501 10 08
501 10 08
501 10 08
Rice University
ECO 501: Microeconomic Theory I
———————————————–
Lecture 10: Risk
———————————————–
Christian Roessler
November 5, 2008
1 Money Lotteries
A lottery over continuous amounts of money x 2 R can be described
most generally in terms of its cumulative distribution function F : R !
[0; 1]. (The more direct approach would be to use density functions
f ( ), but these do not always exists and exclude
Rx the case of discrete
outcomes. If f ( ) does exist, then F (x) = 1 f (t) dt.)
R(Note that f (x)R dF (x) =dx, so that dF (x) = f (x) dx, and thus
u (x) dF (x) = u (x) f (x) dx whenever the density exists.)
1
that u ( ) is increasing, continuous and bounded. (If it were unbounded,
small probability events could make a lottery in…nitely desirable - the
St. Petersburg paradox.)
2 Risk Attitude
A risk-averse agent is someone who rejects fair gambles (that have
neither an expected gain nor loss).
The criterion for risk aversion implies, when U ( ) has the expected
utility form, Z Z
u xdF (x) u (x) dF (x) :
2
Figure 1: Bernoulli utility functions for risk-averter (left) and risk-seeker
(right)
utility increases more slowly with gain than it decreases with a loss.
Since the agent has, in utility terms, more to lose than gain from a
lottery that is fair in money terms, she declines the lottery unless the
odds are strictly favorable.
3
Figure 2: Certainty equivalent for risk-averter (left) and risk-seeker (right)
u ( ): Z
u (c (F; u)) = u (x) dF (x) :
4
Beyond these formal characterizations, risk-averse behavior is evident
in the propensity to buy insurance, even when premia are not "actuar-
ially fair" (i.e. the expected payout is less than the premium).
Example. A strictly risk averse agent with initial wealth w faces a possible
damage of $D with probability . The agent is o¤ered insurance at a fair
premium per dollar-payout in the event of a loss. If dollars of insurance
(i.e. conditional payout) are purchased at this premium, the agent’s wealth
will be either w (if no damage occurs) or w D+ = w+
(1 ) D (if there is damage). Expected utility from a choice of ,
which induces a lottery over w + (1 ) D and w with probabilities
( ;1 ), is then
U ( ) = u (w + (1 ) D) + (1 ) u (w ):
u0 (w + (1 ) D) = u0 (w );
(at anRinterior solution). Since the left side is greater than zero at = 0,
given zdF (z) > 1 and that u ( ) is increasing everywhere, we must have
5
> 0, whether or not the individual is risk-averse. The general principle
is that an agent will always invest some share of wealth in an actuarially
favorable asset.
De…nition. The Arrow-Pratt coe¢ cient of absolute risk aversion is, for a
twice di¤erentiable Bernoulli utility function u ( ) at x,
u00 (x)
rA (x; u) = :
u0 (x)
6
sides, we have u0 (x) =u (x) = @ ln u (x) =@x = a, and integrating once more
on both sides, u (x) = e ax , i.e. the utility function is exponential when the
Arrow-Pratt coe¢ cient is constant. I have constructed one particular utility
function, assuming the integration constants are zero, but others are still
exponential (solve the di¤erential equation to see this). Exponential utility
functions therefore constitute the CARA (constant absolute risk aversion)
class.
The DARA class of Bernoulli utility functions has the plausible prop-
erty that wealthier people tend to be less risk-averse.
De…nition. The coe¢ cient of relative risk aversion is, for a twice di¤eren-
tiable Bernoulli utility function u ( ) at x,
u00 (x)
rR (x; u) = x :
u0 (x)
7
3 Stochastic Dominance
Up to now, we have compared agents in terms of the risk aversion
exhibited by their utility functions. Now we are interested in compar-
ing lotteries and …nding criteria by which they can be ranked, given
properties of preference, such as risk attitude.
If distribution F yields a higher expected utility than lottery G, re-
gardless of risk attitude (i.e. the speci…c form of the Bernoulli utility
function), F is said to …rst-order stochastically dominate G.
8
The next results make use of some integral relationships that may be
found through "integration by parts." The technique is based on the
product rule applied to u (x) F (x):
d
u (x) F (x) = u0 (x) F (x) + u (x) f (x)
dx
implies
d
u (x) f (x) = u (x) F (x) u0 (x) F (x)
dx
and, integrating both sides,
Z Z
u (x) f (x) dx = u0 (x) F (x) dx;
and Z Z Z x
0 1 00
u (x) F (x) dx = u (x) F (t) dt dx:
2 1
R1
(where is a constant, since 21 u0 (1) 1
F (t) dt = 12 u0 (1)).
Hence
Z Z
u (x) dF (x) = u0 (x) F (x) dx
Z Z x
1 00
= + u (x) F (t) dt dx:
2 1
9
Proposition. The payo¤ distribution F ( ) …rst-order stochastically domi-
nates G ( ) if and only if 8x, F (x) G (x).
Proof.R (If) Let F (x) GR(x) for all x. From Rintegration by parts,
we
R 0 have u (x) dF (x) = u0 (x) F (x) dx and u (x) dG (x) =
u (x) G (x) dx, so
Z Z Z Z
0 0
u (x) F (x) dx u (x) G (x) dx () u (x) dF (x) u (x) dG (x) :
Rx Rx
Proof. (If) Let 1 F (t) dt 1
G (t) dt for all x. From integrating
R R Rx
by parts, we have u (x) dF (x) = + 21 u00 (x) 1 F (t) dt dx and
R R Rx
u (x) dG (x) = + 12 u00 (x) 1 G (t) dt dx. If u ( ) is concave, then
u00 (x) < 0, so
Z x Z x Z Z
F (t) dt G (t) dt () u (x) dF (x) u (x) dG (x) :
1 1
10
Hence F second-order Rdominates G. R
x x
(Only if) Suppose 1 F (t) dt > 1 G (t) dt for some x. To show that
F fails to second-order
R dominateR G, we need to …nd a concave function
u ( ) such that u (t) dF (t) < u (t) dG (t) at x. Let u (t) = t, except
R x0 R x0
in an interval [x; x] containing x where 1 F (t) dt > 1 G (t) dt for all
x0 2 [x; x]. On this interval, let u (t) be strictly concave.
From integration by parts,
Z Z Z Z x Z Z x
00 00
u (t) dF (t) > u (t) dG (t) () u (x) F (t) dt dx > u (x) G (t) dt dx:
1 1
Since u00 (x) = 0 for all x 2= [x; x] and u00 (x) < 0 for all x 2 [x; x], where
Rx Rx R
F (t) dt > x G (t) dt, the left inequality cannot hold, so u (x) dF (x) <
R x
u (x) dG (x). This means G SOSD F , a contradiction.
Example. Consider two lotteries that reward outcomes of rolling a fair die.
F gives $1 if a number up to 3 is rolled and $2 if the number is greater
than 3. G pays nothing for a 1 and $5 for a 6, and $1 otherwise. These
lotteries have the same mean, 3=2, and probabilities (1=2; 1=2) over ($1; $2),
respectively (1=6; 2=3; 1=6) over ($0; $1; $5). To obtain G from F , replace
the $1 and $2 wins in F with lotteries that give ($0; $1; $5) respectively with
probabilities (1=3; 7=12; 1=12) and (0; 3=4; 1=4). Observe that the expected
values of these lotteries are $1 and $2. The compound lottery over ($0; $1; $5)
that plays (1=3; 7=12; 1=12) and (0; 3=4; 1=4) with equal probability reduces
to (1=6; 2=3; 1=6) = G. So we have constructed G as a mean-preserving
spread of F , i.e. F %SOSD G.
11
is the lottery (7=10; 0; 3=10). This is a mean-preserving spread via lotteries
(1; 0; 0), (4=5; 0; 1=5) and (0; 0; 1) in place of the $0, $1 and $5 wins.
12