
The result of this is not only the historical changeability of characters but also
conflict that lies in the very heart of their essence. This conflict concerns the real
essence of a particular character (MacIntyre 1984, 30) but it is also the conflict
with which the individual is faced because of the tension between the ties of
the tradition and the demands of modernity and, at the same time, between
different interpretations of the character. For every individual, with their own
background, interprets the demands of the character in a slightly different way.
It is also, so to say, a moment of one’s individualization whereby the person,
while interpreting the demands of the tradition-based character, adjusts them
to modernity.
Thus, the character is unique in its openness. It is open to the variety
of interpretative contexts and practices, as well as to reinterpretation due to
changes possible in the nature of practice or in the social environment. That is
why incorporating the individual’s thinking into the social and cultural life of the
community must be recognized as the main goal and the basic good of this kind
of education. What is more, the good that we gain while being involved in some
practice is not only a specific practical goal of the craft, but also the narrative and
intelligible order of our lives that we thus acquire. For paradigms of perfection, as
Macintyre remarks, are not only exemplifications of the best standards reached
so far but, in the first place, they are the guidelines for further development
(MacIntyre 1990, 65–66). That statement enables us to define the good which
we acquire due to practice and contact with the relevant authority. First, only
good internal to practice and connected with the standards of perfection may be
126
Piotr Machura
pointed out as the real goal of activity within the practice. External good, which
can be acquired in different ways is, in MacIntyre’s view, genuine good which
makes the identification of practice qua practice and personal development of the
person involved in it impossible. Finally, general good reached by the individual
who identifies their personality by the system of social roles connected with
practice is the narrative unity of their life. It is the narrative unity that makes
the person’s life and action intelligible not only to others but also to themselves.
It is done in that way because the way in which the individual learns how to
became an independent subject of the practice is also a way in which they learn
how to become an independent subject as such. It is the authority that embodies
and shows the apprentice what it means to be a person in a particular community
and what the idea of the common life is.
2. What is Wrong With A Public Life?
Let us consider now MacIntyre’s critique of modern culture, starting with an
analysis of three characters typical of modern culture: Rich Aesthete, Manager
and Therapist. The essence of the critique of these characters comes down to
two things. The moral culture which they represent is the culture of unencumbered self, whose will and preferences are not regulated in any socially accepted
way. Because of this the world and social environment seem to them “nothing
but a meeting place for individual wills, each with its own set of attitudes and
preferences” (MacIntyre 1984, 25), that is, an area of action free of any moral
judgements as they are covered up by ‘professional’ jargon (see Ballard 2000,
9), as in the case of Rich Aesthete or Therapist. What is more, nobody is responsible for that kind of actions, as there is no source of responsibility. Second,
in Therapist’s actions, as well as in those of Manager, the difference between
manipulative and non-manipulative social relations is blurred.
The key role of Manager as a central character emerges from the combination
of these two features. Lawlessness and unencumberency of Aesthete’s actions become ‘professionalised’ here. Private, so to say, preferences of the individual are
elevated to a fundamental mechanism of the organization of social life. Effectiveness taken unilaterally as the only criterion for Manager’s actions does not allow
formulating the question about the good, which could be the aim of practice
managed by him. From this point of view, as well as from that of Therapist, the
question about such good is, in fact, ridiculous. The situation of Manager is, as
a matter of fact, symptomatic: he cannot justify the premises of his own actions
and nor can he question the rationale behind his own goals. Hence, MacIntyre
claims, the difference between the authority of Manager and his power is erased.
The power, being effective, legitimises itself and, as such, is given authority.
Subsequently, in absence of any other criteria except for effectiveness, the power
shifts into the hands of the most effective person. In this sense an expert of a
bureaucratic organization, that is Manager, legitimises himself.
This situation brings us to the problem of political subjecthood. For if MacIntyre’s view on bureaucracy is true, the state based on such a view must take
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
127
the power as its subject. From this point of view, the ‘democratic institutions’
are, first of all, bureaucratic institutions and the democracy appears to be a
façade. True expression of preferences, interests and good of the citizens is not
what we can be sure to find behind it. The state organised by the standards of
modern bureaucracy is governed according to the rules of mutually contradictory
inclinations, in which a reflection on how to realise the real needs of citizens has
been displaced with the power of money. In MacIntyre’s own words: “although
most citizens share, although to greatly varying extents, in such public goods as
those of a minimally secure order, the distribution of goods by government in no
way reflects a common mind arrived at through widespread shared deliberation
governed by norms of rational enquiry” (MacIntyre 1999, 131).
For that purpose the individual is able to achieve their goods only by letting
bureaucracy take control over them, yet in this way they slip into, as Slavoy
Žižek calls it, interpassivity (see Žižek 1997). Interpassivity of the political self,
as seen by MacIntyre, should be understood as laying the burden of political
activity onto the institutions of power. How this mechanism works is very elusive.
For there is still, on the one hand, the facade of the democratically-run public
order with the demos retained as the subject of the politics, but, on the other
hand, both the spectrum of acceptable views and forms of their expression are
restricted (because of the very narrow spectrum of political representation, as
in the United States, and some political views labelled as incompatible with the
‘common sense’). That is why MacIntyre’s critique of modernity is directed not
only against the bureaucratic state, but also against liberal ‘common sense’ and
‘professionalism’ in social sciences.
The modern interpassive self is the subject in politics only occasionally. They
cannot change it for the social environment in which they live cannot furnish him
with the background for an alternative vision of the social and political status
quo. The modern self is faced with the following choice: liberalism and emotivism which prevent them from formulating any view of themselves that would
include their social background and temporal dimension of existence, versus the
unconsciousness of the Volk which generates not only a similarly interpassive
relation to the institutions of power, but also interferes with their developing
their capabilities of practical and theoretical reasoning. In both cases it is a
‘professional expert’ appointed by the institution of power who is the real political agent. Even if the good is the declared goal of the expertise management,
its formulation cannot be clear in the public discourse. This is why MacIntyre
calls modern politics the theatre of illusions in which money and rhetorical skills
are the most important tools of power (MacIntyre 1984, 76–77).
This situation, MacIntyre claims, is the result of the changes not only in
politics but also in the shared conception of the society. The construal of the
‘individual’ as the unencumbered self independent of their social environment
has caused ‘the blending of languages’ which results in the impossibility of individuals reaching a consensus in the debates on individual and common good.
The famous call to construct new communities “within which civility and the
intellectual and moral life can be sustained through the new dark ages” (Mac-
128
Piotr Machura
Intyre 1984, 263) from the very end of After Virtue should be understood as an
appeal to reconsider our political agency.
Importantly, form this point of view, we cannot draw dividing lines between
the political, social and intellectual (or educational) dimensions of the agency.
For if we want to describe the poverty of the modern self, we have to notice
that it cannot find any antidote for its interpassivity in the education system.
Both modern philosophy, especially the western analytical philosophy, as MacIntyre claims, and the most common type of the western university are organised
according to the intellectual and moral standards embodied by Manager. Philosophy has lost its status of the master-craft thereby becoming a problem for itself
while fragmentation and ‘scientific’ demands of philosophical analysis discourage
rather than encourage an intellectual quest for the sense of life and good. Along
the same lines, the university as an institution whose function is to manufacture qualified professionals does not allow for the search of self-knowledge or the
ability of discussion with others (MacIntyre 1990, 7–8).
As a result, due to MacIntyre’s diagnosis, the man turns out to be deprived of
his subjecthood and his ability to realize his essential nature can be questioned.
For what modern culture misses is the fundamental intellectual character of
human beings which enables us to exercise the powers of practical reasoning and
reflection that makes it possible for us to make crucial decisions about our lives
(see MacIntyre 1990, 175).
3. Politics, Virtues and Intellectualism
What then, contrary to the situation described above, should the well-ordered
self be like? What is the essential nature that we should realize in our lives?
The subjecthood of man is organised in two dimensions—biological and cultural. In Dependent Rational Animals MacIntyre approaches (at least to some
extent) evolutionary psychology (see e.g. Tomasello 1999) in that he points out
that we cannot think of human agency and the relation of the individual to the
tradition without taking the fundamental biological dimension of our existence
into account. The fundamental dimension of the existence is determined by the
vital dependency for we need others just to survive, especially at the very early
stage of our lives.
The well ordered community renders it possible for man to not only obtain
one’s goals and realize one’s desires but also to realize their human capabilities.
It is crucial to consider what MacIntyre calls ‘distinctively human’ possibilities
and capabilities which should be developed in the network of communal help
starting at the stage of parental care. Witness, however, that this consideration
is possible only within an Aristotelian perspective but not within any postEnlightenment one. The cognitive resources of Aristotelianism allow us to realize
that in modern, post-Enlightenment culture we lose the possibility to exercise
our intellectual and reflective abilities, that is, our distinctively human nature
and distinctively human way of life.
For the man in full bloom is, as MacIntyre calls it, an ‘independent practical
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
129
reasoner’. We become such reasoners by exercising our rationality in the framework of language and culture. During the socialization process it is not that the
individual is ‘given’ the ability to use language nor are they ‘forced’ into the
framework of a particular tradition. Their primary animal capabilities evolve
in the context of this tradition, instead. This is why MacIntyre emphasizes the
significance of socialization. To learn a language is to learn the modes of understanding the world typical of a particular culture. For language, as MacIntyre
maintains, is not only a medium of communication but also a mode of structuring the world and as such it is not impartial. While describing the environment,
man simultaneously builds a system of senses and values, that is, a culture which
is their natural environment.
MacIntyre claims that the roots of language go back to the ability to achieve
good (MacIntyre 1999, 25). Language should be, most of all, understood as a
medium of communication of intentional states and emotions. The cognition
of these states is an “interpretative knowledge”, a practical ability derived from
social relations. The knowledge of emotions and plans is derived from responsive
sympathy and empathy “elicited through action and interaction and without
these we could not, as we often do, impute to those others the kind of reasons
for their actions that, by making their actions intelligible to us to respond to
them in ways that they too can find intelligible” (14). In the community while
learning a language we recognize the ways of action typical of the cultural code of
this community and we acquire the ability to relate to the other members of the
community and, thereby, to understand them. The development of intellectual
traditions within the framework provided by a language, established narrative
forms and practical rationality is based on this distinctively human element of
our nature.
Similarly, it is also due to being introduced to a particular cultural code that
we can come to control our emotions. To learn how to do this and how to make
them intelligible to others is an important component of moral education that is
possible only within the framework provided by the community. MacIntyre calls
emotions “norm-governed” (MacIntyre 1988, 76) for the forms of their expression
are strictly connected with the set of norms typical of a particular community and
with the rules and standards of rationality determined by a particular culture.
Also, it is during socialization taken as the introduction to the culture of a
particular community that the individual is provided with the intellectual tool of
acquiring self-knowledge. For, as stressed by MacIntyre, we learn a language by
being introduced to the set of texts which determine the paradigms of expressions
typical of this language (382–383). At the same time, we are introduced to the
set of texts which describe or, more precisely, illustrate the way of understanding
human life in this tradition. It is only through the construal of our life as a unity
that we can find sense in it and recapitulate and judge our deeds (MacIntyre
1984, 218–219). It is impossible to understand a human out of the context of the
history of their life. Only after considering life as a unity of the quest for good
can we judge whether the life was successful or not. What is specifically meant
here is a possibility of such a quest without specifying a priori any particular
good. For, as Macintyre claims, “a quest is always an education both as to
130
Piotr Machura
the character of that which is sought and in self-knowledge”, which makes him
further argue that ‘the good life for man is the life spent in seeking for the good
life for man” (MacIntyre 1984, 219).
MacIntyre approximates here to the construal of human life from the perspective of the hermeneutical circle. For if it is not our decision to enter a
particular narrative and it is not us who determine our starting point but it
is socialization and primal education that establish those conditions and forms.
It is the possibility of a reflective understanding of our own life that promotes
a ‘transcendental analysis’ of our self-knowledge and renders us able to move
towards our true telos. But what, in fact, are we looking for?
MacIntyre as accepts the Aristotelian vision of the end of human life. Accordingly what we are looking for is the happiness, eudaimonia. It is in Short
History of Ethics that MacIntyre pays attention to the intellectual character of
eudaimonia in Aristotle (MacIntyre 1998b, 57–58). In After Virtue he broadens
this interpretation and connects the meaning of this term with good fortune,
which makes him claim, that “what constitutes the good for man is a complete
human life at its best” (MacIntyre 1984, 149). MacIntyre’s positions are thus
close to Aristotle’s. Still, it is interesting to note that in Whose justice? Which
Rationality? and Three Rival Version he is barely interested in this concept. It
is not till Dependent Rational Animals that he formulates the idea of flourishing
as a way of understanding eudaimonia.
The basic dimension of human good is thus determined by its biological
nature. This basis is then structured by providing an outlet for the forms of
expressions of emotions and taking control over them. The distinctively human
attitude is thus to distance oneself from one’s emotions and to be able to take
over intellectual control (MacIntyre 1999, 69 and 105–106). As MacIntyre claims:
“what is for human beings to flourish does of course vary from context to context,
but in every context it is as someone exercises in a relevant way the capabilities
of an independent practical reasoner that her or his potentialities for flourishing
in a specifically human way are developed. So if we want to understand how
it is to be good for humans to live, we need to know what it is to be excellent
as an independent practical reasoner, that is, what the virtues of independent
practical reasoner are.” (MacIntyre 1999, 77)
In Practical Rationalities as Forms of Social Structures MacIntyre links practical rationality with actions and says that “to learn to be rational is to be initiated into and trained in the habits of action and judgement which dispose
one to be so moved. So also to be rational as a member of a particular social
order is to participate in some particular community in the relevant ways and
to be moved by the acknowledged or to be acknowledged good reasons of that
particular social order.” (MacIntyre 1998d, 121) We gain this kind of rationality
through the reflection on the principles of our actions and actions of others. It
is then in some part an empirical element of our personality derived from the
practical knowledge of interpersonal relationships. We are gradually brought to
this kind of rationality form the very beginning of our lives. To introduce some
distance between the self and its emotions so that it could analyse the emotions
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
131
is a key element of this education. It is also a prerequisite for assessing reasons
for action (MacIntyre 1999, 68–69).
The practical rationality thus conceived provides the basis of our moral life. It
is the possibility of reasoning, distancing oneself and analysing one’s passions and
motives that makes their evaluation and hierarchization possible. In Dependent
Rational Animals MacIntyre argues that it takes the ability to come up with
alternative solutions for the future. Hence the conclusion that practical reasoning
is a syllogism (MacIntyre 1984, 161–162; MacIntyre 1988, 129–130, 139–140).
Notice that it follows that the moral decisions are, in fact, a matter of knowledge.
It is also of crucial importance that MacIntyre equates the major (initial) premise
of that syllogism with the good which is the goal of action. But where is the
idea of such good taken from?
The individual’s reasoning and their quest for good is based on the idea of
good given through the standards of practice and social relations in which the
individual is involved. It is in this context that the intellectual character of the
quest, which, for MacIntyre, is the sense of human life, becomes obvious. Every
man organises his life in the way which is determined by this person’s possibilities, capabilities, received education and aspirations as well as the possibilities
offered by a particular tradition. Real life defines good for, as MacIntyre claims,
“the grasp of the concept of human flourishing to which reasoner appeals had
to itself to be acquired in the course of practical experience” (MacIntyre 1999,
113). Outside of practice, there is no possibility to define the horizon within
which the idea of flourishing (and happiness) could appear.
Nevertheless, it is only a conscious life that may lead to the formulation of
such an idea. This statement refers to Aristotle’s concept of the contemplative
life as the best way to human goal. MacIntyre seems to agree with this concept
for, as I noticed above, MacIntyre’s idea of practice does, in fact, reach beyond
itself and, as a result, the individual can finally ask the question about their
good qua a human being.
In Dependent Rational Animals MacIntyre writes: “those quantities of mind
and character that enable someone both to recognize the relevant goods and
to use the relevant skills in achieving them are the excellences, the virtues, that
distinguish or should distinguish teacher from apprentice or student” (MacIntyre
1999, 92). It is because of the virtues, as classified by Aristotle, that we can
not only control our practice by force of habit, but also to assess our goals
correctly. The virtues can be gained only in the course of practice as it is
practice that determines our status within the community (it furnishes us with
social role). That is why, as MacIntyre claims, learning virtues is not only a
moral education but by learning them we also learn how to play our social roles
correctly (88–89). Virtues should then be understood as “those dispositions
which will not only sustain practices and enable us to achieve the goods internal
to practices, but which will also sustain us in the relevant kind of quest for
the good, by enabling us to overcome the harms, dangers, temptations and
distractions which we encounter, and which will furnish us with increasing selfknowledge and increasing knowledge of the good” (MacIntyre 1984, 219). They
are a mediator between human nature and the good (MacIntyre 1999, 159). For
132
Piotr Machura
it is natural human temper that lies in the heart of the virtues but if they are
practiced rightly than they can furnish us with the ideas of good that extend
beyond the biological dimension of human nature. What is more, the criterion
for the correctness of their practice is certified by the harmony between the
animal and cultural dimensions of human nature.
It appears then that the idea of virtues, as in the case of the ideas of practice
and the moral example, extends beyond the sphere of praxis. The reflective
character of virtues emphasizes the rational aspect of human nature while the
answer to the question of what is the proper virtuous deed exceeds the provisional
character of a one-time solution. That is why MacIntyre says that “it is for the
sake of achieving this letter good [the good of a human as such—P. M.] that we
practice the virtues and we do so by making choices about means to achieve that
end [. . . ] Such choices demand judgments and the exercise of the virtues requires
therefore a capacity to judge and to do the right thing in the right place at the
right time in the right way. The exercise of such judgement is not routinizable
application of rules” (MacIntyre 1984, 150).
That is why the fundamental role is played by the virtue of practical wisdom,
phronesis, the concept of which is strictly connected with the distinction into
two kinds of knowledge: a practical knowledge (phronesis) and a theoretical
knowledge (sofia).
In Whose Justice? Which Rationality? MacIntyre points out that the function of phronesis is to apply the general statements (truths) concerning the good
of a person qua human to the particular person and situation (MacIntyre 1988,
115–116). It is then a kind of an interpretative knowledge, intermediate between
‘professional’ intellectual activity (philosophy) and everyday practice. It is then
crucial to notice that, in the light of the above statements, it is clear that MacIntyre takes phronesis as a virtue that not only determines the person’s right
conduct, but also makes the intellectual (reflective, philosophical) way of life possible. The individual’s aspiration to become phronemos enables them to achieve
sofia. Accordingly, MacIntyre claims that every moral conduct is determined
by the first philosophical premises which for the particular community members
are the first principles embodied in the tradition of the community. What is
more, in On Not Having the Last Word he points out that the difference between “different types of interpretative practice” can be grasped only after being
introduced into the exercise of this practice (MacIntyre 2002, 165). It is only in
this context that the sense of MacIntyre’s statement that “hermeneutics [. . . ] is
a subdiscipline of ethics” (169) is clear, for without making the initial decisions
concerning the ways of establishing cognitive possibilities and the knowledge of
modes of human acting, it is impossible to build moral philosophy. But every
recognition of such a possibility is already determined by cultural presuppositions prior to the individual’s consciousness. That is to say, the circular character
of hermeneutical cognition determines the character of the relationship between
the first premises of thought, its object and the possibilities of the application
of its results. In Whose Justice? Which Rationality? MacIntyre writes:
“the deliberative task of rational construction is [. . . ] one which is-
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
133
sues in an hierarchical ordering of means to their ends, in which the
ultimate end is specified in a formulation which provides the first
principle or principles from which are deduced statements of those
subordinate ends which are means to the ultimate end. What is an
ordered hierarchy of ‘for the sake of’ relations leading to the arche
is also a deductive hierarchy descending from the arche. It is only
of course by invoking additional premises, independently supported,
that deliberation can arrive at an end product in which the particular types of circumstance of this particular agent can be understood
to make it the case that for him to pursue the good and the best
involves the here-and-now pursuit of this highly specific good. And
[. . . ] one of the marks of phronesis is that someone is able to identify
just which circumstances are relevant and therefore which premises
must be utilized in the deliberative construction.” (MacIntyre 1988,
132)
This kind of reasoning is apparently circular. The first premises must be known
to make the practical reasoning possible. MacIntyre agrees with Aristotle that
it is a syllogism (129–130). But how can the first premises be known if they
simultaneously appear to be the conclusion of this syllogism?
In answer to this question we must take note of MacIntyre’s partial dependency on Gadamer. For if it is the cultural heritage of the community embodied
in the tradition that is a source of the moral content reflected by the individuals, it follows that the arche of reasoning must also be the arche of the tradition. MacIntyre generally accepts Gadamer’s stance on this point (MacIntyre
2002, 170–171). What we can understand is language, but it is understood in
a Gadamerian way, i.e. as a distinctively human environment (Umwelt). The
unique character of conscious human life rests on the fact that the possibility
of transcending the everyday experience towards the episteme is facilitated by
language. Reflection on the resources of language understood as reflection on
the cultural heritage that determines the self is conducted in this particular language. To make an attempt to find one’s own identity is to make an attempt to
find its general principles. This means that phronetic reasoning taken as a move
towards the individual’s self-consciousness must include theoretical reflection on
those principles (archai ) (MacIntyre 1998a, 171–175).
MacIntyre notices that the first principles thus understood can be conceived
only within a particular intellectual scheme. We use its contents as a self-evident
argument supported by language norms. That is why, in MacIntyre’s view, the
epistemological stand is always first-person. But from his point of view, based on
the Aristotelian and Thomistic ideas, it is the third-person objective perspective
that we should try to reach. We can achieve this perspective by realizing the
modes of our cognition. “My mind or rather my soul is only one among many
and its own knowledge of my self qua soul has to be integrated into general
account of souls and their teleology” (176). For when we make an analysis of a
particular problem we must start with the starting point of our tradition, but
then we can subject our consciousness to some kind of ‘transcendental analysis’
134
Piotr Machura
(or better—hermeneutical analysis) which faces us with the enclosed character
of our enquiry. For the object of such an enquiry is in some way primarily
recognized within the intellectual scheme within which we enquire.
Enquiring from the standpoint of a particular intellectual scheme, the self in
the first place recognises the structure of this scheme. Thus practical reasoning
appears as the only introduction to theoretical enquiry which is essential for
finding the solution to practical problems. As MacIntyre claims: “the telos/finis
of any type of systematic activity is [. . . ] that end internal to activity of that
specific kind, for the sake of which and in the direction of which activity is carried forward” (182). The difference between practical and theoretical philosophy
is thus the difference in the goal, which is the action for practical and cognition
for theoretical philosophy. The structure of the two kinds of philosophy is the
same while the goals are connected with each other. This makes MacIntyre claim
that “achieved understanding is the theoretical goal of the practical activity of
enquiry” (183). For every intellectual activity must be confronted with theoretical problems. The goal of such a theoretical enquiry being achieved, we can go
back to its practical application.
The goal of intellectual activity should be then taken as clarifying. Philosophy is a type of enquiry which transcends the particularities of human activity
and is itself involved in its starting point, but it is also this point that makes
any rational enquiry possible. For, as MacIntyre claims, in both practical and
theoretical enquiry the goal is also “the telos of moral enquiry, which is excellence
in the achievement not only of adequate theoretical understanding of the specifically human good, but also of the practical embodiment of that understanding
in the life of the particular enquirer” (MacIntyre 1990, 62–63). It is crucial for
my interpretation of MacIntyre’s thought to stress his view of philosophy as the
way of life which is facilitated by phronesis (see MacIntyre 1998a, 189).
It is clear now why philosophy thus seen must be taken as enquiry in the
history of culture, due to which it is possible not only to account for a particular situation but also to find its cause, to identify its relation with the broader
cultural context and, by the analysis on the level of metaphysics, to set criteria
for assessing similar problems. An important part of such philosophy must be
the spinning of narratives, both individual and communal, and their intellectual
analysis. That is why MacIntyre accepts Aristotle’s claim that the person interested in myths is already a philosopher (193). To recognize one’s own history
as a part of a broader narrative is an important part of tradition-based enquiry
in both practical and theoretical dimensions. For I cannot stake claims to the
truth of my statements independently of the history of my enquiries and independently of the history of intellectual scheme within which I speak and the society
of which I am a member. The claims to the truth may then be approached only
with warranted assertibility.
MacIntyre calls philosophy seen along such lines craft (techne). It is, of
course, craft understood as ars liberalis or the practice in the sense of MacIntyre.
It is then a kind of intellectual craft whose structure is similar to every other
kind of craft (MacIntyre 1990, 61). In both cases an apprentice to the craft
has to learn to tell the difference between what is good and best for them at
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
135
their level and in general, and to judge their mistakes in applying standards
considered best in particular craft. The ability of such a judgement must be
derived not only form the practical reasoning (phronesis) but also, as we are
to discover the objective nature of particular practice, from theoretical enquiry.
Every craft (practice) demands the knowledge of its tradition, the ability of its
critical analysis and the possibility of applying its heritage. In philosophy as
well as in every other craft, the apprentice has to learn to recognize their own
weaknesses which limit their heading for the telos of the craft and to recognize
the virtues, which they should exercise in the course of achieving the goal of the
craft (61–62).
Thus, there is no significant difference between moral and scientific thinking.
Without proper conduct, the individual is not able to recognize their true good
and, as a consequence, they are not able to flourish. So philosophy thus construed
is the techne of self-knowledge which can transcend our particular point of view.
What is more, when philosophy is understood as a techne of ‘moral enquiry’,
it can be exercised not only as a kind of science but also as philosophy which
important part is its practical application. In ‘master-craft’ thus conceived the
existential consequences of the enquiry’s results cannot be separated from the
results themselves. It is reflection that permits right and successful action and
these two dimensions are strictly connected (62). For the techne of philosophy
appears the most important human practice which enables man to live a proper
life and to move towards both personal and essential goods. Philosophy is then
a ‘spiritual guide’. It is human practice that crowns all human intellectual
activities.
If my interpretation of MacIntyre’s philosophy is correct, it is possible now to
pinpoint an ideal that represents it. I consider the character of the Philosopher
to be such an ideal.
The two levels of thought mentioned above converge when it comes to their
goal. For, as MacIntyre claims:
“to live a practically well-ordered life is to embody the universal concepts which we comprehend and justify in (moral) enquires in the
particularities of our individual lives. So the moral life is the life of
embodied moral enquiry and those individuals who live out the moral
life as farmers, or fishermen, or furniture makers embody more or
less adequately in those lives, devoted in the key parts to their own
crafts, what may often not be recognized as a theory, the product of
the theorist’s very different craft, but which nevertheless is one. And
the particularities of such lives in a variety of significant ways embody and continue the traditions, moral, religious, and intellectual,
of such communities as those of family, the city, the clan, and the
nation. Thus political narratives of success or failure in the making
and sustaining of such communities are also inescapably narratives
of embodied moral enquiry, itself successful or unsuccessful.” (80)
In this context it becomes apparent why in Dependent Rational Animals MacIntyre calls man ‘the reasoner’. Man is taken as a rational being, and the exercise
136
Piotr Machura
of their reflective capabilities is crucial for them to develop not only within the
practices that they undertake but also by identifying themselves within the network of the practices as a human. What is more, in MacIntyre’s view, these
two moments cannot be separated. Being involved in the relationship with the
tradition and authority connected with some practice makes the individual open
to the contact with the social and cultural heritage and gives them a possibility
to establish their identity and to define their goals. These possibilities are, nevertheless, preceded by the reflective abilities of the individual of both practical
reasoning and theoretical enquiry. Practical reasoning is thus only a beginning
of the exercise of the individual’s intellectual possibilities which should be exercised by every single man and woman as much as it is possible for him or her
to became a philosopher, i.e. the searcher of wisdom which can be taken as the
knowledge of good à la Socrates.
On the other hand in some parts of Three Rival Versions MacIntyre, while
describing the person involved in ‘moral enquiry’ taken as a curricular discipline,
uses the term ‘enquirer’ and concentrates on this person’s duties as a scientist.
For there can be no distinction between practical reasoning of particular people
and the ‘professional’ philosophical enquiry. Being introduced to the network
of practices, the individual recognizes the teleological scheme of understanding
which is best described, in MacIntyre’s opinion, in Nicomachean Ethics. Simultaneously, philosophy can be either a part of social life (and in antiquity it was
a central element—see MacIntyre 1984, 36–37; MacIntyre 1988, 247) or a professionalized academic activity in which case it excludes itself from this life and
becomes part of a curriculum of an unknown purpose (Macintyre 1990, 168).
In search of identity, the individual learns how to use its reflective capabilities
in the way typical of classical philosophy (MacIntyre 1998c, 140). In trying to
understand their own good as well as the ultimate human good, the individual
is faced with the necessity to acquire at least the basics of philosophical skills.
But to exercise the capabilities of practical reasoning, the plain person needs
the teacher, i.e. the authority who can introduce them to the proper ways of
thought and continuously inspire them to develop their intellectual skills.
Philosophy thus, from MacIntyre’s point of view, must be rooted in the everyday routine of the community to the degree that not only academic philosophers
are the subject of the moral discourse. For MacIntyre’s goal, if my interpretation
of his work is correct, is to reformulate the culture in the way in which every
single individual will be aware of the necessity of intellectual activity in their life.
For that purpose the Philosopher must be conceived as a central character. As
the character they must embody the interpretative conflict concerning not only
the status and goals of philosophy, but also, and in the first place, concerning
the goal of human activity and the best ways of achieving it. As a character
the Philosopher is something more than a social role of an academic researcher.
They represent MacIntyre’s vision of the human as an intellectual being. As a
character the Philosopher should be taken as a ‘measure’ of communal life. But
as such they are also a role model for ‘professional’ philosophers.
The Philosopher as an embodiment of reflectiveness thus understood must
then be the return to the ancient idea of the wisdom searcher. But this character
MacIntyre’s Radical Intellectualism: The Philosopher as a Moral Ideal
137
is based on the social role of the ‘professional’ philosopher undertaking ‘moral
enquiry’. The mode of establishing their status within the community and in
which the results of their work are transferred to the community is an indicator
of the relationship of the society to the sphere of scientific research. In this
character the efforts to understand (clarify) our own identity, the claims to the
truth and applications of the results are joined.
The Philosopher seen in this way cannot be a ‘holy man’ who knows the
objective truth, but rather a master in a master-craft, a guide in a quest for the
good and unity of life, but also a member of the community, not an ‘independent
expert’ (as the Therapist and the Manager are). The Philosopher’s efforts to
clarify the world (biological as well as social and cultural) involve in some part
the continuous reminding of the historical character of every cognition and claim
to the truth. This kind of spiritual (intellectual) guidance does not consist in
making others move towards the ends defined a priori, but rather in encouraging
them to exercise theirs abilities to reason and initiate the discourse with the
heritage of a given tradition as well as with others. In this sense the Philosopher,
unlike the Manager and the Therapist, tries to establish non-manipulative social
relations within the community. Socrates, that is to say, is the paradigm of such
a character.
The first step for individuals involved in ‘moral enquiry’ at the level of both
academic and everyday reflection is a conversion of the individual’s personality
to the position of an apprentice in one of practices (crafts), for “unless we already
have within ourselves the potentiality for moving towards and achieving the relevant theoretical and practical conclusions we shall be unable to learn. But
we also need a teacher to enable us to actualize that potentiality.” (MacIntyre
1990, 63) The basis of the philosophical conduct at both levels is the acknowledgement of our ignorance and the virtue of modesty connected with it. Starting
with modesty, ‘virtues of acknowledged dependence’ can be derived to tie the
individual consciously with the particular community. Those virtues (as well as
the virtue of justice) to some extent constitute phronesis which concerns both
the ability of just assessment of a situation and self-knowledge. The character
of the Philosopher is especially important in this context, as it is by reflecting
its content that the individual can assess their own actions as well as successes
or failures in developing their intellectual capabilities.
The aim of the Philosopher’s work is to teach or rather promote a theoretical
way of life, according to Aristotle’s teaching. The personal virtue of the individual lies in intellectual perfection and contemplation. The Philosopher as a
character is not an ‘ideal’ in the meaning of perfected man but rather an object
of social identification and the model of a social change. For that purpose it
should be considered, just as the exemplars of wisdom in ancient philosophical
school were, an object of contemplation and debate, the exemplar which should
encourage personal development. It is crucial to notice that this development
has to have important social and political consequences. Only from this point
of view, I think, can we understand the importance of the family and university
as the key institutions of the state, as MacIntyre sees it, and the stress he puts
138
Piotr Machura
on the necessity of the role played by the educated public in the well ordered
community (MacIntyre 1987).
What MacIntyre wants us to remember, from this point of view, is that the
only cure for the poverty of modern agency is the radical turn towards conscious
subjecthood based on the intellectual, reflective capabilities of man. MacIntyre’s
conception of the state, the state that respects the autonomy of the individual
and puts stress upon their political subjecthood, should be rooted in the society
in which individuals can not only express their opinions but also take part in
the institutions of power as much as possible. In this way MacIntyre’s radical
intellectualism focused on the character of the Philosopher turns out to be the
remedy for the interpassivity of modernity.
Bibliography
Adler, F. (1910), The Moral Ideal, in: The International Journal of Ethics 20(4),
387–394
Ballard, B. W. (2000), Understanding MacIntyre, Lanham–New York–Oxford
MacIntyre, A. (1984), After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory (2nd edition), Notre
Dame
— (1987), The Idea of an Educated Public, in: 1985, Haydon, G. (ed.), Education
and Values. The Richard Peters Lectures delivered in the Institute of Education,
London
— (1988) Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, Notre Dame
— (1990), Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and
Tradition. Being Gifford Lectures delivered in the University of Edinburgh in 1998,
Notre Dame
— (1998a), First Principles, Final Ends and Contemporary Philosophical Issues, in:
K. Knight (ed.). The MacIntyre Reader, Cambridge
— (1998b), A Short History of Ethics. A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century (2nd edition), London–New York
— (1998c), Plain Persons and Moral Philosophy: Rules, Virtues and Goods, in:
Knight, K. (ed.), The MacIntyre Reader, Cambridge
— (1998d), Practical Rationalities as Forms of Social Structures, in: Knight, K. (ed.),
The MacIntyre Reader, Cambridge
— (1999), Dependent Rational Animals. Why Human Beings Need The Virtues, London
— (2002), On Not Having the Last Word: Thoughts on Our Debts to Gadamer, in:
Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Malpas, J./von
Arnswald, U./Kretscher, J. (eds.), Boston
Scheler, M. (1987), Exemplars of Persons and Leaders, in: Scheler, M.,Persons and
Self-Value: Three Essays, Dordrecht–Boston–Lancaster, 127–198
Tomasello, M. (1999), The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Cambridge
Urmson, J. O. (1958), Saints and Heroes, in: Melden, A. J. (ed.), Essays in Moral
Philosophy, Washington, 198–216
Wolf, S. (1982), Moral Saints, in: The Journal of Philosophy 79(8), 419–439
Žižek, S. (1997), The Plague of Fantasies, London