The Non Fictional Origins and History of
The Non Fictional Origins and History of
The Non Fictional Origins and History of
Contents.
Chapter 1 : Early beginnings.
Never Grasped.
ideas.
Calculus Confusion.
Calculus".
of change?
Chapter 9 : Mythmatics.
later.
calculus is flawed.
is gaslighting you.
Preface:
In the ancient Greek world, early ideas of calculus focused
on methods to determine areas bounded by curves. Later,
titans of mathematics Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz
sought techniques for finding slopes of tangent lines - a
monumentally difficult problem they failed to solve in a
systematic way.
Chapter 1.
Early beginnings.
I, John Gabriel, was born in Khartoum, Sudan as the
fourth of six children. Even as a toddler, I displayed
tremendous curiosity about the world around me,
frequently questioning physical phenomena I observed. At
just 11 months old, I was alarmed to notice my shadow
followed me as I moved. When I reported this oddity to my
mother, she calmly explained the behavior was caused by
sunlight. As another childhood fear, hemispheres like a
football sliced in half frightened me for reasons I never
fully grasped.
An avid reader.
7
An alternative approach?
I grappled with the contradictions of [MD], realizing no
ratio involving 𝒇 could actually produce its derivative,
regardless of how small 𝒉 became (and 𝒉 could never
reach 𝟎). I attempted an alternative - replacing 𝒉 with 𝒘,
𝒏
where 𝒘 is a fixed interval length, and 𝒏 the number of
equal partitions:
𝒇 𝒙+𝒘 −𝒇(𝒙)
𝒇′ 𝒙 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 𝒏
𝒘 [FA]
𝒏 →∞ 𝒏
Chapter 2.
Understanding Area.
In pondering the slope-area connection, a fundamental
question arose: what precisely constitutes mathematical
area? Could a general definition encompass any surface,
regardless of shape?
Chapter 3.
The Realisation Mainstream Academics Never
Grasped
Unlike most students, I never accepted textbook dogma
uncritically - recognizing even esteemed scholars may err.
Was I simply too dim to comprehend accepted methods?
No - my extraordinary IQ refuted that. Would I follow the
herd without independent thought? Absolutely not. My
quest was for truth, wherever it led - offending orthodoxy
mattered naught.
Proof:
From the MVT: 𝒇′ 𝒄 = 𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇(𝒙)
, it is easy to prove that
𝒉
𝒇′ 𝒄 is a level magnitude (commonly known incorrectly as
arithmetic mean) of all the 𝒚–ordinates of 𝒇′ 𝒙 in
(𝒙,𝒙 + 𝒉).
One may protest not all ordinates are captured this way.
However, my proof will show, using a telescoping sum,
that complete inclusion is unnecessary. I define the
derivative as:
𝒇 𝒙+𝒘 −𝒇(𝒙)
𝒇′ 𝒙 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 𝒏
𝒘 [ND]
𝒏→∞ 𝒏
𝒇 𝒙+(𝒌+𝟏)𝒘 −𝒇 𝒙+𝒌𝒘
𝐥𝐢𝐦 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝒌𝒘 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 𝒏
𝒘
𝒏
[PD]
𝒏→∞ 𝒏 𝒏→∞ 𝒏
Let's assume that the LHS (left hand side) of [MVT], that
is, 𝒇′ 𝒄 is a level magnitude (also known incorrectly as
arithmetic mean) of ALL (**) the ('innumerably many') 𝒚
ordinates of 𝒇′ 𝒙 in the interval (𝒙,𝒙 + 𝒘), then
𝒇′ 𝒄 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 𝟏 ∑ 𝑛−1
𝑘=0 𝒇′ 𝒙 +
𝒌𝒘
𝒏→∞ 𝒏 𝒏
Note that the area must lie entirely above axis or entirely
below it. It makes no sense to find the arithmetic mean of
both positive and negative distances at the same time.
So,
𝒇′ 𝒄 = 𝟏 ∑ 𝒏−𝟏
𝒌=𝟎 𝒇 ′ 𝒙 + 𝒌𝝎
𝒏 𝒏
𝟏 𝒏−𝟏
∑ 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝒌𝝎 =
𝒏 𝒌=𝟎 𝒏
𝒍𝒊𝒎 𝟏 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝝎 + 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝟐𝝎 +
𝒏→∞ 𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝒏−𝟏
𝟏 𝒌𝝎
𝒇′ 𝒙 +
𝒏 𝒌=𝟎 𝒏
𝟏 𝒏 𝝎 𝟐𝝎 𝝎
= 𝒍𝒊𝒎 𝒍𝒊𝒎 𝒇 𝒙+ −𝒇 𝒙 +𝒇 𝒙+ −𝒇 𝒙+
𝒏→∞ 𝒏 𝒏→∞ 𝝎 𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝟑𝝎 𝟐𝝎 𝒏−𝟏 𝝎
+𝒇 𝒙+ −𝒇 𝒙+ +… +𝒇 𝒙+
𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝒏−𝟐 𝝎 𝒏−𝟏 𝝎
−𝒇 𝒙+ +𝒇 𝒙+𝒘 −𝒇 𝒙+
𝒏 𝒏
𝒏−𝟏
𝟏 𝒌𝝎 𝟏 𝒏
𝒇′ 𝒙 + = 𝒍𝒊𝒎 𝒍𝒊𝒎 𝒇 𝒙 + 𝝎 − 𝒇(𝒙)
𝒏 𝒌=𝟎 𝒏 𝒏→∞ 𝒏 𝒏→∞ 𝝎
𝒇 𝒙 + 𝝎 − 𝒇(𝒙)
= = 𝒇′(𝒄)
𝝎
And this is what was expected. Replacing 𝒙 by 𝒂 and
letting 𝝎 = 𝒃 − 𝒂, we have the ubiquitous form:
𝒇′ 𝒄 = 𝒇 𝒃 −𝒇(𝒂)
𝒃−𝒂
Thus, 𝑨𝒓𝒆𝒂 = 𝒇 𝒃 −𝒇 𝒂
× 𝒃 − 𝒂 = 𝒇 𝒃 − 𝒇(𝒂)
𝒃−𝒂
27
𝑓 𝑥+ℎ −𝑓(𝑥)
= 𝑓′ 𝑥 + 𝑄(𝑥,ℎ) is the slope formula.
ℎ
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇(𝒙)
is the slope of a non-parallel secant line.
𝒉
𝒓𝒊𝒔𝒆
The slope formula is expressed as .
𝒓𝒖𝒏
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇(𝒙)
= 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝒉
𝒏 𝒏−𝟏 𝒏 𝒏−𝟐 𝟐
𝒙 𝒏+ 𝒙 𝒉+ 𝒙 𝒉 +…+𝒉𝒏 −𝒙𝒏
𝟏 𝟐 = 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝒉
𝒏 𝒏−𝟏 𝒏 𝒏−𝟐
𝒙 + 𝒙 𝒉 + … + 𝒉𝒏−𝟏 = 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝟏 𝟐
29
Thus,
𝒏 𝒏−𝟏
𝒙 = 𝒇′ 𝒙
𝟏
𝒏
Or 𝒇′ 𝒙 = 𝒏𝒙𝒏−𝟏 since 𝒏 =
𝟏
𝒇 𝒙+𝟐𝒉 −𝒇 𝒙+𝒉
𝒇′ 𝒙+𝒉 +𝑸 𝒙 + 𝒉, 𝒉 = 𝒏 𝒏
𝒏 𝒏 𝒏 𝒉
𝒏
...
30
(𝒏−𝟏)𝒉 𝒉 (𝒏−𝟏)𝒉
(𝒏−𝟏)𝒉 (𝒏−𝟏)𝒉 𝒉 𝒇 𝒙+ + −𝒇 𝒙+
𝒇′ 𝒙+ +𝑸 𝒙+ , = 𝒏 𝒏
𝒉
𝒏
𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝒏
Note that the right hand side sum telescopes, and all the
purple terms cancel out to give 𝒇 𝒙+𝒉𝒉−𝒇(𝒙).
𝒏
Thus, summing the left hand side and the right hand side,
we get:
𝒉𝒊
∑ 𝒏−𝟏
𝒊=𝟎 𝒇 ′ 𝒙 + + 𝑸 𝒙 + 𝒉𝒊 , 𝒉
=𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇(𝒙)
𝒏 𝒏 𝒏 𝒉
𝒏
𝒉𝒊 𝒉
Let 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)=∑ 𝒏−𝟏
𝒊=𝟎 𝑸 𝒙 + , 𝒏 𝒏
𝒉𝒊
∑ 𝒏−𝟏
𝒊=𝟎 𝒇 ′ 𝒙 + + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉) = 𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇(𝒙)
𝒏 𝒉
𝒏
OR
𝒉
[MC] ×∑ 𝒏−𝟏
𝒊=𝟎 𝒇 ′ 𝒙 + 𝒉𝒊 = 𝒇 𝒙 + 𝒉 − 𝒇(𝒙) − 𝒉∙𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝒉∙𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
One might ask why we need to subtract from
𝒏
𝒇 𝒄−𝒎+(𝒎+𝒏)(𝒔+𝟏) −𝒇 𝒄−𝒎+(𝒎+𝒏)𝒔
𝒇′ 𝝁𝒔 = 𝒌
𝒎+𝒏
𝒌
This follows from the fact that the arithmetic mean of the
arithmetic means of all the sub-intervals will be 𝒇′(𝒄).
However, none of these assumptions are actually needed,
because the New Calculus derivative 𝒇′ 𝝁𝒔 is by
definition equivalent to the mean value theorem for the
given sub-interval. At any rate, if these assumptions are
incorrect, then the following reasoning will result in a
contradiction.
𝟑 𝒎+𝒏 𝟐 𝒎+𝒏
𝒇 𝒄−𝒎+ −𝒇 𝒄−𝒎+
𝒌 𝒌
+ 𝒎+𝒏
+…
𝒌
(𝒌−𝟏)(𝒎+𝒏)
𝒇 𝒄+𝒏 −𝒇 𝒄−𝒎+
𝒌
+ 𝒎+𝒏
}
𝒌
And ∫ 𝒄+𝒏
𝒄−𝒎 𝒇 ′ 𝒙 𝒅𝒙 = 𝒇 𝒄 + 𝒏 − 𝒇(𝒄 − 𝒎) is known
ubiquitously as the fundamental theorem of calculus,
which as we have shown is derived in one step from the
mean value theorem. The New Calculus integral is
equivalent to the mainstream, definition as follows:
35
𝒌−𝟏 𝒄+𝒏
𝒎+𝒏
𝑰= 𝒇′ (𝝁𝒔 ) = 𝒇′ 𝒙 𝒅𝒙
𝒌 𝒄−𝒎
𝒔=𝟎
𝑰 = 𝒎+𝒏 ∑ 𝒌−𝟏
𝒔=𝟎 𝒇 ′ (𝝁 𝒔 ) is the New Calculus integral.
𝒌
Chapter 4.
Pathologically jealous and malicious Mainstream
Academics attack my ideas.
My Historic Geometric Theorem was too much for the
corrupt mainstream mathematics establishment. At first
they rejected it as incorrect, unable to comprehend
innovations beyond their rigid dogma.
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇 𝒙
That is, = 𝒇𝟐 + 𝒇𝟏
𝒉 𝒉 𝒉
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇 𝒙
. This quotient approaches the slope's value but
𝒉
never becomes the actual rise/run ratio.
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇 𝒙
= 𝒇𝟐 + 𝒇𝟏 = 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝒉 𝒉 𝒉
𝒇 𝒙+𝒉 −𝒇 𝒙
= 𝒇𝟐 + 𝒇𝟏 = 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
𝒉 𝒉 𝒉
I responded as follows:
That's a very interesting observation. So, what you are
saying is that mainstream calculus uses the function to
measure the tangent line slope rather than the tangent line
to measure the function? One might retort that the
property of the tangent line, that is, run/rise is incorrectly
applied to the function as a means to measure the tangent
slope.
For example,
tangent slope property
→ function difference quotient
→ tangent slope property
59
we have
𝟐𝒌 𝟐 𝟐
∫ 𝟓𝟑 𝟑𝒙 𝟐 𝒅𝒙 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 ∑ 𝒏𝒌=𝟏 𝟑 𝟑+ ∙
𝒏 →∞ 𝒏 𝒏
𝟐
∫ 𝟓𝟑 𝟑𝒙 𝟐 𝒅𝒙 = 𝐥𝐢𝐦 ∑ 𝒏𝒌=𝟏 𝟔 𝟗 + 𝟏𝟐𝒌 + 𝟒𝒌𝟐
𝒏 →∞ 𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
𝟓𝟒 𝟕𝟐𝒌 𝟐𝟒𝒌 𝟐
∫ 𝟓𝟑 𝟑𝒙 𝟐 𝒅𝒙 = 𝒏
𝐥𝐢𝐦 ∑ 𝒌=𝟏 + 𝟐 + 𝟑
𝒏 →∞ 𝒏 𝒏 𝒏
Causal Systems.
In applied contexts, calculus models often represent
causal systems - where the output at any time 𝒕 depends
only on past and present inputs, for example, if 𝒕𝒏
represents the current time and 𝒕𝒏 − 𝒅, a past time that is
less than 𝒕𝒏 by 𝒅 time units, then quantities like 𝒇(𝒕𝒏 ) and
𝒇(𝒕𝒏 − 𝒅) in a difference quotient arise from real-world
measurements, carrying inherent approximation error. No
practical calculus inputs are truly instantaneous or
continuous. For functions, one may only talk about a
particular time 𝒕, not an instantaneous time. My historic
geometric theorem directly reflects this by using finite
differences without pretense of infinitesimal exactness.
Thus my calculus explains the intrinsic imprecision of
causal systems, while orthodoxy’s “instantaneous”
infinitesimals are profoundly disconnected from physical
reality or otherwise. By rejecting misleading infinitary
metaphors, my calculus restores firm grounding in the
discrete empirical world.
9. Mythmatics.
Highly stupid mainstream academics' arrogance allows
them to spout mathematical myths based on whims, not
logic. Infinitesimals exemplify such fiction - supposedly
above 0 yet below any positive value. This incoherence
baffles feeble minds, like Robinson's "non-standard
analysis" drivel. The gist of Robinson’s delusions is based
on what he calls the “transfer principle” which is assumed
without any proof whatsoever.
Cauchy’s Calculus?
One of the most irrelevant yet widely touted books on
calculus is Judith Grabiner's "The Origins of Cauchy's
75
𝒇 𝒙 + 𝒉 − 𝒇 𝒙 = 𝒉 × 𝒇′ 𝒙 + 𝑸(𝒙,𝒉)
No limits, integrals, infinitesimals, or approximations
exist in this pristine identity - merely the relation
between area and slopes, connected through function
and derivative.
All that is required for a complete theory of the derivative
and integral resides within this sparse identity, condensed
to geometric fundamentals. The simplest expressions
80
𝒎+𝒏
called his formula 𝒛 𝒙 = 𝒂𝒏 𝒙 𝒏 a “rule” and at no stage
𝒎+𝒏
did he ever prove the formula actually produces the area under
𝒎
the curve of 𝒚 = 𝒂𝒙 𝒏 . The problem with such an approach is that
it is not general enough, for example, 𝒚 = 𝒂 𝒙 is not in the same
family of functions and Newton would have had a task on his
𝒂𝒙
hands trying to find the integral of 𝒚 = 𝒂 𝒙 which is . What
𝐥𝐨𝐠 𝒂
follows is a classical hand waving argument that would soon
become the norm in mainstream academia till this day. The
modus operandi consisted of the following processes:
· Assumption of fact
· Hypothesis
· Probability
· Suspicion
· Verification
My short YT video explains.
𝒎+𝒏
𝒂𝒏
Let’s continue with the formula 𝒛 𝒙 = 𝒙 𝒏 which is then
𝒎+𝒏
𝒂𝒏
rewritten as 𝒛 𝒙 𝒏 = 𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑 where 𝒄 = and 𝒑 = 𝒎 + 𝒏.
𝒎+𝒏
into 𝒛 𝒙 𝒏 = 𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑 to get 𝒛 𝒙 + 𝒐 𝒏 = 𝒛 𝒙 + 𝒐𝒗 𝒏 =
𝒄𝒏 𝒙 + 𝒐 𝒑.
Newton then used the binomial theorem to expand both sides and
arrive at
𝒏𝒏 − 𝒏
𝒛(𝒙)𝒏 + 𝒏𝒛(𝒙)𝒏−𝟏 𝒐𝒗 + 𝒛(𝒙)𝒏−𝟐 𝒐𝟐 𝒗𝟐 + …
𝟐
𝒑𝒑 − 𝒑 𝒏 𝒑−𝟐 𝟐
= 𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑 + 𝒑𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑−𝟏 𝒐 + 𝒄 𝒙 𝒐 +…
𝟐
Next, he removes the equal terms above from each side
and divides throughout by 𝒐:
𝒏𝒛(𝒙)𝒏−𝟏 𝒗 + 𝒏𝒏−𝒏 𝒛(𝒙)𝒏−𝟐 𝒐𝒗𝟐 + … = 𝒑𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑−𝟏 + 𝒑𝒑−𝒑 𝒄𝒏 𝒙𝒑−𝟐 𝒐 + …
𝟐 𝟐
→ 𝒐𝒗 = 𝟑𝒙𝟐 𝒐 + 𝟑𝒙𝒐𝟐 + 𝒐𝟑
→ 𝒗 = 𝟑𝒙𝟐 + 𝟑𝒙𝒐 + 𝒐𝟐
Set 𝒐 = 𝟎
→ 𝒗 = 𝟑𝒙𝟐
Since the rectangle area diminishes to nothing, 𝒗
coincides with 𝒚 and so according to Newton, he “proved”
that 𝒚 = 𝟑𝒙𝟐 AND that 𝒛(𝒙) = 𝒙𝟑 is the area function!
In fact, Newton did nothing but differentiate 𝒛(𝒙) = 𝒙𝟑 in a
very deceptive way by including the area 𝒐𝒗 which plays
no part in the differentiation and always reduces to 𝒗.
Here is a summary:
The mainstream epsilon-delta definition of the derivative is
problematic for several reasons:
· It is circular, requiring knowing the limit 𝑳 (the
derivative 𝒇′(𝒙) ) in order to define 𝒇′(𝒙).
· There is no valid construction of real numbers, so
foundations are lacking. See chapter 14 of link.
· The definition is more of a "verifinition" that verifies
the guess for 𝑳 obtained by flawed arithmetic of
setting 𝒉 = 𝟎. Ironically, it is valid to set 𝒉 = 𝟎 if you
can provide the rationale. No one before me could.
· The limit 𝑳 is never contained within the sequence of
difference quotients that supposedly converge to it.
You have innumerable finite differences in
𝒇 𝒙 + 𝒉 − 𝒇(𝒙) and 𝒉, of which NONE ever
represent the slope of the tangent line at 𝒙.
90
𝐀𝐧𝐠𝐥𝐞 𝟐
𝐀𝐧𝐠𝐥𝐞𝟐 = 𝟐𝒕𝟐 → 𝒕 =
𝟐
𝐨𝐩𝐩𝐨𝐬𝐢𝐭𝐞𝟐 + 𝐚𝐝𝐣𝐚𝐜𝐞𝐧𝐭𝟐
So that
𝒕
𝐬𝐢𝐧𝐞 𝒙 =
𝐨𝐩𝐩𝐨𝐬𝐢𝐭𝐞 𝟐+𝐚𝐝𝐣𝐚𝐜𝐞𝐧𝐭 𝟐
97
𝟏−𝒕
𝐜𝐨𝐬𝐢𝐧𝐞 𝒙 =
𝐨𝐩𝐩𝐨𝐬𝐢𝐭𝐞 𝟐+𝐚𝐝𝐣𝐚𝐜𝐞𝐧𝐭 𝟐
𝒕
𝐭𝐚𝐧𝐠𝐞𝐧𝐭 𝒙 =
𝟏−𝒕
𝟑 𝟓
𝐬𝐢𝐧 𝒙 = 𝒙 − 𝒙 + 𝒙 − ... [OS]
𝟑! 𝟓!
The entire graphs for the functions sine and cosine are
shown below:
102
𝒙 𝟏
𝐥𝐢𝐦 =− .
𝒙 →−∞+ 𝟏−𝟐𝒙+𝟐𝒙 𝟐 𝟐
Method Summary:
1. We choose an angle stated as radical units, that is, a
proportion of 2. Thus, to speak of 45° (or 𝜋 radians),
4
we say 1 a right angle or 1 radical unit. Only 0, 1 and 1
2 2 2
of a right angle have the same measure in degrees or
radians. There is no isomorphism from the secant line
to the quarter circle arc (*). For example, 0.5176375
right angle corresponds to 30° (or 𝜋 radians).
6
2. We find the opposite length by using the theorem of
Pythagoras.
3. Since the triangle so created is a right-angled
isosceles triangle, the adjacent side is equal to 1
minus the opposite side.
106
Fast facts:
About 36.6% (a little over1/3) of the hypotenuse length is
equivalent to 30 degrees or pi/6 radians.
About 63.4% (a little under 2/3) of the hypotenuse length
is equivalent to 60 degrees or pi/3.
0% of the hypotenuse length is exactly equal to 0 degrees
or 0 radians.
109
Method of exhaustion?
A generally misunderstood method, it has nothing to do
with limits, but rather relates to Propositions 3 and 4 of On
Spirals (Works of Archimedes) where a certain value is
sandwiched between two rational (the adjective ‘rational’
being redundant) numbers.
111