Vitale Between Deliberative and Participatory Democracy
Vitale Between Deliberative and Participatory Democracy
Vitale Between Deliberative and Participatory Democracy
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Philosophy & Social Criticism can be found at: Email Alerts: http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
Denise Vitale
Abstract Deliberative democracy has assumed a central role in the debate about deepening democratic practices in complex contemporary societies. By acknowledging the citizens as the main actors in the political process, political deliberation entails a strong ideal of participation that has not, however, been properly claried. The main purpose of this article is to discuss, through Jrgen Habermas analysis of modernity, reason and democracy, whether and to what extent deliberative democracy and participatory democracy are compatible and how they can, either separately or together, enhance democratic practices. Further exploration of this relationship will permit a better understanding of the possibilities and limits of institutionalizing both discourses, as well as of developing democracy in a more substantive dimension. Key words deliberation democracy discourse theory modernity participation
This article contributes to the debate about deliberative democracy by exploring the relation between the conceptions of deliberative and participatory democracy. Taking Jrgen Habermas analysis of deliberative democracy as my starting point, I begin by identifying the role democracy plays in contemporary societies and examine how democracy can be implemented under the procedural and deliberative approaches. I then discuss the idea of participatory democracy in order to clarify the relation between the participatory and deliberative perspectives and to highlight the main characteristics necessary for contemporary democratic practice. I have chosen this topic because of the importance of the debate about these two democratic discourses at the turn of the 21st century.
PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL CRITICISM vol 32 no 6 pp. 739766
Copyright 2006 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) www.sagepublications.com DOI: 10.1177/0191453706064022
PSC
745 Vitale: Deliberative and participatory democracy Conceptualizing two discourses: deliberation and participation Habermas deliberative conception of democracy
Habermas constructs the concept of democracy from a procedural dimension that is grounded in discourse theory and political deliberation. Democratic legitimacy requires that the process of political decision-making occur in a framework of broad public discussion, in which all participants can debate the various issues in a careful and reasonable fashion. Decisions can be made only after this process of discussion has taken place. In this sense, the deliberative aspect corresponds to a collective process of reection and analysis, permeated by the discourse that precedes the decision.12 Habermas is convinced of the decisive role played by both democracy and law in the process of overcoming the philosophy of the subject and, consequently, in the completion of the modern project. Discourse, law and democracy are intimately linked. The understanding of the democratic idea concerns the analysis of the various relations that are established between these three elements. According to his vision, discourse and democracy are two sides of the same coin, mediated by the law. Once legally institutionalized, the discourse principle is transformed into the principle of democracy. Both, however, share a common source, since all political power has to be extracted from the communicative power of the citizens.13 If, according to the discourse principle, the rules that claim validity must command the potential assent of all individuals, the principle of democracy guarantees the reasonable process of political opinion- and will-formation through the institutionalization of a system of rights that assures equal participation to each individual in a process of legislation.14 The crucial importance of law lies in its potential to institutionalize procedures that guarantee the formative principles of discourse theory. The result, therefore, is a procedural theory that measures the legitimacy of juridical norms in terms of the rationality of the democratic process of political legislation.15 The legitimacy of the results is grounded in the correct use of the procedure, which is discursive and deliberative and, therefore, democratic.16 When it mediates the relation between discourse and democracy, law takes on an essential role in linking the lifeworld, which is governed by communicative action, and the system, comprised of the subsystems of the economy and public administration, which are governed by instrumental reason. In this sense, it is also through law, and through a normative perspective, that, as poses Habermas:
Habermas concept of deliberative democracy can be claried in terms of the distinction he draws between the republican and liberal visions of citizenship. He sees deliberative politics as theoretically situated in an intermediate position between these two perspectives, and constructed with elements of both. Like the republican vision, the procedural alternative based on discourse theory understands democracy as an essentially communicative process, giving pride of place to the process of political opinion- and will-formation. The democratic paradigm replaces the competition between interests typical of the market paradigm with dialogue. Since debate about laws and policies concerns questions of the common good and the justice of political society, the deliberative perspective stands in direct contrast to the elitist and pluralist conceptions, which are based on competition between group interests.18 Moreover, it retains the instrumental component, given the need to reach political compromises, which represents the pragmatic dimension of politics, although this dimension is also subject to procedures justied by criteria of justice.19 The reduction of excessive ethical charge and the careful introduction of procedures governing compromise between interests renders the democratic conception less idealistic than the republican view and less utilitarian than the liberal perspective. The establishment of an ideal procedure for deliberation and decision-making processes, which is drawn from the interaction of these two perspectives, depends on the adequate institutionalization of corresponding communicative forms. In this sense, the success of deliberative politics depends not on a collectively acting citizenry but on the institutionalization of the corresponding procedures and conditions of communication, as well as on the interplay of institutionalized deliberative processes with informally developed public opinions.20 When these two elements are synthesized, the processes and communicative presuppositions of deliberative politics become the focal point of the discursive alternative, legislated within a constitutional framework. As such, the processes and conditions for the process of democratic opinion- and will-formation are institutionalized through the medium of law, crystallizing in a group of fundamental rights in the institutionalized deliberations of the parliaments and in the informal ow of communication from the public sphere.
Clearly, deliberation will not be fostered by the institutionalization of mechanical, non-interactive direct decision-making procedures that are inadequately organized and subject to manipulation. And only the rational principle of deliberation can guarantee the legitimacy of the decisions. The debate about deliberative democracy seems to focus primarily on the parliamentary sphere, that is, on the representative system. It is worth noting, however, that representative democracy shares some of the same shortcomings as direct democracy, since under certain conditions it too lacks the prerequisites of the deliberative process. Lobbying, corruption, private campaign nancing, manipulation of the media, lack of publicity and transparency in political parties as well as in the government; hierarchical and bureaucratized party structures and low levels of voter turn-out are problems of representative democracies that seriously challenge the legitimacy of any deliberative aspiration.71 Despite the inevitable problems and distortions that exist in any democratic institution, the great virtue of deliberative theory is that it illuminates the exact dimensions of the aspiration to legitimacy: the deliberative process of opinion- and will-formation among free and equal citizens, the presumptions and pre-conditions of which must be legally institutionalized. This dimension certainly qualied the debates on participation during the late 1960s and 1970s, and raised the discussion to levels of abstraction more appropriate to modern complexity. Nevertheless, the opposite is also true. It is necessary to retrieve the debate on participation in order to ascertain the real potential of deliberative politics. The focus on substantive democracy, grounded on a
PSC
Notes
I would like to thank Nadia Urbinati, Douglas Chalmers, Alessandro Pinzani and Aysen Candas Bilgen for their very useful comments on drafts of this essay. 1 Jrgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984[1981]), p. 163. 2 Max Weber, Religious Rejections of the World and their Directions, in H. Gerth and C. W. Mills (eds) From Max Weber: Essays on Sociology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), pp. 32359. 3 Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, pp. 1657, 23740. 4 Instruments of mediation are needed if the imbalance among the spheres of knowledge that comprise the lifeworld is to be avoided. Jrgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987[1985]), pp. 208, 340. 5 Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, p. 70. 6 Jrgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. II, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1987), p. 134. 7 Weber, Bureaucracy, in From Max Weber: Essays on Sociology, p. 230. 8 ibid., pp. 2302. 9 Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, p. 183.
24 25 26
27 28 29 30
31 32 33 34
35
36
41 42
43
44
45 46 47
59
60 61
62
63
64
65 66