4 Efficient Process Tracing: Analyzing The Causal Mechanisms of European Integration
4 Efficient Process Tracing: Analyzing The Causal Mechanisms of European Integration
4 Efficient Process Tracing: Analyzing The Causal Mechanisms of European Integration
Frank Schimmelfennig
Introduction
An earlier version was presented at the workshop on “Process Tracing in the Social Sciences,” Georgetown
University, March 2012. I thank the editors, Alan Jacobs, and the other the participants of the workshop, as
well as Andrew Moravcsik and Craig Parsons for helpful comments.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
99 Efficient process tracing: European integration
broad functional scope – the EU covers all policy areas and some of them are
exclusive competences of the Union – makes it an outlier in the population of
international organizations. As a consequence, most students of European
integration prefer focusing on within-case analysis rather than comparing
the development of the EU to that of other organizations and polities.
In addition, European integration is generally studied as a series or sequence
of individual big decisions: for instance, to establish the common market or
monetary union, to expand to Eastern Europe and start accession negotiations
with Turkey, to empower the European Parliament, or to conclude separate
treaties on free travel (Schengen) and fiscal stability outside the Community
framework. In the first decades of European integration, such big decisions were
arguably too rare, too causally heterogeneous, or too dependent on each other,
to qualify for comparative analysis.
Even though these obstacles do not necessarily hold any more, there are
also theoretical reasons for process tracing. Many of the theoretical con-
troversies in the study of European integration have to do with motivation
and process. Take the traditional theoretical debate between intergovern-
mentalism and neofunctionalism (or supranationalism). Both schools of
thought broadly agree that governments negotiate and decide on integration
in order to cope with international interdependence. They disagree, how-
ever, regarding the sources of interdependence, the nature and sources of
government preferences, the relevant actors in negotiations, and the ways in
which decisions are reached.
Liberal intergovernmentalism (Moravcsik 1993; 1998) claims that inter-
dependence is exogenous (to the integration process); government prefer-
ences are conditioned by the interests of powerful domestic interest groups;
negotiations are intergovernmental; and outcomes are determined by the
relative bargaining power of governments. By contrast, supranationalists
(Pierson 1996; Stone Sweet and Sandholtz 1997) argue that interdependence
is endogenous, i.e. generated by the “spill-over” of previous integration
decisions; government preferences are reshaped and constrained by such
spill-overs in addition to transnational interest groups and supranational
institutions; and both negotiations and their outcomes are influenced
by supranational actors such as the Commission. The more recent arrival
of constructivism added more variation to this debate. According to con-
structivism, ideas matter for how governments deal with interdependence;
government preferences are constituted by identities; and negotiations and
their outcomes are constrained by European norms (Schimmelfennig 2012).
Finally, on a more methodological note, studies of European integration are
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
100 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
101 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
102 Frank Schimmelfennig
Resource
It is generally agreed that process tracing can “require enormous amounts of
information” (George and Bennett 2005: 223). To some extent, the process-
tracing best practices proposed in Chapter 1 are general standards of good
scientific practice: the search for alternative explanations, the consideration of
potential bias in sources, and the gathering of diverse evidence. In addition,
any research design needs to make a decision on how far “down” and “back”
the researcher wants to go in the search for “the cause.”
In process tracing, however, the per-unit (case) investment of time and
resources is likely to be much higher than in comparative analyses. This has
mainly to do with design: whereas comparative analysis may work with a
few data-set observations per case measuring the independent variables
and the dependent variable, the sequence of causal-process observations in
process-tracing analysis can become very long. This is especially true if
process taking is of the “soaking and poking” kind requiring immersion in
the details of a case (Chapter 1, p. 18) or if researchers heed the warning by
George and Bennett that process tracing “provides a strong basis for causal
inference only if it can establish an uninterrupted causal path” (George and
Bennett 2005: 222). Because we never really know whether we have soaked
and poked enough, and any causal path can always be more fine-grained
and extended into history, process tracers are at risk of ending up in an
“infinite regress.” Moreover, process tracing analyses cannot use the stan-
dardized, computer-based data-processing techniques on offer for com-
parative analysis.1 Finally, process tracing analyses generally take up much
more space – again on a per-case basis – for presenting findings than
comparative analyses.
1
A partial exception would be the application of agent-based modeling to process-tracing accounts, as
discussed by Checkel, this volume, Chapter 3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
103 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Measures of fit
How do we know that the process-tracing evidence is good enough to accept
or discard a hypothesis? Statistical analyses work with levels of significance for
individual factors or measures of fit for entire models. Qualitative comparative
analysis (QCA) (Ragin 1987) tests for necessity and sufficiency of conditions,
and uses consistency and coverage to assess the fit of causal configurations.
Both designs benefit from analyzing a data set with clearly delineated and
(ideally) independent units of analysis and a defined number of observations.
Such formal measures of significance and fit do not seem to exist in process
tracing. In part, this has to do with “the non-comparability of adjacent pieces
of evidence” in process tracing (Gerring 2007a: 178; Beach and Pedersen
2013a: 72–76). The units of process tracing, the individual steps in a causal
path or the elements of a causal sequence, are neither independent nor
comparable. Moreover, Gerring claims that the elements of the causal
process chosen by the researcher, and how many of them, can be arbitrary
(Gerring 2007a: 179). It is also difficult to say what qualifies as an “uninter-
rupted” causal path in George and Bennett’s criterion for causal inference.
Finally, whereas Bayes’s Theorem provides a general standard for evaluating
process-level evidence, its application to process tracing remains informal and
less quantifiable than the measures of fit for QCA with which process-tracing
shares the non-frequentist mode of inference (Bennett 2008: 708–709;
Bennett, this volume, Appendix).
Storytelling
Because the standards for selecting causal-process observations and making
valid inferences are relatively open and malleable in process tracing, it is
relatively easy to select, arrange, and present the material more or less con-
sciously in a way that appears plausible to the reader (see also the discussion in
Dunning, this volume, Chapter 8). We may extend Popper’s classical critique
of empiricism by saying that humans have an innate propensity not only for
seeing patterns and regularities (Popper 1963: 62), but also for constructing
and telling coherent stories.
Generalization
Whereas process tracing maximizes the internal validity of causal inferences,
it does not generate any external validity per se. In all fairness, process
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
104 Frank Schimmelfennig
tracing is not meant to produce external validity, and other methods suffer
from the same trade-off between internal and external validity. However, in
combination with the high costs of process tracing for producing a highly
valid explanation of a single event of the past, the uncertainty about general-
izability can be discouraging (see also Checkel and Bennett, this volume,
Chapter 10).
The ten criteria of good process tracing proposed by Bennett and Checkel
go a long way in acknowledging these challenges and devising ways to bound
them (Chapter 1, pp. 20–22). “Efficient process tracing” builds on these
criteria, in particular on the Bayesian intuition guiding process-tracing
inferences, but seeks to increase the efficiency of theory-testing process-
tracing designs.
Efficient solutions
I suggest that process tracing deals best with these challenges and is used most
efficiently if it is complementary to the analysis of congruence or covariation;
if it is used on cases that promise a maximum of external validity; if the causal
mechanism is specified ex ante; and if the process links to be examined are
carefully selected to provide for crucial, competitive theory tests.
Complementarity
First, process tracing is best used to complement analyses of congruence
(for single cases) and comparative analyses (for two or more cases). The
high investment in process tracing is most efficient if we have an “initial
suspicion” that the causal mechanism has actually been at work and
effective. For a single case, preliminary evidence is given if the values for
the outcome and the explanatory factor(s) match the hypothetical expecta-
tion (congruence). Statistically significant and substantively relevant
correlations serve as a useful starting point in quantitative studies. In
QCA, conditional configurations with high consistency and substantial
coverage are worth exploring further. Process tracing then serves the
purpose of checking the causal mechanism that is supposed to link the
factors or configurations with the outcome. Sometimes, it may also be
interesting to find out why a condition that is present and that we assumed
to be causally relevant did not produce the outcome – but even for process
tracing of a deviant case, we need first to establish the relationship between
cause and effect to know that it is deviant.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
105 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Case selection
If process tracing follows a single-case congruence analysis or explores a
deviant case, case selection is not an issue. If it is designed to probe further
into the causal validity of small-n or large-n correlations, however, the
researcher needs to decide which case or cases to select for process tracing –
assuming that it is so resource-intensive that it can only be conducted for
one or two cases. This selection should again be based on considerations of
efficiency: to maximize external validity while checking internal validity.
Gerring and Seawright suggest selecting a typical case, which represents a
cross-case relationship well, to explore causal mechanisms (Gerring 2007a:
93; Seawright and Gerring 2008: 299). If there is time for two process tracing
analyses, the study of diverse cases that illuminate the full range of variation
in the population is also advisable in order to see how the causal mechanism
plays out for different starting conditions (Gerring 2007a: 97–99; Seawright
and Gerring 2008: 300–301). Both typical and diverse case-study types
maximize external validity on the basis of the assumption that the findings
of process tracing in the selected case(s) are representative for the entire
population.
Alternatively, the process tracing analysis of a crucial case also pro-
mises to be efficient. When dealing with positive outcomes, the best case
is a hard or least-likely case. Based on theoretical expectations, the
researchers choose a case in which the presumed cause is only weakly
present, whereas presumed counteracting factors are strong. If process
tracing shows that the causal process triggered by the presumed cause
produces the positive outcome nevertheless, there is good reason
to conclude that this is even more likely in cases in which the
causal condition is more strongly present and counteracting factors are
weaker.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
106 Frank Schimmelfennig
2
“Coleman’s bathtub” or “boat” refers to the way in which James Coleman’s scheme of macro-micro-
macro linkages is usually drawn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
107 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
108 Frank Schimmelfennig
1. Cast the net widely for alternative explanations Yes, but focus on those that are compatible with
findings from analysis of congruence or correlation
2. Be equally tough on the alternative Yes, but eliminate them if their core causal-process
explanations expectations are disconfirmed
4. Take into account whether the case is most Yes, but also select representative or crucial cases in
or least likely for alternative explanations order to maximize external validity
5. Make a justifiable decision on when to start Yes, but let this decision be guided by the relevant
theories and standard analytical templates
6. Be relentless in gathering diverse and relevant Yes, but limit yourself to the evidence that is needed to
evidence discriminate between competing theories
7. Combine process tracing with case Yes, but start with comparison to establish correlation
comparisons and select the best case for process tracing
8. Be open to inductive insights Yes, if theoretically specified causal mechanisms fail to
explain the case
Table 4.1 illustrates how “efficient process tracing” builds on and further
develops most of the process-tracing “best practices” advanced in Chapter 1.
Efficient process tracing strongly concurs with the advice to specify testable
process-tracing expectations deductively (criterion 9), and it agrees with the
caveats that process tracers need to consider biases in the evidentiary sources
(criterion 3) and take into account that process tracing may be inconclusive in
the end (criterion 10). For the other criteria, it puts the emphasis on efficiency-
enhancing deduction, selection, and generalizability. Deduction helps us make
a justifiable decision on when to start and how to specify causal mechanisms
(criterion 5); it helps us design more decisive and focused tests (criteria 2 and
6); and it limits the relevance of inductive insights to instances of general
theory failure (criterion 8). Selection of theories based on prior evidence
derived from congruence or correlation limits the number of explanations
to be considered (criteria 1 and 7); and selection of cases based on representa-
tiveness increases external validity and generalizability (criterion 4).
In this main part of the chapter, I present and discuss examples from the
literature on European integration. As already mentioned in the introduction,
many if not most studies of integration use process tracing as their main
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
109 Efficient process tracing: European integration
National
Stages of preference
negotiation formation Interstate bargaining Institutional choice
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
110 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
111 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
112 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
113 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
114 Frank Schimmelfennig
MICRO-LEVEL
ADAPTATIONS
(“Sunk Costs”) INSTITUTIONAL
INTERSTATE AND POLICY
BARGAINING MEMBER STATE OUTCOMES
BARGAINING
ACCUMULATED POWER
POLICY
CONSTRAINTS
HEAVILY
DISCOUNTED
INSTITUTIONAL OR UNINTENDED
AND POLICY EFFECTS POWER OF
OUTCOMES OTHER ACTORS
(e.g. European
Court)
TIME: T0 T1 T2
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
115 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
116 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
117 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
118 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
119 Efficient process tracing: European integration
view, we can ask again whether the analysis of this link is necessary. First, is
this link the crucial one for any of the competing theories? Second, is it
conceivable that structuralism or institutionalism explains the feedback
stage if the study shows that the French debate on European integration
does not follow structural lines (and that government leaders pursue
European policy independent of structural cleavages)? Both questions can
be answered in the affirmative. First, as I have argued in my criticism of
Moravcsik, the institutional feedback is central for neofunctionalism. Second,
Parsons argues that even if structural factors were indeterminate at the
beginning, structural signals may “have clarified over time” and shape
preferences at subsequent stages of the integration process (Parsons 2003: 15).
Were it correct, we would expect that the earlier dissidents’ adjustments traced to
identifiable structural shifts (economic, geopolitical, or electoral); that French groups
or parties displayed greater internal agreement before deciding on later institutional
steps (the imperatives forward now being clear); and that dissidents pointed to
exogenous pressures to justify their alignment. (Parsons 2003: 16)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
120 Frank Schimmelfennig
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
121 Efficient process tracing: European integration
incentives to admit the CEECs. First, the CEECs’ economic and trade
relevance for most member states was low. Second, the prospect of their
accession raised concerns about trade and budget competition. Third, massive
enlargement dilutes the old members’ voting power. Finally, the CEECs
depended much more on the EU than the other way around and did not
have the bargaining power to put pressure on the EU to admit them.
In contrast, a second congruence analysis based on sociological or con-
structivist institutionalism shows a strong fit of explanatory conditions and
outcome. Starting from the assumption that the EU is a community of liberal
European states, the sociological or constructivist hypothesis posits that all
liberal European states are entitled to membership in the EU if they so desire.
This holds even if their admission produces net costs for the organization or
individual old member states. In cases of conflict between material (economic)
interests and liberal community norms, the norm of liberal membership
overrides the economic interests and the superior bargaining power of
member states. The analysis shows that the EU invited those ex-communist
countries to accession negotiations that had consolidated liberal democracy;
in addition, those that had become consolidated democracies earlier were in
general also invited to membership talks earlier. In a next step, the book
reports a large-n event-history analysis of enlargement decisions in three
major Western European international organizations: the EU, NATO, and
the Council of Europe. This analysis confirms democracy in European non-
member countries as the most relevant factor of enlargement. In summary,
the study establishes a robust correlation between liberal democracy and
EU enlargement, which serves as a starting point for the exploration of the
causal mechanism linking community norms with enlargement decisions.
The need for process tracing arises from the fact that various modes of action
are theoretically compatible with the covariation between community norms
and enlargement decisions: habitual, normative, communicative, and rhetorical
action. I suggest that the causal mechanism of social action can be conceived as a
sequence of four stages or links (Schimmelfennig 2003: 157–159). The first is
cognitions, that is, the set of beliefs or ideas actors hold about the world and the
actors’ ways of thinking and making decisions. The second level is the goals
actors set for themselves and seek to attain through their actions. The third is
the individual behavior actors choose in light of their goals and cognitions.
Finally, two or more individual behaviors form an interaction that brings about
a collective outcome. Social norms can become influential at each of these stages
or levels. The earlier in the process they do, the deeper the institutional impact
on social action. Each of the four modes of action is based on the assumption
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
122 Frank Schimmelfennig
Table 4.3 Modes of action in The EU, NATO, and the Integration of Europe
Norm impact on
Habitual X X X X
Normative X X X
Communicative X X
Rhetorical X
Rational
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
123 Efficient process tracing: European integration
Finally, note that, even though process analysis results in a more narrative form of
presentation than the correlational outcome analysis of NATO and EU enlargement, I
do not provide a full chronological account of the enlargement decision-making
processes that one would expect in a historiographical perspective. Rather, I present
“analytical episodes” focused on examining the empirical implications of the process
hypotheses under scrutiny. These episodes sometimes violate the chronological order
and regularly neglect those aspects of the enlargement process that are not relevant for
hypothesis-testing. (Schimmelfennig 2003: 159)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
124 Frank Schimmelfennig
But was it necessary to study all five links in order to determine the causal
mechanism linking community norms and enlargement decisions? In hind-
sight, two of them appear redundant. First, since what really matters is the
decision-making of the international organization, the preferences of the appli-
cants do not seem to be relevant. The four modes of social action under study
could have been causally effective regardless of the motivations and goals of the
CEECs. (And, indeed, the analysis of their preferences proved inconclusive.)
Second, the brief analysis of subsequent enlargement rounds was not necessary
either. Even though this analysis provides further evidence for the rhetorical
action hypothesis, the effect of the first round of Eastern enlargement in the EU
or NATO was not crucial for any of the competing hypotheses nor needed to
discriminate between any of them. From the point of view of efficiency, it would
have been enough to study the member states’ enlargement preferences and
initial reactions as well as the subsequent negotiating behavior resulting in the
decision to admit the democratically consolidated CEECs.
Finally, I do not explicitly discuss the generalizability of the findings of the
process-tracing analysis. I chose the case of Eastern enlargement out of
interest in the issue and based on the perception that Eastern enlargement
was a highly relevant event in the history of European integration. Whereas it
is plausible to assume that Eastern enlargement constitutes a hard case for
rationalist institutionalism, it may well constitute an easy case for sociological
institutionalism. The external validity of my 2003 findings is thus uncertain
(see also Checkel, this volume, Chapter 3).
Conclusions
In this chapter, I have made the case for “efficient” process tracing, which
builds on the best practices advanced by Bennett and Checkel in the intro-
ductory chapter. However, I further elaborate on these practices to cope with
four core challenges that hamper the effectiveness and efficiency of process
tracing as an inferential method: the large amount of resources needed; the
absence of formal, quantifiable measures of fit; the temptation of storytelling;
and the limits to generalization.
As a partial remedy to these problems, I proposed making process tracing
complementary to analyses of congruence and correlation; selecting repre-
sentative or crucial cases; specifying causal mechanisms and their observable
implications ex ante and according to basic templates of analytic social
science; and designing process tracing as competitive theory testing with a
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007
125 Efficient process tracing: European integration
focus on the crucial process links on which the theories differ. Following these
recommendations, I suggest, helps us design harder tests, impedes storytell-
ing, reduces the required time and resources for conducting process tracing,
and improves generalizability. It thus makes process tracing both more
rigorous and more efficient.
There are several prerequisites of efficient process tracing. It requires
studies establishing congruence or correlation in our area of interest; theories
with a well-specified causal mechanism; and clear and observable implications
of this causal mechanism. These prerequisites for engaging in efficient process
tracing may not be fulfilled. This does not mean, however, that the researcher
should delve inductively into the case. Often, time and resources are better
spent by doing a comparative analysis that helps us pick a suitable case for
process tracing and by elaborating and operationalizing the causal mechan-
ism. In principle, social scientists have a big toolbox full of the “nuts and bolts”
or “cogs and wheels” (Elster 1989) to construct theoretically plausible and
consistent causal mechanisms deductively.
Efficient process tracing will also be undermined if either the implications
of the theories or the available evidence do not lend themselves to rigorous
tests that allow the researcher to accept and reject theories “beyond reasonable
doubt.” But this applies to research in general. Importantly, because of its
deductive design, efficient process tracing is more likely to alert us to problems
of indeterminacy than the inductive search for causal processes.
At the same time, efficient process tracing does come at a price in that it
passes over several features that researchers may particularly value. First, it
replaces the full narrative from cause to outcome with a few process snapshots.
Second, we may rashly accept an explanation if one theory quickly outper-
forms alternative explanations at an early stage of process-tracing analysis. It
may well be that this explanation would not have performed well at later stages
of the causal process or with regard to process links that were not tested
because they were uncontroversial. Third, by privileging hypothesis testing
over hypothesis generation or the open exploration of explanations, efficient
process tracing discourages or even prevents researchers from discovering
new causal mechanisms or process features. Fourth, efficient process tracing is
mainly designed to bring about scientific development. It is certainly not the
best approach to make process tracing relevant for policy.
As a final thought, we need to bear in mind that efficiency is about designing
process-tracing studies, rather than actually conducting the analysis. In the
end, the quality of the data, their analysis, and their interpretation are decisive
for the conclusions we draw on the basis of efficient process tracing.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Stockholm University Library, on 17 Mar 2021 at 07:10:20, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available
at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139858472.007