On The Teaching Situation of Conceptual Change: Epistemological Considerations of Irrational Numbers
On The Teaching Situation of Conceptual Change: Epistemological Considerations of Irrational Numbers
On The Teaching Situation of Conceptual Change: Epistemological Considerations of Irrational Numbers
Generally we can point out two different ways in introducing new kinds of numbers as
follows (e.g., Courant & Robbins, 1941/ 1996). The first is to represent a result of
measurement. The second is to solve algebraic equations. However the relation
between the two ways does not still seem to be clear. Although this issue might have
been overlooked in any teaching situations, this can be didactically explicit in the
teaching situation of irrational numbers from the conceptual change perspective. The
purpose of this paper is to derive some didactical implications for a conceptual change
situation by focusing on a knowing of “incommensurability” that can be an essential
aspect of irrationals. For attaining this purpose, the epistemological considerations
take place in three contexts: curricular contents, history and teaching experiment.
2007. In Woo, J. H., Lew, H. C., Park, K. S. & Seo, D. Y. (Eds.). Proceedings of the 31st Conference of
the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, Vol. 4, pp. 185-192. Seoul: PME. 4-185
Shinno
EPISTEMOLOGICAL CONSIDERATIONS
Issues in the mathematics curricular contents relating to irrational numbers
The significance of irrational numbers as a subject matter can be described as follows:
the existence of incommensurable quantity; its admittance and symbolism; curiosity
about that the computational rules with infinite non-repeating decimals are available
same as with rational numbers; and the rationale of the new number system, so on.
Irrational numbers are introduced in the forms of “square root numbers” at lower
secondary level (15-year-old students in the case of Japan). In the teaching situation of
the square root, it is usually introduced in light of the practical need to express the
concrete quantity (magnitude) as well as the teaching situations at the primary school
level. For examples, it has been often taken the instructional way for finding out the
length of the diagonal of the square, or the side of square having the double area of a
given square. Indeed “quantity” is an object of measurement. However a naïve
practical conception cannot reach to the essential understanding of the square root
because here we deal with “incommensurable quantity” in question. In addition, the
teaching situation of irrational numbers can distinguish the situation dealing with the
concrete quantity and the situation dealing with the computational rules following
introduction of the symbol√. In doing so, it is not just the transition between situations
but it is required to prepare mediated activities shifting from concrete/ practical
conception to more theoretical/ formal one.
Students come to learn new kinds of numbers as school year advances. The
introduction of new numbers must be a purposeful activity to respond to some
4-186 PME31―2007
Shinno
The situation is, however, by no means so simple. It was getting to be doubtful to the
existence of a kind of the segment, according to Boyer (1968), the Pythagorean's
successors raised the question of incommensurability in earlier than B.C.410. The
Euclid's Elements Book X Def. 1 states that “Those magnitude are said to be
commensurable which are measured by the same measure, and those
incommensurable which cannot have any common measure”(Heath, 1956, p.10). The
PME31―2007 4-187
Shinno
4-188 PME31―2007
Shinno
In the phase (i) and (ii), students worked on the task 1 and some extra tasks. They came
to know a conception of Euclidean algorithm under a concrete situation of finding the
GCD (greatest common divisor) of given two positive integers by folding a sheet and
by showing algebraic expressions. In the phase (ii), students recognized the fact that if
one finds a remainder then measure the previous measure by the remainder as a new
measure, and if one finds no remainder then the algorithm terminates; common
measure is found.
In the phase (iii), students worked on the task 2 by applying Euclidean algorithm to a
side of square and the diagonal (i.e. in the A3 standard sheet, the larger side is equal to
the diagonal of the square with the smaller side). Students developed gradually their
activities with the help of some geometrical relationship, which can be illustrated as
follows (Fig.1). In doing so, such operative activities could undergo a kind of thought
experiment.
C
J
r2 r2
D C
I
r1 r2 G
G
E
H
E
r1 r1
1
F r1
r1
A 1 B F
PME31―2007 4-189
Shinno
10 S4: The square…because if squares are found, then we can always find the right
isosceles triangle.
All participating students became aware of the constancy of the procedure though
above conversations. At the end, teacher suggested that the continued fraction might be
useful for formalizing the operative processes. As a result, we obtained the
development of the diagonal (=x) in the general form: (r: remainder)
1 1 1
x = 1+ r1 = 1+ = 1+ = … = 1+
1 r2 1
2+ 2+
r1 r1 2 +.
..
rn +1
O 2+
rn
It is well known that we can obtain an approximate value of the square root of 2
successively using the form above.
DIDACTICAL IMPLICATIONS
Let me summarize the main points that have made. Firstly the curricular contents show
that new numbers have been introducing from the practical need in the course of
learning, while irrationals tend to be introduced from theoretical need. But there are no
didactical opportunities to relate two different ways. Secondly the historical context
shows that the discovery of the incommensurability can lead to the theoretical nature of
mathematics by establishing the reductio ad absurdum. Thirdly the teaching
experiment shows that students can be minimally understood the conception of the
incommensurability under the thought experiment. As a result of such consideration, it
can be pointed out that as implications for designing the teaching in the conceptual
change situation, at least the following three items have to be taken into account.
(1) Questioning, say, is it possible to represent a result of measurement of
incommensurable magnitudes?
The numbers that students have already learned can be represented as a ratio of
integers, but students may not always be aware of this explicitly. Paradoxically say, the
“incommensurable” situation only enables them to be aware of “commensurability”.
There is no situation for appreciating the idea of dividing of unit, except for the
situation of introducing square root.
(2) Eliminating the tendency to cling to the “concrete”.
A conception of numbers clinging to the concrete has been well acting on the old
numbers (rationals) in taking into consideration of its existence, and these numbers can
become intuitive on the number line. However we should not overlook the following
remarks: ‘Nothing in our “intuition” can help us to “see” the irrational points as distinct
from the rational ones’ (Courant & Robbins, 1941/1996, p. 60). A practical conception
of quantities (magnitudes) involving the concrete cannot be a position to make the
incommensurability sense. It will be important to eliminate such a tendency
ontologically (it is also discussed in the case of negative numbers in
4-190 PME31―2007
Shinno
Hefendehl-Hebeker (1991)). It does not only suggest the instruction of square root
numbers by approaching to the existence of solution of x 2 = 2 . As a didactical
implication, the tasks used in the teaching experiment can be effective settings for
becoming aware of incommensurability. In short, context of justification in the history
could be recontextualized into the context of discovery in the classroom.
(3) Shifting on value judgments toward the mathematical knowledge
More important point to note is, belonging to ‘meta-mathematical layer’ in Sierpinska
& Lerman (1996)’ sense, what we aim at by developing Euclidean algorithm as a
learning activity. The interactive activities of operating with folding a sheet and
expressing its process have to lead to the activities by the thought-experiment. In doing
so, Euclidean algorithm is primitively regarded as a practical method, for applying it to
the material (real) objects, measuring the diagonal of square with its side. The view on
the method can undergo changes though students’ applying the method and then
deriving the theoretical conclusion from its infinite process. This implies students’
seeing as the ideal object. Under the thought-experiment it is expected or required for
students to shift their value judgments toward the mathematical knowledge underlying
item (1) and (2).
Appendix
The picture shows a student’s writing on the blackboard (T: the diagonal of the square; S: the
side of the square; a, b, c, d, e: remainders)
References
Balacheff, N. (1990). Future perspective for research in the psychology of mathematics
education. In Nesher, P. & Kilpatrick, J. (eds.), Mathematics and cognition: a research
synthesis by the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education. (pp.
135-148). Cambridge University Press.
Boyer, C. B. (1968). A history of mathematics. John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.
Courant, R. & Robbins, H. (1941/1996). What is mathematics?. Oxford University Press.
diSessa, A. A. (2006). A history of conceptual change research. In Sawyer, R. K. (ed). The
Cambridge Handbook of the Learning Sciences.(pp.265-281) Cambridge University Press.
PME31―2007 4-191
Shinno
Fischbein, E., Jehiam, R., Cohen, C. (1994). The irrational numbers and the corresponding
epistemological obstacles. In da Ponte, J. P. & Matos, J. F. (eds.), Proc. 18th Conf. of the Int.
Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, (Vol. 2, pp. 352-359). Lisbon.
Hashweh, M. Z. (1986). Toward an explanation of conceptual change. European Journal of
science education, 8(3), 229-249.
Heath, T. L. (1956). The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. Dover Publications, Inc.
Hefendehl-Hebeker, L. (1991). Negative numbers: obstacles in their evolution from intuitive
to intellectual constructs. For the Learning of Mathematics, 11(1), 26-32
Iwasaki, H. (2004). Developing mathematics lessons that encourage students’ awareness of
incommensurability: what a student Ta’s activities suggest us for improving our teaching
methods, An occasional paper for International Mathematics Education Workshop with
Prof. Dr. E. Ch. Wittmann, Nara University of Education.
Merenluoto, K. & Lehtinen, E. (2004). Number concept and conceptual change: towards a
systemic model of the processes of change. Learning and Instruction, 14, 519-539.
Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., Gertzog, W. A.(1982).Accommodation of a
scientific conception: toward a theory of conceptual change. Science Education, 66(2),
211-227.
Radford, L. (1997). On psychology, historical epistemology, and the teaching of
mathematics: towards a socio-cultural history of mathematics. For the Learning of
Mathematics, 17(1), 26-33.
Sierpinska, A. & Lerman, S. (1996). Epistemologies of mathematics and of mathematics
education. In Bishop, A. et al.(eds.), International Handbook of Mathematics Education,
(Part 2, pp. 827-876). Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Szabó, Á. (1969/ 1978). Anfänge der griechischen Mathematik. Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.
(Japanese translation in 1978 by Tamagawa University Press)
Tirosh, D. & Tsamir, P. (2006). Conceptual change in mathematics learning: the case of
infinite sets (Research Forum), In Novotná, J., Moraová, H., Krátká, M.. & Stehlíková, N.
(eds.), Proc. 30th Conf. of the Int. Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education,
(Vol. 1, pp. 155-184). Prague.
Vosniadou, S., Ioannides, C., Dimitrakopoulou, A., & Papademetriou, E. (2001). Designing
learning environments to promote conceptual change in science. Learning and Instruction,
11, 381-419.
Vosniadou, S. & Verschaffel, L.(2004). Extending the conceptual change approach to
mathematics learning and teaching. Learning and Instruction, 14, 445-451.
Wilder, R. L. (1968/ 1987). Relativity of standards of mathematical rigor. In Wiener, P. P.
(ed.). Dictionary of the History of Ideas. (Japanese translation in 1987 by Heibonsya)
Zazkis, R. & Sirotic, N. (2004). Making sense of irrational numbers: focusing on
representation. In Høines, M. J. & Fuglestad, A. B. (eds), Proc. 28th Conf. of the Int. Group
for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, (Vol. 4, pp. 497-504). Bergen.
4-192 PME31―2007